💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › chris-beaumont-defending-an-anarchist-society.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:22:50. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Defending an Anarchist Society
Author: Chris Beaumont
Date: 2017
Language: en
Topics: after the revolution, theory and practice, Revolutionary Anarchism, revolutionary strategy, anarcho-communism, war, warfare, governance, authoritarian socialism, theory
Source: Masteral dissertation submitted to the University of Bristol.

Chris Beaumont

Defending an Anarchist Society

Abstract

Anarchism, when applied consistently, provides structures allowing for

highly advantageous strategies when defending society, making anarchist

social structures capable of defence against external invasion when

fully established.

I used Gray’s 17 core dimensions of military strategy as a framework for

what determines strategic success, what I called authoritarian-communism

as a benchmark for successful strategy when defending a revolutionary

society, and Kropotkin’s anarcho-communism as a framework for an

established anarchism. Comparing authoritarian-communist strategies to

the strategies implementable under a fully established anarchist society

in a context where the survival of the society is at stake, anarchist

structures are more strategically advantageous in 16 of the dimensions

whilst still proving capable regarding the 17^(th) dimension. Because of

the defensive successes of authoritarian-communism, anarchist structures

being more advantageous than authoritarian-communism in this context

gives theoretical grounding for maintaining that an anarchist society

could sufficiently defend itself against military aggression.

Demonstrating that anarchist societies are theoretically defensible,

provides a strong counter to the intuition that anarchist societies

would be doomed to fall under external aggression if implemented,

therefore the research maintains anarchism’s viability as a

revolutionary theory within this context. Moreover, because the research

focuses on anarchism and its survivability against neighbouring states,

this research provides a strong contribution to anarchist international

relations theory which, because of anarchism’s neglect in larger

international relations discussions, means this research also strongly

contributes to international relations theory as a whole.

Introduction

In order to survive, a society must defend itself against aggression; it

should be expected that a society unable to defend itself would

eventually be conquered. If an anarchist society is viable, it must be

capable of defending itself against military aggression. However, given

anarchism is an often revolutionary philosophy (Marshall; 1993; px-xi

(introduction)), which rejects authority (Marshall; 1993; p42), and

militaries traditionally follow a command hierarchy (HS; 2017) and are

therefore authoritarian, it seems doubtful that an anarchist society has

the capacity to defend itself against a state military and would

therefore be indefensible and therefore unviable as a model for a

revolutionary society. Hart defines strategy as ‘...applying military

means to the end of policy’ (Baylis & Wirtz; 2002; p4). For anarchist

defence, this means knowing what is required for defence and having the

means to execute it. Fully answering whether anarchist social structures

are capable of effective defence therefore means answering the following

questions:

However, current literature addressing anarchist defence fails to answer

these questions, partially because little is written on the topic, but

also because the few existing works answer very little. Taylor (1982)

notes that historically, non-state societies, although internally

stable, are usually destroyed by state conquest (p168). Kropotkin (1902)

echoes this reasoning, observing that self organising mutual-aid

societies, such as village communities, lasted centuries (p115-120), but

were destroyed by state aggression (p223-227). Woods (2011) also

highlights how the anarchist revolution in the Spanish civil war in the

1930’s would have defeated fascism, but was destroyed after being

betrayed by the Stalinists.

This seemingly confirms the intuition that anarchist societies cannot

defend themselves. However, these accounts simply highlight that these

societies were destroyed, not whether they were incapable of defence;

these societies could have made the wrong choices. It also doesn’t

confirm that no anarchist society could ever be defensible; others may

succeed in the future. Anarchism’s record of failure, although

potentially problematic, doesn’t provide sufficient answers.

Supporting evidence for anarchist defence is also uninformative.

Regarding the Spanish anarchists during the civil war, Alexander (1999)

highlights how Orwell held that the Anarchist militias could have

improved their efficiency whilst retaining trade union control (p254),

meaning centralisation wasn’t needed for efficiency. Marshall (1993)

also noted how Orwell held that the ‘Anarchist were the best fighters

amongst the purely Spanish forces’(462). Dolgof (1974), highlights how

Trotsky conceded that the Spanish anarchist fighters were superior to

the Russian proletariat (p7).

Gelderloos (2010) observes other anarchist successes, for example the

Ukrainian anarchists achieved highly organised and mobile combat when

fighting the USSR, making defeating the Ukrainians difficult for the

Bolsheviks (p244-245). The Mapuche defended their society for centuries

against the Spanish, being conquered in 1865, with the Mapuche’s

decentralised structures proving advantageous compared to the more

authoritarian Aztecs, who were defeated much sooner because they would

surrender after the loss of a leader or capital (p247).

These accounts of successful strategies employed by anarchists are

encouraging for anarchism. However, despite their successes, these

societies all eventually lost. Therefore, there are no accounts of

whether anarchism in the face of state aggression, is able to

sufficiently defend itself.

Moreover, these works are largely historically based, and although

potentially informative, alone, they don’t meaningfully answer the

question about how well an anarchist society could defend itself. I am

analysing anarchism’s defensive capabilities in the abstract. This is

therefore a theoretical rather than historical research. Therefore,

although potentially useful, the writing directly addressing this topic

cannot provide sufficient findings.

The paucity of work directly addressing this topic and the broad

theoretical nature of the research means this research will be more

similar to an extended theoretical essay rather than a traditional

research. This will provide a more open structure, allowing me to fully

address this issue, despite the broad theoretical scope and lack of

direct source material. Therefore, the research will be structured as

follows:

Part 1: Needs

I will first define anarchism as the dismantling of illegitimate

hierarchy in pursuit of equality and freedom, and assert Kropotkin’s

mutual-aid principle as a practicable means of achieving freedom and

equality. This will lead me to argue that anarcho-communism acts as an

example of a society which successfully dismantles hierarchy based on

freedom and equality, therefore justifying anarcho-communism as the

basis for an established anarchism.

I will then pose the issue that historically, anarchism has failed to

defend itself against aggression, contrasting this with the successes of

what I will call authoritarian-communism, therefore arguing that for

anarchism to be considered a viable revolutionary practice, anarchism

must prove at least as defensible as authoritarian-communism.

To establish how an anarchist society would coordinate against

aggression, I will then outline the institutional framework of an

established anarchism as bottom-up decentralised direct-democratic

institutions based on free association. I will show how this is

implemented in industry through industrial committees and apply this

framework to defence, therefore establishing the Mutual-aid Militia

(MAM’s), defence forces based locally on democratically appointed

commanders, and large-scale operations being coordinated by strategic

committee. This will establish the organisational forms available to

anarchism and indicate what must be achieved to defend the society,

namely: repelling the enemy and the preservation of these anarchist

social relations.

I will then argue that because anarchism must prove at least as

defensively viable as authoritarian-communism to be considered

sufficiently defensible, anarchist structures must be analysed in

isolation against authoritarian-communism to determine what strategic

impacts both these structures have on a society. Anarchism will be

compared with authoritarian-communism based on Gray’s 17 core strategic

dimensions. Therefore anarchism, in the context of military defence,

must prove just as, or more advantageous than authoritarian-communism in

regards to all these dimensions to be considered defensively viable. I

will then outline how advantage or disadvantage will be established,

arguing that because of the paucity of direct evidence, the analysis

will be open to a variety of evidence, while allowing for a degree of

interpretation to ensure sufficient analysis.

Part 1 will therefore answer the first question. Anarchism needs to

repel invaders and preserve its institutions. To be sufficiently capable

of this, anarchism must prove that within Gray’s 17 core dimensions, it

is either just as, or more advantageous than authoritarian-communism

when defending a society against aggression.

Part 2: Capabilities — Analysis

Part 2 will outline each strategic dimension and I will from this,

interpret what defensive success regarding each dimension entails. Based

on the social structures of anarchism and authoritarian-communism, I

will describe which strategies can best be used by each social

structure, whichever social structure is most capable of successful

strategy is granted the advantage in that dimension. Following analysis

of the dimensions, I will summarise the findings in the discussion

chapter, therefore allowing me to determine whether anarchism indeed

succeeds in comparison to authoritarian-communism, therefore determining

whether anarchism is capable of sufficient defence and therefore

answering the second question.

If anarchism proves successful, I will address why the historical record

doesn’t reflect this, therefore allowing for a fuller account of

anarchism’s defensive capabilities and therefore viability in this

respect. I will then reflect on the significance of the research and how

further study could build on the findings.

Part 1: Needs

Chapter 1: The established anarchist society

1.1: What is anarchism?

Anarchism is a political philosophy advocating a stateless society

(Taylor; 1982; p1). States are political institutions which successfully

claims a monopoly on legitimate violence within a given territory,

meaning the state must be the only institution able to enact or sanction

violence which is seen as legitimate (Munro; 2013). Other actors may

commit violence within the state’s territory, but this violence must be

seen as illegitimate.

Although Taylor (1982) maintains that a total monopoly has never been

realised (p5), statehood can be assessed based on the extent to which

such a monopoly is established. If a state cannot enforce its own laws

or territorial integrity, it is considered it a failed state, whereas

states that uphold their laws and integrity have established their

sovereignty (Barma; 2017). The state’s essence is therefore the

realisation of a violent monopoly. An anarchist society would therefore

be a society whose means of violence are not monopolised, but

redistributed among as much of the population as possible and doesn’t

use violence to enforce decisions (Taylor; 1982; p7).

Defining anarchism as simply the rejection of the state only provides a

skeletal and negative definition of Anarchism. However, beyond this

negative definition, what qualifies as authentically anarchist is

contested. I will address two definitions.

Marshall (1993), notes how it is usual for anarchists to see freedom as

the absolute ideal (p36), whilst also holding equality as an important

goal (p48) whilst also being concerned with individuality (p50). From

this framework one could identify anarchism as the complete freedom and

equality of individuals. Chomsky (1995) sees Anarchism as the process of

dismantling illegitimate hierarchy.

The first definition is far too impracticable to be useful.

Although the idea of complete equality and freedom is useful because it

introduces an ethical element to anarchism, such a definition isn’t

practicable. Humans are social beings and must interact, which means

being subjected to the actions of others. Kropotkin held that complete

individual freedom is impossible, but individuals can become more

meaningfully free when they engage in a collective spirit towards the

whole society (Miller; 1976; p197). Therefore, alone, humans would live

impoverished lives, making the impositions of others necessary. However,

this makes absolute freedom impossible because we are subjected to the

other. Moreover, the focus on individuals ignores collectivist theories;

humanity’s social need raises doubts of our freedom being found under

pure individualism, making this definition both impractical and unsuited

to human wellbeing.

Chomsky’s definition is much more useful because it is more practicable.

Whilst holding freedom and equality (both important anarchist

principles), as an ethical guide, anarchists can then determine which

hierarchies should and shouldn’t be dismantled. I therefore have a

practical and ethical framework for an established anarchist society.

Anarchism will be defined as the process of dismantling illegitimate

hierarchy with freedom and equality as guiding principles. This

definition will then shape the essential aspects of an established

anarchist society.

1.2: Mutual-Aid

If anarchism is practicable, I must ground its structure in what humans

have created when free of centralised authority; these real world

structures will then indicate what is possible for an established

anarchism.

According to Kropotkin (1902), humans have historically utilised

mutual-aid when organising without centralised authority (p.xiv-xv

(introduction)). Mutual-aid is an evolutionary principle which holds

that the most successful species are cooperative; when individuals in

the same species put collective needs over themselves, the collective

prospers, because there is less competition over resources. Therefore,

cooperation is more efficient for survival (Goodwin; 2010; p111-114).

Successful species therefore usually form cooperative societies, these

societies are distinct social ontologies, not reducible to the sum of

the interests of the individuals (Goodwin; 2010; p115-116).

This irreducibility is because societies follow complexity theory,

forming what I will call “complex systems”. Complex systems are holistic

phenomena, meaning they are observable as functioning wholes and

therefore may not be explainable through reductive/mechanical scientific

methods (Goodwin; 2010; p108-109). This is because the individual’s

cooperative behaviour isn’t based on enlightened self interest; their

interests are directed towards the collective itself (Goodwin; 2010;

114), meaning mutual-aid societies have an independent collective

identity.

These societies find their highest level of size and complexity amongst

humans. Mutual-aid societies range from the hunter-gatherer level, to

the medieval guild cities (Korpotkin; 1902; p.xv (introduction)),

demonstrating that mutual-aid can be practiced even on a large complex

scale.

These societies were largely or entirely self governing (Korpotkin;

1902; p132), with decisions made based on differing forms of collective

consensus. These could be direct-democratic institutions such as the

folkmote (Kropotkin; 1902; p126), where the society would gather and

deliberate on issues collectively. Societies would also appoint judges

and arbiters who made deliberations but had no enforcing power other

than the moral authority of the commune (Kropotkin; 1902; p130-132),

therefore requiring a collective understanding of morality. Because

decisions were made collectively or necessitated collective consent,

these communities were fully engaged in their own organisation, making

these societies remarkably free.

Although less technologically developed mutual-aid societies were only

collectively free, having very strict rules on individual conduct, these

rules were based on general understandings of what is beneficial for all

and mostly followed voluntarily (Kropotkin; 1902; p112), making these

rules often necessary and legitimate.

Moreover, as mutual-aid societies grew, the complexity and affluence

they achieved afforded much more individual freedom, with the guild

cities giving “full liberty of expression to the creative genius of each

separate group of individuals” (Kropotkin; 1902; p186). Therefore,

although some un-freedom can be observed for individuals, this was due

to perceived necessity. When individual freedom was viable for the

society, it was embraced; both individual and collective freedom are

achievable in mutual-aid societies.

Moreover, these communities usually owned property collectively.

According to Kropotkin (1902), humans throughout history organised

largely based on communist principles (p313). Individuals were expected

to contribute what they could to the whole society. In some tribes, if

someone obtains food, they are expected to shout three times to offer to

share before they could eat (p112). Moreover, if members had certain

needs, they were met without the expectation of direct reciprocity. In

certain villages, pregnant women and the sick had privileged access to

things like meat (p144) because of their needs. Serving the needs of all

first therefore means these societies were very equal.

Moreover, as discussed, mutual-aid societies were also stable, typically

lasting hundreds of years before being destroyed by states. Therefore,

mutual-aid achieved high levels of equality, freedom and stability,

making mutual-aid a successful means of organising society without a

state.

Therefore, according to Kropotkin, free and equal, humans are capable of

creating large, complicated and cooperative social structures based on

free and equal association independent from state coercion. Moreover,

modern evolutionary biologists’ and anthropologists’ work have validated

Kropotkin’s assessment (Anarcho; 2008). For example, Dawkins (2006)

asserts that altruism at the individual level can be a means of a gene

maximising its interests (p.viii(introduction), exactly Kropotkin’s

argument. Graeber (2004) has also demonstrated that there exist many

varieties of human societies, ranging from fully authoritarian, to

aggressively libertarian (p53-54).

This gives contemporary validation to Kropotkin’s theory that human

society has heavily relied on cooperation rather than competition.

Although Graeber also records authoritarian human societies, this

doesn’t invalidate mutual-aid; Kropotkin (1902) maintains that

cooperation is innate in humans, but self-assertion of individuals is

still present (p294-295). Cooperation is therefore very possible and

much more successful for survival than hierarchy. The presence of

libertarian human societies attests to mutual-aid’s possibility, while

modern evolutionary biologists’ assertions regarding altruism’s

evolutionary importance, supports mutual-aid’s success. Therefore,

mutual-aid can be used as a model for a successful practicable anarchy.

1.3: Anarcho-communism

I defined anarchism as the dismantling of illegitimate hierarchies in

pursuit of equality and freedom, and found that when free from the

state, humans, when organising equally and freely, utilise mutual-aid

principles. Because, as mentioned, mutual-aid has meant humans have

largely governed under communist principles, an established anarchist

society would therefore be anarcho-communist.

Anarcho-communism advocates a stateless society where all is owned

collectively (Kropotkin; 1913; p34) and individuals organise based on

free agreement. Collective ownership mean individuals necessarily work

in the interests of the collective because the fruits of individual

labour become the property of the collective. Free agreement means that

individuals associate voluntarily, absent from central authority when

organising (p172), rather than through centralised coercion.

Because association isn’t centralised, individuals associate directly

through de-centralised, local organisation (Miller; 1976; p193). This

local organisation, being based on common ownership, could then be

federalised (Mashall; 1993; p8) if associates strive for larger scale

organisation.

Because everything is owned collectively, this free agreement doesn’t

mean total individual freedom. Because everything belongs to everyone,

there are limits on how one can behave towards the society’s

possessions. For example, one can’t demolish a factory if the collective

doesn’t consent because the collective has an equal claim to said

factory.

Therefore, anarcho-communism emphasises collective freedom and wellbeing

over individual freedom. However, through collective association,

individual freedom and development is still important because this

creates more responsible and sociable members of society, what Kropotkin

calls “communist sociability”. This develops sociable individuality,

which is richer and more meaningful than the more isolated egoistic

individuality of capitalist society. (Miller; 1976; p197).

This collectivist anarchism aligns with mutual-aid principles. Free from

centralised authority, humans tend to associate collectively based on

communist principles as discussed. Therefore, collective ownership suits

human’s cooperative and altruistic tendencies. An established anarchist

society needs practicable structures, because anarcho-communism is

compatible with the highly practicable mutual-aid principle,

anarcho-communism becomes a suitable form of anarchism due to this

practicability.

Moreover, mutual-aid as the practical foundation for an established

anarchism mean anarcho-communism provides freedom and equality by

dismantling hierarchies. Anarcho-communism dismantles the hierarchy of

centralised states, but also the hierarchies created by capitalism and

private ownership, which in practice have created massive inequality

(Hodgson; 2016) and what Chomsky (2000) describes as private tyrannies,

in the form of private capitalist firms. Therefore, anarcho-communism

succeeds in dismantling important illegitimate hierarchies.

However, the collectivist principles of mutual-aid place the collective

above the individual, this is a hierarchy. However, the collective, as

we’ve discussed, is also an important social ontology; the individual

being more important than the collective would also be a hierarchy.

Therefore, which hierarchy is more legitimate?

Marshall (1993) states that a core anarchist principle is to reject all

forms of external government (p.xiii (introduction)). Therefore, if when

organising free from centralised power, humans collectivise, based on

anarchist principles this hierarchy must be justified. Achieving

individualistic structures would require external coercion because

without it humans collectivise; if anarchists believe in humans’ ability

to self organise, they must believe in collectivism.

Therefore, anarcho-communism is a practicable and justifiable form of

anarchism, therefore justifying anarcho-communism as the model for an

established anarchist society.

Chapter 2: Problem of defence

Although anarchist societies have historically achieved internal

stability, because anarchist societies are usually destroyed by state

conquest, anarchism seems vulnerable to state aggression. Moreover,

because anarchist theorists haven’t addressed this issue sufficiently,

anarchism’s vulnerability to conquest remains a large obstacle to

anarchism’s viability. If anarchists can’t defend themselves, because

anarchist societies have often faced military aggression, the

survivability of anarchism would be highly doubtful.

Anarchism is often considered a revolutionary philosophy, especially

given the radical demands intrinsic to establishing anarchist society

which would mean the powers of state and capital wouldn’t allow it

(Berkman; 1942; p44-45). However, Marxism’s central critique of

anarchism as a form of revolution, is that because anarchism rejects the

state it can’t survive because the state is necessary to guard against

counter-revolution (Engels; 1974/[1873]; p105). Heeding his warning, in

1917, Lenin seized the state and established central control through the

state (Zurbrugg; 2014; p31-32) to ensure central control of the

revolution. The USSR survived until 1991 (Aron; 2011), much longer than

the Ukrainian anarchists within the USSR (Marshall; 1992; p475); the

anarchists endured for a time, but they were soon crushed by state

power.

Moreover, the communist nations which have survived, Cuba, China,

Vietnam, Laos and North Korea (Porzuki; 2010), are all authoritarian

states under one-party rule (Cote; 2013, Guardian; 2016). Lenin

(1999/[1920]) himself attributed the success of his revolution to the

‘iron discipline’ his party imposed (p30). Given the relative success of

authoritarianism compared to anarchism regarding survival, if a

communist revolution is desirable, it seems this ‘iron discipline’ is

necessary to guard revolution against violent aggression. I will call

the tactic of imposing a centralised authoritarian state to protect

revolution, authoritarian-communism.

However, although authoritarian-communist states have managed to survive

aggression, less can be said beyond this point. Although,

authoritarian-communist societies were able to make huge strides in

industrialisation as in the USSR (Milne; 2006), and Cuba met the basic

needs of their population (Philips; 2012) despite the US embargo (Perez;

1997; p250-251), socialism requires that ‘the means of production’ (MOP)

be handed to the workers (Chomsky; 1986).

These states kept MOP under state ownership as happened with Cuba and

the USSR (Chomsky; 1986, Rosen; 1969) or have become capitalist as

happened with Laos and China (Fuller; 2009, Holmes; 2015). It is

therefore difficult to describe any of these societies as even

socialist, let alone communist. Lenin himself repealed all worker

control when he disempowered the soviets (Chomsky; 1986), bringing them

under centralised control (Zurbrugg; 2014; p31-32). Lenin even admitted

that his industrial policy was a form of state capitalism (Zurbrugg;

2014; p17). Therefore despite achieving survival, these societies have

fallen far short of being viable methods of achieving communism.

On the other hand, in anarchist Spain, the workers themselves seized the

means of production, although usually the more privileged workers such

as technicians, office workers and union activists often maintained more

power (Casanova; 2004; 141), achieving voluntary collectivisation of

industry and agriculture (Marshal; 1993; 463), often abolishing money

entirely (Bolloten; 1991; p66), demonstrating that a modern communist

society can be achieved through anarchism.

Revolutionaries are therefore left in a quandary, do they advocate for a

society which achieves ideals of equality and freedom, but is likely

doomed to be destroyed when invaded? Or compromise when needed, and

embrace social structures which will likely ensure survival, but have

consistently failed at achieving of the revolution’s ideological aims?

This problem can be mitigated if anarchist societies can effectively

defend themselves. Given that we have shown that anarchism can create

communist social relations, demonstrating that anarchist society can

survive counter-revolutionary aggression, would then provide a social

theory which is both defensible and can achieve its ideals.

However, if anarchism cannot withstand this criticism, anarchism in

modern times would be highly discredited, as it would be unachievable.

Therefore, justifying an anarchist society’s defensive capability is

essential for the continuation of anarchism as a meaningful form of

revolutionary social theory. However, if anarchism can be shown to be

defensible it will provide a vital rebuttal against one of the most

neglected and possibly most powerful criticisms of anarchism, making

addressing this problem, a vital component in defending anarchism as a

viable revolutionary theory.

Because authoritarian-communism is a strategy which has proven

relatively successful at defending itself against aggression, anarchism

would therefore be defensively viable if it can prove more, or just as

defensible as authoritarian-communism. Therefore to demonstrate

anarchism’s defensibility, I will analyse whether anarchist structures

can be at least as defensible as authoritarian-communist structures.

Chapter 3: Anarchist institutions

3.1: Coordination under anarchism

To determine what strategies are available to anarchism, its

institutional forms must be elucidated, this will determine how

anarchism organises, and therefore what is possible under anarchist

structures. I will begin by outlining the economic organisation of

anarchism and apply this model to defence forces.

An established anarcho-communist society’s economic structure would be

based in common ownership of MOP, namely land, natural resources,

factories etc, and organised politically, based on voluntary association

governed by mutual-aid principles. Collective ownership means industry

would be organised collectively and principles of free agreement means

these industries would be run direct-democratically. To facilitate

direct-democracy these collectives are decentralised with production

being locally based.

Although association is localised, larger scale anarcho-communist

organisation would be possible through federalisation, this can be

achieved through worker committees. Different communities appoint their

own delegates to create advisory committees in order to coordinate

larger-scale organisation (Berkman; 1942; p72-73).

These committees have no power beyond those granted by the local

communities; committees advise on coordination and collaboration, but

have no enforcing power. Committees could then collaborate with other

committees of the same nature by creating their own larger committees

(Murphy; 2006/[1917]). These committees could then be formed at as large

a scale as desirable meaning no upper limits to cooperation. However,

these committees, no matter how large, still have no independent

authority; they still only operate based on consent from below.

Therefore, large-scale organisation can be achieved without the need for

centralised authority, therefore making these structures compatible with

anarcho-communism.

Conversely, military structures have historically been hierarchical

command structures where power is concentrated at the top with strict

discipline and obedience demanded from those below. These structures are

diametrically opposed to anarchism’s decentralised and democratic

nature, embracing elements of command structures has therefore been

problematic for anarchists.

For example, although there was some democratisation of the anarchist

forces in CataluĂąa (Marshall; 1993; p461), and Ukraine (p474), in

Ukraine, because the army wasn’t directly accountable to the population,

it often behaved dictatorially, like a band of warrior chiefs (p474).

This would have antagonised the society it was supposed to protect as

they had established aspects of communal self rule (p473-474). In

CataluĂąa, after the anarchist leaders allowed anarchist militias to be

brought under the central control of the government, the anarchists were

greatly demoralised (p465), this would have harmed the war effort given

the importance of morale. It also marked the end of the revolution,

causing the revolution to survive for less than a year (465–466).

The centralised nature of militaries clearly harms combat effectiveness

and general ability to defend a society when adopted by anarchists and

should therefore be avoided. Moreover, anarchist forces must be

answerable to their communities, thus preventing militias from becoming

antagonistic towards the society as a whole, while keeping power in the

community’s hands. Structures more compatible with anarchist principles

must therefore be established.

3.2: Mutual-Aid Militia

The method of decentralised large-scale organisation in industry

previously discussed, can be applied to defence forces. I will call

these decentralised forces, Mutual Aid Militia (MAM). Engel’s

(1974/[1873]) asserted that anarchism was impossible because complex

organisation requires coordination, which in turn requires authority

(p102-104). This logic applies to fighting forces because to fight as a

whole, fighters need to strictly coordinate action, which implies the

need for a command structure. However, Engels’ assertions are based on

misrepresenting anarchism. Anarchism rejects political authority, but

not authority of expertise. Bakunin (1999/[1871]) differentiates

political authority which is imposed by an external agent, and the

authority of “specialists”, whose expertise is followed by choice and

reason. Commanders can coordinate forces, but this role isn’t

un-anarchist unless they are imposed coercively.

If commanders are given decision making capabilities through appointment

by the collective, the fighters themselves recognise the need for the

expertise and coordination commanders provide. Therefore, the role is

justifiable under Anarchism. Therefore, much like in CataluĂąa,

militia-fighters would appoint their own commanders (Marshall; 1993;

p461).

Directly appointing commanders will be implemented whenever feasible,

with smaller units combining to appoint higher ranking officers.

However, the fact that large-scale decentralised organisation under

anarchism seemingly requires appointing committees at a certain level,

highlights that direct-democracy isn’t practicable once coordination

becomes large enough. Therefore militia structures need to create their

own committee structures for larger scale coordination.

Therefore, once these direct-democratic units require larger scale

coordination, each unit can elect a delegate(s) to represent them,

delegates would then form a strategic committee, this committee will

then advise on larger scale strategy. Delegates could also appoint their

own commander amongst themselves within committees when quick decisions

need to be made. When even larger coordination is needed, committees can

coordinate with other committees to form higher order committees. Much

like workers committees, higher order committees can expand to as large

a scale as needed, allowing for coordination on as large a scale as

needed.

Committees, even their commanders, being appointed to advise on

coordination, don’t have the same powers as the unit commanders as they

aren’t as directly accountable given the limits of direct-democracy.

Therefore, unit commanders retain autonomy on whether to heed the advice

of the committee, therefore maximising the power of the troops on the

ground by delegating autonomy to the most accountable agents.

It follows however, from their role as larger scale coordinators, that

committees occupy a position where they can comprehend events on a

larger scale. Therefore, they are in a better position to determine

whether to scale up coordination. Therefore, the committees have the

freedom to form larger committees, given that they are in the best

position to make a sound judgement regarding this. However, this ability

doesn’t translate to a centralisation of power; committees don’t have

ultimate power of command, as discussed, the directly appointed unit

commanders retain this role and maintain the power to ignore these

committee, therefore allowing for effective large-scale coordination

without creating centralisations of power.

Because I have outlined structures where large-scale coordination is

enabled whilst retaining bottom-up power, I have outlined combat

structures which both adhere to anarchist principles whilst enabling the

scale of coordination needed for effective defence while avoiding the

problem of forcing fighters under central control as was found in

CataluĂąa.

However, these militia must also be accountable to the community to

prevent them from repeating the chieftain behaviour as in Ukraine.

Luckily, because under anarcho-communism all is owned collectively, the

means militia have of fighting is in the hands of the population at

large. Fighters need guns and bullets and vehicles etc to fight. It

follows that the society who owns these things must permit use of these

resources in order for forces to fight. Therefore, it follows that to

fight, these militias must gain the consent of their local communities.

If the militia then misbehave, their power to fight can be revoked,

mitigating the issues found in Ukraine.

3.3: What constitutes survival?

Now the anarchist societies defence structures are outlined, I will

determine what successfully defending the society entails. This research

examines an anarchist society’s ability to survive external aggression,

this assumes scenarios where the society is being invaded by outside

forces which threaten to destroy the society. Because historically,

anarchist societies have been destroyed by states imposing sovereignty,

I will assume the aggressor is a state imposing state rule over the

anarchist society.

Anarchism has been defined as a stateless social structure which

dismantles illegitimate hierarchy in pursuit of freedom and equality.

Therefore to survive aggression, an anarchist society must retain its

independence from external state control (conquest). It must also resist

developing authoritarian structures internally; even if anarchists

repels the aggressor state, if anarchists must develop authoritarian

social relations to achieve this, thus dissolving the libertarian

institutions discussed, the society has ceased to be anarchist, meaning

the anarchist society still hasn’t survived.

Therefore, an anarchist society only survives aggression when it has:

Chapter 4: How to assess anarchist defence

4.1: Isolating anarchism

Now that anarchism’s survival criteria are established, I must determine

how to assess anarchism’s ability to meet these criteria. I previously

established that anarchist societies would prove defensible if they were

capable of being equally as defensible as authoritarian-communism. I am

also discussing anarchism in a generalised theoretical sense. Therefore

examining both anarchism’s and authoritarian-communism’s impact on

defence strategy, means examining both these structures in isolation,

abstracting them from other determining factors which could impact

strategic performance.

This is necessary because as Howard highlights, military success is

determined by many factors including logistics, operational,

technological etc, which are separate from social factors (Baylis &

Wirtz; 2002; p5); any of these factors could have caused the defeat of

previous anarchist societies. To determine whether it was anarchism

itself which doomed these societies, the impact of social structure on

defence must be examined separately from these other potential factors.

Examining how each of these social structures in-and-of-themselves

contribute to defensive strategy will therefore allow me to determine

which social structures facilitate better strategy, and therefore which

holds the most defensive advantage.

Comparing anarchism and authoritarian-communism in every possible

context is impossible, to have a comprehensive account of how these

social structures compare, I must establish in a broad theoretical

manner, the fundamental factors which determine strategic success in any

and every conflict. Examining how both anarchism and

authoritarian-communism contribute to these fundamental factors will

allow me to determine in a broad generalised sense, which social

structure best guarantees defensive success.

4.2: Core dimensions of strategy

Gray (1999) outlines 17 core dimensions for strategic success in any and

every military conflict (p17). He then splits these into three

categories, people and politics, war preparation, and war proper (p24).

Considering the sweeping claim that these dimensions cover every

conflict, Gray’s theory that there are core strategic dimensions to

every conflict could be questioned, however, due to restrictions, I will

not be able to support his theory directly.

However, using a theoretical model which asserts core dimensions of

strategy allows for the broad and generalised criteria required to

sufficiently address the research questions. I will therefore assume the

veracity of Gray’s theory of core strategic dimensions. Other notable

theorist on strategy have included, Sun Tzu and Clausewitz (Stevens &

Baker; 2006; p27-29), meaning there are multiple frameworks to chose

from. However, I chose Gray’s theory because he comes from a

contemporary context, allowing his theories to be better applied to a

modern context. Moreover, his 17 dimensions are very comprehensive

whilst also being manageable within the research’s constraints.

These 17 dimensions are as follows (Gray; 1999; p24):

Administration, Information and Intelligence, Strategic Theory and

Doctrine, Technology.

and Uncertainty, Adversary, Time.

To determine which social structure is superior regarding each

dimension, I will first briefly describe the nature of the dimension and

then interpret from this description, the general requirements needed

from these structures to best guarantee strategic success in a defensive

context. I will then examine how each structure responds to this need.

Whichever structure best contributes to effectiveness in a given

dimension, enjoys a strategic defensive advantage in regard to that

dimension.

As discussed, anarchism has two survival criteria, 1) independence from

external states, 2) maintaining anarchist structures internally. Because

authoritarian-communism requires the establishment of a sovereign

centralised state, it shares the first criterion but not the second, to

preserve its structure, it must instead retain state rule over the

society. Both social structures therefore have different imperatives

when ensuring their own survival.

Therefore, I will address each society’s ability to ensure its internal

structure (criterion 2) and how this impacts defensibility, when

examining politics, as this dimension is well suited to this issue.

Otherwise, each social structure’s ability to retain its internal

structure will be assumed because if an anarchist society is indeed

capable of for example, effective organisation aimed at repelling

invasion, it will be because the organisation is done through anarchist

structures, which assumes the structures survival and likewise for

authoritarian-communism.

Moreover, if when defending a society, anarchist structures are more

effective at repelling invasion, there is no reason to assume

authoritarian structures will emerge in response to aggression because

it will only harm the war effort if the society opts for less

advantageous social structures. Therefore, success in criterion 1)

implies success in criterion 2). Therefore, the other dimensions will

only focus on effectiveness in criterion 1).

Therefore, the other dimensions will only focus on each structures’

ability to effectively repel an aggressor. Therefore, what is needed to

effectively perform in these dimensions remains very simple, because all

that is needed is the ability to ensure a strong defensive response

through the already existing social structures.

For example, regarding people, each structure must guarantee a healthy

population (Gray; 1999; p26-27) to ensure a strong defence, whichever

structure is best suited to meet this need, has the advantage.

Which factors determine success is contextual, in one conflict geography

might be the determining factor, in another, it may be organisation; for

anarchism to be a strategically advantageous social structure in a

general sense, it must at least match authoritarian-communism in all

dimensions. If anarchism has advantages regarding some dimensions but

disadvantages elsewhere when compared to authoritarian-communism, it is

only a viable social structure in certain contexts, making generalised

conclusions impossible. Therefore, for anarchism to be considered

generally as viable or even superior to authoritarian-communism

regarding defence, anarchism needs to be either advantageous or at least

match authoritarian-communism in all 17 dimensions.

Therefore, if anarchist structures beget either advantages or matches in

all categories, because these dimensions cover all conflict, I can

conclude that anarchist structures are in general more defensively

advantageous than authoritarian-communist structures, whilst

consistently matching authoritarian-communism would mean anarchism was

simply as defensible. Because authoritarian-communism’s level of

defensibility acts as a benchmark for adequate defence, if anarchism

achieves the results discussed, it will prove generally defensible.

4.3: What will determine strategic advantage?

As discussed, anarchism’s defensibility is a largely neglected topic;

confirming evidence will therefore be sparse. I must therefore utilise

whatever analytic tools are available. This could include historical

evidence, theoretical reasoning, relevant social studies; ultimately

using any tool available to reach conclusive findings.

For example, if structures exist which are compatible with one of the

social structures and provide important information relevant to one of

the dimensions, this will inform the research. For example, worker owned

industry is compatible with anarchist organisation because they share

the features of collective ownership of MOP (Herbst; 2012), these

structures could be used if they inform strategic advantage for

anarchism in any relevant dimension.

This accommodating approach means objectively quantifiable results will

be largely unavailable, it follows that a degree of interpretation must

be utilised. However, this method will then give the most comprehensive

account possible given the paucity of existing evidence, allowing me to

conclude the research much more fully, therefore making up for the

unavailability of quantifiable certainty.

Part 2: Capabilities — Analysis

Chapter 5: People and politics

5.1: People

A healthy population is required to ensure they sustain the war effort,

this doesn’t just mean having enough people, but also ensuring the

people are healthy (Gray; 1999; p26-27). Therefore, for effective

defence, the social structures must be able to ensure the wellbeing of

the population.

Anarchism would be organised around mutual-aid principles. As discussed,

mutual-aid has been the strategy used by the most numerous and

successful species in ensuring their survival. Kropotkin observed how

cooperation through mutual-aid ensured the survival of many species

through serious hardship. The most advanced human mutual-aid societies,

such as guild cities, shortage was dealt with effectively meaning

starvation was unheard of (Kropotkin; 1902; p182). Therefore, mutual-aid

by design, ensures the sustenance of as healthy a population as

possible. Because anarchism would use mutual-aid as its societal

foundation, anarchism would be adept at maintaining a healthy

population.

Conversely, although authoritarian-communism has often historically

achieved high human development, for example, despite Cuba’s isolation,

it enjoys a very high human development index (Farber; 2015),

populations have often been neglected for development which benefits the

interests of centralised authority. In the USSR in 1932–33, as a result

of Stalin’s forced collectivisation and industrialisation, millions of

peasants starved (Goodman; 1986). This demonstrates that while both

structures are designed to ensure collective wellbeing,

authoritarian-communism has a tendency to neglect this issue when the

interests of the state conflict with the wellbeing of the population,

while anarchism exhibits no such deficiency, giving the advantage to

anarchism.

5.2: Society

War is carried out through social institutions (Gray; 1999; p27-28),

these social institutions comprise the society and must support

defending the society in order to repel an invasion. Anarchism as

discussed has numerous autonomous and interconnected institutions,

assessing how each one and the free individuals within them would react

to aggression is impossible given the research’s constraints.

However, as discussed, although anarchism functions through free

association, its reliance on mutual-aid makes anarchism a complex

system; the connections within the society form a coherent whole which

can be observed as a totality. We can therefore observe how anarchist

societies as a whole would respond to aggression without needing to

explain the sum of its parts.

Mutual-aid/non-state societies respond to aggression with resistance in

many different contexts. Tribes in Europe formed confederacies for

mutual defence (Kropotkin; 1902; p112), guild cities hired militia for

self-defence (p180-181). We can therefore assume that an anarchist

society as a whole would resist aggression.

Moreover, resistance from decentralised non-state societies has often

been very difficult to crush. The Aztecs, being a centralised

authoritarian society were crushed very quickly by the Spanish; their

ability to fight was destroyed following the capture of their leader.

Because their institutions relied on a very small set of leaders, the

society was vulnerable when leaders were eliminated, therefore making

resistance through centralised leadership a liability.

Conversely, the Mapuche organised in a decentralised, self-governing

manner and void of such liable leaders, were able to keep fighting for

300 years. Their decentralisation was a huge benefit because the society

as a whole could support the resistance; the whole society (complex

system), had to be crushed as opposed to a select few leaders. Because

anarchist structures rely on these decentralised complex systems, their

institutions’ ability to sustain resistance are much greater.

By comparison, authoritarian-communism is defined through centralisation

of power, this would therefore make authoritarian-communism vulnerable

to the elimination of their leaders. Moreover, centralising power under

state control has historically meant eliminating community owned

self-governing institutions, such as when Lenin disempowered the

worker-controlled soviets. This then eliminates the same self-governing

decentralised relations the Mapuche utilised to sustain such a prolonged

resistance. This means that authoritarianism requires the construction

of highly vulnerable social institutions and the elimination of

institutions capable of strengthening the society.

Therefore, anarchism, being based on decentralisation, creates

institutions capable of less vulnerable, sustained resistance, whilst

authoritarian-communism means the elimination of these advantages in

pursuit of power. Therefore, anarchist social structures have a strong

advantage when creating institutions which support defence.

5.3: Culture

All strategic behaviour is entrenched in a cultural context, culture

being the values and attitudes which inform strategy (Gray; 1999;

p28-29). Culture therefore influences strategic behaviour; this

influence creates a strategic culture (p129). Strategic culture

therefore frames how a society interprets strategy . Therefore, for an

effective defence, a society’s strategic culture must be capable of

influencing good strategic decisions.

Authoritarian-communism has been largely shaped by Marxism-Leninism, and

has therefore had a huge impact on the Soviet Union’s culture and

strategic behaviour (Gray; 1999; p143). Marxism-Leninism’s rigid

understanding of history lead the Comintern to initially view fascism as

simply a stage of capitalism. The Comintern used this as a means of

attacking social-democrats whilst assuming that fascism would collapse

by itself through its own contradictions. This meant the USSR failed to

articulate a mass line against capitalism by alienating potential allies

(Kitchen; 1976; p1-11). This contributed to the USSR’s failure to

adequately prepare for fascist aggression, supporting Gray’s (1992)

claim that Russia’s strategic culture nearly caused the USSR’s collapse

in 1941–42 (p147). This demonstrates how the ideological rigidity

produced by authoritarian-communist culture can lead to serious

strategic disadvantage.

In contrast, some anarchist cultures exhibit remarkable strategic

flexibility entrenched in cultural practice. Certain upland south-east

Asian cultures utilised practices which were designed to resist state

power (Scott; 2009), from shifting cultivation (swiddening) in

agriculture, which helps people evade state control because sedentary

agriculture helped bring populations under state control (p77-78), to

mythologies cautioning the dangers of centralised power (p176-177), to

maintaining a society’s linguistic differences from a nearby state or

event adopting linguitic differences to maintain distance from states

(p173-174). These practices demonstrate how none-state societies can

invent ingenious strategies of state avoidance directly through an

anti-state culture, demonstrating notable strategic adaptation through

culture itself as opposed to the dangerous rigidity governing

authoritarian-communist culture. Therefore, anarchism can create a more

advantageous strategic culture than under authoritarian-communism.

5.4: Politics

War is a political tool, meaning it is used to achieve policy (Gray;

1999; p29-30, p55); a war is harder to win when fought in pursuit of

difficult policy. Therefore to be strategically effective, the policy

goals of defending a society must be as realisable as possible.

Both social structures share the first policy goal of repelling

invasion. However, authoritarian-communism must also impose its own

sovereignty. Authoritarian-communism is a revolutionary and therefore

liberator movement; it must achieve certain liberations such as

achieving some economic and gender equality (Zurbrugg; 2014; p21, p26),

whilst also suppressing the population under authoritarian rule.

This is difficult to balance because revolutions as Chomsky

(2012/[1989]) states, are generally spontaneous and libertarian, making

mobilising through ‘iron discipline’ difficult because the population is

likely imbued with a libratory spirit. Lenin faced two rebellions

seeking further freedoms, the Ukrainian anarchists as discussed

previously, but also the Kronstadt rebellion, sailors integral to the

revolution who mutinied in demand for democracy (Marshall; 1993;

p476-477). This demonstrates how revolutionary authoritarian movements

create contradictions, simultaneously fostering libratory feeling which

are then suppressed. This as seen provokes rebellion, therefore

fostering internal disunity. This disunity forces the state to lose

cohesion and spend energy crushing rebellions, which then makes

defending the society from potential external threats harder, because

the state has less energy and resources committed to external defence,

thus harming the state’s defensive capability.

Anarchist societies such as CataluĂąa also saw internal political moves

harm the society, as discussed the CNT leaders collaboration with the

state virtually destroyed the revolution. However, this was due to the

CNT leaders collaborating with state power and therefore failing to be

consistently anarchist. The provocation and then suppression of

rebellions by the Soviet state was entirely consistent with

authoritarian-communism’s contradictory roles of liberator and

suppressor, making internal strife much more intrinsic to

authoritarian-communism than to anarchism.

Anarchist societies conversely, must resist internal state formation,

which many anarchist societies deal with effectively. Anthropological

studies show that in non-state societies, power-seeking behaviours where

members attempt to establish power over the society do exist, but that

the societies are capable of responding to this quickly and effectively.

One account documents how a Pygmy tribal member attempting to gain

privileged access to resources and chief status is halted and the

society democratically decides to punish him. Not only is this behaviour

dealt with quickly and effectively, this behaviour is rare for this

society (Johnson; 2015).

The fact that these society rarely face these internal threats, yet can

deal with them so effectively when they arise, shows why mutual-aid

societies lasted for centuries and required external state conquest to

destroy them.

Anarchist societies therefore enjoy much more internal stability than

authoritarian-communism, making anarchism’s secondary goal of retaining

internal social structure more achievable than under

authoritarian-communism, which suffers inherent internal contradictions

not shared by anarchism. Therefore in respect to when policy goals

differ, anarchism’s imperatives are less demanding and therefore more

achievable, giving anarchism the advantage regarding politics.

5.5: Ethics

For a war to be won, it helps if the population are ethically motivated

to support it (Gray; 1999; p30-31). Therefore, to defend a society, the

population must be ethically motivated in defending the social

structures under attack.

Mutual-aid principles have historically been the main way humans have

ensured the survival of the collective, being essential during crises

such as droughts or famines. Kropotkin also observed how mutual-aid

societies are often governed by strict moral codes aimed at supporting

the society. For example the Aleoutes always feed their children first

during protracted scarcity and are not inclined towards theft

(Kropotkin; 1902; p99-100). The evolutionary success of mutual-aid

through strong moral conviction towards ensuring society’s survival

during crisis, (for example how the guild cities managed to prevent

famine during shortages), indicates that a society governed by these

principles would be highly motivated when resisting such an extreme

existential threat such as invasion. Mutual-aid would therefore be an

ideal moral force in motivating the population to fight for its

survival. These advantages, because anarchism would be based on

mutual-aid, would also benefit anarchists.

High motivation and ethical conviction has also been observed in

anarchists by Hobsbawm (2007), believing they shown ‘deeply moving

idealism and heroism’ (p112). This also suggests that when defending a

society against a state, anarchists would show remarkable moral

conviction.

Authoritarian revolutions often saw very high popular support. The

Vietnam war could have only been won if the fighters had the support of

the population (Hobsbawm; 2007; p226-227). If support was lost, the

peasants could have informed the USA of the Vietnamese locations (p226),

and they would have been destroyed. However, authoritarian social

relations implicitly indicate a lack of needed morale.

When fighting to secure Bolshevik power in the Russian civil war,

Trotsky (1920) described humans as naturally lazy, requiring coercion to

force the population to work. Conversely, mutual-aid societies lacked

the need for centralised control to motivate individuals. Folkmotes, for

example only enforced decisions based on their moral authority

(Kropotkin; 1902; p131), not needing coercion to motivate its members to

obey their decisions. Therefore, Trotsky requiring coercion to motivate

the population demonstrates a lack of popular support; if the population

fully supported the war effort, they would be motivated enough not to

appear so lazy that they needed coercion. Ultimately, this contrast

highlights authoritarian-communisms’ ethical shortcomings.

If self-governing humans don’t need centralised force to motivate them

to support a cause, the need for coercion highlights the lack of support

that a cause enjoys. Therefore, if it is necessary to achieve “iron

discipline” before a cause is achieved, that cause mustn’t enjoy as much

ethical support as causes where force isn’t needed to achieve them.

Therefore, calls for authoritarianism to achieve revolution implicitly

admit that said revolution lacks a certain amount of ethical support

which anarchist societies can readily rely on.

Anarchist societies can therefore expect more ethical support than

authoritarian-communist societies, because authoritarian-communism

feeling the need to resort to coercion to achieve its goals, implies an

ethical deficit. Anarchism as discussed, has exhibited high levels of

ethical conviction, motivating the society to pursue its goals without

coercion. Therefore anarchism enjoys an ethical advantage.

Chapter 6: War Preparations

6.1: Economics and Logistics

To support a war, the economy must be productive enough to materially

support the effort (Gray; 1999; p31-32), these materials must then reach

their needed destination. Therefore, social structures must support a

productive economy with logistical efficiency.

Regarding economics, some studies show worker owned industries are often

more productive than under traditional structures (Chen; 2016, Dolack;

2016, Harvey; 2016, Logue & Yates; 2006). Because anarchism has achieved

worker ownership of the means of production, this would explain why the

voluntary collectives in anarchist Spain, who achieved worker ownership,

increased production both in industry and agriculture (Dolgof; 1974;

p6), demonstrating that anarchist structures are beneficial to economic

productivity.

As discussed, authoritarian-communism has historically failed to achieve

worker ownership of industry. Moreover, worker-ownership was prevented

when Lenin brought the workers councils under centralised state control.

The fact that these structures of worker-ownership were disempowered in

pursuit of centralisation, indicates that not only has

authoritarian-communism historically failed to achieve worker control,

its need for centralisation of power make authoritarian-communism

intrinsically hostile to worker-ownership. Therefore,

authoritarian-communism cannot enjoy the advantages gained through

worker-owned structures.

Moreover, after 10 years under centralised Soviet rule the workers were

observed to be ‘docile, backwards and incapable of action’ (Zurbrugg;

2014; p27), demonstrating the comparative failures regarding industrial

effectiveness under authoritarian-communism. Moreover, the forced

agricultural collectivisation under Stalin failed to produce the grain

needed to feed the whole population as discussed whereas comparatively,

guild cities faced shortages but famine’s were avoided. This

demonstrates how economic output is greatly aided by anarchist

structures and can be greatly harmed by authoritarian-communism.

Logistics also benefits greatly from decentralised networked relations;

modern logistics firms have usually embraced network organisation.

Rather than compete with other firms within a supply chain, firms have

decided to collaborate, sharing information which increases innovation.

This then increased competitive advantage and performance through

learning from best practice (Chapman et al.; 2002; p366-368). Learning

from other’s practice necessitates decentralisation; when organisation

is centrally controlled, practice is homogenised. Therefore new, better

practices are less likely to emerge under centralisation. Therefore,

these benefits couldn’t be achieved under the hierarchical centralised

structures of authoritarian-communism.

However, Spanish anarchists exhibited similar collaboration between

experts and workers. Both consulted one another when proposing project

ideas, sharing information the others lacked (Zurbrugg; 2014; p24), to

determine the best approach. This demonstrates how anarchists can also

achieve this form of network collaboration and therefore demonstrates

the advantages of anarchism regarding logistics.

6.2: Administration

For effective armed forces, effective day-to-day management of resources

and people is required (Gray; 1999; p34-35). Therefore, for effective

defence, social structures must create effective administrative

structures.

Within industry, administrative systems based on collective decision

making have attracted interest because of their potential to mitigate

efficiency problems related to traditional capitalist hierarchies

(Cheney et al.; 2014; p595). For example, collaborative leadership,

where workers are active in management, has shown promise for

organisations facing scarcity (p596). This is very important for

militia, as they need to manage resources efficiently to support a war

effort.

Social leadership, where managers are appointed by workers, allows for

the selection of managers who work towards the collective’s interests.

This ensures more ethical leadership, which then promotes a sense of

satisfaction and meaningfulness; and increases ‘psychological

ownership’, where workers feelings of “efficacy, accountability and

belongingness” increases their effectiveness through motivation (Cheney

et al.; 2014; p595-596). The MAM’s, who like the Spanish anarchist

militia, collectively appoint leadership, have a suitable structure for

adopting this practice. MAM’s could therefore appoint other leaders such

as trainers and other administrators in a similar fashion to create

better motivated and more effective and efficient forces.

Therefore, anarchist structures could easily utilise these advantageous

administrative models. Authoritarian-communism however, because of its

centralised nature, must rely on the less effective authoritarian

management models. Lenin implement Taylorist labour relations,

empowering the managers and disempowering workers (Zurbrugg; 2014; p27),

which then contributed to the ineffectiveness of the Soviet workforce

previously discussed. Therefore, because anarchism can utilise more

effective administration, anarchism gains the advantage in this

dimension.

6.3: Organisation

Relying on the genius of individuals means strategy could be compromised

by individual incompetence (Gray; 1999; p33-43). Therefore, strong

institutional structures are needed to act as a check on this individual

incompetence. Therefore, effective defence requires structures which

ensure ineffective members are checked.

This institutional fool-proofing is aided by MAM’s collective power;

when leaders are incompetent, MAM’s can remove them. However,

authoritarian structures by definition centralise power into fewer

hands, ensuring the strategy is much more reliant on the abilities of

individuals. For example, when Stalin, against the advice of his

generals, failed to properly prepare for a German attack; when Germany

attacked in 1941, Russia suffered massive military losses. Stalin then

retired to his room for three days (Admin; 2011). The USSR was forced

into disaster and then left leaderless.

This demonstrates authoritarianism’s extreme vulnerability regarding

individual incompetence, therefore anarchist structures hold

organisational advantage because anarchism does not share the extreme

disadvantages of authoritarianism-communism.

6.4: Intelligence and Information

Intelligence is important to a war effort (Gray; 1999; p35). If a

military can attack without warning, the enemy will be ill prepared to

respond, making success more likely. Conversely, if one gather’s

intelligence on the enemy, they can effectively prepare for attack or

attack them at their weakest. Therefore when defending against invasion,

one should conceal their activities and uncover the intentions and

abilities of the enemy.

The democratic nature of anarchism implies higher transparency which

makes secretiveness difficult because more people are privy to more

information. However, within mutual-aid societies can social rules which

can strictly govern behaviour when the need arises, as seen in

Kropotkin’s observations of Aleoutes. These strict social rules are

found amongst hunter-gatherers, smaller intimate groups. Therefore

secretiveness could be achieved within smaller MAM units.

Although larger scale operations may be more difficult to conceal for

anarchists, these disadvantages are balanced by the ability of

decentralised organisations to be very difficult to predict. Al Qaida

has planned attacks through a ‘complex constellation of different

groups’ and cells are often forged through kin relationships and

friendship (Ranstorp; 2005; p41), namely horizontal free agreement, this

can make them very hard to monitor (p41) due to their complex

decentralised structure.

MAM’s can imitate these structures, relying on horizontal unit-to-unit

planning because smaller units retain autonomy, therefore, as under Al

Qaida, MAM’s would be difficult to predict. Because authoritarianism

relies on centralised control, this type of evasive networking is not as

much of an option. Therefore, although authoritarian-communism could

possibly secure traditional top-down secrecy through discipline,

anarchism can achieve alternative forms of effective secrecy unavailable

to authoritarian-communism.

Therefore, both structures have their advantages and disadvantages, yet

none are clearly superior. On balance, anarchism at least doesn’t

exhibit any clear disadvantages compared with authoritarianism regarding

secrecy.

Regarding accessing enemy secrets, decentralised grassroots ‘Hacktivist’

groups such as anonymous, mainly teenagers or unemployed individuals,

have executed numerous raids on large US corporations and the US

government (Caldwell; 2015; p12-13), including leaking around 4,000

documents from the US census bureau (Huffadine; 2016). This means that

non-hierarchical groups of relatively ordinary individuals were able to

gain hidden information from the most powerful state in the world. This

highlights how anarchist structures would be more than capable of

retrieving information about the enemy, showing no clear disadvantage

for anarchism.

Therefore, regarding both secrecy and espionage, anarchism has shown

capability at executing both effectively. Therefore appearing to show no

sign that anarchism is clearly disadvantaged compared to

authoritarianism.

6.5: Technology

Technology is an important dimension of strategy (Gray; 1999; p37-38);

access to equipment which increases military effectiveness through

intelligent design generally aid’s strategic effectiveness. Therefore,

when defending a society, the society should be able to invent

technology which best aids defensive capability. To this end, society’s

social structure would benefit from facilitating technological

innovation.

Mason (2015), states that information-based businesses function best

under network structures. For Mason, ‘cooperative, self-managed,

non-hierarchical teams are the most technologically advanced form of

work’ (p287), whereas hierarchy stifles innovation. Hierarchical

management means managing people, ideas and resources for a planned

outcome (p287). This limits exploration within the confines of the

planned outcome.

The absence of strict planning allows networks to creatively explore new

possibilities, which allows for new and unplanned innovations, therefore

making networks highly innovative. The structures which encourage the

most technological innovation are indeed decentralised, non-hierarchical

cooperative structures, matching anarchist structures perfectly.

Moreover, networks are problematic for authoritarian-communism because

they ‘disrupt everything above’ (Mason; 2015; p288), meaning they would

undermine authoritarian-communism’s hierarchy. This explains why Lenin

embraced Taylorism despite the innovation issues with hierarchies;

networks would have been a threat to centralised power. Therefore,

despite their advantages, networks are dangerous for

authoritarian-communism. Therefore, anarchist structures are better

suited to embracing structures which facilitate innovation and can

therefore better guarantee a technological edge, again giving a strong

advantage to anarchism.

6.6: Strategic theory and doctrine

Strategic theory is the ideas which guide and inform strategic behaviour

(Gray; 1999; p35-36). To defend against aggression, the society must

have structures conducive to the creation of effective theory. This

would require the facilitation of innovation so that the best theories

are enacted. As discussed, network structures facilitate greater

innovation in the economic sphere, and networks are best utilised by

anarchism. Therefore, anarchism would facilitate the most innovative

theories, making anarchism more of an asset for effective strategic

theory.

There is also a need for effective doctrine. Doctrines are the beliefs

that frame strategy by establishing what to think and do (Gray; 1999;

p36). For effective defence, doctrine must frame a strategic outlook

which encourages effective theory and practice. I have already discussed

how Marxist-Leninist dogma restricted the strategic outlook of the USSR

to the extent that they failed to appreciate the threat of NAZI Germany.

This not only permeates through culture, but applies more so to

doctrine; Marxism-Leninism was a belief structure which as discussed

ultimately shaped USSR strategy. Therefore, for the same reason

Marxism-Leninism restricted strategic culture, it restricted Soviet

doctrine. This once again demonstrates how the ideological rigidness of

authoritarian-communism is a strategic liability.

In the same vein, the advantageous cultural practices of some anarchist

societies which demonstrate an effective strategic culture, can be

easily applied to strategic doctrine, because these cultural practices

can also be seen as beliefs and values which guide action, making

anarchism once again advantageous and authoritarian-communism a

liability.

Chapter 7: War Proper

7.1: Military operations

For any successful execution of war, fighters must fight well (Gray;

1999; p38-39). The performance of the Spanish anarchists noted by

Marshall and Dolgof provides evidence that anarchist structures can

create better fighters than if they were under authoritarian structures.

Moreover, contemporary military sociologists highlight the need for

flexible forces to respond quickly to rapid changes in combat

situations. Proposals to achieve this have included reducing hierarchy

(Dedenker; 2003; p415, Bjørnstad & Lichacz; 2011). This means creating

network structures which reducing long chains of command (flat

structure), and giving lower ranks more autonomy (decentralisation). Not

needing to seek permission from a long chain of superiors permits more

efficient information sharing, meaning fighters can achieve faster

responses. Lower-rank autonomy means those more immediately involved in

combat with access to on-the-ground intelligence, can make higher

quality responses. Units would achieve faster, better suited responses,

making the forces more flexible and therefore more effective (Bjørnstad

& Lichacz; 2011; p316-318).

This proposal was tested in training exercises, researchers gave various

units questionnaires asking scaled questions on how the test subjects

perceived a given exercise. Namely, how flat, decentralised, flexible

and effective were each exercise (Bjørnstad & Lichacz; 2011; p319-323).

The results were measured and compared and both flat structure and

decentralisation related positively to flexibility and effectiveness

(p323-326). The links between decentralisation and flatness, and

effectiveness were almost entirely mediated through flexibility

(p326-327), indicating that flatness and decentralisation ensures

effectiveness through flexibility.

Another similar study measuring the relationship between

decentralisation and flatness, and flexibility further supported these

findings, reporting a relationship between flatness and flexibility, and

a stronger positive relationship to decentralisation and flexibility

(Bjørnstad & Lichacz; 2013). This provides evidence that reducing

hierarchy and decentralisation make forces more effective through

flexibility.

However, traditional military structures as discussed, are centralised

and hierarchical, indicating difficulties in adopting these new

structure. Recently, instead of embracing these new processes militaries

have maintained centralisation (Bjørnstad & Lichacz; 2013; p778).

Therefore, authoritarian structures are unlikely to utilise these

advantages.

Moreover, studies of military (Vego, 2003) and civilian (Kvande, 2007)

organisations indicate that retaining some authoritarian features while

loosening others can create misalignment problems. ‘If the structure is

changed from hierarchical to flat at the same time as the

decision-making authority is centralized...’ (Bjørnstad & Lichacz; 2011;

p318), the decision-making load on top management is liable to become

too heavy and render the organization inefficient’. Maintaining

authoritarian-communist structures means maintaining centralisation,

indicating that the suggested network organisations would be unsuitable

for authoritarian-communism. Therefore, authoritarian-communism likely

wouldn’t benefit from network organisational models.

Conversely, MAM’s are highly well-suited to utilising these advantageous

structures. MAM’s are by design, decentralised structures where autonomy

rests at the smaller unit level. MAM’s are already flat, decentralised

structures, allowing for the faster, high quality responses discussed,

without the potential misalignment issues plaguing

authoritarian-communism. Therefore, anarchist structures are able to

fully utilise a more advantageous organisational model for combat

effectiveness unavailable to authoritarian-communism. Therefore in terms

of combat ability, anarchism enjoys the advantage.

7.2: Command

Gray (1999) notes how the quality of command is an important dimension;

effective leaders execute effective strategy. Social structures must

therefore facilitate effective leadership able to exploit advantages and

avoid harm when executing defensive strategy (p39-40).

Firstly, if command is to be effective, command must be followed by

those they command. This may seem problematic for anarchist structures

to achieve, given anarchism’s anti-authoritarian nature. However, as

discussed, Orwell observed that the Spanish anarchist’s could have

improved efficiency without sacrificing their democratic command

structure, indicating the MAM’s similar strategy of collective

appointment of commanders would retain unit cohesion, therefore,

commanders would still be obeyed. Moreover, as discussed, in industry,

leadership being collectively chosen increases senses of belonging and

accountability, which motivates those being lead to support the

organisation and therefore creates more effective leadership. We can

therefore expect the same effects for MAM units.

Moreover, authoritarian-communism as Lenin proposes, requires iron

discipline, strict obedience is required from the rank and file. This

would clearly be required in a military context. Imposing this

discipline means commanders must rely on coercion rather than the

collective sense of ownership and accountability supporting less

hierarchical organisations. This seems less efficient as fighters aren’t

as motivated by a sense of ownership and accountability. Therefore,

anarchist leadership would be both effective and more efficient than

authoritarian-communism.

Leadership must also effectively exploit advantage and avoid harm.

MAM’s, as discussed, would through network organisations, allow lower

ranking commanders to make quicker and more informed decisions.

Therefore, anarchist command would be more effective by allowing those

in the best position to seize an advantage or quickly avoid disaster, to

do so.

Conversely, when authority is too strictly imposed, higher level

commanders who are more distant from the facts on the ground, are freer

to ignore their better informed subordinates. We have already discussed

how Stalin ignored his generals about Hitler’s war preparations meaning

authoritarian-communism has exhibited these deficiencies. This can be

very dangerous, as Gray (1999) notes, it is often vital that low ranking

fighters educate their superiors on events for effective strategy to be

realised (p44-45). Therefore, authoritarian-communism creates structures

that obstruct a commander’s ability to seize advantage and avoid harm.

Therefore, not only can Anarchism establish cohesive leadership more

efficiently than authoritarianism, it also facilitates command which

effectively takes advantage of opportunities and avoiding harm better

than authoritarian structures. Therefore, anarchism holds the advantage

regarding command.

7.3: Geography

Geographic consideration greatly affect military considerations (Gray;

1999; p40-41). To defend against aggression, forces must be able to

utilise the geography to their advantage. Geography varies drastically

from mountains, to flat plains, fields, deserts marshes rivers and even

oceans all play a significant strategic roles based on both their

presence and positioning, but also their absence. There are also manmade

factors to consider, such as cities, oil pipelines etc. An exhaustive

account of how anarchist and authoritarian-communist structures respond

to these variants within this research is impossible. I will therefore

focus on two broad and significant geopolitical considerations anarchist

and authoritarian-communist structures are able to effect, how

infrastructure can be protected, and how well forces can execute

guerrilla warfare.

Authoritarian-communist states have historically shown promise of rapid

industrial development as discussed. However, because these states

retain centralised authority, this means centralised industrial

development where large cities become important industrial centres. This

concentrated industry is easier to manage for centralised authority.

However, this centralisation of industry would make these states

vulnerable to targeted attacks because they present a concentrated

target. This makes industrially developed authoritarian-communist states

vulnerable to bombings, especially a nuclear attack. When used

offensively, nuclear weapons are used for targeting concentrated

industry to cripple a states military industrial capabilities (Hobsbawm;

2007; p235).

In contrast, anarchist societies are decentralised, therefore having

decentralised industry. This would disperse industry, making targeted

attacks which cripple industry much more difficult and resource

intensive. This parallels why nuclear weapons were never used in

Vietnam, as the peasant society was agrarian, which meant the country’s

resources were dispersed (p235). Therefore anarchism’s decentralised

structure allows for the development of industry which is much less

vulnerable to attacks than under authoritarian-communism.

Guerrilla warfare is when irregular smaller units, using local support

and the terrain (Guevera; 2006 ;p32), to their advantage, in order to

engage in indirect conflict to exhaust a stronger enemy (Hobsbawm; 2007;

p224-226). This makes using this technique effectively a great assent

when defending a society. Many factors are important for guerrilla

warfare but two are most worthy of mentioning, flexibility and local

support.

Flexibility is important because small units must be able to quickly

coordinate and execute attacks based on their own initiative (Guevera;

2006 ;p28). This allows guerrillas to repeatedly strike without warning

and retreat before the enemy can respond, slowly exhausting the enemies

political will to fight (Gray; 1999; p43). MAM’s are uniquely structured

to achieve flexibility. As discussed, their effectiveness comes from how

their bottom-up decentralised nature grants effectiveness through

flexibility. Therefore anarchist structures are ideally suited to

guerrilla combat, whereas as discussed, authoritarian-communism’s

centralisation inherently clash with the need for flexibility.

Guevara states that popular support is vital; guerrillas rely on the

population for supplies (Guevera; 2006 ;p95) and to help conceal their

location as discussed. If guerrillas lose support, they risk losing the

supplies needed to continue fighting and having their location known to

the enemy. Guerrillas win through outlasting the enemy through avoiding

direct combat, both of which are impossible to achieve when one loses

their main source of resources and the enemy knows one’s location.

MAM’s only fight when the populace supports them. Therefore, MAM’s are

more intimately accountable to the population, meaning MAM’s are less

likely to antagonise those they rely on. Conversely,

authoritarian-communism, being based in centralised authority, is much

less accountable to the population, meaning decisions which lack popular

support, are more likely to me made. Guevara (2006) emphasises the need

to punish this who harm the peasants (p95), he may be corrent in this

assessment, however this indicates that forces under authoritarian

command are liable to commit these acts. Otherwise this would be less

important to emphasise. Therefore, authoritarian-communism would be less

capable of guaranteeing popular support, whereas through MAM’s,

anarchist structures seem much more capable of guaranteeing this vital

factor.

Therefore, based on the examples discussed, anarchist structures,

because they are more capable of executing core requirements of

guerrilla warfare (flexibility and ensuring popular support), indicates

that anarchists would better utilise geography in combat. Moreover,

because of their dispersed industry, anarchist infrastructure would also

be much better protected. Therefore, anarchism gains the advantages when

exploiting geography.

7.4: Friction, Chance, Uncertainty

In war, things often do not go as planned; a surprise attack or

uncertain weather conditions, can seriously impede defence. Even if one

plans as much as they can, information is never perfect and uncertainty

is certain (Gray; 1999; 41). When fighting a war, social structures must

facilitate adaptation to inevitable surprises.

MAM’s flexible structure accounts for this. When smaller units have more

autonomy in the field, they are able to quickly change their plans and

adapt when things go wrong. I have discussed how smaller units can make

plans quicker and with richer information. Being more informed allows

them to reduce uncertainty and be quick to respond to the unplanned.

MAM’s can therefore adapt to their environment effectively and overcome

friction. As discussed authoritarian-communism’s centrality prevents

this same flexibility, and therefore authoritarian-communist structures

will be slower and less effective when responding to the unplanned.

Therefore, anarchism once again enjoys a strong advantage.

7.5: Adversary

All war is fought against an enemy, whether a strategy is effective

depends on how suitable it is against said enemy. Most importantly, the

enemy is an intelligent wilful force, which responds to ones actions;

‘strategy can work today but fail tomorrow because it worked today’

(Gray; 1999; p42). To effectively defend against invasion, forces must

therefore be able to respond intelligently to the invader.

The flexibility achieved by reducing hierarchy and centralisation, and

the suitability of MAM’s in utilising these techniques, makes anarchists

structures uniquely suited to responding to a responsive enemy. MAM’s

flexibility means anarchists can adapt and change strategy very quickly,

making anarchist forces difficult to quickly respond to. Because I

assume an invasion by a state, the adversary will be hampered by the

obstacles to achieving flexibility through reducing hierarchy previously

discussed. The adversary’s comparative shortcomings regarding

flexibility, and therefore adaptability, mean they will be at a

disadvantage when fighting anarchist forces.

Anarchist structures would therefore often be one step ahead of the

enemy. Moreover, because authoritarian-communism is inherently statist,

it has the same inflexibility problems plaguing traditional militaries,

making it not as suitable at dealing with a responsive enemy as

anarchism. This therefore highlights another significant advantage for

anarchism.

7.6: Time

All strategy is governed by time, attacks can be too early or late.

Geographical distance or rough terrain effects strategy because of the

temporal delays this creates. Ultimately, time is a significant

strategic factor (Gray; 1999; p42-43). Time is also ultimately far too

expensive a topic to cover satisfactorily within the given limits.

Therefore, I will simply examine which social structures best utilise

time during a protracted defence because this is an important factor

during defence; the defenders must therefore outlast an enemy’s attack

to survive.

Gray highlights that time is on the side of irregular (guerrilla) forces

in war, because they can avoid battle and outlast the enemy by sapping

their political will (Gray; 1999; p43). We have already shown that MAM’s

are a better means of engaging in guerrilla warfare because of their

superior flexibility and popular support. It follows that they would

then have a temporal advantage because their flexibility allows them to

better avoid conflict and the increased support better sustains the

forces. Therefore once again anarchism demonstrates its strategic

superiority to authoritarian-communism.

Chapter 8: Discussion

8.1: People and Politics

The People and Politics chapter demonstrates how within all dimensions

pertaining to the abilities of the population as a whole, anarchism

proved more defensively advantageous in all five categories. This is

because without the interference of the state, the population can

directly pursue success in each of the categories, whereas to ensure

state supremacy, authoritarian-communism often obstructs these efforts.

In people, because society without authority follows mutual-aid,

ensuring collective wellbeing holds primacy, allowing the needs of the

population to be pursued directly. Authoritarian-communism being

statist, must put state interests first. This does not mean the state

never cares for the population, but that this imperative is filtered

through state interest. If state interests require that other issues are

prioritised, the population itself could suffer, as demonstrated during

the Soviet famine.

This statist prioritisation becomes more relevant for society because of

the centralisation of power. This may ostensibly be so that the

population can be mobilised to serve the common good. However,

mutual-aid demonstrates how human society is already capable of action.

This political centralisation actually limits the societies ability to

sustain defence through the pursuit of securing centralised power.

Authoritarian-communism renders the populace further incapable of action

by limiting its intellectual potential. Culture highlighted how the

state’s need for control meant rigidly imposing a cultural framework

which bound thought to an extent where the USSR failed to anticipate the

threat of fascism, therefore endangering the society. Conversely,

anarchist cultural expression in itself employed strategically ingenious

methods of guarding against threat.

This popular suppression would explain the contrast between how

motivated mutual-aid societies are compared with authoritarian-communist

society. In ethics, Trotsky’s call for labour armies was based on a

perception of a humanity drastically different from self organised

society. This evidence highlighted how the need for authoritarianism

implicitly concedes that the population is less motivated to action than

they could be. This implicitly indicated that authoritarian-communism

always suffers from a deficit in ethical motivation.

These findings highlight how the population under

authoritarian-communism, because it requires imposing centralised

authority, weakens the society by limiting its capacity to flourish and

act, therefore making the population more vulnerable when under attack.

By pursuing its own interests, authoritarian-communism inherently makes

itself vulnerable in a way anarchist societie do not.

Authoritarian-communism further compounds these troubles by demanding

political goals which are harder to achieve. Authoritarian-communism’s

acts of suppression also antagonises the population it relies on, as

demonstrated by the numerous rebellions the Soviets faced.

Authoritarian-communism must repel an invader, but also maintain its

control over this antagonised society, whereas anarchism’s historical

stability means it is free to focus solely on repelling attackers.

Therefore, authoritarian-communism inherently weakens the population

whilst simultaneously requiring more from said population in order to

survive. Therefore, the finding demonstrate how authoritarian-communism

is a defensive liability in these respects.

8.2: War Preparations

The war preparations chapter demonstrates how the structure of anarchism

permits superior organisational capacity within the MAM’s and in

industry, while the restrictions discussed previously, prevent

authoritarian-communism from utilising these advantages. Five dimensions

proved advantageous to anarchism with a sixth merely matching

authoritarian-communism.

Examining economics and logistics showed how anarchism allows for

popular control which as discussed, enables anarchism to be more

economically productive by mimicking worker-owned industry. Anarchism’s

decentralised nature also allows anarchism to embrace network structures

which facilitate better logistics. Conversely, authoritarian-communism’s

centralisation and aversion to popular control, means these benefits are

not available.

Moreover, in administration, anarchism, once again through popular

control proved capable of more effective and efficient leadership models

which better ensure good day-to-day management of the militia. This is

once again unavailable to authoritarian communism, as

authoritarian-communism requires hierarchical structures which preclude

such models. Moreover in organisation, anarchism through these same

leadership models proved capable of accounting for individual

incompetence therefore better fool-proofing its organisations. This

again is unavailable to authoritarian-communism as its centralised

nature relies too heavily on the ability of a few, mirroring the issues

found in society.

Anarchism’s ability to create non-hierarchical, cooperative organisation

also allowed for superior innovation. Anarchism would facilitate more

advanced technology and strategic theory, this once again being

unavailable to authoritarian-communism due to its hierarchical nature.

Moreover, the advantages discussed pertaining to strategic culture

translated over to strategic doctrine; the same beliefs and values which

permeate culture simultaneously impact doctrine, meaning anarchism

enjoys similar advantages over authoritarian-communism.

The dimension disrupting this trend was information and intelligence. I

suggested that anarchism’s anti-authoritarianism prevented it from

traditional secrecy, and contradicting evidence was only forthcoming for

smaller units, rendering anarchism unlikely to be as secretive on a

large scale. However, this was mitigated by anarchism’s ability to

better pursue non-traditional secrecy by imitating the networks Al Qaida

utilises, meaning that effective strategies for concealing activities

were still available. Moreover, the ability of amateurs in decentralised

groups to infiltrate some of the world’s most powerful organisations,

proved that anarchism would be more than capable of retrieving enemy

information.

Because evidence which provides a comparison between

authoritarian-communism and anarchism was not found, I was unable to

compare the two structures as in other dimensions. However, because

anarchism’s suggested problems can be mitigated by a highly effective,

non-traditional solution, and that the successes of methods available to

anarchism has managed to cause serious problems for Al Qaida’s enemies,

provides strong reasons to infer from the evidence that anarchism would

at least prove formidable in this regard. It is therefore safe to

maintain that anarchism would not be disadvantaged overall in this

regard, meaning the best conclusion to make in this dimension is that

anarchism and authoritarian-communism would at least match one another.

When examining the social structures’ organisational capabilities, it

can be concluded that anarchist models beget a plethora of advantages

unavailable to authoritarian-communism.

8.3: War Proper

The war proper chapter continued the trend of consistent advantages for

anarchist structures, showing that during combat itself,

authoritarian-communisms structural necessities once again disqualify it

from reaping the benefits available for decentralised structures.

This was first demonstrated through military operations. The Spanish

anarchists proved better fighters than many hierarchical factions. Also,

recent findings in military sociology support the superior effects of

decentralisation and reduced hierarchy, on flexibility, and therefore

effectiveness. Anarchism once again proved capable of embracing these

structures due to MAM’s democratic bottom-up structure while

authoritarian-communism would be inherently less capable of utilising

these strengths given the inherent misalignment issues.

This increased flexibility would then make anarchism more capable of

responding to the enemy as found in adversary, and also better equipped

to deal with unplanned contingencies as was shown in Friction, Chance,

Uncertainty.

The practice of selecting leaders, which gave the anarchist society

better leadership in administration, also ensured the same benefits of

motivation would give anarchist structures superior command compared to

authoritarian-communism. Moreover, the bottom-up structure of MAM’s

ensured that the best informed commanders were free to execute the most

appropriate actions, which once again wasn’t available to

authoritarian-communism.

I had to narrow my focus when tackling geography and time due to the

various ways to address the question and the restrictions on this

research. However, what I was free to focus on highlighted significant

and noteworthy advantages for anarchism. Decentralisation of industry,

not only protected anarchist society by ensuring its productive would be

base difficult to disrupt, therefore better protecting industry, it also

proved a very effective tool against the most destructive man-made

weapons, nuclear weapons. This is significant because previously only

under-developed agrarian nations enjoyed this advantage, indicating a

trade-off between industrialisation and vulnerability. Anarchism

provides both protection and development, making this a significant

advantage over authoritarian-communism, whose centralisation guarantees

such a trade-off.

Moreover, guerrilla warfare was very important because it provided an

effective tactic against a stronger enemy. Anarchism’s ability to excel

at two of the most significant aspects of this tactic (popular support

and flexibility), not only provides anarchism with the means to defend

itself against much larger foes, but advantages in geography, and also

time because of the temporal advantages given to irregular troops.

Therefore overall, when comparing anarchism to authoritarian-communism,

anarchism enjoys significant strategic advantages in 16/17 dimensions

whilst being effective enough in the 17^(th) dimension that disadvantage

shouldn’t be assumed. Anarchism as a means of defensive strategy is just

short of being completely superior to authoritarian-communism.

Therefore, because authoritarian-communism acted as the benchmark for a

defensible social structure, the findings show that anarchism far

exceeds my established requirements for being suffinciently capable of

defence against aggression.

8.4: Explaining the failures of anarchism, impact of the research

and suggestions for further research

However, how can these findings be valid given the consistent failure of

anarchism regarding defence?

Firstly, this study assesses comparative advantage, I inquired into

whether when establishing an revolutionary society, should authoritarian

or anarchist social relations govern the society when considering

defence? Because I isolate the effects of social structure, I assess

whether a single given society would be better off against invasion if

they chose anarchism or authoritarianism. Therefore the research

investigates whether for example, Anarchist Spain, would have had a

better chance of survival if it were authoritarian. Therefore, the fact

that it failed while other authoritarian societies succeeded is

irrelevant.

Moreover, the finding provide indications of why these anarchists

revolutions failed outside of an inability to fight due to limitations

inherent to anarchism. Firstly, much like conflicting social relations

can cause misalignment problems for networks, the fact that the

Ukrainian’s and Cataluña embraced some authoritarian relations caused

issues for their war effort. Makno’s antagonism of his population and

the CNT’s collaboration with the state caused issues that wouldn’t have

been possible in a consistently anarchist society. This is why imagining

alternative combat structures were important, because they mitigate

these issues.

Another issue is popular faith and support in anarchism. This study

assumes a society where anarchism is fully established. This assumes the

population already perceives anarchist tactics as viable. However,

anarchism suffers a reputation as unworkable and ineffective. Those such

as Hobsbawm perpetuate this assumption when they describes anarchists as

hopeless and ineffective (p113); more damaging is how anarchists often

contribute to this reputation. The paucity of anarchist work directly

addressing defence is one way this happens. More significant is how

anarchist revolutionaries like the CNT leadership, feel they must resort

to authoritarian tactics, like allowing the anarchists to be brought

under government control, to achieve their goals. If anarchist tactics

are not trusted, they will not be implemented, and therefore will never

be given a chance to succeed.

Conversely, authoritarian tactics enjoy a tacit support because they are

assumed to work. Although Lenin emphasised discipline which implies

coercing the populace regardless of their desires, however popular

support as discussed can also be important. The state’s rule therefore

requires some level of popular consent; the success of authoritarian

tactics therefore indicates at least a tacit support. Combined with the

previous findings, this indicates that the challenge anarchists face is

in establishing a strong base of support, only then would anarchism have

a chance to become a successful social movement. For anarchism to

succeed it must therefore gain this much needed popular support and

faith in its effectiveness, only then will the potential successes found

in this research be realised.

Because anarchism has proved more defensible than

authoritarian-communism in this research, whilst accounting for why this

defensibility is not reflected in the historical record, it can be

concluded that anarchism has proved to be highly defensible when

established, and has therefore defended itself in this regard as a

viable form of revolutionary praxis.

Because this research addresses a very neglected aspect of anarchism,

the finding demonstrating anarchism’ defensibility clearly make a very

large contribution to an important and neglected topic in anarchism.

Following this, because the research focuses on anarchism and its

interaction with neighbouring states, this research on anarchism

directly contributes to international relations theory. This is very

important, firstly, because it makes a contribution to an almost

entirely neglected area of study within international relations theory

(Prichard; 2011). Moreover, this contribution aims at a topic in

international relations which is often the purview of realists (Baylis &

Wirtz; 2002 ;p6), military strategy.

Therefore the research has made headway in establishing anarchist

international relations theory as a body of though which can tackle

issues often only addressed by mainstream international relations.

Therefore, the research helps anarchism make a strong impact on the

larger body of international relations thought. This impact is that

because anarchism can prove defensively viable, that a fully anarchist

society or even several could find a strong footing in international

order. This would be a huge change in global order and provide a very

strong challenge to more state centric international relations theories.

Moreover, because I addressed the issue of defence for anarchists in

juxtaposition authoritarian-communist states’ failure to achieve

socialism while anarchist Spain demonstrated remarkable successes in

this regard, establishing anarchism’s defensive viability therefore

allows this other advantage to pose a more serious challenge to

authoritarian-communism.

Previously, it could be assumed that authoritarian-communism’s failures

in creating true socialism was a necessary trade-off because otherwise

the society couldn’t survive and therefore no gains could be made. Now

that anarchism can demonstrate itself as more defensible that

authoritarian-communism, this paradigm is disrupted, making

authoritarian-communism appear as a much less viable option. Anarchism

can be both defensible and communist, while authoritarian-communism

can’t even claim greater defensibility. Therefore, this research

provides a strong challenge to the viability of authoritarian-communist

revolutionary theories.

However, because this research assumes already established anarchist

societies, the issue of establishing anarchism has been neglected.

Building upon this research means analysing how to best secure the

establishment of such societies in order for these defensively

advantageous qualities of anarchism to be realised. This could be done

by re-raising the issue touched on by Rossdale (2010) surrounding

whether anarchists should emphasise resisting existing structures or

building new ones (p486-492). The right balance regarding this issue

could help anarchist societies gain a much needed foothold within

international order.

Conclusions and limitations

I began by defining anarchism as the dismantling of illegitimate

hierarchy in pursuit of freedom and equality, combining this with the

mutual-aid principle to argue that an established anarchist society

would be anarcho-communist. I then raised the issue that despite

anarchism’s other successes, it has historically proved indefensible

which is problematic when comparing it the more successful revolutionary

strategy of authoritarian-communism. I therefore argued that for

anarchism to be deemed a viable revolutionary theory, anarchism must

prove at least as defensible as authoritarian communism.

I then elaborated on how anarcho-communist principles, when implemented

institutionally create bottom-up decentralised direct-democratic

institutions of free association and applied this model to defence

forces, thus creating MAM’s. Once fully outlined I described how

defending anarchism meant repelling invasion but also preserving its

institutions.

Based on what was previously established, for anarchism to be defensible

it must prove in isolation to hold as much or more strategic advantage

as authoritarian-communism when comparing each structures’ strategic

success in a defensive context when analysed through the paradigm of

Gray’s 17 dimensions. I argued that anarchism would be defensible if it

proved at least a match to authoritarian-communism in all 17 dimensions,

outlining that advantage would be proven based on any available evidence

supported by a degree of interpretation to secure a sufficient analysis.

The finding showed that in 16 of the dimensions anarchism proved more

strategically advantageous which proving effective enough in

intelligence and information to be considered at least a match to

authoritarian-communism. This demonstrated that based on the analysis

that anarchism when established is much more defensible than

authoritarianism. Because authoritarian-communism acted as the benchmark

for defensibility, the fact that anarchism exceeds this in all but one

dimension means the findings provide considerable weight to the claim

that an anarchist society could defend itself against external military

aggression which therefore means in this respect anarchism has proved a

viable form of revolutionary praxis.

A limitation of this research is firstly that because of constraints I

was forced to limit my scope with notable examples being time, where I

was only able to focus on a small aspect of the dimension because of its

scope. The fact that I had to narrow my focus because of the size of the

topic emphasises the need to focus on this dimension. This was further

compounded with geography where once again because of constraints I had

to narrow my focus to two subjects, guerrilla war and infrastructure,

then narrow it again with guerrilla warfare to simply flexibility and

time when there are many other issues worth addressing in that subject

alone. This neglect could cause problems for the research as it may

neglect important points which would alter the findings of this

research. However, this doesn’t prevent the finding discussed from being

significant.

Another limitation is the reliance on Gray’s theories of strategic

dimensions as any issues with this theory would pose problems for the

research finding. The research would have benefited from gaining the

space to fully critically assess Gray’s theory to fully determine

whether the theory was completely sound. However, given the finding

achieved through this paradigm mitigates the heavy reliance on this

theory.

Bibliography

Admin [author not named]. (2011). Stalin’s Breakdown. Available:

www.historyinanhour.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Alexander, R (1999). The Anarchists in the Spanish Civil War, Volume 1.

London: Janus Publishing Company . p254.

Anarcho [alias]. (2008). Mutual Aid: An Introduction and

Evaluation.Available:

anarchism.pageabode.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Aron, L. (2011). FEATURE Everything You Think You Know About the

Collapse of the Soviet Union Is Wrong. Available:

foreignpolicy.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Bakunin, M. (1999/[1871]). What is Authority?. Available:

www.marxists.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Barma, N. (2017 [last viewed, date not given]). Failed State. Available:

www.britannica.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Berkman, A (1942). A.B.C of Anarchism. 2^(nd) ed. London: Freedom Press.

p3-101.

Bjørnstad, A ; Lichacz, F. (2011). Exploring Network Organization in

Military Contexts: Effects of Flatter Structure and More Decentralized

Processes. Military Psychology. 23 (3), p315-31.

Bjørnstad, A, L. Lichacz, F, M, J. (2013) “Organizational flexibility

from a network organizational perspective: A study of central predictors

and moderating factors in military contexts”, Leadership & Organization

Development Journal, Vol. 34 Issue: 8, pp.763–783,

Bolloten, B, (1991). The Spanish Civil War: Revolution and

Counterrevolution. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina. p66.

Caldwell, T. (2015). Hacktivism Goes Hardcore. Network Security. 2015

(5), p12-17.

Casonova, J (2004). Anarchism, the Republic and Civil War in Spain:

1931–39. 2^(nd) ed. London: Routledge. p99-158.

Chapman, Ross L., Soosay, Claudine and Kandampally, Jay 2002, Innovation

in logistic services and the new business model : a conceptual

framework, Managing service quality, vol. 12, no. 6, pp. 358–371.

Chen, M. (2016). Worker Cooperatives Are More Productive Than Normal

Companies. Available:

www.thenation.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Cheney, G. Santa Cruz, I. Peredo, A, M. Nazareno, E. (2014). Worker

cooperatives as an organizational alternative: Challenges, achievements

and promise in business governance and ownership. Organisation. 21 (5),

p591-602.

Chomsky, N. (1986). The Soviet Union Versus Socialism. Available:

chomsky.info

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Chomsky, N. (1995). Noam Chomsky on Anarchism, Marxism & Hope for the

Future. Available:

www.ditext.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Chomsky, N. (2000). Globalization and its Discontents Noam Chomsky

debates with Washington Post readers. Available:

chomsky.info

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Chomsky, N. (2012/[1989]). What Was Leninism?, March 15^(th), 1989

(.Available:

www.youtube.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Cote, R. (2013). The Five Remaining Communist Countries. Available:

www.therichest.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Dandeker, C. (2003). Building Flexible Forces for the 21^(st) Century:

Key challenges for the contemporary armed services. In: Caforio, G

Handbook of the Sociology of the Military. New York: Plenum Publishers.

p415.

Dawkins, R (2006). The Selfish Gene. 30^(th) anniversary ed. New York:

Oxford University Press. p.viii.

Dolack, P. (2016). Working Collectively Beats Working for a

Boss.Available:

www.counterpunch.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Dolgof, S (1974). The Anarchist Collectives. Quebec: Black Rose Books.

p6-7.

Engels, F. (1974/[1873]). On Authority. In: Bean, B. Daglish, R. and

Ryanzanskaya, S, W. Marx, Engels, Lenin: Anarchism and

Anarcho-Syndicalism. 2^(nd) ed. Moscow: Progress Publishers. p102-105.

Farber, S. (2015). Cuba’s Challenge. Available:

www.jacobinmag.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Fuller, T. (2009). Communism and Capitalism Are Mixing in

Laos.Available:

www.nytimes.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Gelderloos (2010). Anarchy Works. San Fanscisco: Ardent Press. p245-247.

Goodman, W. (1986). PUTTING PIECES TOGETHER FOR SOVIET FAMINE BOOK.

Available:

www.nytimes.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Goodwin, A. (2010) Evolution and Anarchism in International Relations:

The Challenge of Kropotkin’s Biological Ontology, Global Discourse, 1:2,

p107-126.

Gray, C (1999). Modern Strategy. New York: Oxford University Press.

p1-152.

Graeber, D (2004). Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology. Chicago:

Prickly Paradigm Press. p53-54.

Guardian [author not named]. (2016). One-party rule best for Vietnam,

says leader.Available:

www.theguardian.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Guevara; E, C (2006). Guerrilla Warfare. New York: Ocean Press. p1-128.

Harvey, R. (2016). Changing our view of worker co-operatives.Available:

www.thenews.coop

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Herbst, M. (2012). America’s ‘actually existing’ worker-owned

capitalism. Available:

www.theguardian.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Hodgson, G. (2016). How Capitalism Actually Generates More Inequality.

Available:

evonomics.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

HS (hierarchy structure) [author not named]. (2017). Military Command

Structure. Available:

www.hierarchystructure.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Huffadine, L. (2016). Could our Census be hacked? How ‘Anonymous’ leaked

thousands of usernames, passwords and emails from the US Census Bureau

last year. Available:

www.dailymail.co.uk

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Johnson, E. (2015). Ayn Rand vs. Anthropology. Available:

evonomics.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Kitchen, M (1976). Fascism. Hampshire: Macmillan. p1-11.

Kropotkin, P (1902). Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution. New York:

McClure, Philips & Co.. p1-328.

Kropotkin, P (1913). The Conquest of Bread. London: Chapman and Hall

Ltd. p1-297.

Kvande, E. (2007). Doing gender in flexible organizations. Bergen,

Norway: Fagbokforlaget.

Lenin, V (1999[1920]). “Left-Wing” Communism: an Infantile Disorder.

Australia: Resistance Books. p1-136.

Logue & Yates. (2006). Cooperatives, Worker-Owned Enterprises,

Productivity and the International Labor Organization. Sage Journals. 12

(4), p686-690.

Marshall, P (1993). Demanding the Impossible: A history of Anarchism.

London: FontanaPress. p.iv-700.

Mason, P. (2015). Postcapitalism. London: Allen Lane, pp. 280–289

Miller, M (1976). Kropotkin. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

p181-199.

Milne, S. (2006). Communism may be dead, but clearly not dead enough.

Available:

www.theguardian.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Munro, A. (2013). State monopoly on violence. Available:

www.britannica.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Murphy, J. T (2006/[1917]). The Workers’ Committee An Outline of its

Principles and Structure.

www.marxists.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Perez, L, A. (1997). Revolution an Response. In: Perez, L, A Cuba and

The United States: Ties of Singular Intimacy. 2^(nd) ed. USA: University

of Georgia Press. 238–273.

Prichard, A. (2011). What can the absence of anarchism tell us about the

history and purpose of International Relations?. British International

Studies Association. 37 (1), 1647–1669.

Phillips, P. (2012). Cuba Sets a Global Example for the Achievements of

Socialism. Available:

www.globalresearch.ca

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Porzuki, N. (2010). Can you name the five remaining communist countries

in the world?. Available:

www.pri.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Ranstorp. M (2005) Al-Qa’ida — An expanded global network of terror, The

RUSI Journal, 150:3, 40–43.

Rosen, J. (1969). Is Cuba Socialist? – Elite Runs the Show. Available:

www.marxists.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017. (Transcription: Paul Saba. credited

to: Encyclopedia of Anti-Revisionism On-Line)

Rossdale, C. (2010). Anarchy is What Anarchists Make of it: Reclaiming

the Concept of Agency in IR and Security Studies. Millennium: Journal of

International Studies. 39 (1), 483–501.

Scott, J (2009). The art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist History of

Upland Southeast Asia. London: Yale University Press. p64-178.

Stevens, A. Baker, N. (2006). Making Sense of War. Melbourne: Cambridge

University Press. p27-29.

Taylor, M (1982). Community, Anarchy and Liberty. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press. p1-168.

Trotsky, L. (1920). About the organisation of Labour. Available:

www.marxists.org

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Vego, M. (2003). Net-centric is not decisive. U.S. Naval Institute

Proceedings, 129(1), 52–57

Woods, A. (2011). The Spanish Revolution Betrayed. Available:

www.marxist.com

. Last accessed 1^(st) Sept 2017.

Zurbrugg, A. (2014). Socialism and Strategy: A Libertarian Critique of

Leninism. Anarchist Studies. 22 (1), p17-51.