💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › mark-fisher-capitalist-realism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:41:17. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Capitalist Realism
Author: Mark Fisher, (k-punk)
Date: 2009
Language: en
Topics: capitalism, neoliberalism, history, zizek

Mark Fisher, (k-punk)

Capitalist Realism

Capitalist

Realism

Is There No Alternative?

First published by O Books, 2009

O Books is an imprint of John Hunt Publishing Ltd., The Bothy, Deershot

Lodge, Park Lane, Ropley, Hants, SO24 0BE, UK

office1@o-books.net

www.o-books.net

Distribution in:

UK and Europe

Orca Book Services

orders@orcabookservices.co.uk

Tel: 01202 665432 Fax: 01202 666219

Int. code (44)

USA and Canada

NBN

custserv@nbnbooks.com

Tel: 1 800 462 6420 Fax: 1 800 338 4550

Australia and New Zealand

Brumby Books

sales@brumbybooks.com.au

Tel: 61 3 9761 5535 Fax: 61 3 9761 7095

Far East (offices in Singapore, Thailand,

Hong Kong, Taiwan)

Pansing Distribution Pte Ltd

kemal@pansing.com

Tel: 65 6319 9939 Fax: 65 6462 5761

South Africa

Stephan Phillips (pty) Ltd

Email:

orders@stephanphillips.com

Tel: 27 21 4489839 Telefax: 27 21 4479879

Text copyright Mark Fisher 2008

Design: Stuart Davies

ISBN: 978 1 84694 317 1

All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in critical articles or

reviews, no part of this book may be reproduced in any manner without

prior written permission from the publishers.

The rights of Mark Fisher as author have been asserted in accordance

with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

A CIP catalogue record for this book is available from the British

Library.

Printed by Digital Book Print

O Books operates a distinctive and ethical publishing philosophy in all

areas of its business, from its global network of authors to production

and worldwide distribution.

Capitalist

Realism

Is There No Alternative?

Mark Fisher

Winchester, UK

Washington, USA

Mark Fisher is a writer, theorist and teacher. His writing regularly

appears in frieze, New Statesman, The Wire and Sight & Sound. He was a

founding member of the Cybernetic Culture Research Unit. He is now a

Visiting Fellow in the Centre for Cultural Studies at Goldsmiths,

University of London and a tutor in Philosophy at the City Literary

Institute, London. His weblog can be found at

http://k-punk.abstractdynamics.org

. He is married and lives in Suffolk.

To my wife, ZĂśe, my parents, Bob and Linda, and the readers of my

website

1

It’s easier to imagine the end of the world than the end of capitalism

In one of the key scenes in Alfonso Cuarón’s 2006 film Children of Men,

Clive Owen’s character, Theo, visits a friend at Battersea Power

Station, which is now some combination of government building and

private collection. Cultural treasures – Michelangelo’s David, Picasso’s

Guernica, Pink Floyd’s inflatable pig – are preserved in a building that

is itself a refurbished heritage artifact. This is our only glimpse into

the lives of the elite, holed up against the effects of a catastrophe

which has caused mass sterility: no children have been born for a

generation. Theo asks the question, ‘how all this can matter if there

will be no-one to see it?’ The alibi can no longer be future

generations, since there will be none. The response is nihilistic

hedonism: ‘I try not to think about it’.

What is unique about the dystopia in Children of Men is that it is

specific to late capitalism. This isn’t the familiar totalitarian

scenario routinely trotted out in cinematic dystopias (see, for example,

James McTeigue’s 2005 V for Vendetta). In the PD. James novel on which

the film is based, democracy is suspended and the country is ruled over

by a self-appointed Warden, but, wisely, the film downplays all this.

For all that we know, the authoritarian measures that are everywhere in

place could have been implemented within a political structure that

remains, notionally, democratic. The War on Terror has prepared us for

such a development: the normalization of crisis produces a situation in

which the repealing of measures brought in to deal with an emergency

becomes unimaginable (when will the war be over?)

Watching Children of Men, we are inevitably reminded of the phrase

attributed to Fredric Jameson and Slavoj ŽiŞek, that it is easier to

imagine the end of the world than it is to imagine the end of

capitalism. That slogan captures precisely what I mean by ‘capitalist

realism’: the widespread sense that not only is capitalism the only

viable political and economic system, but also that it is now impossible

even to imagine a coherent alternative to it. Once, dystopian films and

novels were exercises in such acts of imagination – the disasters they

depicted acting as narrative pretext for the emergence of different ways

of living. Not so in Children of Men. The world that it projects seems

more like an extrapolation or exacerbation of ours than an alternative

to it. In its world, as in ours, ultra-authoritarianism and Capital are

by no means incompatible: internment camps and franchise coffee bars

co-exist. In Children of Men, public space is abandoned, given over to

uncollected garbage and stalking animals (one especially resonant scene

takes place inside a derelict school, through which a deer runs).

Neoliberals, the capitalist realists par excellence, have celebrated the

destruction of public space but, contrary to their official hopes, there

is no withering away of the state in Children of Men, only a stripping

back of the state to its core military and police functions (I say

‘official’ hopes since neoliberalism surreptitiously relied on the state

even while it has ideologically excoriated it. This was made

spectacularly clear during the banking crisis of 2008, when, at the

invitation of neoliberal ideologues, the state rushed in to shore up the

banking system.)

The catastrophe in Children of Men is neither waiting down the road, nor

has it already happened. Rather, it is being lived through. There is no

punctual moment of disaster; the world doesn’t end with a bang, it winks

out, unravels, gradually falls apart. What caused the catastrophe to

occur, who knows; its cause lies long in the past, so absolutely

detached from the present as to seem like the caprice of a malign being:

a negative miracle, a malediction which no penitence can ameliorate.

Such a blight can only be eased by an intervention that can no more be

anticipated than was the onset of the curse in the first place. Action

is pointless; only senseless hope makes sense. Superstition and

religion, the first resorts of the helpless, proliferate.

But what of the catastrophe itself? It is evident that the theme of

sterility must be read metaphorically, as the displacement of another

kind of anxiety. I want to argue this anxiety cries out to be read in

cultural terms, and the question the film poses is: how long can a

culture persist without the new? What happens if the young are no longer

capable of producing surprises?

Children of Men connects with the suspicion that the end has already

come, the thought that it could well be the case that the future harbors

only reiteration and re-permutation. Could it be that there are no

breaks, no ‘shocks of the new’ to come? Such anxieties tend to result in

a bi-polar oscillation: the ‘weak messianic’ hope that there must be

something new on the way lapses into the morose conviction that nothing

new can ever happen. The focus shifts from the Next Big Thing to the

last big thing – how long ago did it happen and just how big was it?

T.S. Eliot looms in the background of Children of Men, which, after all,

inherits the theme of sterility from The Waste Land. The film’s closing

epigraph ‘shantih shantih shantih’ has more to do with Eliot’s

fragmentary pieces than the Upanishads’ peace. Perhaps it is possible to

see the concerns of another Eliot – the Eliot of ‘Tradition and the

Individual Talent’ – ciphered in Children of Men. It was in this essay

that Eliot, in anticipation of Harold Bloom, described the reciprocal

relationship between the canonical and the new. The new defines itself

in response to what is already established; at the same time, the

established has to reconfigure itself in response to the new. Eliot’s

claim was that the exhaustion of the future does not even leave us with

the past. Tradition counts for nothing when it is no longer contested

and modified. A culture that is merely preserved is no culture at all.

The fate of Picasso’s Guernica in the film – once a howl of anguish and

outrage against Fascist atrocities, now a wall-hanging – is exemplary.

Like its Battersea hanging space in the film, the painting is accorded

‘iconic’ status only when it is deprived of any possible function or

context. No cultural object can retain its power when there are no

longer new eyes to see it.

We do not need to wait for Children of Men’s near-future to arrive to

see this transformation of culture into museum pieces. The power of

capitalist realism derives in part from the way that capitalism subsumes

and consumes all of previous history: one effect of its ‘system of

equivalence’ which can assign all cultural objects, whether they are

religious iconography, pornography, or Das Kapital, a monetary value.

Walk around the British Museum, where you see objects torn from their

lifeworlds and assembled as if on the deck of some Predator spacecraft,

and you have a powerful image of this process at work. In the conversion

of practices and rituals into merely aesthetic objects, the beliefs of

previous cultures are objectively ironized, transformed into artifacts.

Capitalist realism is therefore not a particular type of realism; it is

more like realism in itself. As Marx and Engels themselves observed in

The Communist Manifesto,

[Capital] has drowned the most heavenly ecstasies of religious fervor,

of chivalrous enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism, in the icy water

of egotistical calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange

value, and in place of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms,

has set up that single, unconscionable freedom — Free Trade. In one

word, for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it

has substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation.

Capitalism is what is left when beliefs have collapsed at the level of

ritual or symbolic elaboration, and all that is left is the

consumer-spectator, trudging through the ruins and the relics.

Yet this turn from belief to aesthetics, from engagement to

spectatorship, is held to be one of the virtues of capitalist realism.

In claiming, as Badiou puts it, to have ‘delivered us from the “fatal

abstractions” inspired by the “ideologies of the past”’, capitalist

realism presents itself as a shield protecting us from the perils posed

by belief itself. The attitude of ironic distance proper to postmodern

capitalism is supposed to immunize us against the seductions of

fanaticism. Lowering our expectations, we are told, is a small price to

pay for being protected from terror and totalitarianism. ‘We live in a

contradiction,’ Badiou has observed:

a brutal state of affairs, profoundly inegalitarian – where all

existence is evaluated in terms of money alone – is presented to us as

ideal. To justify their conservatism, the partisans of the established

order cannot really call it ideal or wonderful. So instead, they have

decided to say that all the rest is horrible. Sure, they say, we may not

live in a condition of perfect Goodness. But we’re lucky that we don’t

live in a condition of Evil. Our democracy is not perfect. But it’s

better than the bloody dictatorships. Capitalism is unjust. But it’s not

criminal like Stalinism. We let millions of Africans die of AIDS, but we

don’t make racist nationalist declarations like Milosevic. We kill

Iraqis with our airplanes, but we don’t cut their throats with machetes

like they do in Rwanda, etc.

The ‘realism’ here is analogous to the deflationary perspective of a

depressive who believes that any positive state, any hope, is a

dangerous illusion.

In their account of capitalism, surely the most impressive since Marx’s,

Deleuze and Guattari describe capitalism as a kind of dark potentiality

which haunted all previous social systems. Capital, they argue, is the

‘unnamable Thing’, the abomination, which primitive and feudal societies

‘warded off in advance’. When it actually arrives, capitalism brings

with it a massive desacralization of culture. It is a system which is no

longer governed by any transcendent Law; on the contrary, it dismantles

all such codes, only to re-install them on an ad hoc basis. The limits

of capitalism are not fixed by fiat, but defined (and redefined)

pragmatically and improvisationally. This makes capitalism very much

like the Thing in John Carpenter’s film of the same name: a monstrous,

infinitely plastic entity, capable of metabolizing and absorbing

anything with which it comes into contact. Capital, Deleuze and Guattari

says, is a ‘motley painting of everything that ever was’; a strange

hybrid of the ultra-modern and the archaic. In the years since Deleuze

and Guattari wrote the two volumes of their Capitalism And

Schizophrenia, it has seemed as if the deterritorializing impulses of

capitalism have been confined to finance, leaving culture presided over

by the forces of reterritorialization.

This malaise, the feeling that there is nothing new, is itself nothing

new of course. We find ourselves at the notorious ‘end of history’

trumpeted by Francis Fukuyama after the fall of the Berlin Wall.

Fukuyama’s thesis that history has climaxed with liberal capitalism may

have been widely derided, but it is accepted, even assumed, at the level

of the cultural unconscious. It should be remembered, though, that even

when Fukuyama advanced it, the idea that history had reached a ‘terminal

beach’ was not merely triumphalist. Fukuyama warned that his radiant

city would be haunted, but he thought its specters would be Nietzschean

rather than Marxian. Some of Nietzsche’s most prescient pages are those

in which he describes the ‘oversaturation of an age with history’. ‘It

leads an age into a dangerous mood of irony in regard to itself, he

wrote in Untimely Meditations, ‘and subsequently into the even more

dangerous mood of cynicism’, in which ‘cosmopolitan fingering’, a

detached spectatorialism, replaces engagement and involvement. This is

the condition of Nietzsche’s Last Man, who has seen everything, but is

decadently enfeebled precisely by this excess of (self) awareness.

Fukuyama’s position is in some ways a mirror image of Fredric Jameson’s.

Jameson famously claimed that postmodernism is the ‘cultural logic of

late capitalism’. He argued that the failure of the future was

constitutive of a postmodern cultural scene which, as he correctly

prophesied, would become dominated by pastiche and revivalism. Given

that Jameson has made a convincing case for the relationship between

postmodern culture and certain tendencies in consumer (or post-Fordist)

capitalism, it could appear that there is no need for the concept of

capitalist realism at all. In some ways, this is true. What I’m calling

capitalist realism can be subsumed under the rubric of postmodernism as

theorized by Jameson. Yet, despite Jameson’s heroic work of

clarification, postmodernism remains a hugely contested term, its

meanings, appropriately but unhelpfully, unsettled and multiple. More

importantly, I would want to argue that some of the processes which

Jameson described and analyzed have now become so aggravated and chronic

that they have gone through a change in kind.

Ultimately, there are three reasons that I prefer the term capitalist

realism to postmodernism. In the 1980s, when Jameson first advanced his

thesis about postmodernism, there were still, in name at least,

political alternatives to capitalism. What we are dealing with now,

however, is a deeper, far more pervasive, sense of exhaustion, of

cultural and political sterility. In the 80s, ‘Really Existing

Socialism’ still persisted, albeit in its final phase of collapse. In

Britain, the fault lines of class antagonism were fully exposed in an

event like the Miners’ Strike of 1984-1985, and the defeat of the miners

was an important moment in the development of capitalist realism, at

least as significant in its symbolic dimension as in its practical

effects. The closure of pits was defended precisely on the grounds that

keeping them open was not ‘economically realistic’, and the miners were

cast in the role of the last actors in a doomed proletarian romance. The

80s were the period when capitalist realism was fought for and

established, when Margaret Thatcher’s doctrine that ‘there is no

alternative’ – as succinct a slogan of capitalist realism as you could

hope for – became a brutally self-fulfilling prophecy.

Secondly, postmodernism involved some relationship to modernism.

Jameson’s work on postmodernism began with an interrogation of the idea,

cherished by the likes of Adorno, that modernism possessed revolutionary

potentials by virtue of its formal innovations alone. What Jameson saw

happening instead was the incorporation of modernist motifs into popular

culture (suddenly, for example, Surrealist techniques would appear in

advertising). At the same time as particular modernist forms were

absorbed and commodified, modernism’s credos – its supposed belief in

elitism and its monological, top-down model of culture – were challenged

and rejected in the name of ‘difference’, ‘diversity’ and

‘multiplicity’. Capitalist realism no longer stages this kind of

confrontation with modernism. On the contrary, it takes the vanquishing

of modernism for granted: modernism is now something that can

periodically return, but only as a frozen aesthetic style, never as an

ideal for living.

Thirdly, a whole generation has passed since the collapse of the Berlin

Wall. In the 1960s and 1970s, capitalism had to face the problem of how

to contain and absorb energies from outside. It now, in fact, has the

opposite problem; having all-too successfully incorporated externality,

how can it function without an outside it can colonize and appropriate?

For most people under twenty in Europe and North America, the lack of

alternatives to capitalism is no longer even an issue. Capitalism

seamlessly occupies the horizons of the thinkable. Jameson used to

report in horror about the ways that capitalism had seeped into the very

unconscious; now, the fact that capitalism has colonized the dreaming

life of the population is so taken for granted that it is no longer

worthy of comment. It would be dangerous and misleading to imagine that

the near past was some prelapsarian state rife with political

potentials, so it’s as well to remember the role that commodification

played in the production of culture throughout the twentieth century.

Yet the old struggle between detournement and recuperation, between

subversion and incorporation, seems to have been played out. What we are

dealing with now is not the incorporation of materials that previously

seemed to possess subversive potentials, but instead, their

precorporation: the pre-emptive formatting and shaping of desires,

aspirations and hopes by capitalist culture. Witness, for instance, the

establishment of settled ‘alternative’ or ‘independent’ cultural zones,

which endlessly repeat older gestures of rebellion and contestation as

if for the first time. ‘Alternative’ and ‘independent’ don’t designate

something outside mainstream culture; rather, they are styles, in fact

the dominant styles, within the mainstream. No-one embodied (and

struggled with) this deadlock more than Kurt Cobain and Nirvana. In his

dreadful lassitude and objectless rage, Cobain seemed to give wearied

voice to the despondency of the generation that had come after history,

whose every move was anticipated, tracked, bought and sold before it had

even happened. Cobain knew that he was just another piece of spectacle,

that nothing runs better on MTV than a protest against MTV; knew that

his every move was a clichĂŠ scripted in advance, knew that even

realizing it is a clichĂŠ. The impasse that paralyzed Cobain is precisely

the one that Jameson described: like postmodern culture in general,

Cobain found himself in ‘a world in which stylistic innovation is no

longer possible, [where] all that is left is to imitate dead styles, to

speak through the masks and with the voices of the styles in the

imaginary museum’. Here, even success meant failure, since to succeed

would only mean that you were the new meat on which the system could

feed. But the high existential angst of Nirvana and Cobain belongs to an

older moment; what succeeded them was a pastiche-rock which reproduced

the forms of the past without anxiety.

Cobain’s death confirmed the defeat and incorporation of rock’s utopian

and promethean ambitions. When he died, rock was already being eclipsed

by hip hop, whose global success has presupposed just the kind of

precorporation by capital which I alluded to above. For much hip hop,

any ‘naïve’ hope that youth culture could change anything has been

replaced by the hard-headed embracing of a brutally reductive version of

‘reality’. ‘In hip hop’, Simon Reynolds pointed out in a 1996 essay in

The Wire magazine,

‘real’ has two meanings. First, it means authentic, uncompro-mised music

that refuses to sell out to the music industry and soften its message

for crossover. ‘Real’ also signifies that the music reflects a ‘reality’

constituted by late capitalist economic instability, institutionalized

racism, and increased surveillance and harassment of youth by the

police. ‘Real’ means the death of the social: it means corporations who

respond to increased profits not by raising pay or improving benefits

but by …. downsizing (the laying-off the permanent workforce in order to

create a floating employment pool of part-time and freelance workers

without benefits or job security).

In the end, it was precisely hip hop’s performance of this first version

of the real – ‘the uncompromising’ – that enabled its easy absorption

into the second, the reality of late capitalist economic instability,

where such authenticity has proven highly marketable. Gangster rap

neither merely reflects pre-existing social conditions, as many of its

advocates claim, nor does it simply cause those conditions, as its

critics argue – rather the circuit whereby hip hop and the late

capitalist social field feed into each other is one of the means by

which capitalist realism transforms itself into a kind of anti-mythical

myth. The affinity between hip hop and gangster movies such as Scarface,

The Godfather films, Reservoir Dogs, Goodfellas and Pulp Fiction arises

from their common claim to have stripped the world of sentimental

illusions and seen it for ‘what it really is’: a Hobbesian war of all

against all, a system of perpetual exploitation and generalized

criminality. In hip hop, Reynolds writes, ‘To “get real” is to confront

a state-of-nature where dog eats dog, where you’re either a winner or a

loser, and where most will be losers’.

The same neo-noir worldview can be found in the comic books of Frank

Miller and in the novels of James Ellroy. There is a kind of machismo of

demythologization in Miller and Ellroy’s works. They pose as unflinching

observers who refuse to prettify the world so that it can be fitted into

the supposedly simple ethical binaries of the superhero comic and the

traditional crime novel. The ‘realism’ here is somehow underscored,

rather than undercut, by their fixation on the luridly venal – even

though the hyperbolic insistence on cruelty, betrayal and savagery in

both writers quickly becomes pantomimic. ‘In his pitch blackness’, Mike

Davis wrote of Ellroy in 1992, ‘there is no light left to cast shadows

and evil becomes a forensic banality. The result feels very much like

the actual moral texture of the Reagan-Bush era: a supersaturation of

corruption that fails any longer to outrage or even interest’. Yet this

very desensitization serves a function for capitalist realism: Davis

hypothesized that ‘the role of L.A. noir’ may have been ‘to endorse the

emergence of homo reaganus’.

2

What if you held a protest and everyone came?

In the cases of gangster rap and Ellroy, capitalist realism takes the

form of a kind of super-identification with capital at its most

pitilessly predatory, but this need not be the case. In fact, capitalist

realism is very far from precluding a certain anti-capitalism. After

all, and as ŽiŞek has provocatively pointed out, anti-capitalism is

widely disseminated in capitalism. Time after time, the villain in

Hollywood films will turn out to be the ‘evil corporation’. Far from

undermining capitalist realism, this gestural anti-capitalism actually

reinforces it. Take Disney/ Pixar’s Wall-E (2008). The film shows an

earth so despoiled that human beings are no longer capable of inhabiting

it. We’re left in no doubt that consumer capitalism and corporations –

or rather one mega-corporation, Buy n Large – is responsible for this

depredation; and when we see eventually see the human beings in offworld

exile, they are infantile and obese, interacting via screen interfaces,

carried around in large motorized chairs, and supping indeterminate slop

from cups. What we have here is a vision of control and communication

much as Jean Baudrillard understood it, in which subjugation no longer

takes the form of a subordination to an extrinsic spectacle, but rather

invites us to interact and participate. It seems that the cinema

audience is itself the object of this satire, which prompted some right

wing observers to recoil in disgust, condemning Disney/Pixar for

attacking its own audience. But this kind of irony feeds rather than

challenges capitalist realism. A film like Wall-E exemplifies what

Robert Pfaller has called ‘interpassivity’: the film performs our

anti-capitalism for us, allowing us to continue to consume with

impunity. The role of capitalist ideology is not to make an explicit

case for something in the way that propaganda does, but to conceal the

fact that the operations of capital do not depend on any sort of

subjectively assumed belief. It is impossible to conceive of fascism or

Stalinism without propaganda – but capitalism can proceed perfectly

well, in some ways better, without anyone making a case for it. Žižek’s

counsel here remains invaluable. ‘If the concept of ideology is the

classic one in which the illusion is located in knowledge’, he argues,

then today’s society must appear post-ideological: the prevailing

ideology is that of cynicism; people no longer believe in ideological

truth; they do not take ideological propositions seriously. The

fundamental level of ideology, however, is not of an illusion masking

the real state of things but that of an (unconscious) fantasy

structuring our social reality itself. And at this level, we are of

course far from being a post-ideological society. Cynical distance is

just one way … to blind ourselves to the structural power of ideological

fantasy: even if we do not take things seriously, even if we keep an

ironical distance, we are still doing them.

Capitalist ideology in general, ŽiŞek maintains, consists precisely in

the overvaluing of belief – in the sense of inner subjective attitude –

at the expense of the beliefs we exhibit and externalize in our

behavior. So long as we believe (in our hearts) that capitalism is bad,

we are free to continue to participate in capitalist exchange. According

to ŽiŞek, capitalism in general relies on this structure of disavowal.

We believe that money is only a meaningless token of no intrinsic worth,

yet we act as if it has a holy value. Moreover, this behavior precisely

depends upon the prior disavowal – we are able to fetishize money in our

actions only because we have already taken an ironic distance towards

money in our heads.

Corporate anti-capitalism wouldn’t matter if it could be differentiated

from an authentic anti-capitalist movement. Yet, even before its

momentum was stalled by the September 11^(th) attacks on the World Trade

Center, the so called anti-capitalist movement seemed also to have

conceded too much to capitalist realism. Since it was unable to posit a

coherent alternative political-economic model to capitalism, the

suspicion was that the actual aim was not to replace capitalism but to

mitigate its worst excesses; and, since the form of its activities

tended to be the staging of protests rather than political organization,

there was a sense that the anti-capitalism movement consisted of making

a series of hysterical demands which it didn’t expect to be met.

Protests have formed a kind of carnivalesque background noise to

capitalist realism, and the anti-capitalist protests share rather too

much with hyper-corporate events like 2005’s Live 8, with their

exorbitant demands that politicians legislate away poverty.

Live 8 was a strange kind of protest; a protest that everyone could

agree with: who is it who actually wants poverty? And it is not that

Live 8 was a ‘degraded’ form of protest. On the contrary, it was in Live

8 that the logic of the protest was revealed in its purest form. The

protest impulse of the 60s posited a malevolent Father, the harbinger of

a reality principle that (supposedly) cruelly and arbitrarily denies the

‘right’ to total enjoyment. This Father has unlimited access to

resources, but he selfishly – and senselessly – hoards them. Yet it is

not capitalism but protest itself which depends upon this figuration of

the Father; and one of the successes of the current global elite has

been their avoidance of identification with the figure of the hoarding

Father, even though the ‘reality’ they impose on the young is

substantially harsher than the conditions they protested against in the

60s. Indeed, it was of course the global elite itself – in the form of

entertainers such as Richard Curtis and Bono – which organized the Live

8 event. To reclaim a real political agency means first of all accepting

our insertion at the level of desire in the remorseless meat-grinder of

Capital. What is being disavowed in the abjection of evil and ignorance

onto fantasmatic Others is our own complicity in planetary networks of

oppression. What needs to be kept in mind is both that capitalism is a

hyper-abstract impersonal structure and that it would be nothing without

our co-operation. The most Gothic description of Capital is also the

most accurate. Capital is an abstract parasite, an insatiable vampire

and zombie-maker; but the living flesh it converts into dead labor is

ours, and the zombies it makes are us. There is a sense in which it

simply is the case that the political elite are our servants; the

miserable service they provide from us is to launder our libidos, to

obligingly re-present for us our disavowed desires as if they had

nothing to do with us.

The ideological blackmail that has been in place since the original Live

Aid concerts in 1985 has insisted that ‘caring individuals’ could end

famine directly, without the need for any kind of political solution or

systemic reorganization. It is necessary to act straight away, we were

told; politics has to be suspended in the name of ethical immediacy.

Bono’s Product Red brand wanted to dispense even with the philanthropic

intermediary. ‘Philanthropy is like hippy music, holding hands’, Bono

proclaimed. ‘Red is more like punk rock, hip hop, this should feel like

hard commerce’. The point was not to offer an alternative to capitalism

– on the contrary, Product Red’s ‘punk rock’ or ‘hip hop’ character

consisted in its ‘realistic’ acceptance that capitalism is the only game

in town. No, the aim was only to ensure that some of the proceeds of

particular transactions went to good causes. The fantasy being that

western consumerism, far from being intrinsically implicated in systemic

global inequalities, could itself solve them. All we have to do is buy

the right products.

3

Capitalism and the Real

‘Capitalist realism’ is not an original coinage. It was used as far back

as the 1960s by a group of German Pop artists and by Michael Schudson in

his 1984 book Advertising, The Uneasy Persuasion, both of whom were

making parodic references to socialist realism. What is new about my use

of the term is the more expansive – even exorbitant – meaning that I

ascribe to it. Capitalist realism as I understand it cannot be confined

to art or to the quasi-propagandistic way in which advertising

functions. It is more like a pervasive atmosphere, conditioning not only

the production of culture but also the regulation of work and education,

and acting as a kind of invisible barrier constraining thought and

action.

If capitalist realism is so seamless, and if current forms of resistance

are so hopeless and impotent, where can an effective challenge come

from? A moral critique of capitalism, emphasizing the ways in which it

leads to suffering, only reinforces capitalist realism. Poverty, famine

and war can be presented as an inevitable part of reality, while the

hope that these forms of suffering could be eliminated easily painted as

naive utopianism. Capitalist realism can only be threatened if it is

shown to be in some way inconsistent or untenable; if, that is to say,

capitalism’s ostensible ‘realism’ turns out to be nothing of the sort.

Needless to say, what counts as ‘realistic’, what seems possible at any

point in the social field, is defined by a series of political

determinations. An ideological position can never be really successful

until it is naturalized, and it cannot be naturalized while it is still

thought of as a value rather than a fact. Accordingly, neoliberalism has

sought to eliminate the very category of value in the ethical sense.

Over the past thirty years, capitalist realism has successfully

installed a ‘business ontology’ in which it is simply obvious that

everything in society, including healthcare and education, should be run

as a business. As any number of radical theorists from Brecht through to

Foucault and Badiou have maintained, emancipatory politics must always

destroy the appearance of a ‘natural order’, must reveal what is

presented as necessary and inevitable to be a mere contingency, just as

it must make what was previously deemed to be impossible seem

attainable. It is worth recalling that what is currently called

realistic was itself once ‘impossible’: the slew of privatizations that

took place since the 1980s would have been unthinkable only a decade

earlier, and the current political-economic landscape (with unions in

abeyance, utilities and railways denationalized) could scarcely have

been imagined in 1975. Conversely, what was once eminently possible is

now deemed unrealistic. ‘Modernization’, Badiou bitterly observes, ‘is

the name for a strict and servile definition of the possible. These

‘reforms’ invariably aim at making impossible what used to be

practicable (for the largest number), and making profitable (for the

dominant oligarchy) what did not used to be so’.

At this point, it is perhaps worth introducing an elementary theoretical

distinction from Lacanian psychoanalysis which ŽiŞek has done so much to

give contemporary currency: the difference between the Real and reality.

As Alenka Zupancic explains, psychoanalysis’s positing of a reality

principle invites us to be suspicious of any reality that presents

itself as natural. ‘The reality principle’, Zupancic writes,

is not some kind of natural way associated with how things are ... The

reality principle itself is ideologically mediated; one could even claim

that it constitutes the highest form of ideology, the ideology that

presents itself as empirical fact (or biological, economic...) necessity

(and that we tend to perceive as non-ideological). It is precisely here

that we should be most alert to the functioning of ideology.

For Lacan, the Real is what any ‘reality’ must suppress; indeed, reality

constitutes itself through just this repression. The Real is an

unrepresentable X, a traumatic void that can only be glimpsed in the

fractures and inconsistencies in the field of apparent reality. So one

strategy against capitalist realism could involve invoking the Real(s)

underlying the reality that capitalism presents to us.

Environmental catastrophe is one such Real. At one level, to be sure, it

might look as if Green issues are very far from being ‘unrepresentable

voids’ for capitalist culture. Climate change and the threat of

resource-depletion are not being repressed so much as incorporated into

advertising and marketing. What this treatment of environmental

catastrophe illustrates is the fantasy structure on which capitalist

realism depends: a presupposition that resources are infinite, that the

earth itself is merely a husk which capital can at a certain point

slough off like a used skin, and that any problem can be solved by the

market (In the end, Wall-E presents a version of this fantasy – the idea

that the infinite expansion of capital is possible, that capital can

proliferate without labor – on the off world ship, Axiom, all labor is

performed by robots; that the burning up of Earth’s resources is only a

temporary glitch, and that, after a suitable period of recovery, capital

can terraform the planet and recolonize it). Yet environmental

catastrophe features in late capitalist culture only as a kind of

simulacra, its real implications for capitalism too traumatic to be

assimilated into the system. The significance of Green critiques is that

they suggest that, far from being the only viable political-economic

system, capitalism is in fact primed to destroy the entire human

environment. The relationship between capitalism and eco-disaster is

neither coincidental nor accidental: capital’s ‘need of a constantly

expanding market’, its ‘growth fetish’, mean that capitalism is by its

very nature opposed to any notion of sustainability.

But Green issues are already a contested zone, already a site where

politicization is being fought for. In what follows, I want to stress

two other aporias in capitalist realism, which are not yet politicized

to anything like the same degree. The first is mental health. Mental

health, in fact, is a paradigm case of how capitalist realism operates.

Capitalist realism insists on treating mental health as if it were a

natural fact, like weather (but, then again, weather is no longer a

natural fact so much as a political-economic effect). In the 1960s and

1970s, radical theory and politics (Laing, Foucault, Deleuze and

Guattari, etc.) coalesced around extreme mental conditions such as

schizophrenia, arguing, for instance, that madness was not a natural,

but a political, category. But what is needed now is a politicization of

much more common disorders. Indeed, it is their very commonness which is

the issue: in Britain, depression is now the condition that is most

treated by the NHS. In his book The Selfish Capitalist, Oliver James has

convincingly posited a correlation between rising rates of mental

distress and the neoliberal mode of capitalism practiced in countries

like Britain, the USA and Australia. In line with James’s claims, I want

to argue that it is necessary to reframe the growing problem of stress

(and distress) in capitalist societies. Instead of treating it as

incumbent on individuals to resolve their own psychological distress,

instead, that is, of accepting the vast privatization of stress that has

taken place over the last thirty years, we need to ask: how has it

become acceptable that so many people, and especially so many young

people, are ill? The ‘mental health plague’ in capitalist societies

would suggest that, instead of being the only social system that works,

capitalism is inherently dysfunctional, and that the cost of it

appearing to work is very high.

The other phenomenon I want to highlight is bureaucracy. In making their

case against socialism, neoliberal ideologues often excoriated the

top-down bureaucracy which supposedly led to institutional sclerosis and

inefficiency in command economies. With the triumph of neoliberalism,

bureaucracy was supposed to have been made obsolete; a relic of an

unlamented Stalinist past. Yet this is at odds with the experiences of

most people working and living in late capitalism, for whom bureaucracy

remains very much a part of everyday life. Instead of disappearing,

bureaucracy has changed its form; and this new, decentralized, form has

allowed it to proliferate. The persistence of bureaucracy in late

capitalism does not in itself indicate that capitalism does not work –

rather, what it suggests is that the way in which capitalism does

actually work is very different from the picture presented by capitalist

realism.

In part, I have chosen to focus on mental health problems and

bureaucracy because they both feature heavily in an area of culture

which has becoming increasingly dominated by the imperatives of

capitalist realism: education. Through most of the current decade, I

worked as a lecturer in a Further Education college, and in what

follows, I will draw extensively on my experiences there. In Britain,

Further Education colleges used to be places which students, often from

working class backgrounds, were drawn to if they wanted an alternative

to more formal state educational institutions. Ever since Further

Education colleges were removed from local authority control in the

early 1990s, they have become subject both to ‘market’ pressures and to

government-imposed targets. They have been at the vanguard of changes

that would be rolled out through the rest of the education system and

public services – a kind of lab in which neoliberal ‘reforms’ of

education have been trialed, and as such, they are the perfect place to

begin an analysis of the effects of capitalist realism.

4

Reflexive impotence, immobilization and liberal communism

By contrast with their forebears in the 1960s and 1970s, British

students today appear to be politically disengaged. While French

students can still be found on the streets protesting against

neoliberalism, British students, whose situation is incomparably worse,

seem resigned to their fate. But this, I want to argue, is a matter not

of apathy, nor of cynicism, but of reflexive impotence. They know things

are bad, but more than that, they know they can’t do anything about it.

But that ‘knowledge’, that reflexivity, is not a passive observation of

an already existing state of affairs. It is a self-fulfilling prophecy.

Reflexive impotence amounts to an unstated worldview amongst the British

young, and it has its correlate in widespread pathologies. Many of the

teenagers I worked with had mental health problems or learning

difficulties. Depression is endemic. It is the condition most dealt with

by the National Health Service, and is afflicting people at increasingly

younger ages. The number of students who have some variant of dyslexia

is astonishing. It is not an exaggeration to say that being a teenager

in late capitalist Britain is now close to being reclassified as a

sickness. This pathologization already forecloses any possibility of

politicization. By privatizing these problems – treating them as if they

were caused only by chemical imbalances in the individual’s neurology

and/or by their family background – any question of social systemic

causation is ruled out.

Many of the teenage students I encountered seemed to be in a state of

what I would call depressive hedonia. Depression is usually

characterized as a state of anhedonia, but the condition I’m referring

to is constituted not by an inability to get pleasure so much as it by

an inability to do anything else except pursue pleasure. There is a

sense that ‘something is missing’ – but no appreciation that this

mysterious, missing enjoyment can only be accessed beyond the pleasure

principle. In large part this is a consequence of students’ ambiguous

structural position, stranded between their old role as subjects of

disciplinary institutions and their new status as consumers of services.

In his crucial essay ‘Postscript on Societies of Control’, Deleuze

distinguishes between the disciplinary societies described by Foucault,

which were organized around the enclosed spaces of the factory, the

school and the prison, and the new control societies, in which all

institutions are embedded in a dispersed corporation.

Deleuze is right to argue that Kafka is the prophet of distributed,

cybernetic power that is typical of Control societies. In The Trial,

Kafka importantly distinguishes between two types of acquittal available

to the accused. Definite acquittal is no longer possible, if it ever was

(‘we have only legendary accounts of ancient cases [which] provide

instances of acquittal’). The two remaining options, then, are (1)

‘Ostensible acquittal’, in which the accused is to all and intents and

purposes acquitted, but may later, at some unspecified time, face the

charges in full, or (2) ‘Indefinite postponement’, in which the accused

engages in (what they hope is an infinitely) protracted process of legal

wrangling, so that the dreaded ultimate judgment is unlikely to be

forthcoming. Deleuze observes that the Control societies delineated by

Kafka himself, but also by Foucault and Burroughs, operate using

indefinite postponement: Education as a lifelong process... Training

that persists for as long as your working life continues... Work you

take home with you… Working from home, homing from work. A consequence

of this ‘indefinite’ mode of power is that external surveillance is

succeeded by internal policing. Control only works if you are complicit

with it. Hence the Burroughs figure of the ‘Control Addict’: the one who

is addicted to control, but also, inevitably, the one who has been taken

over, possessed by Control.

Walk into almost any class at the college where I taught and you will

immediately appreciate that you are in a post-disciplinary framework.

Foucault painstakingly enumerated the way in which discipline was

installed through the imposition of rigid body postures. During lessons

at our college, however, students will be found slumped on desk, talking

almost constantly, snacking incessantly (or even, on occasions, eating

full meals). The old disciplinary segmentation of time is breaking down.

The carceral regime of discipline is being eroded by the technologies of

control, with their systems of perpetual consumption and continuous

development.

The system by which the college is funded means that it literally cannot

afford to exclude students, even if it wanted to. Resources are

allocated to colleges on the basis of how successfully they meet targets

on achievement (exam results), attendance and retention of students.

This combination of market imperatives with bureaucratically-defined

‘targets’ is typical of the ‘market Stalinist’ initiatives which now

regulate public services. The lack of an effective disciplinary system

has not, to say the least, been compensated for by an increase in

student self-motivation. Students are aware that if they don’t attend

for weeks on end, and/or if they don’t produce any work, they will not

face any meaningful sanction. They typically respond to this freedom not

by pursuing projects but by falling into hedonic (or anhedonic)

lassitude: the soft narcosis, the comfort food oblivion of Playstation,

all-night TV and marijuana.

Ask students to read for more than a couple of sentences and many – and

these are A-level students mind you – will protest that they can’t do

it. The most frequent complaint teachers hear is that it’s boring. It is

not so much the content of the written material that is at issue here;

it is the act of reading itself that is deemed to be ‘boring’. What we

are facing here is not just time–honored teenage torpor, but the

mismatch between a post-literate ‘New Flesh’ that is ‘too wired to

concentrate’ and the confining, concentrational logics of decaying

disciplinary systems. To be bored simply means to be removed from the

communicative sensation-stimulus matrix of texting, YouTube and fast

food; to be denied, for a moment, the constant flow of sugary

gratification on demand. Some students want Nietzsche in the same way

that they want a hamburger; they fail to grasp – and the logic of the

consumer system encourages this misapprehension – that the

indigestibility, the difficulty is Nietzsche.

An illustration: I challenged one student about why he always wore

headphones in class. He replied that it didn’t matter, because he wasn’t

actually playing any music. In another lesson, he was playing music at

very low volume through the headphones, without wearing them. When I

asked him to switch it off, he replied that even he couldn’t hear it.

Why wear the headphones without playing music or play music without

wearing the headphones? Because the presence of the phones on the ears

or the knowledge that the music is playing (even if he couldn’t hear it)

was a reassurance that the matrix was still there, within reach.

Besides, in a classic example of interpassivity, if the music was still

playing, even if he couldn’t hear it, then the player could still enjoy

it on his behalf. The use of headphones is significant here – pop is

experienced not as something which could have impacts upon public space,

but as a retreat into private ‘OedIpod’ consumer bliss, a walling up

against the social.

The consequence of being hooked into the entertainment matrix is

twitchy, agitated interpassivity, an inability to concentrate or focus.

Students’ incapacity to connect current lack of focus with future

failure, their inability to synthesize time into any coherent narrative,

is symptomatic of more than mere demotivation. It is, in fact, eerily

reminiscent of Jameson’s analysis in ‘Postmodernism and Consumer

Society’. Jameson observed there that Lacan’s theory of schizophrenia

offered a ‘suggestive aesthetic model’ for understanding the fragmenting

of subjectivity in the face of the emerging entertainment-industrial

complex. ‘With the breakdown of the signifying chain’, Jameson

summarized, ‘the Lacanian schizophrenic is reduced to an experience of

pure material signifiers, or, in other words, a series of pure and

unrelated presents in time’. Jameson was writing in the late 1980s –

i.e. the period in which most of my students were born. What we in the

classroom are now facing is a generation born into that ahistorical,

anti-mnemonic blip culture – a generation, that is to say, for whom time

has always come ready-cut into digital micro-slices.

If the figure of discipline was the worker-prisoner, the figure of

control is the debtor-addict. Cyberspatial capital operates by addicting

its users; William Gibson recognized that in Neuromancer when he had

Case and the other cyberspace cowboys feeling insects-under-the-skin

strung out when they unplugged from the matrix (Case’s amphetamine habit

is plainly the substitute for an addiction to a far more abstract

speed). If, then, something like attention deficit hyperactivity

disorder is a pathology, it is a pathology of late capitalism – a

consequence of being wired into the entertainment-control circuits of

hyperme-diated consumer culture. Similarly, what is called dyslexia may

in many cases amount to a post-lexia. Teenagers process capital’s

image-dense data very effectively without any need to read

–slogan-recognition is sufficient to navigate the net-mobile-magazine

informational plane. ‘Writing has never been capitalism’s thing.

Capitalism is profoundly illiterate’, Deleuze and Guattari argued in

Anti-Oedipus. ‘Electric language does not go by way of the voice or

writing: data processing does without them both’. Hence the reason that

many successful business people are dyslexic (but is their post-lexical

efficiency a cause or effect of their success?)

Teachers are now put under intolerable pressure to mediate between the

post-literate subjectivity of the late capitalist consumer and the

demands of the disciplinary regime (to pass examinations etc). This is

one way in which education, far from being in some ivory tower safely

inured from the ‘real world’, is the engine room of the reproduction of

social reality, directly confronting the inconsistencies of the

capitalist social field. Teachers are caught between being

facilitator-entertainers and disciplinarian-authoritarians. Teachers

want to help students to pass the exams; they want us to be authority

figures who tell them what to do. Teachers being interpellated by

students as authority figures exacerbates the ‘boredom’ problem, since

isn’t anything that comes from the place of authority a priori boring?

Ironically, the role of disciplinarian is demanded of educators more

than ever at precisely the time when disciplinary structures are

breaking down in institutions. With families buckling under the pressure

of a capitalism which requires both parents to work, teachers are now

increasingly required to act as surrogate parents, instilling the most

basic behavioral protocols in students and providing pastoral and

emotional support for teenagers who are in some cases only minimally

socialized.

It is worth stressing that none of the students I taught had any legal

obligation to be at college. They could leave if they wanted to. But the

lack of any meaningful employment opportunities, together with cynical

encouragement from government means that college seems to be the easier,

safer option. Deleuze says that Control societies are based on debt

rather than enclosure; but there is a way in which the current education

system both indebts and encloses students. Pay for your own

exploitation, the logic insists – get into debt so you can get the same

McJob you could have walked into if you’d left school at sixteen…

Jameson observed that ‘the breakdown of temporality suddenly releases

[the] present of time from all the activities and intentionalities that

might focus it and make it a space of praxis’. But nostalgia for the

context in which the old types of praxis operated is plainly useless.

That is why French students don’t in the end constitute an alternative

to British reflexive impotence. That the neoliberal Economist would

deride French opposition to capitalism is hardly surprising, yet its

mockery of French ‘immobilization’ had a point. ‘Certainly the students

who kicked off the latest protests seemed to think they were re-enacting

the events of May 1968 their parents sprang on Charles de Gaulle’, it

wrote in its lead article of March 30, 2006.

They have borrowed its slogans (‘Beneath the cobblestones, the beach!’)

and hijacked its symbols (the Sorbonne university). In this sense, the

revolt appears to be the natural sequel to [2005]’s suburban riots,

which prompted the government to impose a state of emergency. Then it

was the jobless, ethnic underclass that rebelled against a system that

excluded them. Yet the striking feature of the latest protest movement

is that this time the rebellious forces are on the side of conservatism.

Unlike the rioting youths in the banlieues, the objective of the

students and public-sector trade unions is to prevent change, and to

keep France the way it is.

It’s striking how the practice of many of the immobilizers is a kind of

inversion of that of another group who also count themselves heirs of

68: the so called ‘liberal communists’ such as George Soros and Bill

Gates who combine rapacious pursuit of profit with the rhetoric of

ecological concern and social responsibility. Alongside their social

concern, liberal communists believe that work practices should be (post)

modernized, in line with the concept of ‘being smart’. As Žižek

explains,

Being smart means being dynamic and nomadic, and against centralized

bureaucracy; believing in dialogue and cooperation as against central

authority; in flexibility as against routine; culture and knowledge as

against industrial production; in spontaneous interaction and

autopoiesis as against fixed hierarchy.

Taken together, the immobilizers, with their implicit concession that

capitalism can only be resisted, never overcome, and the liberal

communists, who maintain that the amoral excesses of capitalism must be

offset by charity, give a sense of the way in which capitalist realism

circumscribes current political possibilities. Whereas the immobilizers

retain the form of 68-style protest but in the name of resistance to

change, liberal communists energetically embrace newness. ŽiŞek is right

to argue that, far from constituting any kind of progressive corrective

to official capitalist ideology, liberal communism constitutes the

dominant ideology of capitalism now. ‘Flexibility’, ‘nomadism’ and

‘spontaneity’ are the very hallmarks of management in a post-Fordist,

Control society. But the problem is that any opposition to flexibility

and decentralization risks being self-defeating, since calls for

inflexibility and centralization are, to say the least, not likely to be

very galvanizing.

In any case, resistance to the ‘new’ is not a cause that the left can or

should rally around. Capital thought very carefully about how to break

labor; yet there has still not yet been enough thought about what

tactics will work against capital in conditions of post-Fordism, and

what new language can be innovated to deal with those conditions. It is

important to contest capitalism’s appropriation of ‘the new’, but to

reclaim the ‘new’ can’t be a matter of adapting to the conditions in

which we find ourselves –we’ve done that rather too well, and

‘successful adaptation’ is the strategy of managerialism par excellence.

The persistent association of neoliberalism with the term ‘Restoration’,

favored by both Badiou and David Harvey, is an important corrective to

the association of capital with novelty. For Harvey and Badiou,

neoliberal politics are not about the new, but a return of class power

and privilege. ‘[I]n France,’ Badiou has said, ‘‘Restoration’ refers to

the period of the return of the King, in 1815, after the Revolution and

Napoleon. We are in such a period. Today we see liberal capitalism and

its political system, parliamentarianism, as the only natural and

acceptable solutions’. Harvey argues that neoliberalization is best

conceived of as a ‘political project to re-establish the conditions for

capital accumulation and to restore the power of economic elites’.

Harvey demonstrates that, in an era popularly described as

‘post-political’, class war has continued to be fought, but only by one

side: the wealthy. ‘After the implementation of neoliberal policies in

the late 1970s,’ Harvey reveals,

the share of national income of the top 1 per cent of income earners

soared, to reach 15 per cent ... by the end of the century. The top 0.1

per cent of income earners in the US increased their share of the

national income from 2 per cent in 1978 to over 6 per cent by 1999,

while the ratio of the median compensation of workers to the salaries of

CEOs increased from just over 30 to 1 in 1970 to nearly 500 to 1 by

2000.... The US is not alone in this: the top 1 per cent of income

earners in Britain have doubled their share of the national income from

6.5 per cent to 13 per cent since 1982.

As Harvey shows, neoliberals were more Leninist than the Leninists,

using think-tanks as the intellectual vanguard to create the ideological

climate in which capitalist realism could flourish.

The immobilization model – which amounts to a demand to retain the

Fordist/disciplinary regime – could not work in Britain or the other

countries in which neoliberalism has already taken a hold. Fordism has

definitively collapsed in Britain, and with it the sites around which

the old politics were organized. At the end of the control essay,

Deleuze wonders what new forms an anti-control politics might take:

One of the most important questions will concern the ineptitude of the

unions: tied to the whole of their history of struggle against the

disciplines or within the spaces of enclosure, will they be able to

adapt themselves or will they give way to new forms of resistance

against the societies of control? Can we already grasp the rough

outlines of the coming forms, capable of threatening the joys of

marketing? Many young people strangely boast of being “motivated”; they

re-request apprenticeships and permanent training. It’s up to them to

discover what they’re being made to serve, just as their elders

discovered, not without difficulty, the telos of the disciplines.

What must be discovered is a way out of the motivation/demotivation

binary, so that disidentification from the control program registers as

something other than dejected apathy. One strategy would be to shift the

political terrain – to move away from the unions’ traditional focus on

pay and onto forms of discontent specific to post-Fordism. Before we

analyse that further, we must consider in more depth what post-Fordism

actually is.

5

October 6, 1979: ‘Don’t let yourself get attached to anything’

‘A guy told me one time’, says organized crime boss Neil McCauley in

Michael Mann’s 1995 film Heat, ’Don’t let yourself get attached to

anything you are not willing to walk out on in 30 seconds flat if you

feel the heat around the corner’. One of the easiest ways to grasp the

differences between Fordism and post-Fordism is to compare Mann’s film

with the gangster movies made by Francis Ford Coppola and Martin

Scorsese between 1971 and 1990. In Heat, the scores are undertaken not

by Families with links to the Old Country, but by rootless crews, in an

LA of polished chrome and interchangeable designer kitchens, of

featureless freeways and late-night diners. All the local color, the

cuisine aromas, the cultural idiolects which the likes of The Godfather

and Goodfellas depended upon have been painted over and re-fitted.

Heat’s Los Angeles is a world without landmarks, a branded Sprawl, where

markable territory has been replaced by endlessly repeating vistas of

replicating franchises. The ghosts of Old Europe that stalked Scorsese

and Coppola’s streets have been exorcised, buried with the ancient

beefs, bad blood and burning vendettas somewhere beneath the

multinational coffee shops. You can learn a great deal about the world

of Heat from considering the name ‘Neil McCauley’. It is an anonymous

name, a fake passport name, a name that is bereft of history (even as,

ironically, it echoes the name of British historian, Lord McCaulay).

Compare ‘Corleone’, and remember that the Godfather was named after a

village. McCauley is perhaps the part that De Niro played that is

closest to the actor’s own personality: a screen, a cipher, depthless,

icily professional, stripped down to pure preparation, research, Method

(‘I do what I do best’). McCauley is no mafia Boss, no puffed-up chief

perched atop a baroque hierarchy governed by codes as solemn and

mysterious as those of the Catholic Church and written in the blood of a

thousand feuds. His Crew are professionals, hands-on

entrepreneur-speculators, crime-technicians, whose credo is the exact

opposite of Cosa Nostra family loyalty. Family ties are unsustainable in

these conditions, as McCauley tells the Pacino character, the driven

detective, Vincent Hanna. ‘Now, if you’re on me and you gotta move when

I move, how do you expect to keep a marriage?’ Hanna is McCauley’s

shadow, forced to assume his insubstantiality, his perpetual mobility.

Like any group of shareholders, McCauley’s crew is held together by the

prospect of future revenue; any other bonds are optional extras, almost

certainly dangerous. Their arrangement is temporary, pragmatic and

lateral – they know that they are interchangeable machine parts, that

there are no guarantees, that nothing lasts. Compared to this, the

goodfellas seem like sedentary sentimentalists, rooted in dying

communities, doomed territories.

The ethos espoused by McCauley is the one which Richard Sennett examines

in The Corrosion of Character: The Personal Consequences of Work in the

New Capitalism, a landmark study of the affective changes that the

post-Fordist reorganization of work has brought about. The slogan which

sums up the new conditions is ‘no long term’. Where formerly workers

could acquire a single set of skills and expect to progress upwards

through a rigid organizational hierarchy, now they are required to

periodically re-skill as they move from institution to institution, from

role to role. As the organization of work is decentralized, with lateral

networks replacing pyramidal hierarchies, a premium is put on

‘flexibility’. Echoing McCauley’s mockery of Hanna in Heat (‘How do you

expect to keep a marriage?’), Sennett emphasizes the intolerable

stresses that these conditions of permanent instability put on family

life. The values that family life depends upon – obligation,

trustworthiness, commitment – are precisely those which are held to be

obsolete in the new capitalism. Yet, with the public sphere under attack

and the safety nets that a ‘Nanny State’ used to provide being

dismantled, the family becomes an increasingly important place of

respite from the pressures of a world in which instability is a

constant. The situation of the family in post-Fordist capitalism is

contradictory, in precisely the way that traditional Marxism expected:

capitalism requires the family (as an essential means of reproducing and

caring for labor power; as a salve for the psychic wounds inflicted by

anarchic social-economic conditions), even as it undermines it (denying

parents time with children, putting intolerable stress on couples as

they become the exclusive source of affective consolation for each

other).

According to Marxist economist Christian Marazzi, the switch from

Fordism to post-Fordism can be given a very specific date: October 6,

1979. It was on that date that the Federal Reserve increased interest

rates by 20 points, preparing the way for the ‘supply-side economics’

that would constitute the ‘economic reality’ in which we are now

enmeshed. The rise in interest rates not only contained inflation, it

made possible a new organization of the means of production and

distribution. The ‘rigidity’ of the Fordist production line gave way to

a new ‘flexibility’, a word that will send chills of recognition down

the spine of every worker today. This flexibility was defined by a

deregulation of Capital and labor, with the workforce being casualized

(with an increasing number of workers employed on a temporary basis),

and outsourced.

Like Sennett, Marazzi recognizes that the new conditions both required

and emerged from an increased cybernetization of the working

environment. The Fordist factory was crudely divided into blue and white

collar work, with the different types of labor physically delimited by

the structure of the building itself. Laboring in noisy environments,

watched over by managers and supervisors, workers had access to language

only in their breaks, in the toilet, at the end of the working day, or

when they were engaged in sabotage, because communication interrupted

production. But in post-Fordism, when the assembly line becomes a ‘flux

of information’, people work by communicating. As Norbert Wiener taught,

communication and control entail one another.

Work and life become inseparable. Capital follows you when you dream.

Time ceases to be linear, becomes chaotic, broken down into punctiform

divisions. As production and distribution are restructured, so are

nervous systems. To function effectively as a component of just-in-time

production you must develop a capacity to respond to unforeseen events,

you must learn to live in conditions of total instability, or

‘precarity’, as the ugly neologism has it. Periods of work alternate

with periods of unemployment. Typically, you find yourself employed in a

series of short-term jobs, unable to plan for the future.

Both Marazzi and Sennett point out that the disintegration of stable

working patterns was in part driven by the desires of workers – it was

they who, quite rightly, did not wish to work in the same factory for

forty years. In many ways, the left has never recovered from being

wrong-footed by Capital’s mobilization and metabolization of the desire

for emancipation from Fordist routine. Especially in the UK, the

traditional representatives of the working class – union and labor

leaders – found Fordism rather too congenial; its stability of

antagonism gave them a guaranteed role. But this meant that it was easy

for the advocates of post-Fordist Capital to present themselves as the

opponents of the status quo, bravely resisting an inertial organized

labor ‘pointlessly’ invested in fruitless ideological antagonism which

served the ends of union leaders and politicians, but did little to

advance the hopes of the class they purportedly represented. Antagonism

is not now located externally, in the face-off between class blocs, but

internally, in the psychology of the worker, who, as a worker, is

interested in old-style class conflict, but, as someone with a pension

fund, is also interested in maximizing the yield from his or her

investments. There is no longer an identifiable external enemy. The

consequence is, Marazzi argues, that post-Fordist workers are like the

Old Testament Jews after they left the ‘house of slavery’: liberated

from a bondage to which they have no wish to return but also abandoned,

stranded in the desert, confused about the way forward.

The psychological conflict raging within individuals cannot but have

casualties. Marazzi is researching the link between the increase in

bi-polar disorder and post-Fordism and, if, as Deleuze and Guattari

argue, schizophrenia is the condition that marks the outer edges of

capitalism, then bi-polar disorder is the mental illness proper to the

‘interior’ of capitalism. With its ceaseless boom and bust cycles,

capitalism is itself fundamentally and irreducibly bi-polar,

periodically lurching between hyped-up mania (the irrational exuberance

of ‘bubble thinking’) and depressive come-down. (The term ‘economic

depression’ is no accident, of course). To a degree unprecedented in any

other social system, capitalism both feeds on and reproduces the moods

of populations. Without delirium and confidence, capital could not

function.

It seems that with post-Fordism, the ‘invisible plague’ of psychiatric

and affective disorders that has spread, silently and stealthily, since

around 1750 (i.e. the very onset of industrial capitalism) has reached a

new level of acuteness. Here, Oliver James’s work is important. In The

Selfish Capitalist, James points to significant rises in the rates of

‘mental distress’ over the last 25 years. ‘By most criteria’, James

reports,

rates of distress almost doubled between people born in 1946 (aged

thirty-six in 1982) and 1970 (aged thirty in 2000). For example, 16 per

cent of thirty-six-year-old women in 1982 reported having ‘trouble with

nerves, feeling low, depressed or sad’, whereas 29 per cent of thirty

year-olds reported this in 2000 (for men it was 8 per cent in 1982, 13

per cent in 2000).

Another British study James cites compared levels of psychiatric

morbidity (which includes neurotic symptoms, phobias and depression) in

samples of people in 1977 and 1985. ‘Whereas 22 per cent of the 1977

sample reported psychiatric morbidity, this had risen to almost a third

of the population (31 per cent) by 1986’. Since these rates are much

higher in countries that have implemented what James calls ‘selfish’

capitalism than in other capitalist nations, James hypothesizes that it

is selfish (i.e. neoliberalized) capitalist policies and culture that

are to blame. Specifically, James points to the way in which selfish

capitalism stokes up

both aspirations and the expectations that they can be fulfilled. ... In

the entrepreneurial fantasy society, the delusion is fostered that

anyone can be Alan Sugar or Bill Gates, never mind that the actual

likelihood of this occurring has diminished since the 1970s – a person

born in 1958 was more likely than one born in 1970 to achieve upward

mobility through education, for example. The Selfish Capitalist toxins

that are most poisonous to well-being are the systematic encouragement

of the ideas that material affluence is they key to fulfillment, that

only the affluent are winners and that access to the top is open to

anyone willing to work hard enough, regardless of their familial, ethnic

or social background – if you do not succeed, there is only one person

to blame.

James’s conjectures about aspirations, expectations and fantasy fit with

my own observations of what I have called ‘hedonic depression’ in

British youth.

It is telling, in this context of rising rates of mental illness, that

New Labour committed itself, early in its third term in government, to

removing people from Incapacity Benefit, implying that many, if not

most, claimants are malingerers. In contrast with this assumption, it

doesn’t seem unreasonable to infer that most of the people claiming

Incapacity Benefit – and there are well in excess of two million of them

– are casualties of Capital. A significant proportion of claimants, for

instance, are people psychologically damaged as a consequence of the

capitalist realist insistence that industries such as mining are no

longer economically viable. (Even considered in brute economic terms,

though, the arguments about ‘viability’ seem rather less than

convincing, especially once you factor in the cost to taxpayers of

incapacity and other benefits.) Many have simply buckled under the

terrifyingly unstable conditions of post-Fordism.

The current ruling ontology denies any possibility of a social causation

of mental illness. The chemico-biologization of mental illness is of

course strictly commensurate with its de-politicization. Considering

mental illness an individual chemico-biological problem has enormous

benefits for capitalism. First, it reinforces Capital’s drive towards

atomistic individualization (you are sick because of your brain

chemistry). Second, it provides an enormously lucrative market in which

multinational pharmaceutical companies can peddle their pharmaceuticals

(we can cure you with our SSRIs). It goes without saying that all mental

illnesses are neurologically instantiated, but this says nothing about

their causation. If it is true, for instance, that depression is

constituted by low serotonin levels, what still needs to be explained is

why particular individuals have low levels of serotonin. This requires a

social and political explanation; and the task of repoliticizing mental

illness is an urgent one if the left wants to challenge capitalist

realism.

It does not seem fanciful to see parallels between the rising incidence

of mental distress and new patterns of assessing workers’ performance.

We will now take a closer look at this ‘new bureaucracy’.

6

All that is solid melts into PR: Market Stalinism and bureaucratic

anti-production

Mike Judge’s unjustly undercelebrated film Office Space (1999) is as

acute an account of the 90s/00s workplace as Schrader’s Blue Collar

(1978) was of 70s labor relations. Instead of the confrontation between

trade union officials and management in a factory, Judge’s film shows a

corporation sclerotized by administrative ‘anti-production’: workers

receive multiple memos from different managers saying the exact same

thing. Naturally, the memo concerns a bureaucratic practice: it aims to

induce compliance with a new procedure of putting ‘cover sheets’ on

reports. In keeping with the ‘being smart’ ethos, the management style

in Office Space is a mixture of shirtsleeves-informality and quiet

authoritarianism. Judge shows this same managerialism presides in the

corporate coffee chains where the office workers go to relax. Here,

staff are required to decorate their uniforms with ‘seven pieces of

flair’, (i.e. badges or other personal tokens) to express their

‘individuality and creativity’: a handy illustration of the way in which

‘creativity’ and ‘self-expression’ have become intrinsic to labor in

Control societies; which, as Paolo Virno, Yann Moulier Boutang and

others have pointed out, now makes affective, as well as productive

demands, on workers. Furthermore, the attempt to crudely quantify these

affective contributions also tells us a great deal about the new

arrangements. The flair example also points to another phenomenon:

hidden expectations behind official standards. Joanna, a waitress at the

coffee chain, wears exactly seven pieces of flair, but it is made clear

to her that, even though seven is officially enough, it is actually

inadequate – the manager asks if she wants to look the sort of person

‘who only does the bare minimum.’

‘You know what, Stan, if you want me to wear 37 pieces of flair,’ Joanna

complains, ‘why don’t you just make the minimum 37 pieces of flair?’

‘Well,’ the manager replies, ‘I thought I remembered you saying that you

wanted to express yourself.’ Enough is no longer enough. This syndrome

will be familiar to many workers who may find that a ‘satisfactory’

grading in a performance evaluation is no longer satisfactory. In many

educational institutions, for instance, if after a classroom observation

a teacher is graded as ‘satisfactory’, they will be required to

undertake training prior to a reassessment.

Initially, it might appear to be a mystery that bureaucratic measures

should have intensified under neoliberal governments that have presented

themselves as anti-bureaucratic and anti-Stalinist. Yet new kinds of

bureaucracy – ‘aims and objectives’, ‘outcomes’, ‘mission statements’ –

have proliferated, even as neoliberal rhetoric about the end of

top-down, centralized control has gained pre-eminence. It might seem

that bureaucracy is a kind of return of the repressed, ironically

re-emerging at the heart of a system which has professed to destroy it.

But the resurgence of bureaucracy in neoliberalism is more than an

atavism or an anomaly.

As I have already indicated, there is no contradiction between ‘being

smart’ and the increase of administration and regulation: they are two

sides of labor in Control societies. Richard Sennett has argued that the

flattening of pyramidal hierarchies has actually led to more

surveillance of workers. ‘One of the claims made for the new

organization of work is that it decentralizes power, that is, gives

people in the lower ranks of organization more control over their own

activities’, Sennett writes. ‘Certainly this claim is false in terms of

the techniques employed for taking apart the old bureaucratic behemoths.

The new information systems provide a comprehensive picture of the

organization to top managers in ways which give individuals anywhere in

the network little room to hide’. But it isn’t only that information

technology has granted managers more access to data; it is that the data

itself has proliferated. Much of this ‘information’ is provided by

workers themselves. Massimo De Angelis and David Harvie describe some of

the bureaucratic measures with which a lecturer must comply when putting

together a module for an undergraduate degree in British universities.

‘For each module’, De Angelis and Harvie write,

the ‘module leader’ (ML, i.e., lecturer) must complete various

paperwork, in particular a ‘module specification’ (at the module’s

start) which lists the module’s ‘aims and objectives’, ILOs, ‘modes and

methods of assessment’, amongst other information; and a ‘module review’

document (at the end of the module), in which the ML reports their own

assessment of the module’s strengths and weaknesses and their suggested

changes for the following year; a summary of student feedback; and

average marks and their dispersion.

This is only the beginning, however. For the degree program as a whole,

academics must prepare a ‘program specification’, as well as producing

‘annual program reports’, which record student performance according to

‘progression rates’, ‘withdrawal rates’, location and spread of marks.

All students’ marks have to be graded against a ‘matrix’. This

auto-surveillance is complemented by assessments carried out by external

authorities. The marking of student assignments is monitored by

‘external examiners’ who are supposed to maintain consistency of

standards across the university sector. Lecturers have to be observed by

their peers, while departments are subject to periodic three or four day

inspections by the Quality Assurance Agency for Higher Education (QAA).

If they are ‘research active’, lecturers must submit their ‘best four

publications’ every four or five years to be graded by panel as part of

the Research Assessment Exercise (replaced in 2008 by the equally

controversial Research Excellence Framework). De Angelis and Harvie are

clear that these are only very sketchy accounts of only some of the

bureaucratic tasks that academics have to perform, all of which have

funding implications for institutions. This battery of bureaucratic

procedures is by no means confined to universities, nor to education:

other public services, such as the National Health Service and the

police force, find themselves enmeshed in similar bureaucratic

metastases.

This is in part a consequence of the inherent resistance of certain

processes and services to marketization. (The supposed marketization of

education, for instance, rests on a confused and underdeveloped analogy:

are students the consumers of the service or its product?) The idealized

market was supposed to deliver ‘friction free’ exchanges, in which the

desires of consumers would be met directly, without the need for

intervention or mediation by regulatory agencies. Yet the drive to

assess the performance of workers and to measure forms of labor which,

by their nature, are resistant to quantification, has inevitably

required additional layers of management and bureaucracy. What we have

is not a direct comparison of workers’ performance or output, but a

comparison between the audited representation of that performance and

output. Inevitably, a short-circuiting occurs, and work becomes geared

towards the generation and massaging of representations rather than to

the official goals of the work itself. Indeed, an anthropological study

of local government in Britain argues that ‘More effort goes into

ensuring that a local authority’s services are represented correctly

than goes into actually improving those services’. This reversal of

priorities is one of the hallmarks of a system which can be

characterized without hyperbole as ‘market Stalinism’. What late

capitalism repeats from Stalinism is just this valuing of symbols of

achievement over actual achievement. As Marshall Berman explained,

describing Stalin’s White Sea Canal project of 1931-33:

Stalin seems to have been so intent on creating a highly visible symbol

of development that he pushed and squeezed the project in ways that only

retarded the development of the project. Thus the workers and the

engineers were never allowed the time, money or equipment necessary to

build a canal that would be deep enough and safe enough to carry

twentieth-century cargoes; consequently, the canal has never played any

significant role in Soviet commerce or industry. All the canal could

support, apparently, were tourist steamers, which in the 1930s were

abundantly stocked with Soviet and foreign writers who obligingly

proclaimed the glories of the work. The canal was a triumph of

publicity; but if half the care that went into the public relations

campaign had been devoted to the work itself, there would have been far

fewer victims and far more real developments – and the project would

have been a genuine tragedy, rather than a brutal farce in which real

people were killed by pseudo-events.

In a strange compulsion to repeat, the ostensibly anti-Stalinist

neoliberal New Labour government has shown the same tendency to

implement initiatives in which real world effects matter only insofar as

they register at the level of (PR) appearance. The notorious ‘targets’

which the New Labour government was so enthusiastic in imposing are a

case in point. In a process that repeats itself with iron predictability

everywhere that they are installed, targets quickly cease to be a way of

measuring performance and become ends in themselves. Anxiety about

falling standards in school examinations is now a regular feature of the

summertime in Britain. Yet if students are less skilled and

knowledgeable than their predecessors, this is due not to a decline in

the quality of examinations per se, but to the fact that all of the

teaching is geared towards passing the exams. Narrowly focused ‘exam

drill’ replaces a wider engagement with subjects. Similarly, hospitals

perform many routine procedures instead of a few serious, urgent

operations, because this allows them to hit the targets they are

assessed on (operating rates, success rates and reduction in waiting

time) more effectively.

It would be a mistake to regard this market Stalinism as some deviation

from the ‘true spirit’ of capitalism. On the contrary, it would be

better to say that an essential dimension of Stalinism was inhibited by

its association with a social project like socialism and can only emerge

in a late capitalist culture in which images acquire an autonomous

force. The way value is generated on the stock exchange depends of

course less on what a company ‘really does’, and more on perceptions of,

and beliefs about, its (future) performance. In capitalism, that is to

say, all that is solid melts into PR, and late capitalism is defined at

least as much by this ubiquitous tendency towards PR-production as it is

by the imposition of market mechanisms.

Here, Žižek’s elaboration of Lacan’s concept of the ‘big Other’ is

crucial. The big Other is the collective fiction, the symbolic

structure, presupposed by any social field. The big Other can never be

encountered in itself; instead, we only ever confront its stand-ins.

These representatives are by no means always leaders. In the example of

the White Sea Canal above, for instance, it wasn’t Stalin himself who

was the representative of the big Other so much as the Soviet and

foreign writers who had to be persuaded of the glories of the project.

One important dimension of the big Other is that it does not know

everything. It is this constitutive ignorance of the big Other that

allows public relations to function. Indeed, the big Other could be

defined as the consumer of PR and propaganda, the virtual figure which

is required to believe even when no individual can. To use one of

Žižek’s examples: who was it, for instance, who didn’t know that Really

Existing Socialism (RES) was shabby and corrupt? Not any of the people,

who were all too aware of its shortcomings; nor any of the government

administrators, who couldn’t but know. No, it was the big Other who was

the one deemed not to know – who wasn’t allowed to know – the quotidian

reality of RES. Yet the distinction between what the big Other knows,

i.e. what is officially accepted, and what is widely known and

experienced by actual individuals, is very far from being ‘merely’

emptily formal; it is the discrepancy between the two that allows

‘ordinary’ social reality to function. When the illusion that the big

Other did not know can no longer be maintained, the incorporeal fabric

holding the social system together disintegrates. This is why

Khrushchev’s speech in 1965, in which he ‘admitted’ the failings of the

Soviet state, was so momentous. It is not as if anyone in the party was

unaware of the atrocities and corruption carried out in its name, but

Khrushchev’s announcement made it impossible to believe any more that

the big Other was ignorant of them.

So much for Really Existing Socialism – but what of Really Existing

Capitalism? One way to understand the ‘realism’ of capitalist realism is

in terms of the claim to have given up belief in the big Other.

Postmodernism can be construed as the name for the complex of crises

that the decline in the belief in the big Other has triggered, as

Lyotard’s famous formulation of the postmodern condition – ‘incredulity

towards metanarratives’ –suggests. Jameson, of course, would argue that

the ‘incredulity towards metanarratives’ is one expression of the

‘cultural logic of late capitalism’, a consequence of the switch into

the post-Fordist mode of capital accumulation. Nick Land gives one of

the most euphoric accounts of the ‘postmodern meltdown of culture into

the economy’. In Land’s work, a cybernetically upgraded invisible hand

is progressively eliminating centralized state power. Land’s 90s texts

synthesized cybernetics, complexity theory, cyberpunk fiction and

neoliberalism to construct a vision of capital planetary artificial

intelligence: a vast, supple, endlessly fissile system which renders

human will obsolete. In his manifesto for nonlinear, decentered Capital,

‘Meltdown’, Land invokes a ‘massively distributed matrix-networked

tendency oriented to disabling ROM command-control programs sustaining

all macro- and micro-governmental entities, globally concentrating

themselves as the Human Security System’. This is capitalism as a

shattering Real, in which (viral, digital) signals circulate on

self-sustaining networks which bypass the Symbolic, and therefore do not

require the big Other as guarantor. It is Deleuze and Guattari’s Capital

as ‘Unnamable Thing’, but without the forces of reterritorialization and

anti-production which they argued were constitutive of capitalism. One

of the problems of Land’s position is also what is most interesting

about it: precisely that it posits a ‘pure’ capitalism, a capitalism

which is only inhibited and blocked by extrinsic, rather than internal,

elements (according to Land’s logic, these elements are atavisms that

will eventually be consumed and metabolized by Capital). Yet capitalism

cannot be ‘purified’ in this way; strip away the forces of

anti-production and capitalism disappears with them. Similarly, there is

no progressive tendency towards an ‘unsheathing’ of capitalism, no

gradual unmasking of Capital as it ‘really’ is: rapacious, indifferent,

inhuman. On the contrary, the essential role of the ‘incorporeal

transformations’ effectuated by PR, branding and advertising in

capitalism suggests that, in order to operate effectively, capitalism’s

rapacity depends upon various forms of sheathing. Really Existing

Capitalism is marked by the same division which characterized Really

Existing Socialism, between, on the one hand, an official culture in

which capitalist enterprises are presented as socially responsible and

caring, and, on the other, a widespread awareness that companies are

actually corrupt, ruthless, etc. In other words, capitalist

postmodernity is not quite as incredulous as it would appear to be, as

the jeweler Gerald Ratner famously found to his cost. Ratner precisely

tried to circumvent the Symbolic and ‘tell it how it is’, describing the

inexpensive jewelry his shops sold as ‘crap’ in an after-dinner speech.

But the consequence of Ratner making this judgment official were

immediate, and serious - ÂŁ500m was wiped off the value of the company

and he lost his job. Customers might previously have known that the

jewelry Ratners sold was poor quality, but the big Other didn’t know; as

soon as it did, Ratners collapsed.

Vernacular postmodernism has dealt with the ‘crisis of symbolic

efficiency’ in a far less intense way than Nick Land, through

metafictional anxieties about the function of the author, and in

television programs or films which expose the mechanisms of their own

productions and reflexively incorporate discussions of their own status

as commodities. But postmod-ernism’s supposed gestures of

demystification do not evince sophistication so much as a certain

naivety, a conviction that there were others, in the past, who really

believed in the Symbolic. In fact, of course, ‘symbolic efficiency’ was

achieved precisely by maintaining a clear distinction between a

material-empirical causality, and another, incorporeal causality proper

to the Symbolic. Žižek gives the example of a judge: ‘I know very well

that things are the way I see them, that this person is a corrupted

weakling, but I nonetheless treat him respectfully, since he wears the

insignia of a judge, so that when he speaks, it is the Law itself which

speaks through him’. However, postmodernism’s

cynical reduction to reality ... falls short: when a judge speaks, there

is in a way more truth in his words (the words of the Institution of

law) than in the direct reality of the person of judge if one limits

oneself to what one sees, one simply misses the point. Lacan aims at

this paradox with his ‘les non-dupes errent’: those who do not allow

themselves to be caught in the symbolic deception/fiction, who continue

to believe their eyes, are the ones who err most. A cynic who ‘believes

only his eyes’ misses the efficiency of the symbolic fiction, and how it

structures our experience of reality.

Much of Baudrillard’s work was a commentary on this same effect: the way

in which the abolition of the Symbolic led not to a direct encounter

with the Real, but to a kind of hemorrhaging of the Real. For

Baudrillard, phenomena such as fly on the wall documentaries and

political opinion polls – both of which claimed to present reality in an

unmediated way – would always pose an insoluble dilemma. Did the

presence of the cameras affect the behavior of those being filmed? Would

the publication of poll results affect the future behavior of voters?

Such questions were undecidable, and therefore ‘reality’ would always be

elusive: at the very moment when it seemed that it was being grasped in

the raw, reality transformed into what Baudrillard, in a much

misunderstood neologism, called ‘hyperreality’. Uncannily echoing

Baudrillard’s fixations, the most successful reality television programs

ended up fusing fly on the wall documentary elements with interactive

polling. In effect, there are two levels of ‘reality’ in these shows:

the unscripted behavior of the ‘real life’ participants onscreen, and

the unpredictable responses of the audience at home, which in turn

affect the behavior of the onscreen participants. Yet reality TV is

continually haunted by questions about fiction and illusion: are the

participants acting, suppressing certain aspects of their personality in

order to appear more appealing to us, the audience? And have the

audience’s votes been accurately registered, or is there some kind of a

fix? The slogan that the Big Brother TV show uses – ‘You decide’ –

captures perfectly the mode of control by feedback that, according to

Baudrillard, has replaced old centralized forms of power. We ourselves

occupy the empty seat of power, phoning and clicking in our responses.

TV’s Big Brother had superseded Orwell’s Big Brother. We the audience

are not subjected to a power that comes from outside; rather, we are

integrated into a control circuit that has our desires and preferences

as its only mandate – but those desires and preferences are returned to

us, no longer as ours, but as the desires of the big Other. Clearly,

these circuits are not confined to television: cybernetic feedback

systems (focus groups, demographic surveys) are now integral to the

delivery of all ‘services’, including education and government.

This returns us to the issue of post-Fordist bureaucracy. There is of

course a close relationship between bureaucracy – the discourse of

officialdom – and the big Other. Witness two of Žižek’s own examples of

the big Other at work: a low-level official who, having not been

informed of a promotion, says ‘Sorry, I have not yet been properly

informed about this new measure, so I can’t help you...’; a woman who

believed that she was suffering bad luck because of the number of her

house, who could not be satisfied by simply repainting a different

number herself , because ‘it has to be done properly, by the responsible

state institution...’ We are all familiar with bureaucratic libido, with

the enjoyment that certain officials derive from this position of

disavowed responsibility (‘it’s not me, I’m afraid, it’s the

regulations’). The frustration of dealing with bureaucrats often arises

because they themselves can make no decisions; rather, they are

permitted only to refer to decisions that have always-already been made

(by the big Other). Kafka was the greatest writer on bureaucracy because

he saw that this structure of disavowal was inherent to bureaucracy. The

quest to reach the ultimate authority who will finally resolve K’s

official status can never end, because the big Other cannot be

encountered in itself: there are only officials, more or less hostile,

engaged in acts of interpretation about what the big Other’s intentions.

And these acts of interpretation, these deferrals of responsibility, are

all that the big Other is.

If Kafka is valuable as a commentator on totalitarianism, it is by

revealing that there was a dimension of totalitarianism which cannot be

understood on the model of despotic command. Kafka’s purgatorial vision

of a bureaucratic labyrinth without end chimes with Žižek’s claim that

the Soviet system was an ‘empire of signs’, in which even the

Nomenklatura themselves –including Stalin and Molotov – were engaged in

interpreting a complex series of social semiotic signals. No-one knew

what was required; instead, individuals could only guess what particular

gestures or directives meant. What happens in late capitalism, when

there is no possibility of appealing, even in principle, to a final

authority which can offer the definitive official version, is a massive

intensification of that ambiguity. As an example of this syndrome, let

us turn once more to Further Education. At a meeting between Trade Union

officials, college Principals and Members of Parliament, the Learning

and Skills Council (LSC), the quango at the heart of the FE funding

labyrinth, came in for particular attack. Neither the teachers, nor the

Principals, nor the MPs could determine how particular directives had

generated themselves, since they are not there in government policy

itself. The answer was that the LSC ‘interpreted’ the instructions

issued by the Department for Education and Skills. These interpretations

then achieve the strange autonomy peculiar to bureaucracy. On the one

hand, bureaucratic procedures float freely, independent of any external

authority; but that very autonomy means that they assume a heavy

implacability, a resistance to any amendment or questioning.

The proliferation of auditing culture in post Fordism indicates that the

demise of the big Other has been exaggerated. Auditing can perhaps best

be conceived of as fusion of PR and bureaucracy, because the

bureaucratic data is usually intended to fulfill a promotional role: in

the case of education, for example, exam results or research ratings

augment (or diminish) the prestige of particular institutions. The

frustration for the teacher is that it seems as if their work is

increasingly aimed at impressing the big Other which is collating and

consuming this ‘data’. ‘Data’ has been put in inverted commas here,

because much of the so-called information has little meaning or

application outside the parameters of the audit: as Eeva Berglund puts

it, ‘the information that audit creates does have consequences even

though it is so shorn of local detail, so abstract, as to be misleading

or meaningless - except, that is, by the aesthetic criteria of audit

itself.

New bureaucracy takes the form not of a specific, delimited function

performed by particular workers but invades all areas of work, with the

result that – as Kafka prophesied – workers become their own auditors,

forced to assess their own performance. Take, for example, the ‘new

system’ that OFSTED (Office for Standards in Education) uses to inspect

Further Education colleges. Under the old system, a college would have a

‘heavy’ inspection once every four years or so, i.e. one involving many

lesson observations and a large number of inspectors present in the

college. Under the new, ‘improved’ system, if a college can demonstrate

that its internal assessment systems are effective, it will only have to

undergo a ‘light’ inspection. But the downside of this ‘light’

inspection is obvious – surveillance and monitoring are outsourced from

OFSTED to the college and ultimately to lecturers themselves, and become

a permanent feature of the college structure (and of the psychology of

individual lecturers). The difference between the old/heavy and

new/light inspection system corresponds precisely to Kafka’s distinction

between ostensible acquittal and indefinite postponement, outlined

above. With ostensible acquittal, you petition the lower court judges

until they grant you a non-binding reprieve. You are then free from the

court, until the time when your case is re-opened. Indefinite

postponement, meanwhile, keeps your case at the lowest level of the

court, but at the cost of an anxiety that has never ends. (The changes

in OFSTED inspections are mirrored by in the change from the Research

Assessment Exercise to the Research Excellence Framework in higher

education: periodic assessment will be superseded by a permanent and

ubiquitous measurement which cannot help but generate the same perpetual

anxiety.)

In any case, it is not as if the ‘light’ inspection is in any sense

preferable for staff than the heavy one. The inspectors are in the

college for the same amount of time as they were under the old system.

The fact that there are fewer of them does nothing to alleviate the

stress of the inspection, which has far more to do with the extra

bureaucratic window-dressing one has to do in anticipation of a possible

observation than it has to do with any actual observation itself. The

inspection, that is to say, corresponds precisely to Foucault’s account

of the virtual nature of surveillance in Discipline And Punish. Foucault

famously observes there that there is no need for the place of

surveillance to actually be occupied. The effect of not knowing whether

you will be observed or not produces an introjection of the surveillance

apparatus. You constantly act as if you are always about to be observed.

Yet, in the case of school and university inspections, what you will be

graded on is not primarily your abilities as a teacher so much as your

diligence as a bureaucrat. There are other bizarre effects. Since OFSTED

is now observing the college’s self-assessment systems, there is an

implicit incentive for the college to grade itself and its teaching

lower than it actually deserves. The result is a kind of postmodern

capitalist version of Maoist confessionalism, in which workers are

required to engage in constant symbolic self-denigration. At one point,

when our line manager was extolling the virtues of the new, light

inspection system, he told us that the problem with our departmental

log-books was that they were not sufficiently self-critical. But don’t

worry, he urged, any self-criticisms we make are purely symbolic, and

will never be acted upon; as if performing self-flagellation as part of

a purely formal exercise in cynical bureaucratic compliance were any

less demoralizing.

In the post-Fordist classroom, the reflexive impotence of the students

is mirrored by reflexive impotence of the teachers. De Angelis and

Harvie report that

practices and requirements of standardisation and surveillance obviously

impose a huge burden of work on academics and few are happy about it.

There have been a number of responses. Managers have frequently

suggested there is no alternative (TINA) and have perhaps suggested that

what we need to do is ‘work smarter, not harder’. This seductive slogan,

introduced to dampen staff resistance to further change which in their

(our) experience has a devastating effects on working conditions,

attempts to couple the need for ‘change’ (restructuring and innovation)

in order to meet the budget pressure and increase ‘competitiveness’,

with staff’s resistance not only to worsening of their condition of

work, but also to the educational and academic ‘meaninglessness’ of the

‘changes’.

The invocation of the idea that ‘there is no alternative’, and the

recommendation to ‘work smarter, not harder’, shows how capitalist

realism sets the tone for labor disputes in post-Fordism. Ending the

inspection regime, one lecturer sardonically remarked, seems more

impossible than ending slavery was. Such fatalism can only be challenged

if a new (collective) political subject emerges.

7

‘...if you can watch the overlap of one reality with another’:

capitalist realism as dreamwork and memory disorder

‘Being realistic’ may once have meant coming to terms with of a reality

experienced as solid and immovable. Capitalist realism, however, entails

subordinating oneself to a reality that is infinitely plastic, capable

of reconfiguring itself at any moment. We are confronted with what

Jameson, in his essay ‘The Antimonies Of The Postmodern’, calls ‘a

purely fungible present in which space and psyches alike can be

processed and remade at will’. The ‘reality’ here is akin to the

multiplicity of options available on a digital document, where no

decision is final, revisions are always possible, and any previous

moment can be recalled at any time. The middle manager I referred to

above turned adaptation to this ‘fungible’ reality it into a fine art.

He asserted with full confidence a story about the college and its

future one day – what the implications of the inspection were likely to

be; what senior management was thinking; then literally the next day

would happily propound a story that directly contradicted what he

previously said. There was never a question of his repudiating the

previous story; it was as if he, only dimly remembered there ever being

another story. This, I suppose, is ‘good management’. It is, also,

perhaps the only way to stay healthy amidst capitalism’s perpetual

instability. On the face of it, this manager is a model of beaming

mental health, his whole being radiating a hail-fellow-well-met

bonhomie. Such cheerfulness can only be maintained if one has a

near-total absence of any critical reflexivity and a capacity, as he

had, to cynically comply with every directive from bureaucratic

authority. The cynicism of the compliance is essential, of course; the

preservation of his 60s liberal self-image depended upon his ‘not really

believing’ in the auditing processes he so assiduously enforced. What

this disavowal depends upon is the distinction between inner subjective

attitude and outward behavior I discussed above: in terms of his inner

subjective attitude, the manager is hostile, even contemptuous, towards,

the bureaucratic procedures he supervises; but in terms of his outward

behavior, he is perfectly compliant. Yet it is precisely workers’

subjective disinvestment from auditing tasks which enables them to

continue to perform labor that is pointless and demoralizing.

The manager’s capacity to smoothly migrate from one reality to another

reminded me of nothing so much as Ursula Le Guin’s The Lathe of Heaven.

It is a novel about George Orr, a man whose dreams literally come true.

In time-honored fairy tale fashion, however, the acts of wish

fulfillment quickly become traumatic and catastrophic. When, for

instance, Orr is induced by his therapist, Dr Haber, into dreaming that

the problem of overpopulation is solved, he wakes to find himself in a

world in which billions have been wiped out by a plague; a plague that,

as Jameson put it in his discussion of the novel, was ‘a hitherto

nonexistent event which rapidly finds its place in our chronological

memory of the recent past’. Much of the power of the novel consists in

its rendering of these retrospective confabulations, whose mechanics are

at once so familiar – because we perform them every night when we dream

– and so odd. How could it ever be possible for us to believe successive

or even co-extensive stories that so obviously contradict one another?

Yet we know from Kant, Nietzsche and psychoanalysis that waking, as much

as dreaming, experience, depends upon just such screening narratives. If

the Real is unbearable, any reality we construct must be a tissue of

inconsistencies. What differentiates Kant, Nietzsche and Freud from the

tiresome cliché that ‘life is but a dream’ is the sense that the

confabulations we live are consensual. The idea that the world we

experience is a solipsistic delusion projected from the interior of our

mind consoles rather than disturbs us, since it conforms with our

infantile fantasies of omnipotence; but the thought that our so-called

interiority owe its existence to a fictionalized consensus will always

carry an uncanny charge. This extra level of uncanniness is registered

in The Lathe of Heaven when Le Guin has Orr’s reality-warping dreams

witnessed by others – the therapist, Haber, who seeks to manipulate and

control Orr’s ability, and the lawyer, Heather Lelache. What, then, is

it like to live through someone else’s dream coming true?

[Haber] could not go on talking. He felt it: the shift, the arrival, the

change.

The woman felt it too. She looked frightened. Holding the brass necklace

up close to her throat like a talisman, she was staring in dismay,

shock, terror, out of the window at the view.

[...] What would it do to the woman? Would she understand, would she go

mad, what would she do? Would she keep both memories, as he did, the

true one and the new one, the old one and the true one?

Does she ‘go crazy’? No, not at all: after a few moments of bewildered

fugue, Heather Lelache accepts the ‘new’ world as the ‘true’ world,

editing out the point of suture. This strategy – of accepting the

incommensurable and the senseless without question – has always been the

exemplary technique of sanity as such, but it has a special role to play

in late capitalism, that ‘motley painting of everything that ever was’,

whose dreaming up and junking of social fictions is nearly as rapid as

its production and disposal of commodities.

In these conditions of ontological precarity, forgetting becomes an

adaptive strategy. Take the example of Gordon Brown, whose expedient

reinvention of his political identity involved an attempt to induce a

collective forgetting. In an article in International Socialism, John

Newsinger remembers how

Brown told the Confederation of British Industry conference that

‘business is in my blood’. His mother had been a company director and ‘I

was brought up in an atmosphere where I knew exactly what was happening

as far as business was concerned’. He was, indeed he had always been,

one of them. The only problem is that it was not true. As his mother

subsequently admitted, she would never have called herself ‘a business

woman’: she had only ever done some ‘light administrative duties’ for ‘a

small family firm’ and had given up the job when she married, three

years before young Gordon was even born. While there have been Labor

politicians who have tried to invent working class backgrounds for

themselves before, Brown is the first to try and invent a capitalist

background.

Newsinger contrasts Brown with his rival and predecessor as British

prime minister, Tony Blair, a very different case. While Blair – who

presented the strange spectacle of a postmodern messianism – never had

any beliefs that he had to recant on, Brown’s move from Presbyterian

socialist to New Labour supremo was a long, arduous and painful process

of repudiation and denial. ‘Whereas, for Blair, the embrace of

neoliberalism involved no great personal struggle because he had no

previous beliefs to dispose of, Newsinger writes, ‘for Brown it involved

a deliberate decision to change sides. The effort, one suspects, damaged

his personality’. Blair was the Last Man by nature and inclination;

Brown has become the Last Man, the dwarf at the End of History, by force

of will.

Blair was the man without a chest, the outsider the party needed in

order to get into power, his joker hysterical face salesman-smooth;

Brown’s implausible act of self-reinvention is what the party itself had

to go through, his fake-smile grimace the objective correlative of

Labour’s real state now that it has completely capitulated to capitalist

realism: gutted, and gutless, its insides replaced by simulacra which

once looked lustrous but now possess all the allure of decade-old

computer technology.

In conditions where realities and identities are upgraded like software,

it is not surprising that memory disorders should have become the focus

of cultural anxiety – see, for instance, the Bourne films, Memento,

Eternal Sunshine Of the Spotless Mind. In the Bourne films, Jason

Bourne’s quest to regain his identity goes alongside a continual flight

from any settled sense of self. ‘Try to understand me... ,’ says Bourne

in the original novel by Robert Ludlum,

I have to know certain things ... enough to make a decision... but maybe

not everything. A part of me has to be able to walk away, disappear. I

have to be able to say to myself, what was isn’t any longer, and there’s

a possibility that it never was because I have no memory of it. What a

person can’t remember didn’t exist.... for him.

In the films, Bourne’s transnational nomadism is rendered in an

ultra-fast cutting style which functions as a kind of anti-memory,

pitching the viewer into the vertiginous ‘continuous present’ which

Jameson argues is characteristic of postmodern temporality. The complex

plotting of Ludlum’s novels is transformed into a series of evanescent

event-ciphers and action set pieces which barely cohere into an

intelligible narrative. Bereft of personal history, Bourne lacks

narrative memory, but retains what we might call formal memory: a memory

– of techniques, practices, actions – that is literally embodied in a

series of physical reflexes and tics. Here, Bourne’s damaged memory

echoes the postmodern nostalgia mode as described by Fredric Jameson, in

which contemporary or even futuristic reference at the level of content

obscure a reliance on established or antiquated models at the level of

form. On the one hand, this is a culture that privileges only the

present and the immediate – the extirpation of the long term extends

backwards as well as forwards in time (for example, media stories

monopolize attention for a week or so then are instantly forgotten); on

the other hand, it is a culture that is excessively nostalgic, given

over to retrospection, incapable of generating any authentic novelty. It

may be that Jameson’s identification and analysis of this temporal

antimony is his most important contribution to our understanding of

postmodern/post-Fordist culture. ‘[T]he paradox from which we must set

forth,’ he argues in ‘Antimonies Of The Postmodern’,

is the equivalence between an unparalleled rate of change on all the

levels of social life and an unparalleled standardization of everything

– feelings along with consumer goods, language along with built space –

that would seem incompatible with such mutability... What then dawns is

the realization that no society has ever been as standardized as this

one, and that the stream of human, social and historical temporality has

never flowed quite so homogenously. ... What we now begin to feel,

therefore – and what begins to emerge as some deeper and more

fundamental constitution of postmodernity itself, at least in its

temporal dimension – is henceforth, where everything now submits to the

perpetual change of fashion and media image, that nothing can change any

longer.

No doubt this is another example of the struggle between the forces of

deterritorialization and reterritorialization which Deleuze and Guattari

argue is constitutive of capitalism as such. It wouldn’t be surprising

if profound social and economic instability resulted in a craving for

familiar cultural forms, to which we return in the same way that Bourne

reverts to his core reflexes. The memory disorder that is the

correlative of this situation is the condition which afflicts Leonard in

Memento, theoretically pure anterograde amnesia. Here, memories prior to

the onset of the condition are left intact, but sufferers are unable to

transfer new memories into long term memory; the new therefore looms up

as hostile, fleeting, un-navigable, and the sufferer is drawn back to

the security of the old. The inability to make new memories: a succinct

formulation of the postmodern impasse....

If memory disorder provides a compelling analogy for the glitches in

capitalist realism, the model for its smooth functioning would be

dreamwork. When we are dreaming, we forget, but immediately forget that

we have done so; since the gaps and lacunae in our memories are

Photoshopped out, they do not trouble or torment us. What dreamwork does

is to produce a confabulated consistency which covers over anomalies and

contradictions, and it is this which Wendy Brown picked up on when she

argued that it was precisely dreamwork which provided the best model for

understanding contemporary forms of power. In her essay ‘American

Nightmare: Neoconservatism, Neoliberalism, and De-democratization’,

Brown unpicked the alliance between neoconservatism and neoliberalism

which constituted the American version of capitalist realism up until

2008. Brown shows that neoliberalism and neoconservatism operated from

premises which are not only inconsistent, but directly contradictory.

‘How’, Brown asks,

does a rationality that is expressly amoral at the level of both ends

and means (neoliberalism) intersect with one that is expressly moral and

regulatory (neoconservatism)? How does a project that empties the world

of meaning, that cheapens and deracinates life and openly exploits

desire, intersect one centered on fixing and enforcing meanings,

conserving certain ways of life, and repressing and regulating desire?

How does support for governance modeled on the firm and a normative

social fabric of self-interest marry or jostle against support for

governance modeled on church authority and a normative social fabric of

self-sacrifice and long-term filial loyalty, the very fabric shredded by

unbridled capitalism?

But incoherence at the level of what Brown calls ‘political rationality’

does nothing to prevent symbiosis at the level of political

subjectivity, and, although they proceeded from very different guiding

assumptions, Brown argues that neoliberalism and neoconservatism worked

together to undermine the public sphere and democracy, producing a

governed citizen who looks to find solutions in products, not political

processes. As Brown claims,

the choosing subject and the governed subject are far from opposites ...

Frankfurt school intellectuals and, before them, Plato theorized the

open compatibility between individual choice and political domination,

and depicted democratic subjects who are available to political tyranny

or authoritarianism precisely because they are absorbed in a province of

choice and need-satisfaction that they mistake for freedom.

Extrapolating a little from Brown’s arguments, we might hypothesize that

what held the bizarre synthesis of neoconservatism and neoliberalism

together was their shared objects of abomination: the so called Nanny

State and its dependents. Despite evincing an anti-statist rhetoric,

neoliberalism is in practice not opposed to the state per se – as the

bank bail-outs of 2008 demonstrated – but rather to particular uses of

state funds; meanwhile, neoconservatism’s strong state was confined to

military and police functions, and defined itself against a welfare

state held to undermine individual moral responsibility.

8

‘There’s no central exchange’

Although excoriated by both neoliberalism and neoconserva-tivism, the

concept of the Nanny State continues to haunt capitalist realism. The

specter of big government plays an essential libidinal function for

capitalist realism. It is there to be blamed precisely for its failure

to act as a centralizing power, the anger directed at it much like the

fury Thomas Hardy supposedly spat at God for not existing. ‘Time and

again’, James Meek observed in an LRB piece on water privatization in

Britain, ‘Conservative and Labor governments have discovered that when

they give powers to private companies, and those private companies screw

up, voters blame the government for giving the powers away, rather than

the companies for misusing them’. Meek was visiting Tewkesbury, one of

the British towns that was the victim of serious flooding in 2007, a

year after the disaster. On the face of it, the flooding and the

consequent failure of services was the fault of privatized water

companies and house builders, yet Meek found that this was not the way

that most of the local residents saw it. ‘In Tewkesbury’, Meeks wrote,

in general there is more hostility towards the government, the council

and the Environment Agency for not stopping house builders than there is

towards house builders for building houses, or buyers for buying them.

When insurers raise their premiums, more blame is directed at the

government for not spending enough on flood defences than at insurers

for raising the premiums, or at people who choose to live in a

flood-prone valley but don’t like paying extra for it.

This syndrome was repeated on a much grander scale with a disaster of a

different kind –the bank crisis of 2008. The media focus was on the

excesses of individual bankers and on the government’s handling of the

crisis, not on the systemic causes of the crisis. I don’t for a moment

want to excuse New Labour for its part in such disasters, but it has to

be recognized that focus on government, like the focus on immoral

individuals, is an act of deflection. Scapegoating an impotent

government (running around to clean up the messes made by its business

friends) arises from bad faith, from a continuing hostility to the Nanny

State that nevertheless goes alongside a refusal to accept the

consequences of the sidelining of government in global capitalism – a

sign, perhaps, that, at the level of the political unconscious, it is

impossible to accept that there are no overall controllers, that the

closest thing we have to ruling powers now are nebulous, unaccountable

interests exercising corporate irresponsibility. A case of fetishist

disavowal, perhaps – ‘we know perfectly well that the government is not

pulling the strings, but nevertheless...’ The disavowal happens in part

because the centerlessness of global capitalism is radically

unthinkable. Although people are interpellated now as consumers – and,

as Wendy Brown and others have pointed out, government itself is

presented as a kind of commodity or service – they still cannot help but

think of themselves as (if they were) citizens.

The closest that most of us come to a direct experience of the

centerlessness of capitalism is an encounter with the call center. As a

consumer in late capitalism, you increasingly exist in two, distinct

realities: the one in which the services are provided without hitch, and

another reality entirely, the crazed Kafkaesque labyrinth of call

centers, a world without memory, where cause and effect connect together

in mysterious, unfathomable ways, where it is a miracle that anything

ever happens, and you lose hope of ever passing back over to the other

side, where things seem to function smoothly. What exemplifies the

failure of the neoliberal world to live up to its own PR better than the

call center? Even so, the universality of bad experiences with call

centers does nothing to unsettle the operating assumption that

capitalism is inherently efficient, as if the problems with call centers

weren’t the systemic consequences of a logic of Capital which means

organizations are so fixated on making profits that they can’t actually

sell you anything.

The call center experience distils the political phenomenology of late

capitalism: the boredom and frustration punctuated by cheerily piped PR,

the repeating of the same dreary details many times to different poorly

trained and badly informed operatives, the building rage that must

remain impotent because it can have no legitimate object, since – as is

very quickly clear to the caller –there is no-one who knows, and no-one

who could do anything even if they could. Anger can only be a matter of

venting; it is aggression in a vacuum, directed at someone who is a

fellow victim of the system but with whom there is no possibility of

communality. Just as the anger has no proper object, it will have no

effect. In this experience of a system that is unresponsive, impersonal,

centerless, abstract and fragmentary, you are as close as you can be to

confronting the artificial stupidity of Capital in itself.

Call center angst is one more illustration of the way that Kafka is

poorly understood as exclusively a writer on totalitarianism; a

decentralized, market Stalinist bureaucracy is far more Kafkaesque than

one in which there is a central authority. Read, for instance, the bleak

farce of K’s encounter with the telephone system in the Castle, and it

is hard not to see it as uncannily prophetic of the call center

experience.

There’s no fixed exchange with the Castle, no central exchange which

transmits our calls further. When anybody calls up the Castle from here

the instruments in all the subordinate departments ring, or rather they

would ring if practically all the departments – I know this for a

certainty – didn’t leave their receivers off. Now and then, however, a

fatigued official may feel the need of a little distraction, especially

in the evenings and at night and may hang the receiver on. Then we get

an answer, but of course an answer that’s a practical joke. And that’s

very understandable too. For who would take the responsibility of

interrupting, in the middle of the night, the extremely important work

that goes on furiously the whole time, with a message about his own

private troubles? I can’t comprehend how even a stranger can imagine

that when he calls up Sordini, for example, it’s Sordini that answers.

K’s response anticipates the bewildered frustration of the individual in

the call center labyrinth. Although many of the conversations with call

center operatives appear Dadaistically nonsensical, they cannot be

treated as such, cannot be dismissed as being of no significance.

‘I didn’t know it was like that, certainly,’ said K. ‘I couldn’t know of

all these peculiarities, but I didn’t put much confidence in those

telephone conversations and I was always aware that the only things of

any importance were those that happened in the Castle itself.’

‘No,’ said the Superintendent, holding firmly onto the word, ‘these

telephone replies from the Castle certainly have a meaning, why

shouldn’t they? How could a message given by an official from the Castle

not be important?’

The supreme genius of Kafka was to have explored the negative atheology

proper to Capital: the centre is missing, but we cannot stop searching

for it or positing it. It is not that there is nothing there – it is

that what is there is not capable of exercising responsibility.

This problem is addressed from another angle in a paper by Campbell

Jones entitled ‘The Subject Supposed To Recycle’. In posing the

question, ‘who is the subject supposed to recycle?’ Jones denaturalizes

an imperative that is now so taken for granted that resisting it seems

senseless, never mind unethical. Everyone is supposed to recycle;

no-one, whatever their political persuasion, ought to resist this

injunction. The demand that we recycle is precisely posited as a pre- or

post-ideological imperative; in other words, it is positioned in

precisely the space where ideology always does its work. But the subject

supposed to recycle, Jones argued, presupposed the structure not

supposed to recycle: in making recycling the responsibility of

‘everyone’, structure contracts out its responsibility to consumers, by

itself receding into invisibility. Now, when the appeal to individual

ethical responsibility has never been more clamorous – in her book

Frames Of War, Judith Butler uses the term ‘responsibi-lization’ to

refer to this phenomenon – it is necessary to wager instead on structure

at its most totalizing. Instead of saying that everyone – i.e. every one

– is responsible for climate change, we all have to do our bit, it would

be better to say that no-one is, and that’s the very problem. The cause

of eco-catastrophe is an impersonal structure which, even though it is

capable of producing all manner of effects, is precisely not a subject

capable of exercising responsibility. The required subject – a

collective subject - does not exist, yet the crisis, like all the other

global crises we’re now facing, demands that it be constructed. Yet the

appeal to ethical immediacy that has been in place in British political

culture since at least 1985 – when the consensual sentimentality of Live

Aid replaced the antagonism of the Miners Strike – permanently defers

the emergence of such a subject.

Similar issues are touched on in a paper by Armin Beverungen on Alan

Pakula’s 1974 film The Parallax View, which sees The Parallax View as

providing a kind of diagram of the way in which a certain model of

(business) ethics goes wrong. The problem is that the model of

individual responsibility assumed by most versions of ethics have little

purchase on the behavior of Capital or corporations. The Parallax View

is in a sense a meta-conspiracy film: a film not only about conspiracies

but about the impotence of attempts to uncover them; or, much worse than

that, about the way in which particular kinds of investigation feed the

very conspiracies they intend to uncover. It is not only that the Warren

Beatty character is framed/killed for the crime he is investigating,

neatly eliminating him and undermining his investigations with one pull

of a corporate assassins trigger; it’s that, as Jameson noted in his

commentary on the film in The Geopolitical Aesthetic, his very tenacity,

quasi-sociopathic individualism, make him eminently frameable.

The terrifying climactic moment of The Parallax View – when the

silhouette of Beatty’s anonymous assassin appears against migraine-white

space – for me now rhymes with the open door at the end of a very

different film, Peter Weir’s The Truman Show. But where the door in the

horizon opening onto black space at the end of Weir’s film connotes a

break in a universe of total determinism, the nothingness on which

existentialist freedom depends, The Parallax View’s ‘final open door ...

opens onto a world conspiratorially organized and controlled as far as

the eye can see’ (Jameson). This anonymous figure with a rifle in a

doorway is the closest we get to seeing the conspiracy (as) itself. The

conspiracy in The Parallax View never gives any account of itself. It is

never focalised through a single malign individual. Although presumably

corporate, the interests and motives of the conspiracy in The Parallax

View are never articulated (perhaps not even to or by those actually

involved in it). Who knows what the Parallax Corporation really wants?

It is itself situated in the parallax between politics and economy. Is

it a commercial front for political interests, or is the whole machinery

of government a front for it? It’s not clear if the Corporation really

exists – more than that, it is not clear if its aim is to pretend that

it doesn’t exist, or to pretend that it does.

There are certainly conspiracies in capitalism, but the problem is that

they are themselves only possible because of deeper level structures

that allow them to function. Does anyone really think, for instance,

that things would improve if we replaced the whole managerial and

banking class with a whole new set of (‘better’) people? Surely, on the

contrary, it is evident that the vices are engendered by the structure,

and that while the structure remains, the vices will reproduce

themselves. The strength of Pakula’s film is precisely to invoke the

shadowy, centerless impersonality proper to a corporate conspiracy. As

Jameson observes, what Pakula captures so well in The Parallax View is a

particular kind of corporate affective tonality:

For the agents of conspiracy, Sorge [conern] is a matter of smiling

confidence, and the preoccupation is not personal but corporate, concern

for the vitality of the network or the institution, a disembodied

distraction or inattentiveness engaging the absent space of the

collective organization itself without the clumsy conjectures that sap

the energies of the victims. These people know, and are therefore able

to invest their presence as characters in an intense yet complacent

attention whose centre of gravity is elsewhere: a rapt intentness which

is at the same time disinterest. Yet this very different type of

concern, equally depersonalised, carries its own specific anxiety with

it, as it were unconsciously and corporately, without any consequences

for the individual villains.

... without any consequences for the individual villains... How that

phrase resonates just now – after the deaths of Jean Charles De Menezes

and Ian Tomlinson and after the banking fiasco. And what Jameson is

describing here is the mortifying cocoon of corporate structure – which

deadens as it protects, which hollows out, absents, the manager, ensures

that their attention is always displaced, ensures that they cannot

listen. The delusion that many who enter into management with high hopes

is precisely that they, the individual, can change things, that they

will not repeat what their managers had done, that things will be

different this time; but watch someone step up into management and it’s

usually not very long before the grey petrification of power starts to

subsume them. It is here that structure is palpable – you can

practically see it taking people over, hear its deadened/ deadening

judgements speaking through them.

For this reason, it is a mistake to rush to impose the individual

ethical responsibility that the corporate structure deflects. This is

the temptation of the ethical which, as ŽiŞek has argued, the capitalist

system is using in order to protect itself in the wake of the credit

crisis – the blame will be put on supposedly pathological individuals,

those ‘abusing the system’, rather than on the system itself. But the

evasion is actually a two step procedure – since structure will often be

invoked (either implicitly or openly) precisely at the point when there

is the possibility of individuals who belong to the corporate structure

being punished. At this point, suddenly, the causes of abuse or atrocity

are so systemic, so diffuse, that no individual can be held responsible.

This was what happened with the Hillsborough football disaster, the Jean

Charles De Menezes farce and so many other cases. But this impasse – it

is only individuals that can be held ethically responsible for actions,

and yet the cause of these abuses and errors is corporate, systemic – is

not only a dissimulation: it precisely indicates what is lacking in

capitalism. What agencies are capable of regulating and controlling

impersonal structures? How is it possible to chastise a corporate

structure? Yes, corporations can legally be treated as individuals – but

the problem is that corporations, whilst certainly entities, are not

like individual humans, and any analogy between punishing corporations

and punishing individuals will therefore necessarily be poor. And it is

not as if corporations are the deep-level agents behind everything; they

are themselves constrained by/ expressions of the ultimate

cause-that-is-not-a-subject: Capital.

9

Marxist Supernanny

Nothing could be a clearer illustration of what ŽiŞek has identified as

the failure of the Father function, the crisis of the paternal superego

in late capitalism, than a typical edition of Supernanny. The program

offers what amounts to a relentless, although of course implicit, attack

on postmodernity’s permissive hedonism. Supernanny is a Spinozist

insofar as, like Spinoza, she takes it for granted that children are in

a state of abjection. They are unable to recognize their own interests,

unable to apprehend either the causes of their actions or their (usually

deleterious) effects. But the problems that Supernanny confronts do not

arise from the actions or character of the children – who can only be

expected to be idiotic hedonists – but with the parents. It is the

parents’ following of the trajectory of the pleasure principle, the path

of least resistance, that causes most of the misery in the families. In

a pattern that quickly becomes familiar, the parents’ pursuit of the

easy life leads them to accede to their children’s every demand, which

become increasingly tyrannical.

Rather like many teachers or other workers in what used to be called

‘public service’, Supernanny has to sort out problems of socialization

that the family can no longer resolve. A Marxist Supernanny would of

course turn away from the troubleshooting of individual families to look

at the structural causes which produce the same repeated effect.

The problem is that late capitalism insists and relies upon the very

equation of desire with interests that parenting used to be based on

rejecting. In a culture in which the ‘paternal’ concept of duty has been

subsumed into the ‘maternal’ imperative to enjoy, it can seem that the

parent is failing in their duty if they in any way impede their

children’s absolute right to enjoyment. Partly this is an effect of the

increasing requirement that both parents work; in these conditions, when

the parent sees the child very little, the tendency will often be to

refuse to occupy the ‘oppressive’ function of telling the child what to

do. The parental disavowal of this role is doubled at the level of

cultural production by the refusal of ‘gatekeepers’ to do anything but

give audiences what they already (appear to) want. The concrete question

is: if a return to the paternal superego – the stern father in the home,

Reithian superciliousness in broadcasting – is neither possible nor

desirable, then how are we to move beyond the culture of monotonous

moribund conformity that results from a refusal to challenge or educate?

A question as massive as this cannot of course be finally answered in a

short book such as this, and what follows here will amount to a few

starting points and suggestions. In brief, though, I believe that it is

Spinoza who offers the best resources for thinking through what a

‘paternalism without the father’ might look like.

In Tarrying with the Negative, ŽiŞek famously argues that a certain

Spinozism is the ideology of late capitalism. ŽiŞek believes that

Spinoza’s rejection of deontology for an ethics based around the concept

of health is allegedly flat with capitalism’s amoral affective

engineering. The famous example here is Spinoza’s reading of the myth of

the Fall and the foundation of Law. On Spinoza’s account, God does not

condemn Adam for eating the apple because the action is wrong; he tells

him that he should not consume the apple because it will poison him. For

ŽiŞek, this dramatizes the termination of the Father function. An act is

wrong not because Daddy says so; Daddy only says it is ‘wrong’ because

performing the act will be harmful to us. In Žižek’s view, Spinoza’s

move both deprives the grounding of Law in a sadistic act of scission

(the cruel cut of castration), at the same time as it denies the

ungrounded positing of agency in an act of pure volition, in which the

subject assumes responsibility for everything. In fact, Spinoza has

immense resources for analyzing the affective regime of late capitalism,

the video-drome-control apparatus described by Burroughs, Philip K. Dick

and David Cronenberg in which agency is dissolved in a phantasmagoric

haze of psychic and physical intoxicants. Like Burroughs, Spinoza shows

that, far from being an aberrant condition, addiction is the standard

state for human beings, who are habitually enslaved into reactive and

repetitive behaviors by frozen images (of themselves and the world).

Freedom, Spinoza shows, is something that can be achieved only when we

can apprehend the real causes of our actions, when we can set aside the

‘sad passions’ that intoxicate and entrance us.

There’s no doubt that late capitalism certainly articulates many of its

injunctions via an appeal to (a certain version of) health. The banning

of smoking in public places, the relentless monstering of working class

diet on programs like You Are What You Eat, do appear to indicate that

we are already in the presence of a paternalism without the Father. It

is not that smoking is ‘wrong’, it is that it will lead to our failing

to lead long and enjoyable lives. But there are limits to this emphasis

on good health: mental health and intellectual development barely

feature at all, for instance. What we see instead is a reductive,

hedonic model of health which is all about ‘feeling and looking good’.

To tell people how to lose weight, or how to decorate their house, is

acceptable; but to call for any kind of cultural improvement is to be

oppressive and elitist. The alleged elitism and oppression cannot

consist in the notion that a third party might know someone’s interest

better than they know it themselves, since, presumably smokers are

deemed either to be unaware of their interests or incapable of acting in

accordance with them. No: the problem is that only certain types of

interest are deemed relevant, since they reflect values that are held to

be consensual. Losing weight, decorating your house and improving your

appearance belong to the ‘consentimental’ regime.

In an excellent interview at the

Register.com

, the documentary film-maker Adam Curtis identifies the contours of this

regime of affective management.

TV now tells you what to feel.

It doesn’t tell you what to think any more. From EastEnders to reality

format shows, you’re on the emotional journey of people – and through

the editing, it gently suggests to you what is the agreed form of

feeling. “Hugs and Kisses”, I call it.

I nicked that off Mark Ravenhill who wrote a very good piece which said

that if you analyse television now it’s a system of guidance – it tells

you who is having the Bad Feelings and who is having the Good Feelings.

And the person who is having the Bad Feelings is redeemed through a

“hugs and kisses” moment at the end. It really is a system not of moral

guidance, but of emotional guidance.

Morality has been replaced by feeling. In the ‘empire of the self

everyone ‘feels the same’ without ever escaping a condition of

solipsism. ‘What people suffer from,’ Curtis claims,

is being trapped within themselves - in a world of individualism

everyone is trapped within their own feelings, trapped within their own

imaginations. Our job as public service broadcasters is to take people

beyond the limits of their own self, and until we do that we will carry

on declining.

The BBC should realize that. I have an idealistic view, but if the BBC

could do that, taking people beyond their own selves, it will renew

itself in a way that jumps over the competition. The competition is

obsessed by serving people in their little selves. And in a way,

actually, Murdoch for all his power, is trapped by the self. That’s his

job, to feed the self.

In the BBC, it’s the next step forward. It doesn’t mean we go back to

the 1950s and tell people how to dress, what we do is say “we can free

you from yourself” – and people would love it.

Curtis attacks the internet because, in his view, it facilitates

communities of solipsists, interpassive networks of like-minds who

confirm, rather than challenge, each others’ assumptions and prejudices.

Instead of having to confront other points of view in a contested public

space, these communities retreat into closed circuits. But, Curtis

claims, the impact of internet lobbies on Old Media is disastrous,

since, not only does its reactive pro-activity allow the media class to

further abnegate its function to educate and lead, it also allows

populist currents on both the left and the right to ‘bully’ media

producers into turning out programming that is anodyne and mediocre.

Curtis’s critique has a point, but it misses important dimensions of

what is happening on the net. Contrary to Curtis’s account of blogging,

blogs can generate new discourse networks that have no correlate in the

social field outside cyberspace. As Old Media increasingly becomes

subsumed into PR and the consumer report replaces the critical essay,

some zones of cyberspace offer resistance to a ‘critical compression’

that is elsewhere depressingly pervasive. Nevertheless, the interpassive

simulation of participation in postmodern media, the network narcissism

of MySpace and Facebook, has, in the main, generated content that is

repetitive, parasitic and conformist. In a seeming irony, the media

class’s refusal to be paternalistic has not produced a bottom-up culture

of breathtaking diversity, but one that is increasingly infantilized. By

contrast, it is paternalistic cultures that treat audiences as adults,

assuming that they can cope with cultural products that are complex and

intellectually demanding. The reason that focus groups and capitalist

feedback systems fail, even when they generate commodities that are

immensely popular, is that people do not know what they want. This is

not only because people’s desire is already present but concealed from

them (although this is often the case). Rather, the most powerful forms

of desire are precisely cravings for the strange, the unexpected, the

weird. These can only be supplied by artists and media professionals who

are prepared to give people something different from that which already

satisfies them; by those, that is to say, prepared to take a certain

kind of risk. The Marxist Supernanny would not only be the one who laid

down limitations, who acted in our own interests when we are incapable

of recognizing them ourselves, but also the one prepared to take this

kind of risk, to wager on the strange and our appetite for it. It is

another irony that capitalism’s ‘society of risk’ is much less likely to

take this kind of risk than was the supposedly stodgy, centralized

culture of the postwar social consensus. It was the public

service-oriented BBC and Channel 4 that perplexed and delighted me with

the likes of Tinker, Tailor, Soldier Spy, Pinter plays and Tarkovsky

seasons; it was this BBC that also funded the popular avant gardism of

the BBC Radiophonic Workshop, which embedded sonic experimentalism into

everyday life. Such innovations are unthinkable now that the public has

been displaced by the consumer. The effect of permanent structural

instability, the ‘cancellation of the long term’, is invariably

stagnation and conservatism, not innovation. This is not a paradox. As

Adam Curtis’s remarks above make clear, the affects that predominate in

late capitalism are fear and cynicism. These emotions do not inspire

bold thinking or entrepreneurial leaps, they breed conformity and the

cult of the minimal variation, the turning out of products which very

closely resemble those that are already successful. Meanwhile, films

such as the aforementioned Tarkovsky’s Solaris and Stalker -plundered by

Hollywood since as far back as Alien and Blade Runner – were produced in

the ostensibly moribund conditions of the Brezhnevite Soviet state,

meaning that the USSR acted as a cultural entrepreneur for Hollywood.

Since it is now clear that a certain amount of stability is necessary

for cultural vibrancy, the question to be asked is: how can this

stability be provided, and by what agencies?

It’s well past time for the left to cease limiting its ambitions to the

establishing of a big state. But being ‘at a distance from the state’

does not mean either abandoning the state or retreating into the private

space of affects and diversity which ŽiŞek rightly argues is the perfect

complement to neoliberalism’s domination of the state. It means

recognizing that the goal of a genuinely new left should be not be to

take over the state but to subordinate the state to the general will.

This involves, naturally, resuscitating the very concept of a general

will, reviving – and modernizing – the idea of a public space that is

not reducible to an aggregation of individuals and their interests. The

‘methodological individualism’ of the capitalist realist worldview

presupposes the philosophy of Max Stirner as much as that of Adam Smith

or Hayek in that it regards notions such as the public as ‘spooks’,

phantom abstractions devoid of content. All that is real is the

individual (and their families). The symptoms of the failures of this

worldview are everywhere – in a disintegrated social sphere in which

teenagers shooting each other has become commonplace, in which hospitals

incubate aggressive superbugs – what is required is that effect be

connected to structural cause. Against the postmodernist suspicion of

grand narratives, we need to reassert that, far from being isolated,

contingent problems, these are all the effects of a single systemic

cause: Capital. We need to begin, as if for the first time, to develop

strategies against a Capital which presents itself as ontologically, as

well as geographically, ubiquitous.

Despite initial appearances (and hopes), capitalist realism was not

undermined by the credit crisis of 2008. The speculations that

capitalism might be on the verge of collapsing soon proved to be

unfounded. It quickly became clear that, far from constituting the end

of capitalism, the bank bail-outs were a massive re-assertion of the

capitalist realist insistence that there is no alternative. Allowing the

banking system to disintegrate was held to be unthinkable, and what

ensued was a vast hemor-rhaging of public money into private hands.

Nevertheless, what did happen in 2008 was the collapse of the framework

which has provided ideological cover for capitalist accumulation since

the 1970s. After the bank bail-outs neoliberalism has, in every sense,

been discredited. That is not to say that neoliberalism has disappeared

overnight; on the contrary, its assumptions continue to dominate

political economy, but they do so now no longer as part of an

ideological project that has a confident forward momentum, but as

inertial, undead defaults. We can now see that, while neoliberalism was

necessarily capitalist realist, capitalist realism need not be

neoliberal. In order to save itself, capitalism could revert to a model

of social democracy or to a Children of Men–like authoritarianism.

Without a credible and coherent alternative to capitalism, capitalist

realism will continue to rule the political-economic unconscious.

But even if it is now evident that the credit crisis will not lead to

the end of capitalism all by itself, the crisis has led to the relaxing

of a certain kind of mental paralysis. We are now in a political

landscape littered with what Alex Williams called ‘ideological rubble’ –

it is year zero again, and a space has been cleared for a new

anti-capitalism to emerge which is not necessarily tied to the old

language or traditions. One of the left’s vices is its endless rehearsal

of historical debates, its tendency to keep going over Kronsdadt or the

New Economic Policy rather than planning and organizing for a future

that it really believes in. The failure of previous forms of

anti-capitalist political organization should not be a cause for

despair, but what needs to be left behind is a certain romantic

attachment to the politics of failure, to the comfortable position of a

defeated marginality. The credit crisis is an opportunity – but it needs

to be treated as a tremendous speculative challenge, a spur for a

renewal that is not a return. As Badiou has forcefully insisted, an

effective anti-capitalism must be a rival to Capital, not a reaction to

it; there can be no return to pre-capitalist territorialities.

Anti-capitalism must oppose Capital’s globalism with its own, authentic,

universality.

It is crucial that a genuinely revitalized left confidently occupy the

new political terrain I have (very provisionally) sketched here. Nothing

is inherently political; politicization requires a political agent which

can transform the taken-for-granted into the up-for-grabs. If

neoliberalism triumphed by incorporating the desires of the post 68

working class, a new left could begin by building on the desires which

neoliberalism has generated but which it has been unable to satisfy. For

example, the left should argue that it can deliver what neoliberalism

signally failed to do: a massive reduction of bureaucracy. What is

needed is a new struggle over work and who controls it; an assertion of

worker autonomy (as opposed to control by management) together with a

rejection of certain kinds of labor (such as the excessive auditing

which has become so central feature of work in post-Fordism). This is a

struggle that can be won – but only if a new political subject

coalesces; it is an open question as to whether the old structures (such

as the trade unions) will be capable of nurturing that subjectivity, or

whether it will entail the formation of wholly new political

organizations. New forms of industrial action need to be instituted

against managerialism. For instance, in the case of teachers and

lecturers, the tactic of strikes (or even of marking bans) should be

abandoned, because they only hurt students and members (at the college

where I used to work, one-day strikes were pretty much welcomed by

management because they saved on the wage bill whilst causing negligible

disruption to the college). What is needed is the strategic withdrawal

of forms of labor which will only be noticed by management: all of the

machineries of self-surveillance that have no effect whatsoever on the

delivery of education, but which managerialism could not exist without.

Instead of the gestural, spectacular politics around (noble) causes like

Palestine, it’s time that teaching unions got far more immanent, and

take the opportunity opened up by the crisis to begin to rid public

services of business ontology. When even businesses can’t be run as

businesses, why should public services?

We must convert widespread mental health problems from medicalized

conditions into effective antagonisms. Affective disorders are forms of

captured discontent; this disaffection can and must be channeled

outwards, directed towards its real cause, Capital. Furthermore, the

proliferation of certain kinds of mental illness in late capitalism

makes the case for a new austerity, a case that is also made by the

increasing urgency of dealing with environmental disaster. Nothing

contradicts capitalism’s constitutive imperative towards growth more

than the concept of rationing goods and resources. Yet it is becoming

uncomfortably clear that consumer self-regulation and the market will

not by themselves avert environmental catastrophe. There is a libidinal,

as well as a practical case, to be made for this new ascesis. If, as

Oliver James, ŽiŞek and Supernanny have shown, unlimited license leads

to misery and disaffection, then limitations placed on desire are likely

to quicken, rather than deaden, it. In any case, rationing of some sort

is inevitable. The issue is whether it will be collectively managed, or

whether it will be imposed by authoritarian means when it is already too

late. Quite what forms this collective management should take is, again,

an open question, one that can only be resolved practically and

experimentally.

The long, dark night of the end of history has to be grasped as an

enormous opportunity. The very oppressive pervasiveness of capitalist

realism means that even glimmers of alternative political and economic

possibilities can have a disproportionately great effect. The tiniest

event can tear a hole in the grey curtain of reaction which has marked

the horizons of possibility under capitalist realism. From a situation

in which nothing can happen, suddenly anything is possible again.

Contemporary culture has eliminated both the concept of the public and

the figure of the intellectual. Former public spaces - both physical and

cultural - are now either derelict or colonized by advertising. A

cretinous anti-intellectualism presides, cheerled by expensively

educated hacks in the pay of multinational corporations who reassure

their bored readers that there is no need to rouse themselves from their

interpassive stupor. The informal censorship internalized and propagated

by the cultural workers of late capitalism generates a banal conformity

that the propaganda chiefs of Stalinism could only ever have dreamt of

imposing. Zero Books knows that another kind of discourse - intellectual

without being academic, popular without being populist - is not only

possible: it is already flourishing, in the regions beyond the striplit

malls of so-called mass media and the neurotically bureaucratic halls of

the academy. Zero is committed to the idea of publishing as a making

public of the intellectual. It is convinced that in the unthinking,

blandly consensual culture in which we live, critical and engaged

theoretical reflection is more important than ever before.