💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › ted-kaczynski-reflections-on-purposeful-work.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:19:39. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Reflections on Purposeful Work
Author: Ted Kaczynski
Date: 1978–1979
Language: en
Topics: work
Source: Retrieved on April 6, 2022 from https://b-ok.asia/book/18603975/54dd69

Ted Kaczynski

Reflections on Purposeful Work

Somewhere previously in my notes I have given it as my opinion that the

reasons modern man is so prone to frustration and other emotional

problems is that in the technological society he lives a life that is

highly abnormal; as compared with the life to which evolution has

adapted him, namely, the life of a hunter-gatherer. I still hold this

opinion; but it leaves open the question of which factors in modern

society are the most important sources of psychological trouble. I have

by this time concluded that the two main problems are (A) absence of a

real purpose in life, and (B) lack of personal autonomy. I think that

for most of these people who are dissatisfied with modern society, the

most important factor by far is absence of purpose; but that for certain

individuals, including me, the lack of personal autonomy is more

important (but these two problems are not completely independent.)

What we discuss here is the problem of purpose. In what follows I will

make a number of statements that are unproved. I am not absolutely

certain that all these statements are correct, but in order to avoid

being tiresome I will generally omit phrases like “in my opinion,” “I

think that,” and so forth, which I usually use to indicate unproved

statements. Also, the following discussion is meant to apply especially

to men. I am uncertain how far it is applicable to women.

Most people (to a greater or lesser extent depending on the individual)

need to make a purposeful effort at something in order to have a

fulfilling life. Note the adjective purposeful — the person must feel

that his activity is not merely a game. Solving crossword puzzles, for

example, requires an effort but cannot form the basis for a fulfilling

life, because the activity has no purpose external to itself — one does

it only in order to have something to do. The same is true of games and

statements generally. What is needed is purposeful work requiring a

reasonable amount of effort and self-discipline.

Among the bulk of the population in modern society (that is, among

people who are more-or-less normal though not necessarily leading

satisfying lives) it is probable that many or most emotional problems

are troublesome only because of a lack of sufficient genuine purpose. A

man who has a purpose, and who feels that he is succeeding in attaining

his purpose, typically will have high morale, and when one has high

morale, hardships (whether physical or psychological) are easy to bear.

When a man’s work is going reasonably well, and he believes in the value

of that work, his guilt feelings or his sex problems or his conflict

with his wife usually will not seem overly important. He is able to

endure these feelings cheerfully along with other hardships. But a man

without purpose will have flabby morale and a vacuum in his life. He is

likely to brood on his problems, and may be made seriously uncomfortable

by problems that would seem trivial to a man with high morale.

In the hunting-gathering life, the most important purpose motivating

work is to procure the necessities of life and some minimal comforts.

Especially food. Those who are ignorant of that kind of life tend to

assume it is miserable, and for this opinion they give reasons of the

following type: (a) hunter-gatherers’ work is monotonous; (b) the work

doesn’t utilize intelligence; (c) the object of the work is purely

materialistic, therefore has no “higher values” and is unfulfilling; (d)

the yield of the work (amount of food obtained, etc.) is very low, so

that the hunter must find his work discouraging; (e) the hunter lives

from hand to mouth and has no long term purpose.

On the basis of prolonged personal experiences of living at the

subsistence level, I assert that the foregoing arguments are based on

completely misunderstanding of the psychology of the hunting life. It is

not my principal purpose here to defend hunting-gathering as a way of

life; however, I will discuss separately each of the above points ((a)

through (e)) because the discussion will involve certain instructive

comparisons between primitive work and work in modern society.

(a) “Hunter gatherers work is monotonous.” Hunting itself is not

typically monotonous (though it can be in certain circumstances), and it

involves ranging over the country, rather than working always in the

same place. On the other hand, some hunter’s work is indeed monotonous

(e.g., picking berries, digging roots, softening animal skins). Monotony

is not ideal, but (for one who is accustomed to it) monotony does not

destroy the value of work or prevent it from being satisfying.

When I first took to the woods, I found burdensome the monotonous task

of dragging poles to the cabin and cutting them up for firewood. But I

became used to the work, and I now feel that it makes a real

contribution to the fulfillment that I get from this way of life. This

does not mean that I actually feel any pleasure in doing the task. It

does mean that, though the work is monotonous, it does not bore me,

because it is purposeful. And cutting a load of firewood gives me a

sense of accomplishment — NOT pride in my ability (anyone but a cripple

can cut firewood), but simply a feeling that I have done something

worthwhile. When I say “worthwhile” I am not referring to any abstract

philosophical notions about the value of work, or any such nonsense. The

accomplishment is worthwhile solely and exclusively because it is my

only means of fulfilling the physical need for winter fuel. If I had a

lot of money and didn’t need to conserve cash, I wouldn’t cut my own

firewood. There would be no point in it. No fulfillment in cutting

firewood unnecessarily. Thus, if I were wealthy, I would be missing the

fulfillment of this kind of purposeful work.

Let me compare this with my feelings about mathematics. I solved

problems in mathematics that had no practical applications; and if they

had had practical applications, it would have made no difference. Even

if some engineering firm had used my theorems for some purpose, those

theorems still would have had no use for me personally, nor for my

family or friends.

Mathematical research work was varied and interesting. It was exciting.

Some of it required me to use the very best of my intellectual powers,

and when I solved a difficult problem, I was rewarded with very intense

ego-gratification. Yet, as I grew older, I was increasingly nagged by a

sense of purposelessness in the work. Having proven a theorem, I would

sit back and think about it, and I would say, “So what? What good does

this do me? Now I’ll go work on another problem. But what for?” Thus, I

eventually became bored with mathematics.

Mathematics, music (listening, playing, composing), reading (light,

serious, fiction, non-fiction), coin-collecting, television — all these

eventually led to boredom.

Another example: I hunt the same areas for snowshoe rabbits over and

over again. It is very hard work, because the rabbits must generally be

hunted on steep slopes. The excitement connected with the first hunts

has long since disappeared. Yet I still enjoy hunting rabbits (which is

more than I can usually say for cutting firewood), and, like

firewood-cutting, rabbit-hunting still gives me solid, substantial

satisfaction. If it wasn’t for the fact that it is a real, physical

hardship to go without the meat, I would long since have grown bored

with rabbit hunting.

(b) “Hunter-gatherer’s work does not require intelligence.” Some aspects

of the hunting life require little intelligence. Other aspects do

require the full use of our intelligence (man didn’t evolve his big

brain for nothing), but a different kind of intelligence from that which

is most important in modern society. The kind of intelligence most

esteemed and most useful in organized society is the capacity for

abstract verbal or symbol-manipulating reasoning. (This is my own

strongest area of intelligence.) In the hunting life, it is intuitive

intelligence that is most important, because the required knowledge and

skills are mostly of a type that cannot be dealt with or transmitted

verbally, except in a partial way.

It seems reasonable to conjecture that the average hunter-gatherer

possesses an amount of skill and knowledge comparable to that of a

modern engineer, though of a very different kind. Be that as it may, it

seems probable that the average hunter possesses much more organized,

useful skill and knowledge than that of the average modern man, since

most people today (including petty technicians) do work that requires

only a limited amount of skill or knowledge, and few people cultivate

any learning outside of what is required for their jobs.

(c) “The object of hunters’ work is purely materialistic, has no higher

values, and therefore must be unfulfilling.” This is intellectual

snobbery. Let us distinguish between the materialism of hunter-gatherers

and the “materialism” (so-called) of modern society.

Hunters’ materialism is directed toward obtaining the physical

necessities of life, and some minimal comforts that actually contribute

to his physical well-being and his happiness. The “materialism” of

modern society is directed toward the accumulation of a surplus of

luxuries that contribute little or nothing to anyone’s physical

well-being. There are various motivations for this accumulation of

luxuries: desire for social status; a need that exists in modern society

for constant distraction and diversion (note how many of our luxuries

are toys — that is, are designed for entertainment); artificial

fulfillment of psychological needs that are otherwise stifled (e.g.,

riding a powerful motorcycle provides a spurious sense of power); and

then there is the fact that shopping in itself is a form of

entertainment. Observe that in each of these cases, material goods are

bought as a means to psychological ends, not physical ones. In some

instances, material goods are sought in order to alleviate the

few-residual physical discomforts remaining in modern society, but the

great mass of modern products are desired mostly for the psychological

effects to be obtained through them. In this sense, modern “materialism”

is not materialism at all, because its goals are not physical, but

psychological. In any case, this “materialism” is something quite

different from the materialism of primitives.

I suggest that the intellectuals’ scorn for “mere materialism” is due to

the fact that most of them have always been provided with an abundance

of material things acquired at the cost of minimal effort. Take food as

an example. The intellectual virtually has his food supply guaranteed to

him by organized society; his palate is jaded by all sorts of delicacies

that are standard fare for everyone today. He need not exert himself to

get food. Thus, he gets only a limited and superficial pleasure from

eating, so that he looks on eating as a lowly and superficial pleasure

that provides no deep fulfillment.

But when good nutrition is not to be taken for granted, and when a good

meal is the result of real effort, then food is really soul-satisfying.

The hunter’s enjoyment of food is not only physical, but psychological,

and involves not only the meal itself but the process by which it was

acquired — the effort and self-discipline involved in hunting the meat

and picking the berries, and certain satisfactions (which might be

called aesthetic) that are connected with having contact with nature and

are probably instinctive in human beings. If intellectuals lived this

way of life (long enough to become adapted to it), perhaps they would

not scorn its materialism.

Of course, though the activities of hunting and gathering themselves are

materialistic, it is true that hunter-gatherers usually have other

activities of an artistic and spiritual order. On the other hand, it

would seem that the artistic and spiritual concerns of the hunter tend

to revolve around his materialistic concerns. For example, animals and

plants depicted in his drawings tend to be those that he uses for food.

It can be argued that, rather than lowering the value of his spiritual

life, this materialistic orientation actually enhances it. The physical,

social, spiritual, artistic, and other aspects of primitive man’s life

all tend to be bound together in a unified whole. The various aspects of

modern man’s life tend to be unconnected and separated into

compartments: His food is not experienced as a direct result of his

labor; the act to which he is exposed typically is not expressive of his

daily work; the people with whom he socializes often are not those wich

whom he works; and so forth.

Before I took to the woods, I never drew pictures except to make

humorous cartoons. But after I had been in the woods long enough so that

the country got into my blood, so to speak, I became interested in

drawing or carving representations of the animals with which I was most

familiar. My most important source of meat, and the animal that I was

most skilled at hunting, was the snowshoe rabbit, and it was this animal

that I was most interested in drawing. The snowshoe rabbit has a special

psychological significance for me, and in my desire to depict it, I felt

I somewhat understood the motivation of the ancient hunters who left

their beautiful drawings of animals on the walls of caves.

(d) “The yield of the hunter’s work is so low that he must find it

discouraging.” The yield of the hunter’s labor may seem small to us; but

usually he gets as much as he needs to live (otherwise man would not

have survived). That is all he expects and all he is accustomed to;

hence the yield does not seem small to him.

In another sense, the yield of the hunter’s labor is far greater than

that of the modern worker. Because the hunter’s work makes the

difference between survival and death by starvation, the yield of his

labor is nothing less than life itself. The yield of the modern worker’s

labor is only a lot of toys like television sets, air conditioners, and

so forth, these being the things that he purchases with his salary.

(e) “The hunter lives from hand to mouth and has no long term purpose.”

Probably this is largely true.

When I was in my teens I often indulged in daydreams of living as a

hunter-gatherer. In my imagination, the round of labor needed to feed

myself in such an existence did not seem sufficient to fill my life, and

I imagined myself setting up artificial long-term purposes for myself —

for example, building systems of primitive bridges over streams. Not

that I thought I would need the bridges, but I thought I would need a

long-term purpose.

Now, having had the experience of hunting for meat, gathering herbs and

berries, cutting firewood, and so forth, as a matter of practical

necessity, I look upon such artificial purposes as silly. I found that

when you go out to hunt knowing that you will or will not have meat to

eat according as you succeed or fail in the hunt, your need for purpose

and importance is fully satisfied — you have no need whatever to look

forward to a goal that is five or ten years in the future. When you have

to really exert yourself to procure the necessities of life, nothing

else seems as purposeful or important.

The need that exists in many civilized people for long-term large-scale

purpose probably results from a need to magnify our goals in an attempt

to make ourselves feel that we have a significant purpose. (But we work

for something over a period of years, and when we finally obtain it, the

reward somehow seems ridiculously small in proportion to the length of

time it took to get it.)

(This concludes our comparison of purposeful work in hunting-gathering

societies with that in civilization.)

I suggest that our own biological predisposition — the purpose that is

more-or-less built into us — is to pursue practical, material, physical

objectives. But practical work is almost impossible today, because The

System takes care of all practical problems. The system is so vast, that

the contribution of any one individual to the system’s practiced work,

is insignificant. Thus, no individual can do any significant practical

work. (The argument is oversimplified, but it contains a large element

of truth, and indicates one of the main themes of this essay.)

This (the suggested predisposition to pursue practical, material

objectives) may be part of the reason for the so-called materialism of

modern society. Most people pursue material wealth because material

wealth represents to them a practical, physical goal. These people don’t

think about the fact that wealth today provides only psychological

gratifications such as entertainment and social status — which are not

what we call practical objectives. (Still, there is reason to suspect

that the majority suffer from a vague sense of purposelessness that they

never analyse.)

There are certain other people to whom the purposelessness of wealth

today is quite obvious; these people accept certain artificial goals

that society has set up — goals like Art, Science, Humanitarianism, etc.

But, again, one suspects that to the majority of these people too, their

artificial goals are not fully satisfactory, and they are vaguely

troubled. Being essentially bored, they brood on their psychological

problems and often lead frustrated, unhappy lives.

We shall now develop in detail the thesis sketched in the foregoing 3

paragraphs. We begin by discussing a certain psychological trait.

Some people have more than other people of a psychological trait that I

shall call close organization. If a person has a closely organized mind,

then each item of information that he possesses is closely integrated

into his thoughts, feelings, and behavior. If a person has a loosely

organized mind, then many items of information that he possesses are not

well integrated into his thoughts, feelings, and behavior. In a closely

organized mind, verbally formulated beliefs or values very readily

affect feelings and behavior. A man with a loosely organized mind may

verbally profess certain beliefs or values, but may fail to make the

connection between these verbal formulations and his feelings or

behavior.

We illustrate with examples:

careful to obey the law himself. If his mind is loosely organized, he

may commit a petty theft without ever worrying about the contradiction

between his belief and his action.

mind, he feels no pride in his grade, because he knows it does not

represent his real level of achievement. If X has a loosely organized

mind, he may feel pride in his A even though he realizes it does not

represent his real level of achievement.

show of enjoying the intercourse, but X knows very well that she is only

doing it for the money. If X has a closely organized mind, his pleasure

with the prostitute is likely to be dampened by his knowledge that she

is only putting on an act. If X has a loosely organized mind, his

knowledge that the prostitute is only putting on an act may not affect

his feelings in having intercourse with her.

known as the “criterion of verifiability” — or suppose that, if he does

not entirely accept it, he at least agrees that in order to fully

understand a statement we must examine to what extent the statement is

“verifiable.”At the same time, this scholar may profess certain

political principles or ideologies without ever having examined these

principles in light of the criterion of verifiability.If his mind were

very closely organized, he would not have omitted such examination.

strongly that “serious” music was very superior to the “popular” forms

of music. He attempted to justify this by asserting that the pleasure

obtained by the “common man” from popular music is of a smaller order of

magnitude than that obtained by intellectuals from “serious” music. Yet

he had no evidence to support this assertion. He was only guessing. In

the scientific realm he never would have accepted such an

unsubstantiated statement. Yet he did not seem to question such a

statement in his personal ideology.

If he had had a very closely organized mind, he would have been aware of

the sloppiness of his thinking here.

We trust that these examples make it fairly clear what we mean by the

distinction between “closely” and “loosely” organized minds.

We make two points:

organized minds, common experience would seem to indicate that there are

quite a few individual exceptions. Intelligence, apparently, is not at

all rigidly related to closeness of organization.

introspection, and a tendency to re-examine one’s own thought-processes;

but I am not convinced that close organization always accompanies these

other characteristics. In any case, close organization is not identical

with these other characteristics. For instance, the closely-organized

response in Example 3 is not the same thing as being thoughtful or

introspective, or examining one’s own thought-processes.

Now let us study the way in which closeness of organization is related

to the problem of purpose.

(alpha) Consider first a person having subnormal intelligence and a very

loosely organized mind. Suppose this fellow is given each day the task

of stacking up wooden blocks in a certain configuration. At the end of

the day, his keeper comes and knocks down all the stacks of blocks, and

next day our moron has to stack them up all over again. Let us suppose

that this fellow is not too stupid to realize that his work accomplishes

nothing, Nevertheless, it is possible that he may get fulfillment from

his work: Each day he simply absorbs himself happily in his task and

doesn’t bother to think about whether it has any purpose.

(beta) Next take the case of a fellow I once knew who discussed his

ambitions with me and said that his hope was simply to keep on

increasing his income indefinitely. When I asked his motive for this, he

answered to this effect: “I have studied economics! I know that man’s

economic wants are never satisfied. No matter how much I have, I will

always want more.” He made no claim that the indefinite increase of

wealth would bring happiness or any other particular benefit. He seemed

to realize in a way that the indefinite increase of wealth was simply a

kind of game people play, having no definite external purpose. Yet this

did not prevent him from absorbing himself in the game and feeling

purpose.

(gamma) For another example we can take any one of a number of young

researchers in pure mathematics whom I knew of in the 1960’s. These

fellows would grind out papers one after another, each being of interest

only to a tiny group of specialists in a narrow area of mathematics, and

none having any practical applications. For the most part they never

thought about the purpose of all this. If pressed, they might claim that

mathematics has “aesthetic” value. Of course, the supposed aesthetic

value in most of the papers they published was accessible only to the

tiny group of specialists who had the knowledge to read these papers.

The obvious question is, why should society pay these fellows

comfortable salaries to gratify each other’s supposed aesthetic

sensibilities in a way that was of no benefit whatever to the public?

Nevertheless, like the moron building his piles of blocks, these guys

would happily absorb themselves in their work and churn out papers

without worrying about what, if anything, they were accomplishing.

Presumably, if their minds had been sufficiently closely organized, they

would not have been able to feel a sense of purpose in their work

without first specifying to themselves some definite goal that they were

pursuing.

(delta) Now we take a more complex example: a research scientist whose

work has clearcut practical applications. Suppose that he describes his

purpose as this: to benefit humanity by contributing to technological

progress. (For the sake of argument, we shall assume for the present

that technological progress does benefit humanity.)

Human beings have an instinct that leads them to want to do good for

their own family and immediate circle of friends. But we feel safe in

asserting that human beings do not have any innate instinct to do good

for humanity at large, which consists of vast masses of unknown, unseen

strangers. (This assertion is confined by the fact that, until very

recently on the historical time-scale, nearly all people hold the

attitude: “My family comes first, then my clan, then my nation, and to

hell with the rest of the human race.” I am not criticizing this

attitude, which is natural and instinctive for human beings.)

So, what is the scientist’s motive for wanting to benefit humanity? He

needs to have work to do, and he needs to feel that work is purposeful.

He decides to benefit humanity only in order to fulfill his need for

purposeful work. But this means that benefiting humanity is not his real

purpose — his real purpose is simply to fulfill his need for work. In

other words, he is working merely for the sake of working — his work has

no purpose external to itself. “Benefiting humanity” is only an

artificial purpose that he has set up in order to make himself feel that

his work is purposeful.

Now, it may be that our scientist is a thoughtful man and is aware of

everything that we have just said. But (perhaps) he is able to absorb

himself contentedly in his work and push the question of purpose out of

his mind. (Here again we have the moron piling up the blocks.) On the

other hand, if our scientist has a very closely organized mind, it may

be that the problem of purpose will always be too much present in his

consciousness for him to feel content in his work.

The foregoing discussion is oversimplified and incomplete. We will now

try to analyze the problem of purpose in more detail.

Let us roughly divide the modern man into two types.

Type I. Those who have routine jobs, who work only because they have to,

who make no effort to excel in their work, and who have no job-related

ambitions.

Type II. Career workers. Those who have ambitions, put a real effort

into their work, and try to excel in it. In Type II we also include

those people who try to satisfy their need for purposeful work through

non-money-earning activities, whether hobbies, or community service, or

whatever.

(Of course, some people may be hybrids between Type I and Type II, but

that does not invalidate our argument.)

First, we consider Type I. These people do work that is purposeful for

them only to the extent that they must work in order to avoid the

humiliation of going on welfare. They feel that they are working to

avoid a punishment, not that they are exerting themselves to gain a

reward. To judge from my own personal observation, morale among type I

workers often is extremely low. This is not always the case — in some

companies I thought morale was pretty good. But it does not seem to me

that Type I work provides an adequate sense of purpose in life for any

but the most placid and unambitious personalities.

Various manipulative tricks are being tried on Type I workers to make

them have a more positive attitude toward their work. For example, one

company, whose employees would formerly each assemble one section of a

telephone book, is now having each employee assemble a whole telephone

book, and this is supposed to give them a sense of accomplishment in

their work. It’s almost a sick-joke. If cheap devices like this actually

succeed, then so much the worse. It would be better for people to be

miserable at their work than to have the company manipulate them in this

way.

In any case, if any employee begins to take pride in his work, to try to

excel in it, or to have job-related ambitions, then this will put him

into Type II, which we are about to discuss.

Type II: Career workers. We shall begin by discussing these career

workers whose work is what is generally called “practical.” This type of

worker we shall call, for brevity, a PCW (Practical Career Worker). In

order to be definite, we will take, say, an aeronautical engineer. Let

us suppose he is improving the design of an aircraft. What is his

purpose in doing this work? Ostensibly it is to make a more efficient

plane. A practical (there are no more pages)