💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › kevin-carson-the-utility-of-disutility.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:49:17. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Utility of Disutility
Author: Kevin Carson
Date: December 11, 2005
Language: en
Topics: utilitarianism
Source: Retrieved on 4th September 2021 from https://mutualist.blogspot.com/2005/12/utility-of-disutility.html

Kevin Carson

The Utility of Disutility

Bill at Impossibilist Blog raises some interesting questions about my

version of the labor theory of value, rooted in the disutility of labor.

Now — I can heartily agree the value of labour — i.e. of work done — is

the labour time invested in it. I can further happily agree that one

basis for this is the disutility to the worker of performing the labour.

The question arises though — does this vary according to the nature of

the work, or is it in fact a generalised disutility common to all

workers. Is it a scalar or binary matter. If the latter, then Marx is

right, we cannot discern the value of a type of labour performed through

the market value of the goods.

To elucidate the question, he proposes a hypothetical example:

A village — small — an homogenous populaton where everyone shares a

common set of core skills and everyone can basically do everyone elses

job.

Thus, everyone could do the work, but for a variety of reasons they

don’t — they specialise. Some might be good at certain tasks. Some might

not like certain tasks. Some might have a favoured location. It might be

heriditory tradition. When they exchange, though, they know they could

have made the product themselves. They know roughly how long it would

have taken them; and how long it is generally taken to perform that

task. They can then exchange goods to what they consider to be an equal

value — if only after haggling.

In that case, Bill says, the disutility of labor would be binary--that

is, “labour time would resolve down to an equal general equivilent

between economic actors.”

Now, according to Mises, the disutility of labor as such has a binary

quality to it; specific forms of work may be more unpleasant or

repugnant than others, but all labor carries some disutility by its very

nature, regardless of the pleasantness or unpleasantness incidental to

the work. Indeed, part of the pleasure incidental to some forms of

skilled work, associated with the sense of craftsmanship, involves

satisfaction at minimizing superfluous or unnecessary efforts.

But despite the binary nature of this basic level of disutility, common

to all labor, the total disutility of labor experienced by a worker has

a scalar quality, resulting from the greater or lesser unpleasantness of

particular forms of work.

Marx may have been right that it is impossible to get, ex post, from the

exchange-value of specific goods to the value of the labor embodied in

them. Even leaving aside the scalar or binary quality of labor’s

disutility, it’s impossible to tell from a snapshot of current prices

how far a specific price deviates from the equilibrium value.

But from the disutility of labor, combined with other a priori

assumptions about the nature of human beings as utility maximizing

beings, we can deduce that all exchange values are a combination of

labor value and scarcity rents. Some of the scarcity rents are for

naturally inelastic goods, like economic rent on land and natural

resources. Others are short-term rents on elastic goods, whose supply

hasn’t yet adjusted to demand. But most important is the category of

rent on artificially inelastic goods, like vacant land to which access

is controlled by a landlord, usurious interest rates resulting from

banking market entry barriers, and monopoly prices to the consumer

resulting from state-enforced cartels.

So even though the labor theory of value, as explained in terms of

subjective disutility, has little use for empirical analysis of specific

prices, it has a great deal of value as an a priori tool of analysis.

The central insight of classical political economy, that price moves

toward cost, unless impeded by secondary factors, is a vitally important

one. The other major insight developed by Ricardo’s radical disciples,

equally important, concerns the role of “artificial rights of property”

and other state-created scarcities, in causing deviation from the cost

principle. Taken together, they can be put to revolutionary conclusions.

And a labor theory of value founded on the disutility of labor ties in

well with both of these insights: As Tucker said, “under free

competition there is no price where there is no burden.” And as a

corollary, “is there anything that costs except labor or suffering

(another name for labor)?” [Instead of a Book, 1973 Gordon Press

facsimile edition, 214, 403]

The scalar quality of the disutility of labor, likewise, may scuttle

Marx’s identification of exchange value with straight labor-time.

Similarly, Bill has in the past, in other venues, raised the question of

identifying the discrete labor-contribution of an individual worker in

production that requires collective labor. The answer: in a free labor

market, the individual worker can withdraw his labor from the production

process when his wages are insufficient to compensate his experienced

disutility. When labor, collectively, receives its full product without

paying scarcity rents to the owners of capital and land, the product of

labor will be distributed among laborers individually according to their

disutility--through, as Hogskin put it, the higgling of the market:

Each labourer produces only some part of a whole, and each part having

no value or utility of itself, there is nothing on which the labourer

can seize, and say: “This is my product, this will I keep to myself.”

Between the commencement of any joint operation, such as that of making

cloth, and the division of its product among the different persons whose

combined exertions have produced it, the judgment of men must intervene

several times, and the question is, how much of this joint product

should go to each of the individuals whose united labourers produce it?

I know no way of deciding this but by leaving it to be settled by the

unfettered judgments of the labourers themselves. If all kinds of labour

were perfectly free, if no unfounded prejudice invested some parts, and

perhaps the least useful, of the social task with great honour, while

other parts are very improperly branded with disgrace, there would be no

difficulty on this point, and the wages of individual labour would be

justly settled by what Dr Smith calls the “higgling of the market.”

Unfortunately, labour is not, in general, free; and, unfortunately there

are a number of prejudices which decree very different rewards to

different species of labour from those which each of them merits.

Bill’s picture, in his hypothetical example above, of the disutility of

labor evening itself out through self-selection in a largely

worker-controlled labor market, reminds me of Franz Oppenheimer’s idea

that under the inducements of a truly free labor market, labor would

distribute itself among employments until incomes became “equal”--in my

terms, equal in relation to given quantities of subjectively perceived

effort. He quoted with approval Adam Smith’s claim that

[t]he whole of the advantages and disadvantages of the different

employments of labour and stock must, in the same neighbourhood, be

either perfectly equal or continually tending to equality.

He also cited, with similar approval, von Thunen’s equilibrium at which

“labor of equal quality is equally rewarded in all branches of

production....”