💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › mortification-of-the-flesh.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:47:34. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Mortification of the Flesh, or, Gymnosophy
Author: Ausonia Calabrese
Date: October 21st, 2019
Language: en
Topics: truth, being, negation, nihilism, theory, language, silence, mysticism, veganism

Ausonia Calabrese

Mortification of the Flesh, or, Gymnosophy

Preface

This work is unfinished. It is a composite of several essays that began,

in some places, as condensations of longer and more academically-tinged

works. In other places, they have their origin in my notes while trying

to construct an imperative logic (hence, the stark change in tone

between my discussions of mystical practice, and my discussions of

logical truth.)

If this unfinished piece is unclear (even Porphyry apologizes, more than

a thousand years before me, for a lack of clarity when attempting to

speak that which cannot be put into words), I hope to write something of

a distillate or abstract of this work. In simple terms:

towards a sort of inversion of anarchy from an aggregate of social

relationships, to anarchy as the attainment of self-liberation.

alternative translation of anarchy: rather than the negation of

authority, one can also interpret the term as a negation of a beginning

principle or cause, i.e., a state of being without beginning or cause.

Compare 無爲 (wú wéi) in Chinese religion, acting-without-acting.

attaining anarchy. I argue that veganism, radical sobriety, and other

forms of self-discipline are closer to the classically anarchist

practices of social warfare than a good portion of anarchist theorists

would credit. That is, they are material and embodied, and work linearly

towards an end outside themselves.

anarchist logic that is entirely outside truth-aptitude, i.e., theory

which does not make claims as to what is true, and thus, what isn't.

This takes the form of imperatives, interrogatives, and speech acts. In

other words -- commands, questions, and non-linguistic acts that take

the form of speech.

I use the Greek work ἐγχειρίδιον (enkheiridion) in some places. This

refers both to a handbook (a manual,) and to a sharp knife, in its

capacity as a tool. It refers in most contexts to the Ἐγχειρίδιον

Ἐπικτήτου (Enkheirídion Epiktḗtou), the Handbook of Epictetus. This

Handbook is a set of techniques and methods for practicing Stoics.

Deleuze is credited with the quip:

Thus, the ἐγχειρίδιον (enkheiridion) is in this sense, a brick. Perhaps

it is no coincidence that the most famous and well-known work that can

be called anarchist in any sense, is not Tolstoy nor Kropotkin. It is a

manual for bomb-making (amongst other things,) and titled the Anarchist

Cookbook. A cookbook, of course, makes no claims as to whether or not

its recipes are true. Perhaps they are successful, perhaps they are not,

but there are many degrees of validity and being that a recipe, or a

method for making explosives, can be satisfied or not-satisfied.

Along with this preface, I have appended a bibliography of works that

were central to the development of this one.

Ausonia Calabrese (T. F. G.)

October 21, 2019

Part 1: Etymology

Arkhḗ

Despite a wide acknowledgment among generations of anarchists, the Greek

etymon (precursor) of anarchy, does not necessarily mean domination, or

oppression, or hierarchy. While it would come to mean all these things,

its primary or original meaning was beginning. It is from this

understanding that the word attains its meaning as superior, and further

thus as power and hierarchy.

I affirm that this understanding has served the development of anarchy

well. There has been a turn in the past couple of decades away from

traditional anarchist schools of thought, towards new and novel forms of

liberation, and distilling the term anarchy into a simple negation of

domination frees the term from the historical baggage of dead European

ideologies. Further, and perhaps more importantly, I enjoy the ambiguity

and potential for play that lies at its center.

There is a certain understanding of ἀρχή (arkhḗ) that is lost when

understood simply as "domination." In Ancient Greek, ἀρχή (arkhḗ) is

singular, as opposed to a plural form. Thus, anarchy preserves a

singular conception of power, what Hobbes, and later, Perlman referred

to as Leviathan. There is an alternative translation here: in its

capacity as being understood as meaning beginning, anarchy can thus mean

"that without a beginning," in the sense of not having an ἀρχή (arkhḗ),

or source. It also refers to the mystical beginning of all, what

Anaximander deems ἄπειρος (ápeiros), analogous in some ways to 道 (Dào)

in China around the same time, about 600 BCE. The term contains its own

negation: a pure sort of negativity. In its sense of being the source of

all being, all things derive their being from the ἀρχή (arkhḗ), but in

its sense of not having a beginning itself, the ἀρχή (arkhḗ) is

anarchic. Thales, the founder of the Milesian school which Anaximander

was a part of, is attributed to the following fragment:

Anarchy, when interpreted this way, moves from an external (i.e.,

political) concept, to an internal one. It is the state of being Unique

and without any relationships, being above all other things. One is

"above" things not in a moral sense, but in the sense that the Creative

Nothing is Stirner's criterion of truth, and thus all other things

derive their truth or substance from the Creative Nothing.

All statements in language are based on presuppositions which cannot be

validated or verified within that language. In this sense, nous proceeds

from the One. Sextus Empiricus, Greek skeptic, writes:

Stirner shares this same sort of critique, but unlike the Skeptics, who

took on a sort of radical agnosticism, he locates the criterion of truth

on the Nothing. He distinguishes between servile criticism, who serves a

phantasmal criterion of truth, and one's own criticism, the criticism

which takes the Subject as the beginning for all knowledge:

He continues:

Anarchism, then, can be said to be separate from anarchy. Anarchism is a

material set of methods for arriving at anarchy. In simpler terms:

anarchism is a body of methods for self-liberation.

Áskēsis

The most prominent critique of vegan, straight edge, and

anti-civilization currents of anarchy is, regardless of validity, that

it represents a sort of meaningless asceticism towards a goal other than

the Individual, and thus is discarded as a moral technology of control.

This view is based on two assumptions.

First, the view that those aforementioned schools of anarchism are

"ascetic" in the sense that they deprive the subject of something they

desire. Thus, this argument is not entirely applicable even accepting

the premises arguendo. A trivial individualist-anarchist veganism can

take the form of simply not wanting to eat animal products. While valid

in this constricted sense, it is passive, toothless even. Disputing the

premise that veganism is a deprivation, however, produces a stronger,

more dangerous veganism.

Secondly, that view that veganism or radical sobriety is intended

outwards towards an external, outside goal. The difference between this

argument and the previous is subtle, though important. The

counter-argument here, though, disputes the implication that outward

goals necessarily need to oppose inward goals. Surely, some practices

satisfy both goals as an effect, regardless of intent. Moreover, there

can be said to be those practices that are stronger on both fronts as

due to their symbiosis.

Take, for example, mutualist relationships in the Wild, that

spontaneously form between unrelated species, or, on a more sentimental

note, that of friendship. Only under the bivalent logic of civilization

does friendship oppose self-transformation and exaltation. Only under

the binary logic of domination does sexual promiscuity necessarily

oppose the notion of healthy romance.

Then, veganism can be rendered as a technique for friendship, and both

radical sobriety and veganism as techniques for self-transformation.

Veganism, as I practice it, is a method for building relationships with

the more-than-human world. I make the concession that these practices

are, in fact, ascetic. Asceticism, despite its religious and moral

connotations, merely refers to practice, or technique. Veganism and

radical sobriety are separate from the pursuits of the "traditional

anarchist" because they share more in common with the militant & active

pursuits of violent rebellion than the more-often-than-not nonviolent

movements and impotent theory. Contrary to mainstream stereotypes, the

individualist-anarchist is a sentimentalist in the sense that she never

loses the hope that anarchy can be brought about here and now. The

result of these techniques are tangible, easily embodied. For the new

generation of anarchist militants, theory is transmuted into tactics and

strategy. One begins to think of anarchism as attack in this sense.

Theōría

From the ancient Greek θεωρία (theōría), "contemplation," evolved the

English theory, and it derives much of its meaning from this etymon.

θεωρία (theōría) also is the root of theater. It derives from theōréō,

"I look." Contemplation, thus, can be said to be the observation of

mental objects or the observation of mental objects. Note here that

θεωρία (theōría) does not denote a body of knowledge as such.

Contemplation, in the Christian tradition (particularly Eastern

Christianity,) refers to a mystical practice. Dionysius the

Areopagite,[^1] writing in 5th or 6th century AD, describes

contemplation as being an exercise in which the intelligible is left

behind to achieve union with that which lies beyond being and knowing:

Theory in the active sense of contemplation becomes anterior to a sort

of silence in the works of Damascius, a late Neoplatonist author. For

Damascius, the Absolute or One, which lies at the base of all existence,

so wholly transcends everything that it cannot even be properly called

"transcendent." That which can be said to be transcendent must

necessarily transcend something, and thus the Absolute cannot be

"transcendent" because it holds no relation to things that are

ontologically inferior to it. The only proper response to something as

Wholly Other as the One would be to remain in indeterminate silence:

The Absolute lies beyond all duality and thus, beyond truth and

falsehood. Rather, it acts as the principle which makes it possible for

things to be true or false, it can be said to be the ἀρχή (arkhḗ) or

first principle. Of course, this statement seems paradoxical. And in the

understanding that this statement perhaps is paradoxical, one cleaves it

of its truth-value and completes what theologians call the negatio

negationis, the negation of the negation (Cl. Hegel).

Damascius likely was influenced by the tradition of Skepticism, and

employs language native to Skepticism. Within Skepticism, there exists a

certain concept of ἐποχή (epokhē), or the "suspension of judgement."

Sextus Empiricus, a Pyrrhonic skeptic writing sometime in the several

centuries before Damascius, define ἐποχή (epokhē) as a "standstill of

the intellect, owing to which we neither deny nor affirm anything." One

must not confuse this with the via negativa in which all propositions

are negated rather it is analogous to a sort of silence of belief, in

which ἀταραξία (ataraxia) or "unperturbedness" can be obtained. The

Pyrrhonic sage makes no assertion or denials, their (un)knowing rendered

free from truth.

Skeptical discourse takes the form of stock arguments meant to bring

about a state of ἀπορία (aporía), literally a "puzzle" or "paradox."

Discourse was intended not as an end in of itself as the object of

philosophy, but rather a practical exercise to induce ἀταραξία

(ataraxia) through ἐποχή (epokhē). This practical property is present

across the board of ancient Greek philosophy, what Pierre Hadot refers

to as "philosophy as a way of life."

Part 2: Negativa

Silence & Mysticism

The so-called "last neoplatonist," Damascius of Syria, developed perhaps

the purest distillate of negation: apophasis, silence, that which

remains after negatio negationis, negating the negation. Later mystical

(and heretical) writers built upon the apophatic logic of the

neoplatonists and developed a negative theology in which self-denial

allows the Spirit of God to indwell within a human subject, thus

liberating them -- as Galatians 5:18 states, "Those who are driven or

led by the Spirit of God are no longer under the law."

Negation in anarchism, however, tends to take an incomplete form: in the

"active" sense embodied by insurrection against power, and in the

"passive" sense embodied in anarchy-as-lack-of-authority. The mystic,

however, categorically rejects all binaries, and thus the

Thing-beyond-language which the mystic seeks appears neither passive nor

active.

For the mystical-anarchist, anarchy manifests not as an action or a

practice, nor as a theoretical organization of society. It acts as a

cleaving off of the ἀρχή (arkhḗ), which leaves an empty void at the

heart of the subject, no longer dressed in the stable mask of the Ego

which lends itself to symbolic control and domination. For the

mystical-anarchist, "complete" anarchy lies beyond the bounds of

language, thus it terminates and negates itself and dwells in silence.

The hermit, the monk, the tree-sitter who carries the heritage of the

ancient ascetic stylites, becomes the site of anarchy, i.e. a negation

of the ἀρχή (arkhḗ), and of the negation-of-the-negation of the ἀρχή

(arkhḗ).

Nihilism

Nihilism, a mythic sign that calls upon its own destruction, necessarily

contains its own self-annihilation. There cannot be “true” nihilism

because a “true” nihilism is literally no-thing. Any conception of

nihilism will thus be incomplete. In classical Aristotlean logic and the

logics which follow from it, the negation of the negation is affirmative

and speaks positively of the object of the former negation. From

Damascius’s negation, however, follows a divine silence, in which

nothing positive or negative is even uttered. This divine silence allows

the Godhead (monad) to come and dwell within one’s self.

Silesius Angelus, 17th century German religious poet, writes:

Some readers will recognize words and pairs such as einig ein from

Stirner. In English, this is rendered:

In simple terms, the Creative Nothing, who’s authenticity is marked by

the failure of language to reach it, is without differentiation. For

Lacan, and for those who follow his school, the in-fant (the

prelinguistic stage of human existence) is in complete union with the

Real, and one in this stage does not perceive anything as “outside

itself.” In contemporary psychology, this is referred to as lack of

differentiation. Many recall a period in their childhood where they

struggled to understand that other “people” possessed a mind and

subjectivity. This is a remnant of this period in development. The

breastfeeding pair of mother and child is, as the child perceives it,

without separation. Once the child acquires language, the child exits

the Real and enters the registers of the Imaginary, and then the

Symbolic. One is now forever divorced from the Real, which is the

unattainable, ineffable transcendent that can never be reached by

language. The Real remains, however, where the subject “lies.” The

subject, properly, is a “lack of being” or in Lacanian jargon,

“want-to-be.”

Passive, Active, and Complete Nihilism

The construction of the citizen in discourse is thus a reification of

the true subject who lies outside the signified. The latter is

indeterminate and cannot be manipulated as the former is. This same

process happens within Alyson Escalante’s writings on radical

negativity. Alyson Escalante was once a stream-enterer of nihilism,

before abandoning her prior leanings in favor of Marxism. For early

Escalante though, the radical loss of self is something to be feared.

She writes that in the demand for a stable identity, the program of

gender nihilism says “no.” Escalante’s nihilism (or ex-nihilism) simply

does not go far enough. The radical loss of being is desirable (and for

Lacan, too, desire is intimately linked with lack.) One should fear not

radical loss because by clearing the Self of its Being, one transcends

it. Direct, unmediated experience of the nothing at the center of all

existence is traumatic: it ruptures the symbolic order.

Escalante states,

This is evidence that Escalante’s nihilism is incomplete. The fate

queerness now "faces" is not one of nonexistence. it is a fate of

definitely continued, stable, cannibalized existence. Existence in this

state is confinement to the social context which produces it.

I believe that the non-essence of queerness is already a sort of

anti-linguistic gesture. It is fundamentally a denial of the rational

technologies that Western-European civilization has used to construct

coherent social identities.

I find that in the context of political negation, too much emphasis is

put within the spoken, crystalline negation of an affirmative. Negation

is never complete in this sense, within the negative-affirmative pair

the contradiction and the tension is preserved.

Negation is the ascension away from being. I should note here that it is

not morally or ethically superior to affirmation in the normal sense,

but it is ascension in the sense that it inverts the "coming into

being," the creatio ex nihilo that constitutes existence. The return to

emptiness (ex nihilo nihil fit) is anti-linguistic. It is not merely

"above" language in the sense that it is superior to it, rather, it

works (in the actual sense of the word) to annihilate the intelligible.

This annihilation is in a sense, a self-censure, a vow of silence that

does not merely negate (or contradict) the intelligible meaning of a

statement (and is thus intelligible itself.) One must be careful not to

reify the censure (in which the act of censorship becomes knowable.) A

successful censure is complete annihilation that results in silence.

Part 3: Pre-Enchiridion

Why should one prefer an anarchist theory free from objective truth?

Truth here refers to the quality of being truth-apt, that is, having a

truth-value, generally true or false (termed bivalence) though some

alternatives have been developed. Thus, to be free of truth refers (a)

to the rejection of truth-aptitude; further, (b) it implies in a certain

sense, that truth-aptitude constricts or subjects us.

The former clarification, despite appearances, enjoys a wide acceptance,

even amongst the staunched logical positivists. Many statements in

natural language are not necessarily truth-apt, such as statements which

linguists refer to as imperative (commands), exclamative (exclamations),

and interrogative (questions). There are also expressives and many other

truth-nonapt categories.

Anarchist theory, thus, can take a form far removed from the "science"

of dialectical Marxism-Leninism, that of prescriptivism. It can take,

rather, the form of artistic & poetic creation undertaken for its own

sake and which has its own end within itself.

Prayers free from truth

The topic of logic is surprisingly ubiquitous amongst anarchist theory

-- there is the near-constant talk of the logic of capitalism, or

settler-colonial logics. A major work of contemporary

Individualist-Anarchist theory is entitled Against the Logic of

Submission, though the question of what logic in this sense entails is

not discussed.

Even Aristotle, the father of logic and perhaps even of the valuation of

truth, states thusly:

An anarchist theory free from truth would be as a prayer is. That is,

imperative and interrogative, as opposed to declarative -- an

Aristotlean prayer, or perhaps, exorcism, rendered free from truth. It

would be an unknowing as opposed to a knowing; which renders a passive

object which is to be known, and an active subject which knows.

The general intention of my inquiry into the nature of disconnection

from truth is one of a wide and varied program, that of the critique of

being. This vein of discourse arrives from everywhere, it seems: from

utilitarian antinatalism, to deep green social activism, to the field of

(informal) pragmatics.

Antinatalism is chief amongst these because it gives moral & ethical

value to nonexistence. This is not to say that I necessarily agree with

their conclusions (I am critical of the nature of universal moral

imperatives. I find that they strip the practical nature of imperative

statements and place them into an abstract realm, in their sense as a

mandate from a creator.) Rather, I enjoy how antinatalists transform

what amounts to merely a mental exercise, a thought experiment, into

something with actuality. As something with real, concrete consequences,

it begs the question: what is to be done?

By purging anarchism of essentialism in all its form, I hope to fold it

in on itself. From the external obsession, which implies the existence

of an atomized social individual, comes an internal obsession, a

looking-inwards. Thus, anarchism is rendered as a concrete set of

methods for obtaining self-liberation.

Mystical anarchy

Anarchism (as opposed to anarchy) is not τέχνη (tékhnē), i.e.,

knowing-in-doing, contrasted with ἐπιστήμη (epistḗmē), knowing in the

theoretical dimension. Rather it is a concrete set of exercises or

praxis in which the end goal is the transformation of the subject. As

Agamben notes, for the ancient Greek, one who has the aim of work

outside one's self, is inferior to one who's subject is himself:

Thus, anarchism (as I define it here) is aimed at producing an "anarchy"

at the site of the individual. Anarchism does not "produce" anarchy in a

generative sense, but rather is a clearing out , a cleaving open within

which that state of undifferentiation can come indwell.

Undifferentiation is, of course, αναρχία (anarkhíā) -- that without a

beginning principle or substratum, the arkhḗ. This clearing out is

practical and attainable: it places anarchy within reach, though not

entirely graspable by normal means.

The One is void-like in a vacuous sense. In its unity, it contains

nothing, no other thing. It is not the same as the empty set, i.e. the

prime, least, first member of all sets because it is not a container in

the same sense that other sets are: it is uninhabited. Hegel, too, calls

the One synonymous with the Void.

For centuries, the dominant ideology of the West has considered the

Signifier (the word, logos) as a sort of “natural fact” arising from a

productive relationship with the referent. Thus, in his mystical

writings on the One, Porphyry argues that the One has no name, even

“One” is inadequate to describe it, as he writes that within the word,

the constituent letters which compose it reveal some hidden (cryptic)

knowledge of the referent within it. This was a common belief in Greece

until relatively recently, and perhaps date back to at least Pythagoras,

who was supposedly a gifted numerologist. On the Pythagoreans, Porphyry

writes that their term for the One, appropriated from the pagan divinity

Apollo, is not an affirmation but rather an unsaying of names: he

derives it from ἀ- (a-) and πολῠ́ς (polús), literally "without parts."

Thus, they are speaking of a (non)being that is a simplex, who they do

not attribute an affirmative name.

Bibliography & Suggested Readings

Religion of Capitalism

Philosophy, Theology, and Theurgy

Socrates to Foucault

Philosophy, Religion, Literature, and the Arts