đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș leonard-williams-language-ideology-and-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:23:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Language, Ideology, and Anarchism Author: Leonard Williams Date: 2011 Language: en Topics: language, university, John Zerzan, theory, academy, ideology Source: Retrieved on January 25th from http://aaaaarg.org/upload/leonard-williams-language-ideology-and-anarchism.pdf Notes: Manchester College North Manchester, Indiana Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Western Political Science Association, San Antonio, Texas, April 20-23, 2011
As an emancipatory perspective, anarchism aspires to replace forms of
domination with forms of freedom. Aspirations are wonderful things; they
push us toward new achievements, and they hold us accountable when we
act. The difficulties begin when our aspirations are not realized, when
we try and fail. The difficulties become apparent when we at last
acknowledge the staying power that forms of domination possess. One
response might simply be to resolve to âfail betterââas Samuel Beckett
suggested in WorstwardHo. The trial-and-error pursuits of activist
practice seem to reflect just such an orientation to the emancipatory
project. Another possible response would be to engage in the sort of
thinking that emerges whenever our expectations do not come to
passâthinking that runs the gamut from pragmatic problem-solving to
academic theorizing. Regardless, anarchists have taken up both the
challenge to act and the challenge to theorize in various ways. A few
anarchist theorists have sought to meet these challenges, at least in
part, by exploring theories of language and ideology.
One among them has been John Zerzan, who devoted an essay to the topic.
His primitivist anarchism attacks civilization and culture generally,
asserts that âthe origin of all symbolizing is alienationâ (Zerzan 2006,
57). It regards language as an alien ideology, an externally imposed
form of domination.
Alternatively, theorists drawing upon post-structuralist strains of
thought have come to see language both as a significantly constraining
and as a potentially liberating force. By further exploring issues
related to language and ideology, then, this paper constitutes a set of
preliminary notes toward articulating an anarchist approach to the
theory of language. I certainly do not claim to have fulfilled any such
aspiration. My aim here is the more limited one of doing some conceptual
or philosophical work that might help further the discussion.
In many respects, language and political theory are coterminous. Plato
and Aristotle certainly ruminated about language as they debated a
theory of Forms or assessed competing claims to rule. Hobbes, cautioning
against the troubles engendered by any âabuse of words,â took particular
pains to set forth an explicitly defined vocabulary for moral and
political thought. Rousseau also made a contributionâhis hypothetical
account of the state of nature gave language an important place in the
prehistory of civilization. Without it, there would be no lasting
communities or societies, and hence, none of the associated inequalities
resulting from property and power. More recently, countless
contributions to academic political theory have taken an explicitly
linguistic turn. This heritage makes it all the more interesting that
anarchist theory, with the exception of the postanarchists, has devoted
relatively little attention to the topic.
In this context, the essay on âLanguage: Origin and Meaningâ by John
Zerzan (2006, 3143) might well be a useful starting point for
reflection. Zerzanâs primitivism is a good place for this study to begin
because in many ways his ideas represent a limit case. Critical of every
aspect of a symbolic culture that underlies civilization itself, he sees
language, thought, and culture as forms of mediated experience that take
us away from our natural essence (Guimaraes 2010, 340). Much as Rousseau
did, Zerzan regards domination and repression as the logically and
practically necessary outcomes of civilization. Because it represents an
aboriginal separation from nature, from direct experience, the advent of
language and other forms of symbolic culture marks nothing less than a
fall from grace. It marks the point where we become estranged not only
from nature and each other, but from life itself.
Beyond that initial estrangement, though, language constitutes another,
more insidious phenomenon. As a means for transmitting ideology,
language becomes the primary vehicle for the sort of subjugation or
domination that anarchists characteristically oppose. Operating through
the âclosure of symbols,â language and ideology work simultaneously to
produce false consciousness, thought control, and unfreedom (Zerzan
2006, 32-34). In every society, language conceals and justifies,
monopolizes and shapes everyday life. âAs the paradigm of ideology,
language stands behind all of the massive legitimation necessary to hold
civilization togetherâ (Zerzan 2006, 35).
Aware that this very critique of reification is itself reified in
language, Zerzan does not see an immediate path out of the ideological
straightjacket in which we find ourselves. Language and ideology are
learned habits of thought, imposed from the outside. They constitute us
as part of an unnatural world. The more we are socialized, the more
embedded in that world we become; the more embedded, the more estranged.
Philosophical insights into language offer no way out, either. To
Zerzan, poststructuralist theories simply drain language of meaning. The
only hope is to restore some form of authentic communication, which he
finds in the sorts of unmediated experiences where language itself is
unnecessary. There are but âtwo kinds of human experience: the
immediate, non-separate reality, and separate, mediated experienceâ
(Guimaraes 2010, 339), and Zerzan clearly prefers the former. In short,
the ideal situation would be âa world of lovers, a world of the
face-to-face, in which even names can be forgotten, a world which knows
that enchantment is the opposite of ignorance. Only a politics that
undoes language and time and is thus visionary to the point of
voluptuousness has any meaningâ (Zerzan 2006, 43).
The task, it seems, is to delineate a perspective on language that
captures and reflects the aspirations of anarchists. Such an
understanding involves an effort to advance a theory of language that is
both attuned to abstract theory and reflective of common sense, that is
both accurate and emancipatory. This is no easy task, to be sure, but
Zerzanâs essay provides us with a starting point insofar as it appears
to make three critical claims: (1) language and ideology are unnatural,
external impositions on the freedom of subjects; (2) language and
ideology are hegemonic tools for the legitimation of domination; and (3)
language and ideology are closed systems of thought. In what immediately
follows, I will examine each of these claims as potential building
blocks for an anarchist understanding of language and ideology.
Zerzanâs core assumption is that language, like ideology, is an external
phenomenon, something imposed by an alien force. We encounter it as the
always already existing medium of communication between people. We are
given a language almost as a birthright, an inheritance from previous
generations. As people develop into subjects, language appears not only
as a vehicle for thought and expression, but also as the embodiment of
the force of societyâ in Lacanian terms, the Symbolic Order. Our choice
as a subject is to integrate and be content, or to rebel and remain an
outsider.
Karl Marxâs oft-quoted observation about history (that we make it, but
not as we please) seems just as apt as a characterization of our
encounter with language. Language stands outside the individual,
appearing as an external and restrictive force. As Max Stirner (1995,
305, original emphasis) put it: âLanguage or âthe wordâ tyrannizes
hardest over us, because it brings up against us a whole army offixed
ideas'â As we learn such things as the rules of a grammar or discourse,
oneâs feral spirit is told either to conform or be crushed. Going oneâs
own way, thinking oneâs own thoughts, expressing oneself in a unique
mannerâthese are simply not possible in the context of a system of
communication based upon experiences and truths that are not our own.
Because language is a given, because it seems to stand opposed to
individual freedom, Zerzan believes that it can only have arisen from an
external source. It can only have appeared as a dastardly means to
unsavory ends. In this context, Zerzan (2006, 36-37) seems drawn to two
possible ends for the advent of languageâone, lying or deceiving in a
world where intentions and emotions were otherwise transparently
conveyed, and two, initiating people into the division of labor that
serves as the foundation of civilization. Regardless of the end,
language and other symbolic forms of communication appear as a limit
upon what is natural and free.
Â
One anarchist who took issue with that view was Rudolph Rocker. In one
chapter of his 1937 work, Nationalism and Culture, Rocker (1978) argued
against any notion that a given language represented the spirit of a
particular people, that language had an essentially national character.
In his view, though language was inextricably involved with social
relations. âIn speech, human thought expresses itself, but this is no
purely personal affair, as is often assumed, but an inner process
continually animated and influenced by the social environment. In man's
thoughts are mirrored not only his natural environment, but all
relations which he has with his fellows.â Though Rocker believes that
language carries culture, he did not believe that either language or
culture represented something alien to humans in their natural state.
âFor language in its widest sense is not the exclusive property of man,
but can be clearly recognized in all social species. That within these
species a certain mutual understanding takes place is undeniable
according to all observations. It is not language as such, but the
special forms of human speech, the articulate language which permits of
concepts and so enables man's thoughts to achieve higher results, which
distinguish man in this respect from other species (Rocker 1978).â
In other words, speech (understood as vocabulary) clearly has to be
taught; however, language (understood as thought and communication) is
entirely natural.
In this sense, then, language cannot be understood as an external
imposition. As he often observes, Noam Chomsky (2004, 85, 128, 429)
believes that language is the outward result of a mental faculty that
all humans naturally possess. This mental faculty represents a
fundamentally biological capacityââan essential component of the human
mindâ (Chomsky 2004, 578)âthat allows us to interact with others, to
create ever new forms of expression. The capacity to learn a language
lies within us and enables us to generate an entire range of sentences
that may never have been uttered before. âA person who knows a
particular language has the capacity to speak and understand an
indefinitely large number of sentences, and uses this ability freely in
normal linguistic behavior: in communication, in expression of thought,
and so onâ (Chomsky 2004, 350). Far from an alien imposition on nature,
then, language is a natural element of human life. As expected, Zerzan
(2009) regards Chomskyâs view of language as a âseverely backward,
nonradical perspective, not unrelated to his unwillingness to put much
else into question, outside of a very narrow political focus.â Where
Zerzan takes the story of the Tower of Babel to be a metaphor for the
loss of innocence and the onset of alienation, Chomsky regards the
multiplicity of human languages to be an important indicator of the
freedom and creativity found in human nature.
The question of how natural language is or should be was certainly an
element in the debate over Esperanto during the late 19th and early 20th
centuries. Certainly, Esperanto is one the most artificial languages one
can imagineâdesigned to be a lingua franca for people from a range of
natural languages. Some anarchists and social reformers were convinced
that its widespread use would not only encourage international
understanding and cooperation, but would also âsomehow make people more
freeâ (Guimaraes 2010, 339). Other radical theorists found that
Esperanto had little to recommend, however. Antonio Gramsci, who had
academic training in linguistics, asserted âthe historicity of languages
in opposition to the illusory utopia of a language created artificially
without any ground or cultural participationâ (Rosiello 2010, 32). In a
similar vein, Gustav Landauer (2010b, 277) observed how artificial
creations such as Esperanto could ânever capture what is most important
in a language: the fine shades, the nuances, the unspeakable. In the
grown languages, a lot of what is said lives between the words as an
unutterable element.â Any insistence on the organic character of
language certainly suggests that not all that is natural is badâeven if
it supports civilization.
To treat language as natural, though, does not wholly undermine Zerzanâs
position on language and ideology. Like language, ideology can never
truly be neutral. Holding an ideology embeds one in and further
legitimizes a pre-existing community; holding an ideology, like speaking
a language, frequently puts one on the side of the established order. As
John Thompson (1984, 130-131, emphasis deleted) has observed, âto study
ideology is to study the ways in which meaning (signification) serves to
sustain relations of domination.â Functional analyses of ideology thus
have noted that, in addition to giving folks some cognitive purchase on
the world, ideological positions put people into relationships with
others. Beyond identifying a person with a particular community,
ideologies also serve a hegemonic functionâthey ratify the choices that
people make by ensuring their legitimacy or rightness.
Mention of hegemony naturally brings to mind the ideas of Gramsci. In
his view, language and ideology helped constitute what he called âcommon
senseââan ordinary understanding of how the world works. For most
people, common sense functions as a kind of philosophy, and it provides
people with the cognitive frameworks through which they grasp the
meaning of social and political phenomena. Gramsci (1971, 377)
acknowledges that, as a âhistorically necessaryâ element of any social
structure, ideologies âhave a validity which is âpsychologicalâ; they
âorganiseâ human masses, and create the terrain on which men move,
acquire consciousness of their position, struggle, etc.â Over time, this
common sense becomes second nature to peopleâs ways of thinking and
acting.
Gramsciâs discussions of hegemony examine language and ideology (or,
more broadly, culture) as a means for advancing the political and
economic interests of particular groups, parties, or social classes. In
his view, âthe State is the entire complex of practical and theoretical
activities with which the ruling class not only justifies and maintains
its dominance, but manages to win the active consent of those over whom
it rulesâ (Gramsci 1971, 244). If the ruling ideas of an epoch are
indeed the ideas of the ruling class, as Marx noted, then the ideas of
classes seeking to rule must somehow be invoked in ways that replace the
others. No revolutionary movement is possible without a revolutionary
consciousness, as we know. As a result, because symbolic systems are
never neutral, the crucial question in evaluating any particular
manifestation of language, ideology, or culture is: Who benefits?
Gramsci observed that all parties (and, we could say, all ideologies)
carry out a policing functionâthe function of safeguarding interests in
the context of maintaining order. It need only be asked whether the
function is performed for a reactionary or a progressive purpose. In
Gramsciâs (1971, 155) words: âDoes the given party carry out its
policing function in order to conserve an outward, extrinsic order which
is a fetter on the vital forces of history; or does it carry it out in
the sense of tending to raise the people to a new level of civilisation
expressed programmatically in its political and legal order?â This
positional question necessarily focuses our attention on the role played
by language as a material force in the political contest between
classes, between the state and its antagonists.
The focus of political action thus has to move from direct challenges to
state power (wars of maneuver) to indirect efforts aimed at undermining
hegemonic world views (wars of position). Because direct challenges to a
hegemonic world view are likely to fail, one must proceed instead with a
patient and difficult siege (Gramsci 1971, 239) that seeks to undermine
the legitimacy of domination by calling common sense into question.
Because language represents the source of identify and understanding in
a system of political and economic stratification, because it offers the
âconcrete space for every possible hegemonyâ (Gensini 2010, 70-71), any
effort to undermine orthodoxies begins in the very domain in which we
are always already embedded. Superseding any hegemony will require
criticizing popular views and transforming common sense. Such a
reorientation is no doubt premised on a situation in which most people
are educated and open enough to hearing arguments, and then acting, on
the social and political questions of the day. Gramsciâs purpose,
according to Marcus Green and Peter Ives (2010, 296), âis to ascertain
the content and meaning of common sense, to understand how the masses
conceive life, the world and politics, with the point of radicalizing
common sense and providing subaltern groups with the intellectual tools
necessary to confront dominant hegemony, philosophy and power.â
Language thus becomes the tool for switching valences from the
reactionary to the progressive pole. Within any hegemonic configuration,
then, the goal must be to transform language from a conservative (for
anarchists, statist) force into a progressive (that is, anti-statist)
one. Logically prior to creating a receptive public, though, is
self-educationâdeveloping a critical perspective on oneâs own conception
of reality or world view. Knowing oneself âas a product of the
historical process to date which has deposited in you an infinity of
traces, without leaving an inventoryâ (Gramsci 1971, 324) is where the
revolution begins. Breaking free of established world views thus becomes
the very essence of dissidence, the necessary precursor to political
transformation.
Loosening the grip of language and ideology in this way might seem
relatively easy, at first glance. All one need do is to take people with
sufficient education and provide them with the facts of the matter. This
rationalist approach to political awareness is what Chomsky (2006, 69)
has advocated: âWith a little industry and application, anyone who is
willing to extricate himself from the system of shared ideology and
propaganda will readily see through the modes of distortion developed by
substantial segments of the intelligentsia.â All it takes is a sound
mind, a bit of intellectual effort, and ideological liberation will soon
be at hand. However, social scientific explorations of framing (Lakoff
2004; Nunberg 2007), our experiences with recent policy debates (e.g.,
health insurance reform in the United States), not to mention our long
delayed emancipationâall these suggest that the easy answer is not a
viable one. People often remain subject to, and at times reinforce, the
very prejudices and stereotypes that they might otherwise decry. How,
then, can hegemonic world views be undermined? What can be done to break
free of our linguistic and ideological chains?
A Gramscian answer would work through the socio-political nature of the
hegemonic situation. Even though a given hegemony seems well-established
and deep-rooted, it remains problematic at its core. Despite its best
efforts, âno matter how totalizing a system might be, it will never
achieve its ambition of totalityâit is impossible to create a system
with no outsideâ (Day 2005, 175). Try as it might to subjectify
individuals in sundry ways, it cannot ever fully succeed; a symbolic
lack (some element that cannot be signified) will always remain. Most
conventional political projects have attempted âto âfillâ or âsutureâ
this fundamental lack in society, to overcome its fundamental
antagonism. But this is an impossibility: the Real of antagonism, which
eludes representation, can never be overcomeâ (Newman 2001, 147). In the
context of Ernesto Laclauâs discourse theory, then, any hegemonic world
view must ever be incomplete, must always remain contestable. âThat is
to say, while discourses endeavour to impose order and necessity on a
field of meaning, the ultimate contingency of meaning precludes this
possibility from being actualizedâ (Howarth 2000, 103). Through
political and linguistic activity, subjectivities and antagonisms
emerge; logics of equivalence and difference are thus configured and (in
moments of dislocation) reconfigured in various ways, as given political
situations warrant (Laclau and Mouffe 1985; Laclau 1996).
A different approach draws on the Situationists, who relied upon such
tactics as the detournement (subversive misappropriation of images and
artifacts) and the creation of âsituationsâ (occasions for unmediated
play) to help people break out of their intellectual imprisonment by the
âspectacleâ (Sheehan 2003, 122-124; Knabb 2006). By creating enough
disruption of our everyday consciousness, we will doubtless be shaken
out of our ideological stupor. Thinking along these same lines, for
example, Hakim Bey aims to disrupt the routines of everyday life, to
disrupt the normal course of business, through such mechanisms as Poetic
Terrorism, Art Sabotage, and most notably, the Temporary Autonomous
Zone. Bey (2003, 33, original emphasis) thus seeks to âmurder the
IDEAâblow up the monument inside usâ in order to shift the balance of
power; he sees this âsabotage of archetypes as the only practical
insurrectionary tactic for the present.â Bey eventually denies having
any overtly political intent or instructional purpose, however. By
focusing on art, imagination, immediacy, and experience, his approach
concludes with a Nietzschean emphasis on âpure expressionâ ("Peter
Lamborn Wilson Interview, Part 2" 2009, section 7).
As Richard Day (2005, 8-9) has noted, anarchist theory and practice has
thus moved from an approach based on the logic of hegemony (taking or
influencing state power) to one based on the logic of affinity (working
with others in ways that prefigure new social relations). Political
theory and action are no longer understood to occur on the large scale
associated with narratives that focus on a cataclysmic political and
social eventââthe Revolution.â Instead, political activity occurs over a
variety of localized domains and emphasizes a micropolitics that calls
âfor social, personal, and political experimentation, the expansion of
situated freedom, the release of subjected discourses and genres, and
the limitation and reorientation of the role of the intellectualâ (May
1994, 112).
As noted above, Zerzan saw language and ideology as a linked system of
hegemonic justification. From Gramsci forward, the question has always
been how exactly one goes about undermining a given hegemonic world
view. An early response was to suggest that oneâs opponents were in the
grip of a false consciousness, that they were mired in the distortions
of ideology. Such a restrictive or negative conception of ideology
(Seliger 1976) falls, though, when it becomes evident that there is no
privileged social class, that no one has a monopoly on either science or
truth, that oneâs own world view is just another ideology among many. In
such a context, the radical political task is âto disarticulate the
ruling discursive structures that guarantee the reproduction of
relations, that is, to undertake an educational work that rearticulates
these discursive structures in the perspective of social transformationâ
(Maas 2010, 92). Here again, though, difficulties abound. We soon come
to face the fact we willingly submit to our own subjectionâwhether
conceived as giving in to the spooks of fixed ideas (Stirner), as
falling prey to the machinations of desire (Deleuze), or as some other
phenomenon. Undermining the legitimacy of a legitimizing ideology
therefore is not easy, nor can the goal be achieved in any direct way.
For many, the aim can be attained only through fostering clever breaks
with the flow of mainstream ideas, patiently organizing ideological and
political coalitions, or crafting new forms of social relations built on
the principle of affinity.
Zerzanâs approach to language seems to foreclose such options for
turning around hegemonic configurations, however. His prevailing view
seems to be that, fundamentally, language and ideology operate as closed
systems. Because they are closed systems, there is no point of working
within them or trying to transform them. The only truly radical option
for Zerzan is to go outside themâto (re)create a world beyond ideology,
beyond language. In making this move, he retraces a familiar route that
insists on âa radical conceptual division between two ontological
ordersâthat of ânatural authorityâ and âartificial authorityâââthe
Manichean route taken by the classical anarchists (Newman 2005, 36).
Zerzan has, in other words, sought to locate nature as the radical
outside of civilization, as an anti-language position from which to
attack symbolic culture.
In a world where our worldviews and identities have all been constructed
by language and ideology, can an emancipatory politics even be conceived
on such a basis? In a world where domination characterizes the vast
range of social relations, is such radical freedom ever really possible?
If we are embedded within language and ideology, are we not also
permanently mired in them? Can radical theorists and activists identify
a language that operates contra language itself? Such questions are at
the heart of recent thinking about language, ideology, and politics;
they are the ones to which we now turn.
Of course, poststructuralists, post-Marxists, and postanarchists alike
have tilled these fields for some time now. Remarkably, for all their
work highlighting the power that linguistic, discursive, and ideological
systems have over us, most such thinkers have not reached the sorts of
conclusions advanced by Zerzan. Poststructuralist thinkers suggest
instead that not only are such linguistic and discursive systems
essentially contestable, they are contingent and open-endedâif not
altogether entropic.
Any synoptic discussion of poststructuralist views of language naturally
must be beyond the scope of this paper. Because capable scholars have
explored the territory so well, it should suffice here merely to review
some of their findings. Perhaps the best place to start is with Saul
Newman (2001; 2005; 2010), whose work provides a thorough examination of
poststructuralist thought from an anarchist perspective. Acknowledging
that it undermines or deconstructs linguistic, political, and other
structures, Newman provides us with an account of the two main positions
in poststructuralist thought. âThe first position, exemplified by
thinkers like Foucault and Deleuze, suggests that rather than there
being a single, centralized structure, there are instead multiple and
heterogeneous discourses, power relations or âassemblages of desireâ
that are constitutive of identity, and are immanent throughout the
social fieldâ (Newman 2005, 5).
Michel Foucaultâs work, it seems to me, primarily has outlined how power
operates in a constructive manner to constitute different subject
positions. Discursive and disciplinary mechanisms fashion the different
sorts of identities that are possible within any given social
configuration, and these identities both enable and constrain us.
âEach society has its regime of truth, its âgeneral politicsâ of
truthâthat is, the types of discourse it accepts and makes function as
true; the mechanisms and instances that enable one to distinguish true
and false statements; the means by which each is sanctioned; the
techniques and procedures accorded value in the acquisition of truth;
the status of those who are charged with saying what counts as true
(Foucault 2006, 168).â
Like Marx before him, Foucaultâs contributions also highlight the
evolving nature of social and political institutions and discourses. To
know that life could be otherwise, to abandon a fatalistic point of
view, is doubtless an important step toward emancipation. If other
identities are possible, and I can choose which ones to adopt, then we
are surely pointed toward one possible exit from the cycle of
subjectification and reproduction. The range of identities available to
us is theoretically quite vast because the linguistic and ideological
systems that we confront are not only filled with contradictions, they
are never wholly systematic. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari (1987,
161) suggest that a different social order, a different machine is
always possible. âLodge yourself on a stratum, experiment with the
opportunities it offers, find an advantageous place on it, find
potential movements of deterritorialization, possible lines of flight,
experience them, produce flow conjunctions here and there, try out
continuums of intensities segment by segment, have a small plot of new
land at all times.â Because multiple codes pervade systems of discourse,
because there exist smooth spaces to contrast with the striated ones,
people have more many options to explore than they realize.
Returning to Newmanâs typology, we find that the âsecond position,
exemplified by thinkers like Derrida and Lacan, places more emphasis on
the structure itself, but sees it as indeterminate and unstableâ (Newman
2005, 5). Indeed, one of the chief contributions that Jacques Derrida
makes is to identify language as a realm of undecidability, âan
indefinite fluctuation between two possibilitiesâ (Derrida 1991, 194).
Even in the most carefully constructed text, there remain concepts and
ideas that do not cohere, problems that are left unstated and
unresolved. The contradictions and aporias that Derrida frequently finds
in literary and philosophical texts suggest that no impregnably closed
system of thought could ever be devised. Jacques Lacan similarly regards
the external orders that constitute subjects as highly capable, but
flawed. They effectively constitute the identity of any subject, but
that identity must ever remain incomplete or inadequate. For example,
once I identify as a _____, it is always in order to ask if being a is
all there is to life. One is always left wanting more, so identification
thus becomes the process of trying to fill the lack at the heart of the
subject (Olivier 2004; Laclau and Zac 1994).
The political implications of poststructuralist thought no doubt are
many, but the one that matters most is this: the subjects, structures,
and discourses that constitute the political are all contingent,
indeterminate, and open-ended (Newman 2005, 140, 154). At this point,
poststructuralism reveals its affinities with anarchism; indeed, under
the influence of poststructuralist critiques of identity and ontology, a
postanarchism that is simultaneously antipolitical and political has
emerged. As an anti-politics, postanarchism shares with traditional
anarchism âits rejection of the state and its suspicion of political
representation, and it endorses its fundamental ethical critique of
political powerâ (Newman 2010, 69). As a political theory and practice,
postanarchism endorses any number of revolutionary projects (insofar as
they are rooted in an ethics that shuns hierarchy and adopts a
prefigurative stance) without having any guarantee that they either will
be successful or will avoid replicating the domination they seek to
replace.
An anarchism built on poststructuralist insights into language and
discourse can take us in any number of directions. One direction would
have us pay attention to the performative aspects of identity suggested
by Foucault and deftly developed by Judith Butler (1999). In her view,
genderâand by extension, ideological identityâis neither a substance nor
a set of attributes; rather, âgender is always a doing.â It is
constituted by âa set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory
frame that congeal over time to produce the appearance of substance, of
a natural sort of beingâ (Butler 1999, 33, 44). In this context,
processes of repetition and iterability, not singular acts of decision,
provide the route to new constructions of oneâs identity (Butler 1999,
179-188). From this point of view, then, one is not born, but becomes an
anarchist. Becoming an anarchist does not mean joining a party, taking a
vow, or making a decision; rather, it likely involves succumbing to a
seduction, giving oneself over to âthe feeling of anarchyâs lureâ (de
Acosta 2009, 27). Becoming an anarchist simply means doing the things
that anarchists do (whatever that might be)âand doing them over and over
again.
A second theoretical direction suggested by poststructuralism affirms
not only that language is contingent and open-ended, but that the
struggle against the State is similarly so. For example, in conceiving
their political practice, postanarchists have settled for âa nomadic
agent of change: one that can disappear, who is not bound by place, or
past experiencesâ (Franks 2007, 138). As nomadic agents learned to flow
in and out of vortices, as they began to explore the smooth spaces in
any social configuration, they recreated the model of revolutionary
struggle. Rather than direct, frontal assaults on the citadels of
powerâassaults designed to acquire powerâthey preferred indirect
encounters focused on creating room for autonomy. In this context, then,
Deleuze and Guattari (1987, 353) certainly altered the metaphors of
political struggle. Traditional images of revolution call to mind a game
of chess: âChess is indeed a war, but an institutionalized, regulated,
coded war, with a front, a rear, battles.â A better image, they suggest,
is that of Goâa game marked by âwar without battle lines, with neither
confrontation nor retreat, without battles even: pure strategy, whereas
chess is a semiology.â The problem with this approach, of course, is
that traditional organizing gives way to expressive actsâresulting in
the tension between âsocial anarchismâ and âlifestyle anarchismâ
featured in the famous polemic by Murray Bookchin (1995).
A final theoretical direction suggested by poststructuralism focuses on
Lacanian psychoanalysis. Famous for having observed that the unconscious
is structured like a language, Lacan reinterpreted Freudâs theories of
psychosexual development in order to account for its linguistic
character. Resolving the Oedipal situation, then, becomes a matter of
integrating into the Symbolic Order or not. Nevertheless, a Lacanian
route to social and political liberation is not immediately obvious.
Ernesto Laclau (1996, 52), for example, points us toward the lack at the
heart of any subjectâa conception in which âantagonism and exclusion are
constitutive of all identity.â To put it another way, âidentity is
constituted around a fundamental lack at the heart of the subject, and
that identity is constituted through the identification with external
objects, thus temporarily filling the lackâ (Thomassen 2004, 558). The
lack, though, can never be successfully overcome. Just as soon as one
identifies as an anarchist, for example, then the expansive content of
what being an anarchist involves beckons; perpetual dissatisfaction and
alienation ensue.
Another Lacanian, Slavoj Zizek, observes that any ideology can only be
maintained by illusion or fantasyâthe illusion that people make
conscious decision; the fantasy that obscures ideologyâs role in
structuring our outlooks. If any ideology functions through fantasy,
then, just how is it possible for individual subjects to emerge from its
grip? The answer that Zizek (1989, 84, original emphasis) offers is to
traverse the fantasy; as âsoon as they perceive that the real goal is
the consistency of the ideological attitude itself, the effect is
self-defeating.â In other words, âbecause ideology expects to be taken
cynically, the ultimate act of transgression is perhaps to follow it to
the letter, to thoroughly identify with itâ (Newman 2005, 67). From a
psychoanalytic standpoint, traversing the fantasy of ideology might make
therapeutic sense.
From the standpoint of political practice, though, the advice seems
problematic. Consider this: In the face of an omnipresent state, how
should an anarchist behave? Taking Zizek seriously would suggest that an
anarchist, opposed to all forms of coercive authority, should embrace
the state to the fullestâbecome its cheerleader, campaign and vote for
candidates, get a degree in public administration, and pursue a
bureaucratic career.
A number of French feminists also found inspiration in Lacanian theory,
as they pondered what it meant for women to be in but not of the
Symbolic Order. In their view, womenâwhose status is outside of
language, who possess a jouissance beyond significationâ would never be
liberated unless a new language could be developed. For Helene Cixous
(2000), this meant creating a feminine writing (Iâecriture feminine) in
which women could write themselves as women, and thereby, break out of a
masculine libidinal and cultural economy. For Cixous (2000, 261,
original emphasis), writing thus represents âthe very possibility of
change, the space that can serve as a springboard for subversive
thought, the precursory movement of a transformation of social and
cultural structures.â If women need to âwrite through their bodiesâ
(Cixous 2000, 267), perhaps anarchists should begin to âwrite through
their freedom.â Perhaps this has already been done, as one could point
to countless examples of writing for anarchist papers, zines, and other
unconventional outlets. Still, might not a postanarchist who is
prescriptive about what form of writing is sufficiently anarchist
ironically fall victim to the very essentialism postanarchism critiques?
Can one even identify a specifically anarchist style, as opposed to a
liberal or Marxist one?
In sum, postanarchism generally offers a useful corrective to the
essentialist ontology held by theorists like Zerzan. As noted above,
Zerzan regards language as the decidedly closed system that undergirds
civilization and its ills. Without any hope of reforming it, or any way
to work within itâdoing so would be akin to collaboration with the
enemyâthere is but one path to liberation, which is to abandon language
altogether. Zerzan urges anarchists to strive for an authentic form of
communication that is beyond words, that is outside symbolic culture.
For poststructuralist theorists, and the postanarchists who have learned
from them, such a pure radical outside is but an impossible dream. As
Newman (2010, 13) observes, anarchist politics should not be based âon
essentialist identities, processes of dialectical unfolding or on a
certain organic conception of the social body; rather the possibilities
of radical transformation should be seen as contingent moments of
openness that break with the idea of a naturally determined order.â
The antiessentialism that makes poststructuralist thought appealing
carries within it this âtheoretical impasse: if there is no
uncontaminated point of departure from which power can be criticized or
condemned, if there is no essential limit to the power one is resisting,
then surely there can be no resistance against itâ (Newman 2001, 5).
Newman and others suggest that poststructuralism nevertheless contains
the answer to the very problem it presents. An outside is possible, but
it is not a permanent or radically exterior outside. Instead, âan
outside can emerge, paradoxically, from the insideâthat is, from within
these very structures of language, discourse, and powerâ (Newman 2005,
159). In this way, poststructuralist ontologies that highlight the
limits of signification and subjectification might provide a suitable
self-understanding for anarchist theory and practice.
In his review of Saul Newmanâs From Bakunin to Lacan, though, Todd May
(2002, par. 11) observed that he was ânot convinced that by utilizing a
deconstructive approach to language and politics there is room for the
kind of collective action that seems necessary for political success.â
The indeterminacy intrinsic to such theories, he suggested, would be
more likely to drive people apart than to bring them together. A better
approach, in Mayâs view, would be to âarticulate a conception of
language that sees meaningâand the political categories that arise from
itâas determinate but contingent, rather than necessarily
indeterminate.â In discerning an anarchist theory of language, one has
to take this concept of âcontingent determinacyâ very much to heart.
Certainly, the analysis above suggests that we need an account of
language that comprehends it as simultaneously natural (rather than
external), hegemonic (rather than politically neutral), as well as
contingently open-ended (rather than closed). The anarchist theorists
treated above appear to provide us with ideas that meet these criteria.
Chomsky, for one, tells us that the language faculty is a natural one
for human beings. It need not be interpreted as natural in the
essentialist sense, but rather, it should be seen as natural in the
biological senseâin other words, the ability to work with language is as
natural to us as the ability to grasp with opposable thumbs. Language is
a great existing social fact; it is one of the most natural things in
the world. As Landauer (2010b, 277) observes: âAnarchists need to
understand that the basis of both individual life and human co-existence
is something that cannot be invented. It is something that has to grow.â
Human communication is necessary, but there is no reason to assume (as
does Zerzan) that it has to be non-symbolic communication; even if there
were such a reason, the possibility of returning to a proto-human form
seems remote at best.
Even though language is natural, it nevertheless confronts us as an
external force because it is always already here. We are embedded within
its rules and discourses as soon as our linguistic faculty begins to
operate. In that context, it becomes easy to regard language and
ideology as agents of social reproduction, as vehicles of and supports
for domination, as âscreens of powerâ (Luke 1989). The great problem for
anarchist and other forms of radical political thought is to show how it
is possible to resist and remove domination. Whether the spark of
resistance stems from conceptual breaks fostered by autonomous practices
and situationist detournements, or from the ontological fissures
highlighted by poststructuralist theorists, anarchists and others have
argued that the existing order need not be a permanent one. As we have
been often reminded, another world is possible.
Reviewing the interactions among language, ideology, and anarchism
traced above, I am reminded of Chomskyâs (2004, 113) observation that âa
Marxist-anarchist perspective is justified quite apart from anything
that may happen in linguistics.â Although he regards any connection
between his linguistic (scientific) and anarchist (political) views as
tenuous at best, Chomsky does notice that they both are imbued with a
spirit of creativity and freedom. Rocker (1978), too, pointed to this
creative aspect when he asserted that language âis a structure in
constant change in which the intellectual and social culture of the
various phases of our evolution is reflected. It is always in flux,
protean in its inexhaustible power to assume new forms.â
Still, the search for a satisfactory account of language that could
support anarchist inquiry and practice has not yet concluded. The
hesitations and concerns about the philosophical and political adequacy
of poststructuralism expressed by May remain to be addressed. In his own
postanarchist classic, May (1994, 94) quotes from Anti-Oedipus, in which
Deleuze and Guattari urge us to âstop asking the question âWhat does it
signify?â and ask instead âWhat does it produce? What can it be used
for?ââ The latter questions are certainly in the spirit of anarchismâs
focus on concrete practice rather than abstract theory, on doing rather
than being. They are very pragmatic questions about how we get on with
things, about how we use language to carry on with the tasks of
lifeâpolitical, social, and otherwise. In other words, they are
questions that point to an as yet unexplored source for an anarchist
account of language that I believe meets the criteria set forth above.
As noted, an adequate account must not only regard language as natural,
hegemonic, and contingently open-ended; in addition, it must also have
some satisfactory implications for anarchist practice.
For all the attractions of poststructuralist thought, I propose that an
adequate account of language could be drawn from Ludwig Wittgenstein.
His approach shares with anarchism a pragmatic orientation that
emphasizes practice over theoryâeven in the course of theorizing. His
focus is not on developing an abstract ontology of the subject, but
rather on what language could do (and not do) for people: âThink of the
tools in a tool-box: there is a hammer, pliers, a saw, a screw-drive, a
rule, a glue-pot, glue, nails, and screws.âThe functions of words are as
diverse as the functions of these objectsâ (Wittgenstein 1958, §11). In
reading a good bit of poststructuralist writing, one often gets the
sinking feeling that language has gone on holiday(Wittgenstein 1958,
§38). Wittgenstein provides an important corrective because, for him, it
is more useful to focus on describing our everyday practices. This
position he shares with Alejandro de Acosta (2010, 119), who noted that
anarchismâs âcommonplaces (direct action, mutual aid, solidarity,
affinity groups, etc.) are not concepts but forms of social practice. As
such, they continually, virally, infect every even remotely
extraparliamentary or grassroots form of political action. And, beyond
politics, they compose a kind of interminable reserve of social
intelligence.â
Wittgensteinâs approach urges us to think pragmatically. In doing so, we
should return to our criteria for an adequate theory of language. First,
it must accept that language is natural, that it represents some great
existing fact. Wittgensteinâs approach most definitely begins with just
such a perspective. For him, language is an integral element of a
communityâs practices; indeed, âthe term âlanguage-gameâ is meant to
bring into prominence the fact that the speaking of a language is part
of an activity, or of a form of lifeâ (Wittgenstein 1958, §23, original
emphasis). Members of a given community do not have to deliberately
impose rules from the outside; they do not have to force creativity and
expressiveness out of an individual. What happens instead is that the
rules inherent in our practices are taught in the context of various
âlanguage gamesâ involving interactions between speakers. The language
games help set the boundaries of appropriate use of words. In so doing,
it establishes individuals as members of the community and gives them
the capacity to act. A Wittgensteinian perspective, without any need for
linguistic science or extra-historical ruminations, allows us to view
language as a natural phenomenon.
Second, an adequate theory of language should acknowledge that language
is not merely natural, but also hegemonic. Though language is âwoven
into all human activities and behavior, and accordingly our many
different uses of it are given content and significance by our practical
affairs, our work, our dealings with one another and with the world we
inhabitâ (Grayling 1996, 79); it should be seen as neither autonomous
nor essentialist. In learning a languageâthat is, in participating in a
form of lifeâwe naturally come to accept certain things as valid and
true. âThe child learns to believe a host of things. I.e., it learns to
act according to these beliefs. Bit by bit there forms a system of what
is believed, and in that system some things stand unshakeably [sic] fast
and some are more or less liable to shift. What stands fast does so, not
because it is intrinsically obvious or convincing; it is rather held
fast by what lies around itâ (Wittgenstein 1969, §144). Doubt never
enters the picture, at least initially; we first have to accept: âThe
child learns by believing the adult. Doubt comes after beliefâ
(Wittgenstein 1969, §160, original emphasis). As certain habits of
thought and action become established, they become constituted as common
sense, as second nature. As Wittgenstein (1980, 64e, original emphasis)
remarked of religion, âalthough itâs belief, itâs really a way of
living, or a way of assessing life. Itâs passionately seizing hold of
this interpretation.â We always learn to interpret our lives through the
prism of the language-games whose lessons we have absorbed. Even so,
Wittgenstein embraces no foundational or essentialist assumptions about
the subject positions available to us, no grand narrative on the order
of either class struggle or hegemonic contest.
Finally, our account of language should acknowledge its contingent and
open-ended character. For Wittgenstein (1969, §559), a language-game
simply exists: âIt is thereâlike our life.â Nevertheless, it is not a
permanently fixed feature. Not only does a language-game change with
time (Wittgenstein 1969, §256), but it is clear that âlanguage has no
single essenceâ and is instead âa vast collection of different practices
each with its own logicâ (Grayling 1996, 79). Although we âmake
ourselves in the practices that make usâ (de Acosta 2009, 31), those
same practices emerge and dissipate in a seemingly perpetual evolution.
At one point in the Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein (1958,
§309) asked himself, âWhat is your aim in philosophy?â His answer: âTo
shew the fly the way out of the fly- bottle.â The emancipatory project
in which anarchists are engaged has much the same orientation. It
involves developing a political space for action, âthe creation of an
interstitial distance within the state, the continual questioning from
below of any attempt to establish order from aboveâ (Critchley 2007,
122-123). That creative activity depends upon using imagination: âIf we
imagine the facts otherwise than as they are, certain language-games
lose some of their importance, while others become more important. And
in this way there is an alterationâa gradual oneâin the use of the
vocabulary of a languageâ (Wittgenstein 1969, §63). Any sustained
alteration in the language-games we play suggests a corresponding
alteration in the practices we perform, in the forms of life we inhabit.
In short, we have arrived in a highly pragmatic fashion at the
âcontingent determinacyâ favored by May, without resort to any elaborate
ontological architecture.
Though a Wittgensteinian account of language has much to recommend it,
its utility for the anarchist project may still remain in
doubtâparticularly because Wittgenstein has been viewed as both a
philosophical and political conservative (Robinson 2006). To show the
fly the way out of the bottle, to show that Wittgenstein might have
something meaningful to say to anarchists, let us return to the issue of
how to construct an alternative, oppositional identity. For Simon
Critchley (2007, 112, original emphasis), âthe labour of politics is the
construction of new political subjectivities, new political aggregations
in specific localities, a new dissensual habitus rooted in common sense
and the consent of those who dissent.â Similarly, the labor of political
theory becomes one of describing how it is possible for all that to
happen. All too often, though, theorists ponder matters at such an
abstract level that they ignore Wittgensteinâs (1958, §66) telling
admonition to look, rather than think, when we contemplate matters such
as the concept of a game or the nature of language. If we take this
admonition seriously, then we need to explore matters such as identity
formation from a more grounded standpoint.
The central question is how might a change in any dominant grammar of
identity be possible? How can we rearrange or articulate that grammarâs
elements in novel ways. When a grammar has become sedimented or
naturalized, subjects come to take things for granted or to see them in
the same wayâa phenomenon that David Owen (2003) has called âaspectival
captivity.â Aspectival captivity develops when a given picture of the
world becomes an implicit background or horizon (ânatural forgettingâ),
when it is taken for a universal (âphilosophical repressionâ), when it
becomes entrancing and captivating (Owen 2003, 87-88). When our
perspective comes into question through genealogical description and
critical reflection, or when things begin to appear in a new light,
genuine transformation is possible. âAspect dawning or change occurs
when one realizes that a new kind of characterization of an object or
situation may be given, and we see it in those termsâ (Norval 2006,
235).
Wittgensteinian reflections about aspect dawning lead one to the view
that identification is largely a retrospective, even retroactive,
process. It emerges not merely through rational persuasion, but also
through a subjectâs active participation in a practice: âThe subject
becomes a democratic subject, not simply because she is rationally
convinced it is the better option, though that may be part of the story,
but rather because she participates in democratic practices, which
retroactively allow her to identify as democratic subjectâ (Norval 2006,
241). In other words, because of this redescription of herselfâbecause
of this aspect changeâthe subject sees herself and things in general
quite differently now. Processes of redescription are central not only
to identity formation but also to the battles over representation, the
âsemiotic street fightsâ (Thompson 2010, 31), that occur after nearly
every major protest. With Black Bloc activists often pegged as
terrorists, with anarchists generally coded in stereotypical ways,
redescription is necessary if the prevailing frames are to be
undermined: âBy speaking about what the mask enables and not what it
means; by not seeking to simply refute possible negative readings ...,
the Black Bloc statement [posted on infoshop.org] effectively
reformulates the relationship between activists and objectsâ (Thompson
2010, 57, original emphasis).
In contexts related to identity, ideology, and language, the prospects
for change seem to be ever problematic. If revolution were easy, it
would be an everyday occurrence; but it is not. Breaking free of old
habits and conventional practices is not for everyone, nor can an
abstract ethics of the demand be particularly motivating for most
people. A more pragmatic orientation to the emancipatory project is
required. Critchley (2007, 147-148) observes that, no matter oneâs
preferred âontological theodicy, politics is the activity of the forming
of a common front, the horizontal aggregation of a collective will from
diverse groups with disparate demands.â Such a conception of politics
can be seen within Laclauâs logics of equivalence and difference. Such a
conception of politics requires confronting a dilemma of
congruenceâreplacing one ideological perspective with another can happen
only if the new perspective is somehow congruent with the old. Agents of
social and political change cannot persuade folks to embrace a new world
view âunless people see the point of itâthat is, unless they can
acknowledge its links to former habits of thought and unless it somehow
speaks to their conditionâ (Williams 1997, 141). The pressure for
congruence, I believe, translates relatively seamlessly into common
anarchist demands for prefigurationâfor being the change we wish to
bring.
In Culture and Value, Wittgenstein (1980, 20e) observes that sometimes
oneâs philosophy appears to be simply âa matter of temperament, and
there is something in this. A preference for certain similes could be
called a matter of temperament and it underlies far more disagreements
than you might think.â Temperament may indeed account for the various
strains of anarchist and radical thought explored above, as well as for
my preference for a pragmatic, Wittgensteinian account of language.
Still, such an account reminds us that language and ideologyâas well as
the forms of domination that they create and supportâare all part of the
life we currently experience. We cannot rest content with that reminder,
though, because the aim of our theoretical and activist practices is to
put us on a path toward liberation.
In this context, it is worth noting Christopher Robinsonâs (2006, par.
31) suggestion that âWittgensteinâs theorizing is not conservative; his
descriptivism entails and even demands a life devoted to non-conformity;
and the conventions he exposes at the base of all human languages is the
source of political and critical freedom.â The free, creative aspect of
his theorizing emerges in the multiplicity of language-games and the
diversity of forms of life that we encounter. As Wittgenstein (1958,
§18) observes: âOur language can be seen as an ancient city: a maze of
little streets and squares, of old and new houses, and of houses with
additions from various periods; and this surrounded by a multitude of
new boroughs with straight regular streets and uniform houses.â In
wandering through that cityâsquatting here, creating a TAZ there;
organizing here, performing direct action thereâwe are noticing
different language-games, observing the range of practices that are
possible, developing resources for both criticism and insurrection. In
short, we are not merely traveling as nomads from one milieu to another,
we are experiencing a life in which the âdogmatism and slogans that
formerly proclaimed a new era, the signposts for utopia, are everywhere
coming to an end. Everywhere, concepts have turned into reality,
becoming unpredictable, shifting, unstable. There is clarity only in the
land of appearances and words; where life begins, systems endâ (Landauer
2010a, 90-91).
Bey, Hakim. 2003. T.A.Z.: The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological
Anarchy, Poetic Terrorism, second ed. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia.
Bookchin, Murray. 1995. Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An
Unbridgeable Chasm. Oakland, CA: AK Press.
Butler, Judith. 1999. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of
Identity, 10th anniversary ed. New York: Routledge.
Chomsky, Noam. 2004. Language and Politics. Edited by C. P. Otero, 2nd
ed. Oakland, CA: AK Press.
. 2006. "Politics." In The Chomsky-Foucault Debate: On Human Nature,
68-116. New
York: New Press.
Cixous, Helene. 2000. "The Laugh of the Medusa." In French Feminism
Reader, ed. Kelly Oliver, 257-275. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Critchley, Simon. 2007. Infinitely Demanding: Ethics of Commitment,
Politics ofResistance. London: Verso.
Day, Richard J. F. 2005. Gramsci Is Dead: Anarchist Currents in the
Newest Social Movements. London: Pluto Press.
de Acosta, Alejandro. 2009. "Two Undecidable Questions for Thinking in
Which Anything
Goes." In Contemporary Anarchist Studies: An Introductory Anthology of
Anarchy in the Academy, ed. Randall Amster, Abraham DeLeon, Luis A.
Fernandez, Anthony J. Nocella and Deric Shannon. London: Routledge.
. 2010. "Anarchist Meditations, or: Three Wild Interstices of Anarchism
and Philosophy."
Anarchist Developments in Cultural Studies (1): 117-138.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus:
Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Translated by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1991. "From âThe Double Sessionâ." In A Derrida
Reader: Between the Blinds, ed. Peggy Kamuf, 171-199. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Foucault, Michel. 2006. "Truth and Power." In The Chomsky-Foucault
Debate: On Human Nature, 140-171. New York: New Press.
Franks, Benjamin. 2007. "Postanarchism: A Critical Assessment." Journal
of Political Ideologies
(2): 127-145.
Gensini, Stefano. 2010. "Linguistics and the Political Question of
Language." In Gramsci, Language, and Translation, ed. Peter Ives and
Rocco Lacorte, 63-79. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Edited by
Quention Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith. New York: International
Publishers.
Grayling, A. C. 1996. Wittgenstein: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Green, Marcus E., and Peter Ives. 2010. "Subalternity and Language:
Overcoming the
Fragmentation of Common Sense." In Gramsci, Language, and Translation,
ed. Peter Ives and Rocco Lacorte, 289-312. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Guimaraes, Rodrigo Gomes. 2010. "Zerzan, Primitivism, and the Value of
Culture." In New
Perspectives on Anarchism, ed. Nathan J. Jun and Shane Wahl, 333-361.
Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Howarth, David. 2000. Discourse. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Knabb, Ken, ed. 2006. Situationist International Anthology, revised and
expanded ed. Berkeley, CA: Bureau of Public Secrets.
Laclau, Ernesto. 1996. Emancipation(s). London: Verso.
Laclau, Ernesto, and Chantal Mouffe. 1985. Hegemony and Socialist
Strategy. London: Verso. Laclau, Ernesto, and Lilian Zac. 1994. "Minding
the Gap: The Subject of Politics." In The Making of Political
Identities, ed. Ernesto Laclau, 11-39. London: Verso.
Lakoff, George. 2004. Don't Think of An Elephant!: Know Your Values and
Frame the Debate-- The Essential Guide for Progressives. White River
Junction, VT: Chelsea Green. Landauer, Gustav. 2010a. "Anarchic Thoughts
on Anarchism." In Revolution and Other Writings: A Political Reader, ed.
Gabriel Kuhn, 84-91. Oakland, CA: PM Press.
. 2010b. "Do Not Learn Esperanto!" In Revolution and Other Writings: A
Political
Reader, ed. Gabriel Kuhn, 276-279. Oakland, CA: PM Press.
Luke, Timothy W. 1989. Screens of Power: Ideology, Domination, and
Resistance in Informational Society. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois
Press.
Maas, Utz. 2010. "Gramsci the Linguist." In Gramsci, Language, and
Translation, ed. Peter Ives and Rocco Lacorte, 81-99. Lanham, MD:
Lexington Books.
May, Todd. 1994. The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist
Anarchism. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
. 2002. "Lacanian Anarchism and the Left." Theory & Event, 6, 1.
http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory and event/v006/6.1may.html.
Newman, Saul. 2001. From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and the
Dislocation of Power. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
. 2005. Power and Politics in Poststructuralist Thought: New Theories of
the Political.
London: Routledge.
. 2010. The Politics of Postanarchism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press.
Norval, Aletta J. 2006. "Democratic Identification: A Wittgensteinian
Approach." Political Theory 34 (2): 229-255.
Nunberg, Geoffrey. 2007. Talking Right: How Conservatives Turned
Liberalism into a Tax-
Raising, Latte-Drinking, Sushi-Eating, Volvo-Driving, New York
Times-Reading, Body- Piercing, Hollywood-Loving, Left-Wing Freak Show.
New York: PublicAffairs.
Olivier, Bert. 2004. "Lacanâs Subject: The Imaginary, Language, the Real
and Philosophy."
South African Journal of Philosophy 23: 1-19.
Owen, David. 2003. "Genealogy as Perspicuous Representation." In The
Grammar of Politics, ed. Cressida J. Hayes, 82-98. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
"Peter Lamborn Wilson Interview, Part 2 of 2: The Economics of
Autonomous Zones." 2009.
March. http://affinityproject.org/interviews/plw2.html (3 April 2011).
Robinson, Christopher C. 2006. "Why Wittgenstein Is Not Conservative:
Conventions and Critique." Theory & Event, 9, 3.
http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory and event/v009/9.3robinson.html.
Rocker, Rudolph. 1978. "The Nation as a Community of Language."
http://www.anarchosyndicalism.net/rocker/nc-17.htm.
Rosiello, Luigi. 2010. "Linguistics and Marxism in the Thought of
Antonio Gramsci." In
Gramsci, Language, and Translation, ed. Peter Ives and Rocco Lacorte,
29-49. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Seliger, Martin. 1976. Ideology and Politics. London: George Allen &
Unwin.
Sheehan, Sean M. 2003. Anarchism. London: Reaktion Books.
Stirner, Max. 1995. The Ego and Its Own. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Thomassen, Lasse. 2004. "Lacanian Political Theory: A Reply to
Robinson." British Journal of Political and International Relations 6
(4): 558-561.
Thompson, AK. 2010. Black Bloc, White Riot: Anti-Globalization and the
Geneaology of Dissent. Oakland, CA: AK Press.
Thompson, John B. 1984. Studies in the Theory of Ideology. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Williams, Leonard. 1997. American Liberalism and Ideological Change.
DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by
G. E .M. Anscombe, 3rd ed. New York: Macmillan.
. 1969. On Certainty. Edited by G. E .M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright.
New York:
Harper Torchbooks.
. 1980. Culture and Value. Translated by Peter Winch. Chicago:
University of Chicago
Press.
Zerzan, John. 2006. Elements of Refusal, 2nd ed. Columbia, MO: C.A.L.
Press.
. 2009. "Who Is Chomsky?". 2 August 2009.
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/HTML/John Zerzan Who is Chomsky .html (30
March 2011).
Zizek, Slavoj. 1989. The Sublime Object of Ideology. London: Verso.