đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș benjamin-mcmyler-theoretical-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:03:13. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Theoretical Anarchism Author: Benjamin McMyler Date: 2014 Language: en Topics: philosophy, theory, Philosophical Anarchism Source: *Philosophical Topics*, Volume 42, Number 1, Spring 2014. DOI:10.5840/philtopics201442110
Philosophical anarchists hold that there is no such thing as genuine
practical authority. Most epistemologists seem to at least tacitly
accept an analogous position with respect to theoretical authority, that
there is no such thing as a kind of authority over belief that is
robustly analogous to genuine practical authority. I argue that
appreciating this has an important consequence. Absent reason to think
that there is a relevant difference between the practical and
theoretical cases, anarchism about practical and theoretical authority
should either stand or fall together.
In his Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Thomas Reid claims that
there is a class of mental capacities or activities that are irreducibly
social in nature. He terms such mental capacities âsocial operations of
mind.â
When [a person] asks information, or receives it; when he bears
testimony, or receives the testimony of another; when he asks a favor,
or accepts one; when he gives a command to his servant, or receives one
from a superior: when he plights his faith in a promise or contract;
these are acts of social intercourse between intelligent beings, and can
have no place in solitude. They suppose understanding and will; but they
suppose something more, which is neither understanding nor will; that
is, society with other intelligent beings.
(2002, 68) [End Page 219]
Reidâs catalogue of social operations of mind includes both theoretical
and practical or cognitive and conative activities. He classes the
asking and receiving of information and the giving and receiving of
testimony alongside the asking and receiving of favors, the giving and
receiving of commands and promises, and the formation of contracts,
claiming that all such activities cannot be reduced to the operation of
some combination of individual solitary capacities.
To ask a question, is as simple an operation as to judge or reason; yet
it is neither judgment, nor reasoning, nor simple apprehension, nor is
it any composition of these. Testimony is neither simple apprehension,
nor judgment, nor reasoning. The same may be said of a promise, or of a
contract. These acts of mind are perfectly understood by every man of
common understanding; but, when Philosophers attempt to bring them
within the pale of their divisions, by analysing them, they find
inexplicable mysteries, and even contradictions, in them.
(2002, 68)
By the âinexplicable mysteriesâ that result when philosophers attempt to
analyze the social operations of mind in terms of solitary operations,
Reid presumably has in mind Humeâs famous discussion of promise and
contract, but he is clear that these mysteries arise much more broadly
whenever one attempts to reduce any of the social operations of mind to
capacities that are solitary.
Stephen Darwall has made similar claims concerning the phenomenon of the
second person. In The Second-Person Standpoint, Darwall claims that
there are a variety of speech acts that purport to provide a distinctive
kind of reason for action that arises only within the context of
interpersonal or social relations. He calls these reasons
âsecond-personal reasons.â
A second-personal reason is one whose validity depends on presupposed
authority and accountability relations between persons and, therefore,
on the possibility of the reasonâs being addressed person-to-person.
Reasons addressed or presupposed in orders, requests, claims,
reproaches, complaints, demands, promises, contracts, givings of
consent, commands, and so on are all second-personal in this sense. They
simply wouldnât exist but for their role in second-personal address.
(2006, 8; original emphasis)
Darwall claims that orders, requests, claims, reproaches, complaints,
demands, promises, contracts, givings of consent, and commands are all
speech acts capable of generating distinctively second-personal reasons,
reasons that âwouldnât exist but for their role in second-personal
address,â and he holds that the phenomenon of the second person cannot
be reduced to or explained in terms of anything non-second-personal.
These notionsâsecond-personal authority, valid claim or demand,
second-personal reason, and responsibilityâtherefore comprise an
interdefinable circle; each implies all the rest. Moreover, I contend,
there is no way to break into this circle from outside it. Propositions
formulated only with normative and evaluative concepts that are not
already implicitly second-personal cannot adequately ground propositions
formulated with concepts within the circle.
(2006, 12) [End Page 220]
Darwallâs conception of the second person is sophisticated and complex,
and it might appear to have little in common with Reidâs discussion of
the social operations of mind. But it is worth noting that Reid himself
explicitly links the exercise of his social operations of mind, many of
which are identical to the speech acts that Darwall claims are capable
of producing irreducibly second-personal reasons, to the phenomenon of
the second person.
In all languages, the second person of verbs, the pronoun of the
second-person, and the vocative case in nouns, are appropriated to the
expression of social operations of mind, and could never have had place
in language but for this purpose: Nor is it a good argument against this
observation that, by a rhetorical figure, we sometimes address persons
that are absent, or even inanimated beings, in the second person. For it
ought to be remembered, that all figurative ways of using words or
phrases suppose a natural and literal meaning of them.
(2002, 70)
Reid claims that the function of the grammatical second person is to aid
in the exercise of the social operations of mind, and he even goes so
far as to claim that without the social operations, language would have
no need for the second person.
In this respect, there is a striking similarity between the phenomena
that Reid identifies under the heading of the social operations of mind
and the phenomena that Darwall identifies under the heading of the
second-person standpoint. Though their respective accounts of these
phenomena differ considerably, they both think that there is something
philosophically significant at work in transactions like promising,
contracting, and commanding. Moreover, they both think that appreciating
the philosophical significance of such transactions requires
appreciating their irreducibly social character. It requires
appreciating that what is going on in such transactions is not something
that can be reduced to some combination of individual or third-personal
materials.
Despite these similarities, Reid and Darwall differ in one crucial
respect. Whereas Reid includes cognitive operations like the asking and
receiving of information and the giving and receiving of testimony among
his social operations of mind, Darwall holds that the phenomenon of the
second person is essentially practical. He claims that there can be no
such thing as an irreducibly second-personal reason for belief, and he
holds that cognitive transactions like the giving and receiving of
testimony must ultimately bottom out in third-personal considerations
(2006, 57). Whereas Reid sees an important continuity between what is
going on in transactions like testifying and commanding, Darwall sees a
striking and important discontinuity.
In Testimony, Trust, and Authority, I argued that there is just as much
reason to think that there can be irreducibly second-personal reasons
for belief as there is to think that there can be irreducibly
second-personal reasons for action and that Darwallâs reasons for
thinking the contrary are unconvincing. I do not wish to rehearse or
defend that argument here. Instead, I would like to begin to approach
the general disagreement between Reid and Darwall by both narrowing my
focus and taking a rather large step back. Rather than focusing on
general claims about [End Page 221] the nature of the second person or
of second-personal reasons, I want to focus on one particular kind of
second-personal transaction, that involved in the exercise of authority,
particularly in the giving and receiving of orders and commands. And
rather than attempt to give a positive general account of the nature of
such authority relations, I want to examine a worry about their very
existence. There is a position in political philosophy that denies that
there is any such thing as genuine, legitimate, or de jure authority,
that there is any such thing as a person or group in a position to make
it the case that others ought to do things simply by directing them to
do so.[1] This position is typically called philosophical anarchism.
Philosophical anarchists admit the existence of de facto
authoritiesâpersons or groups that claim authority and have the power to
make it the case that others comply with their directivesâbut they hold
that power to enforce compliance is insufficient for genuine authority.
A genuine authority is not only able to make people do things but to
make it the case that they ought to do things simply by directing them
to do so. Such genuine authority, claims the philosophical anarchist,
doesnât exist.
Importantly, philosophical anarchism doesnât entail political anarchism.
Philosophical anarchism is a position concerning the existence of
genuine authority. This philosophical position doesnât entail the
political position that existing states and institutions ought to be
opposed or eliminated. Philosophical anarchists hold that even if there
is no such thing as genuine authority, we might still have good moral
and prudential reasons for conforming to the law. Moreover, avowed
philosophical anarchists divide according to whether they take the
anarchist thesis to be an a priori thesis concerning whether there can
possibly be such a thing as genuine authority or an a posteriori thesis
concerning whether existing legal and political institutions are
genuinely authoritative.[2]
In this paper I will be concerned with one particularly austere version
of the a priori philosophical anarchist position. I will argue that most
contemporary epistemologists seem to at least tacitly accept a position
concerning authority over belief that is structurally analogous to this
austere a priori philosophical anarchist position concerning authority
over action. Just as the a priori philosophical anarchist holds that
there can be no such thing as genuine authority over action, most
contemporary epistemologists seem to at least tacitly accept that there
can be no such thing as genuine authority over belief, that the very
idea of a kind of authority over belief that is robustly analogous to
legitimate practical authority is incoherent.[3] Most contemporary
epistemologists are, in this respect, theoretical anarchists.[4]
Appreciating this has an important consequence. If theoretical anarchism
genuinely parallels the a priori philosophical anarchist position with
respect to practical authority, then absent reason to think that there
is a relevant disanalogy between the theoretical and practical cases,
there is good reason to think that the theoretical and practical guises
of philosophical anarchism should either stand or fall together. If we
want to accept theoretical anarchism, as nearly all epistemologists do,
then we should be prepared to accept practical anarchism, and if we want
to [End Page 222] reject practical anarchism, as nearly all political
philosophers do, then we should be prepared to reject theoretical
anarchism.
Some political philosophers, including H. L. A. Hart and Joseph Raz,
seem prepared to reject both practical and theoretical anarchism.[5] I
think that this is the correct course to take, but I will not argue for
this directly here.[6] Rejecting philosophical anarchism ultimately
requires presenting a satisfying general account of the nature of
authority, and in this paper I only try to set the stage for such an
account by arguing that the fate of practical anarchism is quite
plausibly linked to the fate of theoretical anarchism. If this is right,
then there is good reason to think that a satisfying general account of
the nature of authority should be capable of explaining both theoretical
and practical authority. This amounts to a partial defense of Reidâs
contention that the phenomena he identifies under the heading of the
social operations of mind spans the divide between theoretical and
practical reason. At the very least, it should lead us to reconsider
whether and in what way the concept of authority ought to play a role in
epistemological theorizing similar to the role that it typically plays
in social and political theory.
Section II provides a very general characterization of one version of
the philosophical anarchist position with respect to practical
authority. This version of the anarchist position is a position
concerning reasons for action. The anarchist holds that there is no such
thing as what I call a distinctively authoritative reason for action, no
such thing as a reason for action of the kind that authoritative
practical directives purport to provide. Authoritative directives
purport to provide reasons for action that require that an agent
âsuspend her own private judgmentâ concerning what to do in favor of the
judgment of the authority, and this, claims the anarchist, is
incoherent. There can be no such reasons.
Section III applies this philosophical anarchist position to the case of
theoretical authority. Just as the anarchist about practical authority
holds that there is no such thing as a distinctively authoritative
reason for action, the anarchist about theoretical authority holds that
there is no such thing as a distinctively authoritative reason for
belief. There is no such thing as a reason for belief that requires that
a subject suspend her own private judgment concerning what is the case
in favor of the judgment of an authority.
Finally, section IV examines a series of remarks of Elizabeth Anscombeâs
that might be taken to point to a relevant difference between the
theoretical and practical cases, a difference that might give us reason
to think that the truth of theoretical anarchism simply follows from the
distinctive nature of theoretical rationality. If this is the case, then
we neednât think that the theoretical and practical guises of
philosophical anarchism should either stand or fall together. I argue
that although Anscombe identifies a genuine disanalogy between authority
over belief and authority over action, this disanalogy concerns a
feature of practical authority different from that which is targeted by
the philosophical anarchist. It therefore poses no threat to the idea
that practical and theoretical anarchism should either stand or fall
together. [End Page 223]
Arguments for philosophical anarchism are typically cast in moral terms.
Philosophical anarchists typically hold that there is something immoral
or unjust about obedience to authority. William Godwin, possibly the
first modern philosophical anarchist, claims that â[t]o a rational being
there can be but one rule of conduct, justice, and one mode of attaining
that rule, the exercise of his understandingâ (1971, 90). Godwin holds
that genuine obedience to authority involves suspending the exercise of
oneâs understanding and thus that obedience to authority is inherently
unjust. In a similar fashion, Robert Paul Wolff, one of the most
influential contemporary philosophical anarchists, claims that â[w]hen I
place myself in the hands of another, and permit him to determine the
principles by which I shall guide my behavior, I repudiate the freedom
and reason which give me dignity. I am then guilty of what Kant might
have called the sin of willful heteronomyâ (1970, 71â72). Wolff holds
that we have a moral duty to be autonomous, to make ourselves the
ultimate authors of our decisions. Like Godwin, he holds that genuine
obedience to authority involves willingly making someone else the
ultimate author of our decisions. Genuine obedience is therefore
immoral.
One might reasonably question whether autonomy is a moral duty and hence
whether there is something inherently immoral about obedience to
authority. As Scott Shapiro has argued, however, the philosophical
anarchist position can be formulated while abstracting away from such
specifically moral considerations (2002, 390). The reason that
anarchists like Godwin and Wolff hold that there is something immoral or
unjust about genuine obedience to authority is that they have a
particular conception of the nature of obedience. On this conception,
genuinely obeying an authorityâs directiveâtreating the authorityâs
directive as the kind of reason for action that it purports to
beâinvolves acting in a way that is inconsistent with rational autonomy.
This claim is independent of any particular claims concerning the value
of autonomy, and hence one might accept that there is no such thing as
genuine authority without accepting that there is anything immoral about
obedience to authority.
Philosophical anarchism is typically characterized as the denial that
subjects have a duty or obligation to obey the directives of purported
practical authorities. The anarchist position can be construed more
fundamentally, however, as a thesis about reasons for action. In denying
that there is such a thing as a duty or obligation of obedience, the
anarchist is denying that the directives of purported practical
authorities, directives such as orders and commands, provide an audience
with a distinctive kind of reason for action, a distinctive kind of
reason for complying with the directive. Depending on how one construes
the nature of obligation, this distinctive kind of reason for action
might amount to a duty or an obligation. Nevertheless, the anarchist
position can be formulated in such a way as to leave to one side
particular conceptions of the nature of obligation. On this formulation,
philosophical anarchism is the view that there is no such thing as a
distinctively [End Page 224] authoritative reason for action, no such
thing as a reason for action of the kind that orders and commands
intuitively purport to provide.[7]
The philosophical anarchist thus recognizes that practical authorities
purport to exercise a particular kind of normative power. They purport
to have the power to generate for others, through the issuing of
practical directives, reasons for action that would not exist absent the
directive. Authorities purport to create reasons. Moreover, the
anarchist recognizes that the reasons that practical authorities purport
to create are of a distinctive kind. Authoritative practical directives
purport to provide reasons for action that are predicated on the
audienceâs âsuspending her own private judgmentâ concerning what to do
in favor of the judgment of the authority. If the audience acts as
directed but without suspending her own private judgment concerning what
to do, then she conforms to the directive without genuinely obeying. She
acts as directed, but she doesnât act for the distinctive kind of reason
that the directive purports to provide.[8]
Imagine that I order you to give me your wallet. I have no authority
over you, and so my directive doesnât, of itself, give you a reason to
give me your wallet. You might judge that I could really use the money
and on this basis decide to give me your wallet, but here you conform to
my directive without genuinely obeying. You perform the action that I
direct you to perform, but you do not act for the kind of reason that my
directive purports to provide. This is because you have come to your own
conclusionâyou have made up your own mindâthat giving me your wallet is
the thing to do in the situation. Even if you take my order to be a
reliable indicator of the fact that I could really use the money, in
deciding to give me your wallet on the basis of this fact, you are
making up your own mind what to do. Authoritative practical directives
purport to provide reasons for action regardless of the audienceâs own
private judgment concerning the merits of the directed action. Hence, to
the extent that an audienceâs action is based on her own private
judgment concerning what to do, then to that extent she has not acted
for the particular kind of reason that the directive purports to
provide.
This characterization of the kind of reason for action that
authoritative practical directives purport to provide relies heavily on
the unexplained metaphor of suspending private judgment. At this level
of abstraction, however, there is something extremely intuitive about
this metaphor. Authoritative practical directives appear to be
distinguished from other speech acts intended to influence the actions
of others by the way in which they purport to provide reasons for action
that somehow substitute the authorityâs judgment for that of the
audience. In this respect, ordering or commanding someone to do
something is very different from advising someone to do something. In
advising an audience to do something, a speaker is presenting an
audience with considerations that count in favor of a course of action
completely independently of the speakerâs act of presenting them to the
audience. The audience is then in the position of coming to her own
conclusion concerning whether these independently available
considerations make the course of action the thing to do in the
situation. In contrast, when a speaker [End Page 225] commands an
audience to do something, the speaker is not simply presenting the
audience with a consideration that counts in favor of acting
independently of the command, and the audience is not thereby left in
the position of having to come to her own conclusion concerning whether
so acting is the thing to do. The command itself purports to provide a
reason for action regardless of the audienceâs own private judgment
concerning the merits of the directed action. Hence, it can be the case
that the audience ought to act as directed even if she thinks that the
command is mistaken, even if she thinks that, in her own private
judgment, so acting is not the thing to do.[9]
The philosophical anarchist position that I am concerned with here holds
that this intuitive feature of authoritative practical directives is
incoherent. The anarchist accepts that authoritative practical
directives purport to provide reasons for action that are predicated on
an audienceâs suspending her own private judgment concerning what to do
in favor of the judgment of the authority.[10] However, she holds that
to genuinely suspend oneâs own private judgment concerning what to do
would be to divorce oneâs actions from oneâs responsiveness to practical
reasons.[11] Insofar as this is the case, there can be no such thing as
a genuine reason for action that requires such suspension of private
judgment, no such thing as a distinctively authoritative reason. If
there were such reasons, they would be reasons for action acting on
which would be acting for a non-reason. The very idea of such a reason
is incoherent, and insofar as authoritative practical directives purport
to provide such reasons, these directives are incoherent as well. This
means that when an agent takes herself to be acting for such a
distinctively authoritative reason, she is acting irrationally. She is
acting on the basis of a consideration that does not, in the way in
which it purports, bear positively on the question what to do.[12]
Importantly, in claiming that there is no such thing as a distinctively
authoritative reason for action, philosophical anarchists are not
denying that the directives of de facto practical authorities can amount
to genuine reasons for action. Wolff presents an example of a ship
passenger taking the commands of the shipâs captain to be genuine
reasons for acting as directed without genuinely obeying and so without
sacrificing her rational autonomy:
Taking responsibility for oneâs actions means making the final decisions
about what one should do. For the autonomous man, there is strictly
speaking no such thing as a command. If someone in my environment is
issuing what are intended as commands, and if he or others expect those
commands to be obeyed, that fact will be taken account of in my
deliberations. I may decide that I ought to do what the person is
commanding me to do, and it may even be that his issuing of the command
is the factor in the situation which makes it desirable to do so. For
example, if I am on a sinking ship and the captain is giving orders for
manning the lifeboats, and if everyone else is obeying the captain
because he is the captain, I may decide that under the circumstances I
had better do what he says, since the confusion caused by disobeying him
would be generally harmful. But insofar as I make such a decision, I am
not obeying his command; that is, I am not acknowledging him as [End
Page 226] having authority over me. I would make the same decision, for
exactly the same reasons, if one of the passengers had started to issue
âordersâ and had, in the confusion, come to be obeyed.
(1970, 15â16; original emphasis)
This passage has puzzled commentators. Harry Frankfurt, for example,
claims that Wolff is here being flatly inconsistent (1973, 409). Whereas
Wolff sometimes claims that the autonomous agent âmay do what another
tells him, but not because he has been told to do itâ (1970,14), in this
passage, Wolff portrays the ship passenger as maintaining her autonomy
even though she clearly acts as she does because she has been told to do
so. The captainâs issuing of the command is, as Wolff puts it, âthe
factor in the situationâ on the basis of which the passenger
autonomously decides to act.
I think that we can make sense of what Wolff says about the ship
passenger without charging him with inconsistency. The anarchist about
practical authority can reject obedience to authority while at the same
time admitting that the commands of practical authorities can amount to
genuine reasons for action by claiming that the kind of reason for
action provided by a speakerâs command is in no way distinctively
authoritative. Orders and commands are nothing more that ordinary events
that an audience must take into account in making up her own mind
concerning what to do. In certain circumstances, a speakerâs command may
be âthe factor in the situationâ that makes it the case that the
audience ought to act as commanded, but in judging that this is the
case, an audience is doing nothing more than exercising her own
judgment. If an audience proceeds to act as commanded, then she will be
merely conforming to the command. She will not be genuinely obeying.
In this respect, to say that there is no such thing as a distinctively
authoritative reason for action is not to say that de facto
authoritative directives cannot provide genuine reasons for action. The
commands of others can provide perfectly genuine reasons for action
without providing distinctively authoritative reasons. In fact, the view
that authoritative directives cannot provided genuine reasons for
actionâa view encouraged, admittedly, by Wolffâs claim that the
autonomous agent may do what she is told but not because she has been
told to do itâis so profoundly implausible that it is difficult to
imagine any philosophical anarchist actually accepting it. The orders
and commands of speakers are ordinary empirical events that should be
capable of figuring into an agentâs reasoning about what to do in the
same way as any other ordinary events. Just as a childâs scream can give
me a reason to rush to her aid, so can the commands of authorities give
us reasons to act, even reasons to act in conformity with the commands.
To deny this would be to single authoritative directives out as a
special class of events that, for some mysterious reason, are simply
incapable of bearing on the question what to do.
This means that if we are to interpret the anarchist position at all
charitably, we shouldnât interpret it as denying that authoritative
directives can provide genuine reasons for action. When Wolff claims
that the autonomous individual may do [End Page 227] what she is told,
but not because she has been told to do it, he isnât denying that the
autonomous individual may take her being told to do something to bear
positively on the question whether to do it. What Wolff is denying is
that the autonomous individual takes her being told to do something to
be a consideration that counts in favor of doing it in a distinctively
authoritative way, in a way that is predicated on the individualâs
suspending her own private judgment concerning what to do. This helps to
explain Wolffâs claim that, for the autonomous individual, there is
strictly speaking no such thing as a command (1970, 15). Surely, the
autonomous individual recognizes that there are such things as commands.
She recognizes that there exist speech acts that are issued with
particular authoritative intentions and that thereby purport to provide
a distinctively authoritative reason for action. According to the
anarchist, these intentions are incoherentâthere is no such thing as a
distinctively authoritative reason for action, and so the intention to
give such a reason to an audience is an intention that cannot possibly
be fulfilled. De facto authoritative directives therefore cannot provide
reasons for action in the way in which they are intended. Nevertheless,
they can still provide reasons for action in ways other than that in
which they are intended.
With this formulation of the philosophical anarchist position concerning
reasons for action in view, we can now begin to assess how this position
might apply to theoretical authority, or authority over belief.
Philosophical anarchism is almost invariably formulated as a thesis
about practical authority. Anarchists hold that there are no genuine
practical authorities, no persons or groups whose directives generate
for others duties or obligations of obedience. So formulated, this
position might appear difficult to apply to theoretical authority.
Theoretical authorities do not demand obedience, and we donât appear to
have a duty or obligation to believe the statements of theoretical
authorities.
Nevertheless, I have argued that the anarchist position concerning
practical authority can be construed as a position concerning reasons
for action, and theoretical authorities certainly do purport to provide
reasons. A theoretical authorityâs testimony, her telling an audience
that p, purports to provide an audience with an epistemic reason for
belief concerning the content of the testimony. Theoretical authorities
thus purport to exercise a normative power. They purport to have the
power to generate for others through testifying epistemic reasons that
would not exist absent the testimony. Moreover, at least superficially,
the epistemic reasons that theoretical authorities purport to provide
appear very similar to the reasons for action purportedly provided by
authoritative practical directives. A theoretical authorityâs testimony
purports to provide an epistemic reason that is predicated on the
audienceâs somehow suspending her own private judgment concerning what
is the case in favor of the judgment of the authority. If the audience
believes [End Page 228] what the authority says but without suspending
her own private judgment, then she conforms to the testimony but without
genuinely assenting to the authority. She believes what the authority
says, but she doesnât believe for the distinctive kind of reason that
the authorityâs testimony purports to provide.
Imagine that a well-respected climate scientist tells me that global
warming is occurring and is largely the result of human activity. This
gives me an epistemic reason to believe that global warming is
occurring, and it does so even if my own personal experience suggests
otherwise. My own personal experience might suggest that average
temperatures are actually declining, but the climate scientist is in a
better position to know than I am. She is an expert, and her testimony
is offered with the intention that it provide me with an epistemic
reason that is predicated on my suspending my own private judgment
concerning what is the case. The climate scientist is not trying to
rationally persuade me that global warming is occurring. She is not
giving me an argument with the intention that I come to my own
conclusion about things. She is simply telling me that such and such is
the case. Hence, properly accepting her testimonyâtaking her testimony
to be the kind of reason for belief that it purports to beâwould appear
to require suspending my own private judgment in favor of that of the
authority. If I believe what it is that the scientist says but without
suspending my own private judgment concerning the facts, then I conform
to the authorityâs theoretical directive, but I do not believe in the
way in which the authority intends. As Elizabeth Anscombe (1979) puts
it, I believe what it is that the speaker says, but I do not believe
her.[13]
Like the anarchist about practical authority, the theoretical anarchist
holds that this intuitive feature of authoritative theoretical
directives is incoherent. She might accept that authoritative
theoretical directives, such as expert testimony, purport to provide
epistemic reasons that are predicated on an audienceâs suspending her
own private judgment concerning what is the case.[14] However, she holds
that to genuinely suspend oneâs own private judgment concerning what is
the case would be to divorce oneâs beliefs from oneâs responsiveness to
epistemic reasons. Insofar as this is the case, there can be no such
thing as an epistemic reason for belief that requires such suspension of
private judgment, no such thing as a distinctively authoritative reason
for belief. If there were such reasons, they would be epistemic reasons
believing on the basis of which would be believing for a
non-(epistemic)-reason. The very idea of such a reason is incoherent,
and insofar as authoritative theoretical directives purport to provide
such reasons, these directives are incoherent as well. This means that
when an agent takes herself to believe for such a distinctively
authoritative reason, she believes irrationally. She believes on the
basis of a consideration that cannot, in the way in which it purports,
bear positively on the question what is the case.[15]
Just as the anarchist about practical authority is in a position to
accept that purportedly authoritative practical directives can amount to
genuine reasons for action, so the anarchist about theoretical authority
is in a position to accept that purportedly authoritative theoretical
directives can amount to genuinely epistemic [End Page 229] reasons. The
theoretical anarchist can reject assent to theoretical authority while
at the same time admitting that expert testimony can amount to a genuine
reason for belief by claiming that the kind of reason for belief
provided by such testimony is in no way distinctively authoritative. The
testimony of so-called theoretical authorities is nothing more than
ordinary inductive evidence that an audience must take into account in
making up her own mind concerning what is the case. In certain
circumstances, a speakerâs testimony might make it the case that the
audience ought to believe what the speaker says, but in judging that
this is the case, an audience is doing nothing more than exercising her
own judgment. If an audience proceeds to believe what she is told, then
she will be merely conforming to the speakerâs testimony. She will not
be genuinely assenting to theoretical authority. Testimonial belief thus
does not involve any kind of assent to authority. In particular, it
doesnât involve suspending oneâs own private judgment in favor of the
judgment of the authority. Instead, it involves the simple exercise of
oneâs own judgment in proportioning oneâs belief to the evidence.[16]
Most contemporary epistemologists seem to at least tacitly accept this
general position concerning theoretical authority. This includes both
reductionists and anti-reductionists about testimony. Reductionists
about testimony hold that a speakerâs testimony amounts to little more
than a species of ordinary inductive evidence. Anti-reductionists reject
this, but in so doing they rarely go so far as to claim that testimony
amounts to anything like a distinctively authoritative reason for
belief.[17] Anti-reductionists typically construe comprehension of a
speakerâs testimony as providing a prima facie reason for belief
analogous to the prima facie reason for belief provided by perceptual
representation. They thus tend to construe testimony as analogous to the
kind of non-inductive âevidenceâ provided by perceptual experience.
Importantly, the reason for belief provided by this non-inductive
testimonial evidence is not taken to be predicated on anything like the
audienceâs suspending her own private judgment concerning the content of
the testimony, and so these anti-reductionist positions appear to be
consistent with the theoretical anarchist rejection of genuine
theoretical authority.
In this respect, I think that it is fair to say that most contemporary
epistemologists would be inclined to accept theoretical anarchism. This
epistemological position is rarely explicitly formulated, and to my
knowledge it is never referred to as a kind of anarchism. But this
actually points to the strength of the anarchist position. Anarchism
with respect to theoretical authority is typically taken to be so
obviously correct that it is difficult to understand how it could
possibly be denied. How can a speakerâs testimony possibly be anything
other than more or less reliable evidence that an audience uses to make
up her own mind what to believe? Anarchism with respect to practical
authority isnât typically taken to be so obvious, but it isnât clear why
it shouldnât be. One might equally wonder how it could possibly be
denied. How can a speakerâs command that an audience do something
possibly be anything other than a more or less reliable guide that the
audience uses to make up her own mind what to do? [End Page 230]
The general philosophical anarchist position that I have articulated
thus appears to be one that can be applied to both practical and
theoretical authority. Applied to practical authority, it is the view
that there is no such thing as a distinctively authoritative reason for
action. Applied to theoretical authority, it is the view that there is
no such thing as a distinctively authoritative epistemic reason for
belief. Moreover, both the practical and theoretical guises of this
anarchist position stem from a common sourceâthe idea that âsuspending
private judgmentâ in the way that is intuitively required for genuine
obedience or assent to authority involves suspending oneâs
responsiveness to reasons and is therefore inconsistent with rational
agency.[18] According to the philosophical anarchist, the very idea of a
distinctively authoritative reason for belief or action is incoherent,
and so there can be no such thing as genuine theoretical or practical
authority. The philosophical anarchist can admit the existence of de
facto theoretical and practical authorities, authorities whose
directives purport to provide distinctively authoritative reasons for
belief and action, and she can even admit that these directives can, in
the appropriate circumstances, amount to genuine reasons for belief and
action. However, she denies that these reasons are distinctively
authoritative. She denies that there is any such thing as a reason for
belief or action that is predicated on a subjectâs suspending her own
private judgment.
Together?
The structural parallel between the anarchist positions with respect to
theoretical and practical authority suggests, I think, that the two
positions should either stand or fall together. If we accept theoretical
anarchism, as most epistemologists do, then we should be prepared to
accept practical anarchism, and if we reject practical anarchism, as
most political philosophers do, then we should be prepared to reject
theoretical anarchism. Perhaps this can be avoided, however. Perhaps the
fate of theoretical anarchism shouldnât be tied in this way to the fate
of practical anarchism. One might argue that the truth of theoretical
anarchism is simply a function of the nature of theoretical rationality
and, as a result, that it has no implications for practical authority.
One of the ways in which theoretical and practical rationality differ
would then be that only practical rationality admits of distinctively
authoritative reasons, and the concept of legitimate or de jure
authority would then be an essentially practical concept that has no
direct application to belief. This could be construed as a particular
application of Darwallâs broader claim that there is something
essentially practical about the second-person standpoint.
If this is right, then it would explain why the anarchist position
regarding theoretical authority is rarely even formulated let alone
argued for. If theoretical anarchism simply follows from the nature of
theoretical rationality, then this position might look fundamentally
different from the philosophical anarchist [End Page 231] position with
respect to practical authority, so different, in fact, that it might not
even deserve to be called a form of anarchism. If the nature of
theoretical rationality makes it the case that there can be no such
thing as a kind of authority over belief robustly analogous to
legitimate practical authority, then nothing like the anarchist
challenge to the existence of legitimate practical authority can even
arise in the theoretical realm.
Though many philosophers seem to be attracted to the idea that
theoretical and practical rationality differ fundamentally with respect
to the issue of authority, this idea is rarely argued for in any
detail.[19] In the end, countering this idea will require providing a
general theory of the differences between theoretical and practical
rationality and of the way in which authority can be exercised in the
theoretical and practical domains. I hope to provide such a general
theory elsewhere. For now, however, I would like to end by pointing to
some of the difficulties involved in developing a convincing argument
for this widely accepted idea. In order to do this, I want to examine a
series of remarks of Elizabeth Anscombeâs aimed at articulating some of
the important differences between theoretical and practical authority.
While Anscombe does not, as I read her, deny the existence of genuine
theoretical authority, she is at pains to argue that there are
significant differences between authority over belief and authority over
action, differences that might lead one to think that, whatever
theoretical authority actually amounts to, it cannot be something that
robustly parallels legitimate practical authority.
In âAuthority in Moralsâ (1981), Anscombe examines the complex question
of whether and in what respect there can be authorities in moral
matters. Preparatory to her discussion of specifically moral authority,
she describes several interconnected differences between authority over
belief and authority over action. She begins by noting that, in the case
of authority over belief, an audienceâs judging that what the authority
says is mistaken is tantamount to a rejection of her authority, while in
the case of authority over action, an audienceâs judging that what the
authority demands is mistaken is consistent with respecting her
authority (1981, 43). If someone tells me that p, and if I think that
the speaker is mistaken, that p isnât the case, then I am not treating
her as a theoretical authority on the matter. In contrast, if someone
tells me to Ί, and if I think that the speaker is mistaken, that Ί-ing
isnât the thing to do in the situation, then I might very well continue
to treat her as an authority. I might rationally obey the speakerâs
demand while continuing to think that the demand is mistaken.
One might take this as reason to deny that the kind of suspension of
private judgment intuitively required for genuine obedience to practical
authority is so much as possible in the theoretical realm. As we have
seen, such suspension of private judgment makes room for cases in which
it is rational for a subject to obey an authorityâs command to Ί even
though the subject thinks, in her own private judgment, that Ί-ing is
not the thing to do. A soldier might judge that her commanding officerâs
order to Ί is mistaken but still rationally decide to Ί. However, [End
Page 232] it might seem that there is no room for such cases in the
theoretical realm. There is no room for cases in which it is rational
for a subject to judge, in her own private judgment, that p is false and
still accept the speakerâs testimony, thereby believing that p. One
might take this to demonstrate that the kind of suspension of private
judgment that is intuitively required for genuine obedience to practical
authority has no genuine analogue in the theoretical realm.[20]
I think that this purported disanalogy between the theoretical and
practical cases is, at the very least, overblown. Consider, first, the
theoretical case. The case that isnât possible in the theoretical realm
has the following form. The subject both believes that p is false and
accepts the speakerâs testimony, thereby believing that p is true. This
cannot be rational. A subject cannot rationally settle the question
whether p both positively and negatively. However, the same is true in
the practical sphere. A subject cannot rationally settle the practical
question whether to Ί both positively and negatively. To settle the
practical question whether to Ί is, I take it, to set oneâs will or form
an intention.[21] But one cannot rationally settle this question
negatively, thereby willing or intending not to Ί, and accept a
speakerâs command, thereby willing or intending to Ί. Moreover, the case
of the soldier doesnât have this form. The soldier does not both intend
not to Ί and intend to Ί. Rather, she intends to Ί on the basis of her
commanding officerâs order, thereby settling positively the question
whether to Ί, even though, in a sense that remains to be explained, she
judges that the officerâs order is mistaken.
In this respect, whatever exactly it means to say that the soldier
judges that the officerâs command is mistaken, it must amount to
something less than the soldierâs settling negatively the question
whether to Ί. Perhaps the soldier simply counts as having settled
negatively the question whether, absent the officerâs command, Ί-ing
would be the thing to do.[22] This would be to say that, absent the
speakerâs command, the speaker wouldnât settle positively the question
whether to Ί. However, if this is all that is going on in the practical
case, then it appears that something analogous is possible in the
theoretical realm. Imagine that you tell me that something extremely
improbable happened to you in the past. I argue with you, claiming that
the occurrence of such an event is indeed extremely improbable, but you
stick to your guns. You insist that despite the acknowledged
improbability of such an event, the event did indeed occur. After
arguing for a while, you say to me, âLook, Iâm telling you that this
happened. Youâre just going to have to believe me.â This looks like a
case in which it might be perfectly rational for me to believe you that
p in spite of the fact that, absent your testimony, I wouldnât believe
that p. Clearly, this is not a case in which I both believe that p is
false and nevertheless accept your testimony, but as weâve seen, the
case of the soldier isnât like this either. In both this theoretical
case and the practical case of the soldier, we have a subject rationally
accepting a speakerâs testimony or command despite judging that, absent
the speakerâs testimony or command, this wouldnât be the thing to
believe or do. [End Page 233]
Interestingly, Anscombe seems to make this very point herself. In
discussing the idea that oneâs own conscience must be the ultimate
arbiter of right and wrong, she writes:
There is confusion here. Let conscience be oneâs judgment of right and
wrong, i.e. of good and evil in conduct, of what is virtuous and what
vicious to do. Then to say that oneâs own conscience is necessarily
supreme arbiter in such matters is to say that necessarily what one
judges right and wrong, one judges right and wrong.
One could similarly say that one cannot think anything to be true
without thinking it. But that does not tend to show that one cannot
think a thing on the strength of what someone else says, judging that
that is much more likely than what one could have been inclined to think
if left to oneself.
(1981, 46)
Even though accepting a speakerâs testimony requires judging that p is
true, this doesnât show that one cannot believe that p on the strength
of a speakerâs telling one that p while recognizing that, âif left to
oneself,â one wouldnât believe that p. What, then, does it mean to make
a judgment concerning some moral matter âfor oneselfâ?
I call it a judgment that he makes for himself when he judges on a
ground that he can see for himself; he does not merely judge âthat is
wrong,â he judges âthat is wrong because âŠâ and then follows some
further account of the action, which he can judge, and which he also
judges to make the action wrong. To rely exclusively on oneâs own
conscience (oneâs âunaidedâ conscience) is to refuse to judge anything
in practical matters unless in this sense one is able to judge for
oneself. Now in this sense of âoneâs own conscienceâ only a foolish
person thinks that his own conscience is the last word, so far as he is
concerned, about what to do. For just as any reasonable man knows that
his memory may sometimes deceive him, any reasonable man knows that what
one has conscientiously decided on one may later conscientiously regret.
A man may have reason to judge that another manâs moral counsel is more
reliable than his own unaided conscience; he will in any case be well
advised to take counsel with others; he may, moreover, have reason to
believe that some public source of moral teaching is more reliable than
his own unaided judgment. Of course he would not have any basis for such
judgments if he did not already rely on his own moral judgments to some
extent; but it would be sophistical to argue from this that his own
conscience must after all be for him the last word about what he ought
to do.
(1983, 46â47)
Though what Anscombe says here concerns specifically moral matters, it
has wider application. Anscombe distinguishes between two senses of
judging or believing âfor oneself.â In the first sense, to believe for
oneself is simply to believe. Of course, one cannot believe in this
sense without believing for oneself. In the second sense, to believe for
oneself is to believe on the basis of considerations that give âsome
further accountâ of what one believes, for example, to believe that
global warming is occurring on the basis of oneâs understanding of the
scientific evidence that counts in favor of this conclusion. This sense
of believing for oneself rules out belief based on theoretical
authority, but it would be foolish to think that one must [End Page 234]
always believe for oneself in this sense. One might very well judge that
someone elseâs judgment concerning, for example, the relevant scientific
evidence, is more likely to be correct than oneâs own and therefore
substitute anotherâs judgment on these matters for oneâs own.
Anscombeâs discussion of the confusion that can arise from conflating
these two different senses of believing for oneself also applies to the
case of obedience. Here also there are two senses in which one might be
said to settle âfor oneselfâ the question whether to Ί. In the first
sense, to settle for oneself the question whether to Ί is simply to
settle this question, either positively or negatively. Clearly, in this
sense of settling a question âfor oneself,â an agent cannot obey a
speakerâs command to Ί without settling positively the question whether
to Ί. In the case of the soldier obeying her officerâs command to Ί even
while thinking that the command is mistaken, the soldier clearly settles
positively the question whether to Ί. In a second sense of âfor
herself,â however, the soldier doesnât judge âfor herselfâ or âin her
own private judgmentâ that so acting is the thing to do. Instead, on the
basis of only those considerations that the soldier understands as
providing a further account of the character of the action as to be
done, considerations that do not include the officerâs command, the
soldier judges that so acting is not the thing to do. This sense of
judging âfor oneselfâ is one that necessarily factors out the speakerâs
command, but for all that we have seen thus far, this is not relevantly
different from what is going on in cases in which an audience believes a
speaker that p even while judging that, absent the speakerâs testimony,
she wouldnât âin her own private judgmentâ believe that p.
Anscombe is thus concerned to make room for a kind of suspension of
private judgment with respect to belief that, for all that we have seen
thus far, parallels the kind of suspension of private judgment involved
in obedience to practical authority. What, then, of the disanalogy she
wishes to draw between authority over action and authority over belief?
Anscombe goes on to claim that the disanalogy she is concerned with
pertains to what is capable of âmaking it rightâ that a person do or
believe something.
There is a difference between saying: You did not do as I told you, and
that is bad, because it was I, whom you ought to obey, who told you,
and: You did not believe what I said, and that is bad, because it was I,
whom you ought to believe, who told you.
The difference lies in this: that the one with authority over what you
do, can decide, within limits, what you shall do; his decision is what
makes it right for you to do what he saysâif the reproach against you,
when you disobey him, is only that of disobedience. But someone with
authority over what you think is not at liberty, within limits, to
decide what you shall think among the range of possible thoughts on a
given matter; what makes it right for you to think what you think, given
that it is your business to form a judgment at all, is simply that it is
true, and no decision can make something a true thing for you to think
as the decision of someone in authority can make something a good thing
for you to do.
(1983, 44) [End Page 235]
Anscombe claims that a practical authorityâs decision about what you
shall do is what âmakes it rightâ or makes it âa good thing for you to
do.â In contrast, a theoretical authority is not capable of âmaking it
rightâ for you to think something; she is not capable of making
something âa true thing for you to think.â
It is certainly correct that, generally speaking, a speakerâs telling me
that p doesnât make it true that p. There are exceptions. A speakerâs
telling me that she is telling me something does make it true that she
is telling me something, but this is an odd case. A scientistâs telling
me that global warming is occurring does not make it true that global
warming is occurring, and this might make for a difference between
theoretical and practical authority. After all, practical authorities
certainly seem capable of making it right that we do things.
What Anscombe says here, however, fails to distinguish between two
different senses in which an authority might âmake it rightâ that a
speaker do or believe something. Consider first the case of belief. In
one sense, for a belief to be ârightâ is for it to be true. In another
sense, for a belief to be ârightâ is for it to be justified, for it to
be based on sufficient epistemic reasons. A belief can be right in one
of these senses without being right in the other. A belief can be true
without being justified, and a belief can be justified without being
true. Apart from self-referential cases like the one mentioned above,
speakers are not generally capable of making what they say a true thing
to believe. However, they are certainly capable of making what they say
a justified thing to think. A speakerâs testimony that p often amounts
to sufficient epistemic reason for believing that p, and so speakers are
in this sense capable of making it right for an audience to believe
something.
Anscombe seems to be claiming that practical authorities are capable of
doing something analogous to the first sense of making it right to
believe something, something analogous to making something a true thing
to think. Not only are practical authorities capable of making something
a justified thing to do, of giving an audience sufficient reason to do
something, they are capable of making that thing âa good thing to do.â I
think that there is a sense in which this is correct. Imagine that a
group of people determines that a decision needs to be made concerning a
certain course of action, for example, whether to drive on the right- or
the left-hand side of the road. There is disagreement within the group
as to which course of action to pursue. Some people would prefer driving
on the left, while some would prefer driving on the right. It is
imperative that everyone does one or the other, but it doesnât matter
which. The group therefore decides to put one person in charge of making
the decision. This person is charged with determining for everyone else
what to do, and when she makes a decision, when she declares, say, that
everyone must drive on the right, this decision makes it the case that
driving on the right is âa good thing to do.â We can imagine that prior
to her decision, there simply wasnât a fact of the matter concerning
whether driving on the right or on the left was the good or appropriate
thing to do. But after the decision, driving on the right is clearly the
thing to do. This seems to be a clear case in which an authorityâs
decision âmakes it rightâ to do what she demands, and the sense in [End
Page 236] which her decision makes the action right is not only that it
gives the audience a sufficient reason for performing the action. The
authorityâs decision is what makes the action objectively correct.
Anscombe thus points to what I take to be a genuine disanalogy between
theoretical and practical authority. The decisions of practical
authorities are capable of making actions right or good in a way that
the decisions of theoretical authorities are not capable of making
beliefs true.[23] However, practical authorities do not only solve
coordination problems, and when they are not simply solving coordination
problems, it is less clear that they are capable of âmaking actions
rightâ in a sense that goes beyond that of giving the audience a
sufficient (authoritative) reason for performing the action. Consider
the case of arbitration.[24] When disputing parties agree to enter
arbitration, they agree to bind themselves to the decision of the
arbitrator. This is similar to the above case of a group of people
agreeing to bind themselves to the decisions of an authority charged
with solving a coordination problem. However, in the above case, there
was no fact of the matter about whether it was right to drive on the
right or the left prior to the authorityâs decision. In the case of
arbitration, there is a fact of the matter concerning, for example,
whether one of the parties breached a contract, and the arbitrator is
tasked not only with making a decision but with making the right
decision, with determining whether a contract was breached and, if so,
what remedies ought to be implemented. If the arbitrator determines that
a contract was breached and directs one party to pay restitution, then
the arbitratorâs directive gives the guilty party a distinctively
authoritative reason to act. The arbitrator âmakes it rightâ for the
party to pay restitution in that she gives the party good reason to do
so. However, it is not clear that the arbitrator âmakes it rightâ for
the party to do this in the sense of making the action correct. The
arbitratorâs job is to figure out the course of action that is the
independently correct one in the situation and to then give the parties
reason to pursue it. Similarly, the job of a theoretical authority is to
determine what is independently the case and then to give her audience
reason to believe it.
So even though Anscombe is right that in some cases, particularly those
that involve solving coordination problems, practical authorities are
capable of making a certain course of action correct, it would be a
mistake to think that this is true of all cases of legitimate practical
authority. While a military officer may frequently be tasked with
solving coordination problems and, in so doing, may thereby make certain
actions correct, she may often also be tasked with figuring out which
actions are independently correct in certain situations and then giving
her soldiers reason to pursue them. Presumably, the officerâs order to
ceasefire is of this latter variety. What all cases of practical
authority have in common is that they involve the giving of a particular
kind of reason, a distinctively authoritiative reason, but for all that
we have seen thus far, this is something that is true of theoretical
authority as well. So even if theoretical and practical authority
sometimes differ in the sense that Anscombe identifies, there is a
deeper commonality that spans even this difference. [End Page 237]
The philosophical anarchist position that I have been concerned with in
this paper is one that targets this deeper commonality. The anarchist is
not worried about the fact that we must solve coordination problems. In
Wolffâs example of the autonomous ship passenger, the passenger treats
the captainâs orders much as she would the directives of someone charged
with solving a simple coordination problem. Wolff thinks that this is
consistent with refusing to treat what the captain says as a
distinctively authoritative reason for action. It is the idea of
distinctively authoritative reasons, of reasons that require that a
subject suspend her own private judgment, that the anarchist opposes,
and we havenât yet seen good reason to think that the possibility of
such distinctively authoritative reasons for belief is ruled out by the
nature of theoretical rationality. The disanalogy that Anscombe
identifies between authority over belief and authority over action,
though genuine, thus poses no threat to the idea that the theoretical
and practical guises of philosophical anarchism should either stand or
fall together.
Clearly, there is much more to be said about these issues. Nevertheless,
I think that we have here a limited defense of Reidâs contention that,
at least with respect to the particular phenomenon of authority, the
problems involved in understanding this distinctively social phenomenon
are problems that span the divide between theoretical and practical
reason. Philosophical anarchism can be understood as a particular
instance of the general desire to reduce the social or second-personal
operations of mind to operations that are solitary or third personal. In
arguing that there is no such thing as legitimate or genuine authority,
the anarchist contends that the only proper relation we can bear to the
directives of de facto authorities is to treat them as merely reliable
indicators of what to do or believe, just as we treat the output of
ordinary impersonal instruments. Rejecting this position ultimately
requires defending a positive alternative account of the nature of
authority, something that I have not attempted here. However, I do hope
to have motivated the idea that, pace Darwall, the problem here is one
that spans the divide between theoretical and practical reason. The
philosophical anarchist position is one that applies equally to
theoretical and practical authority, and so we have good reason to think
that a positive defense of authority as a distinctively social or
second-personal transaction should be capable of applying to both
authority over belief and authority over action.
Many thanks to Linda Radzik, Linda Zagzebski, and audiences at the
University of Reading and the SIAS Summer Seminar âThe Second-Person:
Comparative Perspectivesâ organized by James Conant and Sebastian Rödl
for helpful comments on this material. [End Page 238]
Anscombe, E. 1979. âWhat Is It to Believe Someone?â In Rationality and
Religious Belief. Edited by C. F. Delaney. Notre Dame: Notre Dame
University Press. 141â51.
Anscombe, E. 1981. âAuthority in Morals.â In The Collected Philosophical
Papers of G. E. M. Anscombe, Vol. III: Ethics, Religion, and Politics.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 43â50.
Darwall, S. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Enoch, D. 2011. âGiving Practical Reasons.â Philosophersâ Imprint 11:
1â22.
Enoch, D. 2012. âAuthority and Reason-Giving.â Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 200: 1â37.
Feyerabend, P. 1975. Against Method. London: Verso.
Frankfurt, H. 1973. âThe Anarchism of Robert Paul Wolff.â Political
Theory 1: 405â14.
Friedman, R. 1990. âOn the Concept of Authority in Political
Philosophy.â In Authority. Edited by Joseph Raz. New York: New York
University Press. 56â91.
Godwin, W. 1971. Enquiry Concerning Political Justice. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Hart, H. 1990. âCommands and Authoritative Legal Reasons.â In Authority.
Edited by Joseph Raz. New York: New York University Press. 92â114.
Hieronymi, P. 2006. âControlling Attitudes.â Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly 87: 45â74.
Hieronymi, P. 2009. âThe Will as Reason.â Philosophical Perspectives 23:
201â20.
Locke, J. 1979. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
McMyler, B. 2011. Testimony, Trust, and Authority. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Milgram, S. 1974. Obedience to Authority. New York: Perennial Classics.
Owens, D. 2008. âRationalism about Obligation.â European Journal of
Philosophy 16: 403â31.
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [End
Page 241]
Raz, J. 2009. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Reid, T. 2002. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. University
Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Shapiro, S. 2002. âAuthority.â In The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence
and Philosophy of Law. Edited by Coleman and Shapiro. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. 382â439.
Simmons, A. J. 1979. Moral Principles and Political Obligations.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wolff, R. 1970. In Defense of Anarchism. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Zagzebski, L. 2012. Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority,
and Autonomy in Belief. New York: Oxford University Press. [End Page
242]
[1] Legitimate or de jure authorities are often characterized as having
a âright to ruleâ that generates for others a corresponding âduty to
obey.â The idea that authorities have a right to rule has been
questioned. See, for example, Enoch (2012). Moreover, as I argue below,
the philosophical anarchist position can be formulated in such a way as
to leave to one side questions about whether subjects have a duty or
obligation of obedience. I thus take the core of the philosophical
anarchist position to target the idea that authorities are in a position
(whether or not they have a right to this position) to make it the case
that others ought to do things (whether or not they have a duty or
obligation to do these things) simply by directing them to do so.
[2] A priori anarchism is defended by Wolff (1970). A posteriori
anarchism is defended by Simmons (1979).
[3] A notable exception is Zagzebski (2012).
[4] Note also that the position I am here calling âtheoretical
anarchismâ is very different from the position that Feyerabend (1975)
famously calls âepistemological anarchism.â Epistemological anarchism is
a position concerning scientific methodology, that there is no
scientific methodology that is in a privileged position to yield
knowledge. Theoretical anarchism, as I explain below, is a position
concerning reasons for belief.
[5] See, in particular, Hart (1990, 107) and Raz (2009, 155â56).
[6] As I argue below, a priori philosophical anarchists hold that the
very concept of authority and the ordinary practices structured in terms
of this concept, practices such as ordering and commanding, are
incoherent. If this is correct, then those who believe in the existence
of genuine authority are not only mistaken, they actually believe
something nonsensical (Shapiro 2002, 383). Like most political
philosophers (including a posteriori philosophical anarchists) I think
that this is enough to make the a priori philosophical anarchist
position highly implausible.
[7] Shapiro argues that the anarchist position is most fundamentally a
position concerning âthe space of reasons,â namely that âthe only
reasons that exist are either content-dependent or non-peremptoryâ
(2002, 390). On Shapiroâs account, the anarchist holds that there is no
such thing as a content-independent peremptory reason. This is very
similar to the position that I present here. However, for reasons that I
cannot get into here, I think that the anarchist might actually be in a
position to accept that authoritative directives amount to
content-independent peremptory reasons. I have thus formulated the
anarchist position as the denial that there is any such thing as a
distinctively authoritative reason, a reason that, as I discuss below,
requires that an agent âsuspend her own private judgmentâ concerning
what to do. Most fundamentally, the anarchist is opposed to the idea
that there can be reasons for action that require that an agent not make
up her own mind about what to do.
[8] For discussion of various examples of the use of the metaphor of
suspending private judgment in relation to authority over both belief
and action, see Friedman (1990).
[9] I raise some problems for understanding what exactly is going on in
such a situation in section IV.
[10] One might reject the idea that authoritative practical directives
even purport to provide reasons that require that an agent suspend her
own private judgment, however, one will then face the difficulty of
finding some other way to distinguish between the speech acts of
commanding and advising. The anarchist accepts that commands are
distinguished from advice in that they require that an agent suspend
private judgment in favor of the judgment of someone else. This is what
makes commanding an (attempted) exercise of authority.
[11] Godwin thus construes obedience to authority as a kind of mental
slavery, a slavery that he claims is actually more injurious to oneâs
humanity than actual physical enslavement (1971, 124). While someone who
is coerced or physically forced into acting at least retains the ability
to exercise her own rational powers, the obedient agent actually cedes
these powers to the authority. Her mind thus becomes a mere instrument
(an âagentâ in another sense of the word) for carrying out the wishes of
another. A strikingly similar picture of obedience emerges from the
social psychologist Stanley Milgramâs analysis of his infamous
experiments on obedience to authority. Milgram claims that when a person
obeys an authority she enters what he calls âthe agentic state,â a state
explicitly opposed to that of autonomy. From within the agentic state, a
person defines herself [End Page 239] as a mere instrument for the use
of others and no longer deems herself responsible for what she does
(1974, 133â34).
[12] The anarchist position that I am concerned with here despairs of
the possibility of making coherent sense of the idea of a distinctively
authoritative reason. Unsurprisingly, philosophers seeking to defend the
existence of de jure authority have for the most part attempted to
provide coherent accounts of this idea. See, for example, Raz (1979) and
(1986), Hart (1990), and Friedman (1990).
[13] I discuss several reasons for thinking that the kind of suspension
of private judgment intuitively involved in obedience to practical
authority is not possible in the theoretical realm in section IV.
[14] One might deny that the testimony of a theoretical authority even
purports to provide a reason for belief that is predicated on the
audienceâs suspending private judgment. I think that this misconstrues
the phenomenology of the speech act of telling as opposed to such speech
acts as arguing and merely expressing an opinion. Nevertheless, I donât
think that this point is crucial for the parallel that I draw here. One
might also deny that the commands of a practical authority even purport
to provide a reason for action that is predicated on an audienceâs
suspending private judgment, and such a position would still plausibly
count as a form of practical anarchism.
[15] To deny that there are any distinctively authoritative epistemic
reasons for belief is not yet to deny that there are any distinctively
authoritative non-epistemic reasons for belief. Genuinely epistemic
reasons for believing that p are considerations that a subject takes to
bear on the question whether p. Non-epistemic reasons for believing that
p are considerations that a subject takes to bear on the question
whether to act so as to bring about the belief that p by, say,
collecting evidence or taking a pill designed to induce the belief. Such
non-epistemic reasons for belief are ultimately reasons for actionâthey
are practical reasonsâand hence questions about whether such reasons can
be distinctively authoritative are questions about practical authority.
Theoretical anarchism is a thesis about epistemic reasons. Theoretical
authorities purport to provide considerations that bear on the question
whether p, and they purport to do so in a distinctively authoritative
way, in a way that is predicated on the audienceâs suspending her own
private judgment. The theoretical anarchist denies that such epistemic
reasons are possible, but this isnât yet to deny that there are
distinctively authoritative non-epistemic reasons for belief. The
theoretical anarchist might accept that a speakerâs command that an
audience act to bring about a particular belief provides the audience
with a distinctively authoritative reason. One might even call this a
distinctively authoritative âreason for belief,â but this is not a
distinctively authoritative epistemic reason.
[16] One of the clearest historical adherents of this kind of
theoretical anarchist position is Locke (1979).
[17] A notable exception is Zagzebski (2012). So-called assurance views
of testimony can also be read as pushing in the direction of construing
testimony as a kind of authoritative directive. I develop an account of
testimony along these lines in McMyler (2011).
[18] Godwin appears to accept both practical and theoretical anarchism,
and his arguments for the significance of private judgment in action are
often bound up with epistemological considerations. Like Locke, Godwin
holds that knowledge consists in the perception of relations of
agreement and disagreement between ideas, and also like Locke, Godwin
thinks that, as a result, genuine knowledge cannot be acquired from
human testimony. In order for me to know, for example, that the three
angles of a plane triangle are equal to two right angles, it is not
enough that Euclid or some other mathematician has told me that this is
so. I must be able to understand the proof for myself. According to
Godwin, this is true not only of propositions of mathematics and
geometry, but of every proposition: âEvery proposition has an intrinsic
evidence of its own. Every consequence has premises from which it flows;
and upon them, and not upon anything else, its validity dependsâ (1971,
92). Godwin thinks that as goes for knowledge, so goes for action. Just
as every proposition has its own âintrinsic evidenceâ that amounts to
the sole basis upon which it can be known, so every action has its own
âintrinsic tendency to be performedâ that amounts to the sole basis upon
which it can be rationally performed. The only truly legitimate form of
authority is thus âthe authority of reasonâ (1971, 121), and the only
truly legitimate form of obedience is obedience to the dictates of oneâs
own understanding: âThe purest kind of obedience is, where an action
flows from the independent conviction of our private judgment, where we
are directed, not by the precarious and mutable interference of another,
but by a recollection of the intrinsic and indefeasible tendency of the
action to be performedâ (1971, 119). [End Page 240]
[19] For some attempts to argue in this direction, in addition to
Darwall (2006), see Owens (2008) and Enoch (2011).
[20] I discuss a similar issue in the context of Darwallâs (2006) claim
that there can be no such thing as a genuinely or irreducibly
second-personal reason for belief in McMyler (2011). My treatment of the
issue here differs slightly from that earlier discussion.
[21] I take it that to settle the question whether to Ί is not to form a
belief or judgment that Ί-ing is the thing to do. For one way of making
out the claim that the conclusion of practical reasoning is action or
intention-formation rather than belief or judgment about what to do, see
Hieronymi (2009).
[22] In McMyler (2011), I argue that such a judgment must be a
theoretical judgment about a practical subject matter. This is a further
issue that leads to confusion concerning what is involved in suspending
private judgment in the practical and theoretical realms, but one that
does not, I think, make for a difference in the possibilities for the
exercise of authority. Since the discussion here is complicated enough,
I have suppressed this issue here.
[23] This is related to a distinction drawn by Friedman (1990) between
being âin authorityâ and being âan authority.â A person is in authority
when there is an established and agreed-upon procedure that puts her in
the position of deciding a course of action concerning which there would
otherwise be disagreement. A person is an authority when she has special
access to an independent order of facts. Friedman thinks that these are
both forms of authority and that in both cases the directives of the
authorities involved amount to distinctively authoritative reasons for
belief or action, but he holds, rightly, that the presuppositions of the
two forms of authority differ. As I read Friedman, however, the
distinction between being in authority and an authority doesnât map
cleanly onto the distinction between practical and theoretical
authority. Friedman holds that all theoretical authorities are in the
position of being an authority, and he holds that only practical
authorities are in the position of being in authority. However, he seems
to hold that some practical authorities are both in authority and an
authority and that some practical authorities may only be an authority.
[24] Raz frequently appeals to the case of arbitration in support of his
service conception of authority.