💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › brian-oliver-sheppard-anarchism-vs-primitivism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:03:28. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism vs. Primitivism
Author: Brian Oliver Sheppard
Date: 2003
Language: en
Topics: anarcho-communist, Chaz Bufe, Feral Faun, Fredy Perlman, John Zerzan, primitivism, syndicalist
Source: Retrieved on December 22, 2009 from http://libcom.org/library/anarchism-vs-primitivism
Notes: This pamphlet was originally published by See Sharp Press, Tucson, Arizona, USA, 2003. It has been digitised by libcom.org with full permission of the publisher.

Brian Oliver Sheppard

Anarchism vs. Primitivism

1. The Demonology of Primitivism

“No one has ever been so witty as you are in trying to turn us into

brutes: to read your book makes one long to go on all fours. Since,

however, it is now some sixty years since I gave up the practice, I feel

that it is unfortunately impossible for me to resume it: I leave this

natural habit to those more fit for it than are you and I.”

— Voltaire, letter to Rousseau, August 30, 1755.

The Demonology of Primitivism: Electricity, Language, and other

Modern Evils

Gar Smith, editor of the Earth Island Institute journal, The Edge, and

critic of modern technology, recently complained to journalists, “I have

seen villages in Africa that had vibrant culture and great communities

that were disrupted and destroyed by the introduction of electricity.”

He added: “I don’t think a lot of electricity is a good thing. It is the

fuel that powers a lot of multi-national imagery.” When asked why lack

of electricity — a hallmark of poverty — ought to be considered

advantageous, Smith said, “The idea that people are poor doesn’t mean

that they are not living good lives.” He added, “there is a lot of

quality to be had in poverty.”

John Zerzan, a leading modern primitivist, writes in a similar vein, but

claims those living in societies before electricity enjoyed higher

standards of mental well-being: “Being alive in nature, before our

abstraction from it [through modern civilization], must have involved a

perception and contact that we can scarcely comprehend from our levels

of anguish and alienation. The communication with all of existence must

have been an exquisite play of all the senses, reflecting the

numberless, nameless varieties of pleasure and emotion once accessible

within us.” Zerzan, the Green Anarchy Collective, and other primitivists

regularly reminisce over an ideal past where “the wheat and corn, pigs

and horses were once freely dancing in the chaos of nature.” In fact,

through their activism primitivists hope to deliver society into this

primal chaos, so that the “wheat and corn, pigs and horses” — and the

rest of us, presumably — may freely dance once more.

On web sites like primitivism.com, primitivists tell us how the Internet

should not exist. In printed magazines like Green Anarchy, they condemn

printing presses and typesetting technology. And in events like the

Green Anarchy Tour of 2001, they complain of the roads that enable them

to travel, the electricity that powers the instruments of their tour’s

musical acts, and of the existence of the facilities that host their

events. Primitivists enjoin their audience to live like early hominids,

though they certainly don’t lead by example.

When analyzing primitivist musings, two mysteries immediately confront

the reader. The first: how can such ideas be seriously entertained by

anyone? Electricity, advanced medical care, information technologies,

artificial heating and cooling, water purification, and countless other

modern innovations are regarded by primitivists as undesirable. One

would think that the lifespan of such notions would be as short as that

of a Palaeolithic tribesman’s. Yet, primitive thinking is currently

enjoying a kind of vogue among the radical left.

The second perturbation: how to begin to make sense of all the rubbish

primitivists write? Some of their screeds, on the one hand, ape (no pun

intended) the most obnoxious, opaque phraseology of post-modernism:

“Symbolizing is linear, successive, substitutive,” John Zerzan

delicately informs us in Running on Emptiness. “It cannot be open to its

whole object simultaneously.” On the other hand, many primitive rants

drop any pretense of sophistication and’ devolve (again, no pun

intended) into infantile histrionics: “Why should I tolerate this

insanity” a writer at insurgentdesire.co.uk bloviates. “Ned Ludd was

right! The machine is the enemy. Smash it without mercy!”

Indeed, why should we tolerate this insanity? How can we understand some

of the genuinely bizarre ideas that litter the pantheon of our primitive

romantics? And how is that the primitivist cocktail of mysticism,

pseudo-science, and wild speculation has serious adherents in the full

light of the 21^(st) century?

Unfortunately for anarchists, plunging into the primitivist miasma has

become necessary. Over the past few decades, primitivists have

successfully assimilated themselves into the anarchist movement. Within

the U.S., their influence has grown so strong that anarchists can no

longer afford to ignore it. The corporate media, in its infinite wisdom,

has often decided to present primitivism as “the new anarchism,”

blissfully ignoring the classical strand of anarchist thought that

agitates for worker and community control within a stateless society.

Unfortunately, this generous free advertising ensures that many new

members of the anarchist movement will arrive through primitivism’s

feral gates.

The primitivists’ stated aim is to reorient anarchism towards the

wholesale destruction of civilization and its attendant technologies.

Their analysis asserts that civilization estranges humanity from its

true, feral nature — a regrettable situation, they say, since humans, as

the Steppenwolf song goes, are born to be wild. Like Christian

evangelists, they maintain that modern living results in spiritual and

emotional poverty — a kind of soullessness that Mammoth hunters did not

experience, and often hint that pagan belief systems are superior to

rational thought. Technology, too, is inherently oppressive, no matter

who wields it or to what uses it is put. In addition, primitivists warn

of the dangers of population growth while Zerzanites even claim language

to be a type of alienation. (Such statements alienate us with their

language, incidentally). Although classical anarchists like Peter

Kropotkin and Mikhail Bakunin spoke of eliminating the state by

transferring ownership of the means of production into the public’s

hands, primitivists have a different agenda: they wish to destroy, not

redistribute, industry and technology.

The problem of primitivism in the anarchist movement is new only in

scope. There have always been those on the fringes of the left who have

hoped to return society to some type of idyllic, Garden of Eden-like

existence. The idea of a noble savage at peace with himself, the

pristine wilderness, and his fellow humans before modern civilization is

as old as the plays of John Dryden in the 17^(th) century. Many before

our modern primitive romantics have advocated bucking it all and getting

back to nature. As the late evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould

counsels in The Mismeasure of Man, “the same bad arguments recur every

few years with a predictable and depressing regularity. No sooner do we

debunk one version than the next chapter of the same bad text emerges to

ephemeral prominence.”

Today, for example, tomes like Future Primitive and primitive

sounding-boards such as Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed (A:AJODA),

Green Anarchy, and Fifth Estate abound. The Rainbow Gathering, nominally

non-anarchist, attracts all manner of tree folk, Middle Earthers,

permaculture fanatics, and mystics to its primitivist-type festivals. At

few points since the 19^(th) century, however, have “primitive man”

fantasists attempted to identify with anarchism. Indeed, a prominent

strain of utopian socialists — romantics wishing to escape the modern

world through communal living — have been a fixture on the left since

the early 1800s, tagging along on the margins of anti-capitalism much

like the apocalyptic Christian cults that gather on society’s fringe.

Marx and Bakunin differentiated this type of utopian socialism from

forward-thinking socialism, which values science and its benefits;

indeed, Bakunin hoped for a revolution in which science “would become

the property of everybody.” And although Marx, for example, recognized

that hunter-gatherer clans did indeed practice a type of “primitive

communism,” neither he nor his anarchist opponents advocated turning

back the clock to relive such times. Anarchists did not consider the

living standards of the Neanderthal worthy of modern humans. The only

ones who felt that people should live like primitives were those

capitalists whose desire to keep business costs down resulted in

primitive living conditions for their wage slaves.

Utopian, “get-back-to-nature” sects attracted anarchist criticism from

the beginning. It was in response to such backwards-thinking romantics

that Mikhail Bakunin affirmed in the late 1800s, “It is not in the past,

nor even in the present that ye should seek the freedom of the masses.

It is in the future.” Anarcho-syndicalist veteran Sam Dolgoff, speaking

of life at the Stelton Colony of New York in the 1930s, noted with

disdain that it, “like other colonies, was infested by vegetarians,

naturists, nudists, and other cultists, who sidetracked true anarchist

goals.” One resident “always went barefoot, ate raw food, mostly nuts

and raisins, and refused to use a tractor, being opposed to machinery,

and he didn’t want to abuse horses, so he dug the earth himself.” Such

self-proclaimed anarchists were in reality “ox-cart anarchists,” Dolgoff

said, “who opposed organization and wanted to return to a simpler life.”

In an interview with Paul Avrich before his death, Dolgoff also

grumbled, “I am sick and tired of these half-assed artists and poets who

object to organization and want only to play with their belly buttons.”

This has been a problem seemingly for as long as anarchism has existed.

Writing nearly a century ago, Malatesta’s comrade Luigi Fabbri noted in

Bourgeois Influences on Anarchism that the anarchist movement has always

been overrun with flakes, parasites, and outright crazies. He wrote that

these “empty-headed and frivolous types...are not repelled by the

absurd, but...on the contrary, engage in it. They are attracted to

projects and ideas precisely because they are absurd; and so anarchism

comes to be known precisely for the illogical character and

ridiculousness which ignorance and bourgeois calumny have attributed to

anarchist doctrines.”

With the rise of the anti-corporate globalization movement in recent

years, the primitivist problem has assumed a new urgency: Whereas in the

past primitive thinkers were consigned to the margins of the movement by

virtue of the absurdity of their ideas, a recent absence of lively, mass

class struggle activism has allowed primitive thinkers to exert greater

influence. The onus is on traditional anarchists to take the movement

back, and force primitive thinkers to their previous place on the

sidelines.

Not to be discounted, either, is the influence of the corporate media,

which has taken primitivism and situated it front and center, presenting

it to the public as the lifeblood of a 2lst-century anarchist

resurgence. Primitivism, the corporate media tells us, is the “new”

anarchism — and young adults, hungry for any ideas that point to a way

out of the capitalist ghetto, sometimes believe it, and sign up. The

popularity of the anti-corporate globalization movement holds much

promise for anarchism; the media’s attempts to associate it with

primitive ideas, however, does not.

Time magazine, for example, ran two articles in 2001 on John Zerzan and

the cult-like following he has attracted in his home town of Eugene,

Oregon (among other places). And a few years prior, Time bestowed the

title “king of the anarchists” upon primitivist/Unabomber Ted Kaczynski

in one of the more than 30 articles they devoted to him. The December

13, 1999, issue of Newsweek featured a picture of anarcho-syndicalist

Noam Chomsky with images of Zerzan and convicted murderer Kaczynski

beside him; the publication associated all three as leading lights of

modern anarchist thought. NPR, 60 Minutes, and other news outlets have

given air time to the absurd proclamations of John Zerzan even as the

unofficial media ban of Noam Chomsky and other more capable analysts

continues. Again, as Fabbri, noted: “[A]nd so anarchism comes to be

known precisely for the illogical character and ridiculousness which

ignorance and bourgeois calumny have attributed to anarchist doctrines.”

The effect of the media’s focus on anarchism’s most embarrassing side

has been advantageous for elites; by focusing laser like on the looniest

elements of anarchism, the entire movement can be marginalized and

discredited. This follows a historical pattern in which anarchist

activists are ignored by the establishment until one does something so

antisocial or outlandish that elites can score cheap points by reporting

it. If the public sees only the primitivist wing of anarchism, it will

be unlikely to support anything associated with anarchism.

Understandably, few people want to support something that is hostile to

the life-saving medical care, information technology, and electronic

entertainment they enjoy.

The media’s gravitation towards primitivism has pressured other parts of

the anarchist movement to accept it as well. The University of

Michigan’s Joseph A. Labadie collection, commonly regarded as an

“archive of record” for the anarchist movement, recently decided to

admit the papers of unabomber Theodore Kaczynski into its vaults. This

includes interviews where Kaczynski reports on attempts to have a

dialogue with terrorist Timothy McVeigh, dragging again the shadiest

figures of modern politics into anarchist history. The shelving of

Kaczynski’s murderous Unabomber Manifesto alongside classics by Emma

Goldman and others is presumably something the anarchist community will

have to live with. The acquisition is of further irony, given that the

figure for which the University of Michigan’s archive is named, labor

activist Joseph Labadie, favored public control over industrial society,

not a Kaczynski-style mail bombing of it. As well, Kaczynski admirer

John Zerzan works with a self-styled “Green Anarchy” collective in

Oregon. When Z Magazine editor Michael Albert approached John Zerzan to

debate primitivism, Zerzan ultimately sniffed, “As an anarchist, I’m not

interested.”

The waxing influence of primitive thinkers threatens to redefine the

character of the anarchist tradition for future generations. It also

threatens to divert eager new activists into its theoretical cul-de-sac

where nothing revolutionary can ever be accomplished. Worst of all, the

primitivist agenda would result in mass scale atrocity if its objectives

were ever met: society would be stripped of the medical can, shelter,

food supplies, distribution networks, and even language (!) that humans

depend upon for life. That primitivists play casually with such globally

catastrophic notions speaks volumes about their real concern for human

well being.

2. An Ignoble Savage

I am as free as Nature first made man,

Ere the base laws of servitude began,

When wild in woods the noble savage ran.

— John Dryden, The Congum of Granada, 1670.

Primitivists emphasize how good ancient humans had it. In this, they

strongly echo Rousseau’s ruminations upon the Noble Savage. Rousseau

stated in Discourse on Inequality that the era of primitive man “must

have been the happiest and most durable of epochs. The more we reflect

on it, the more we shall find that this state was the least subject to

revolutions, and altogether the very best that man could experience.”

Rousseau stated further that “[t]he example of savages, most of whom

have been found in this state, seems to prove that men were meant to

remain in it, that it is the real youth of the world, and that all

subsequent advances have been apparently so many steps towards the

perfection of the individual, but in reality towards the decrepitude of

the species.” Primitive man enjoyed a simple, bliss full life, he said:

‘The produce of the earth furnished him with all he needed, and instinct

told him how to use it. Hunger and other appetites made him at various

times experience various modes of existence; and among these was one

which urged him to propagate his species — a blind propensity that,

having nothing to do with the heart, produced a merely animal act.”

In Against His-story, Against Leviathan, Fredy Perlman acknowledges the

debt to Rousseau — and even to John Zerzan — reporting that they are

“among contemporaries whose lights I’ve borrowed.” Perlman tells us that

prehistoric humans “lived in a condition J.J. Rousseau called ‘the state

of nature.’” In fact, urges Perlman, “Rousseau’s term should be brought

back into common use” because it “makes the armor [of civilization]

visible.” “Insist that ‘freedom’ and ‘state of nature’ are synonyms,”

Perlman writes, “and the cadavers [that is, apologists of civilization]

will try to bite you.” Furthemore, “the state of nature is a community

of freedoms,” he writes. A state of freedom “was the environment of the

first human communities, and such it remained for thousands of

generations.”

In fact, evidence about how the first human communities fared, or around

what principles social life was organized, is sparse. What evidence we

do have should caution us from projecting our own fantasies onto them,

however, or asserting them as desirable alternatives for the future. It

should also go without saying that at all times humanity has lived in “a

state of nature,” including right now. That is, the natural world is

still here and ensconces us, even if aspects of it are modified.

Perlman’s “state of nature” also, by the way, includes hurricanes,

loathsome diseases, life-threatening elements, and other unpleasantness.

It is doubtful that any primitivist would run headlong into a tornado in

order to experience the “state of nature”; if he held his or others’

well being in any regard, he might wish for a weather tracking system

(for example) to tell us when tornadoes were coming, so that we could

avoid them.

In his book Future Primitive, John Zerzan agrees with Rousseau and

Perlman: Human “life before domestication/ agriculture was in fact

largely one of leisure, intimacy with nature, sensual wisdom, sexual

equality, and health.” Zerzan, Eric Blair, and the Green Anarchy

Collective issued a joint statement furthering the point: “Prior to

civilization there generally existed ample leisure time, considerable

gender autonomy and equality, a non-destructive approach to the natural

world, the absence of organized violence and strong health and

robusticity.” George Bradford (David Watson), editor of the primitivist

Fifth Estate, writes that primitive man’s society is “affluent because

its needs are few, all its desires easily met. Its tool kit is elegant

and lightweight, its outlook linguistically complex and conceptually

profound yet simple and accessible to all. Its culture is expansive and

ecstatic. It is propertyless and communal, egalitarian and

cooperative....It is anarchic...free of work....It is a dancing society,

a singing society, a celebrating society, a dreaming society.”

In short, not only were pre-technological societies pleasant places in

which to live, they closely approximated the anarchist ideal. How true

is this, really?

Conservatives often fixate upon an idealized-and unrealistic-notion of

the past, lamenting that society has grown far away from it. Starting

with Christianity, which agonizes over humanity’s expulsion from its

idyll in the Garden of Eden, backwards-looking ideologies have hoped to

restore society to an imagined Golden Age, when things were better. The

Nazi Party presented a story of a once-great Teutonic civilization in

decline, the victim of Jewish parasites and communist forces;

contemporary U.S. conservatives hearken to the wholesome values of

America’s Puritan past, and so on. The primitivists simply trump them

all by going back the farthest, proposing to reconstruct prehistory (or,

alternately, “the Iron Age”) in our modern midst. The problem with such

ideas is that they posit a romanticized vision of an earlier era,

inconsistent with the often unpleasant realities that existed.

Likewise, conservatives often maintain that “poor people really have it

good,” much as primitivists do. Gar Smith’s assurance that “there is a

lot of quality to be had in poverty,” for example, echoes much of the

anti-welfare rhetoric one hears coming from the right (viz., the poor

are really not bad off because they have television or fast food; and

besides, being poor builds character, etc.). Certainly, anyone who wants

to live in a shack and go it alone without electricity or heating, as

primitivist idol Ted Kaczynski did, should be free to do so; but the

poor blacks of the, Mississippi Delta, where Kaczynski’s choice of

living conditions are day-to-day reality whether it is preferred or not,

should have access to many of the amenities (medical care, heating,

better choice of foods, etc.) that Kaczynski chose to abandon.

Anarchists have traditionally favored such a redistribution of society’s

wealth and benefits — and it is in fact the ruling class, much like

Zerzan Company, that prefers to see its workers living primitively.

Primitivists’ fixation upon the imagined mental vigor and “robusticity”

of pre-technological peoples is old hat as well. Again, this notion

gained much currency among the European far right in the early 20^(th)

century, which conceived of, for example, the Anglo-Saxon race as a

hardy, earthy (volkish) people softened by liberal, effeminate notions

of welfare statism and progress. Germans, in fact, enacted racial

hygiene laws to preserve the most robust strains of the species. Murray

Bookchin has noted this ideological tendency in the reactionary

romanticism of Nazi sympathizer Martin Heidegger. As well, Janet Biehl

and Peter Staudenmaier have explored the problem in-depth in the

excellent Ecofascism: Lessons from the German Experience. There is in

fact a contemporary right wing school of thought that claims modern

medicines and even environmental protections are bad because they

contribute to the “softening” of humans; that is, funding for medical

care or environmental regulation should not be increased because it is

through such means that humans trade in “robusticity” for diminished

racial resilience. Experts who assert that there is a kind of

metaphysical wholesomeness in living a rugged, difficult lifestyle can

be found sitting in some of the nation’s most odious conservative think

tanks, reaping large salaries from environmentally destructive (or

simply misanthropic) corporations. Good medical care, subsidies to help

with home heating costs-these amount to mollycoddling, business owners

assert. Real Americans, they maintain, realize that hardship builds

moral fiber and physical stamina-an idea that conveniently justifies

business in behave as irresponsibly as it wants. In insisting upon the

physical and moral “robusticity” that is supposed to accompany primitive

living conditions, primitivists echo this dubious strain of reactionary

thinking.

However, primitivists, unlike the corporate elite, claim to oppose

environmental ruin. Indeed, environmental degradation is one of the

central primitivist grievances with “civilization.” The “strong health

and robusticity” of primitive man arose not through struggle and

hardship, primitivists tell us, but through “ample leisure time,”

“affluence,” and other perks that primitives enjoyed. Like Adam and Eve

in the Garden of Eden, primitive humans had all their needs provided

for, but they also stayed fit.

So, who were the peoples that primitivists seek to emulate? What were

their lives really like? This is, in fact, where the fraud of

primitivist thought reveals itself most clearly.

One of the central flaws in primitivist logic is the conflation of

millennia of various cultures and societies into one entity — “primitive

man.” In fact, in books like Future Primitive or the recent Running on

Emptiness, Zerzan dances across disparate eras and continents wildly,

selectively noting features of this or that radically different tribal,

non-industrialized, or prehistoric people to build his case that there

was a common and wiser way of life that all humans once shared. Much

like ethnocentric Europeans who can distinguish between European

cultures but can not do the same for the many cultures within Africa,

Asia, or the at-least 500 nations of native North America, primitivists

often use the “primitive man” concept as a catch-all into which they

insert their favored virtues.

A composite of “primitive man” is erected in primitivist thought;

glossed over in this process are the less-than-ideal aspects of most

tribal societies. For example, primitivists conveniently fail to mention

the religious notions, patriarchal structures, or strict traditions

(like clitoridectomy, painful coming-of-age rituals, etc.) present in

some non-industrial clans. Perhaps they are aware that most would find

these undesirable. As Hoxie Neale Fairchild wrote in the study Noble

Savage, “The [European notion of the] true Noble Savage arises from a

combination of disillusion about the here and now with illusion about

the there and then.”

3. What is the primitivist ideal?

No Language

“Words are very unnecessary/they can only do harm,” the pop group

Depeche Mode sing in “Enjoy the Silence.” This is a romantic notion, but

without words the songs of Depeche Mode and others couldn’t be performed

by anyone.

According to the Green Anarchy collective, language is out. That is,

people (primitivists wildly conjecture) were psychologically healthier

when they stood in mute awe — or fear — of everything, unable to

communicate with one another. The obnoxious primitivist Feral Faun (less

pretentiously, David Watkins, not to be confused with Fifth Estate

editor David Watson) hisses at “language with its conceptual limits,”

presumably preferring the conceptual limitlessness enjoyed by the dumb

and the mute. Alternatively, as Zerzan infers at his wildest, “we should

instead communicate telepathically.” “Only a politics that undoes

language and time and is thus visionary to the point of voluptuousness

has any meaning,” Zerzan muses at primitivism.com.

Of course, it is unlikely that anatomically modern homo sapiens — that

is, humanity as it has anatomically existed since about 100,000 years

ago — has ever gone without speaking. According to anthropologist

Kenneth Feder, it is likely that approximately 1.8 million years ago

homo erectus first developed the capability to talk:

[T]he base of the erectus cranium — the basicranium — is far more like

that of modern humans than of homo habilis or apes. Because the muscles

involved in the production of speech are connected to the basicranium,

this may indicate that the physical capability for human or human like

speech production was present in homo erectus. From this, [Mt. Sinai

School of Medicine anatomist Jeffrey] Laitman has concluded that homo

erectus could produce speech at the level of a modern six-year-old.”

There is no way to tell absolutely, of course, as no other records exist

from such a time to substantiate any rival hypotheses. There are no

audio recordings from 1.5 million B.C.E., in other words, to indicate

whether people spoke then. Nevertheless, Zerzan, unencumbered by facts,

writes in Running on Emptiness that humans once existed in a

“non-linguistic state,” but have “declined” since then thanks to

acquiring language. He adds, “Literacy ushered us into the society of

divided and reduced senses.” “Verbal communication,” he continues in a

line of pure conjecture, “is part of the movement away from a

face-to-face social reality, making feasible physical separateness.”

Primitivist musings like this have all the character of “someone riffing

ideas off the top of his head who has done no actual research into what

he’s talking about,” John Johnson points out in a recent Imagine

article. (Note, incidentally, that Bradford of Fifth Estate admires the

primitive “outlook [that was] linguistically complex and conceptually

profound yet simple and accessible to all,” revealing that there is much

ideological inconsistency among the primitivists — and let’s not even

bother with how Bradford could “know” this.) In fact, much primitivist

theory relies on wild speculation about how humans organized social life

in eras fiom which we have no written records. Because the least is

known about such eras, primitivists can project their wildest fantasies

onto them and never worry about being proven wrong.

Of course, anarchists have traditionally cited language as evidence of

man’s social nature. “What is speech?” Bakunin asked. “It is

communication. It is the conversation of one human individual with many

other individuals. Only through this conversation and in it can

animalistic man transform himself into a human being, that is, a

thinking being. His individuality as a man, his freedom, is thus the

product of the collectivity.” . Chomsky and other linguists have posited

an innate human predisposition to the use of language, despite Zerzan’s

impassioned insistence that a theory of innate language is “a grave and

reactionary error.” In fact, in 2001 National Geographic reported that

scientists had discovered a gene, FOXP2, “linked to language and speech,

suggesting that our human urge to babble and chat is innate, and that

our linguistic abilities are at least partially hardwired.”

To most people, language seems the last thing worthy of abolition. Many

of us enjoy the work of poets, who use language as their paintbrush to

enrich — not impoverish — our cultural experience. Singing and

storytelling are cultural forms valued by most humans, as well. Other

examples abound, too numerous to mention.

No Technology

No technology above simple tools is to be allowed in the primitivist

utopia, either: “Technology is distinct from simple tools in many

regards,” primitivists claim. Primitivists define technology in a manner

that suits their ends, however: it is “more of a process or concept than

a static form,” they explain. “It is a complex system involving division

of labor, resource extraction, and exploitation for the benefit of those

who implement its process.”

Now, a “system of division of labor, resource extraction, and

exploitation for the benefit of those who implement its process” is

actually a description of the workings of capitalism. Technology,

however, which existed long before capitalism, is defined by most

scientists as the practical application of knowledge towards problem

solving; alternately, most anthropologists agree, it is a manner of

accomplishing a task using technical methods. Despite the protestations

of primitivists, most anthropologists also classify stone tools as a

type of technology. Other technology includes the construction of crude

wells for securing water as well as the most advanced equipment used to

save human life. Deprived of such things, countless humans would

immediately die.

Primitivists say they fear that, like the Skynet computer in the movie

Terminator, technology will develop its own sentience and work to

eradicate humanity. “It’s questionable whether the ruling class (who

still benefit economically and politically from the Technological

System) really have any control over their ‘Frankenstein monster’ at

this point,” Zerzan and the Green Anarchy collective warn, dramatically

suggesting that perhaps technology already works by virtue of its own

prerogatives!

In Against His-story, Against Leviathan, Perlman offers a similar idea,

refering to the “Frankenstein monster” as the “Earthwrecker,” which

“does have a body, a monstrous body, a body that has become more

powerful than the Biosphere. It may be a body without any life of its

own. It may be a dead thing, a huge cadaver. It may move its slow thighs

only when living beings inhabit it. Nevertheless, its body is what does

the wrecking.” Perlman presents the possibility that humans may control

the “Earthwrecker” — but then again, he suggests, maybe they don’t! (“It

may [my emphasis] move its slow thighs only when living beings inhabit

it’ — a pretentious sentence in which it is difficult to find any real

meaning.)

It’s interesting that primitivist activists regularly employ the

“Frankenstein monster” to make mass-produced journals (viz., Green

Anarchy Magazine, electronically reproduced on the web) and web sites

(viz., www.insurgentdesire.co.uk), and to participate in e-mail

discussion lists. Anecdotally, this author can vouch for having met many

primitivists who enjoy their Playstations in their heated apartments,

rent DVDs (Fight Club, Instinct, Matrix, Terminator), and otherwise

gladly partake in privileges unavailable to real-world tribes people.

Delicately shielded from “robusticity”-causing conditions (the elements,

in other words), they pontificate on how everyone else ought to give up

their amenities. Presumably, primitivists are waiting for everyone else

to go primitive first. When asked by a reporter if the fact that he

watches television might make him a bit of a hypocrite, John Zerzan

weakly offered, “Like other people, I have to be narcotized.”

Elsewhere, George Bradford refers to the “Frankenstein monster” of

technology as “the industrial hydra”; Zerzan dubs it the

“everywhere-triumphant Megamachine”; and Theodore Kaczynski simply cites

the “technological system” as if it were a social order unto itself. The

intellectual laziness of these concepts is apparent in how they gloss

over the particular class relations of statism/capitalism. In the

capitalist system, it is true that capitalists direct much technology

towards misanthropic ends-demonstrating that it is class rule that

determines how technology is applied, and not vice versa. Due to the

poverty of their analysis and intellectual sloppiness, however,

primitivists cannot make even such obvious distinctions, and condemn

technology wholesale.

Of course, harmful technology is just that — harmful. It is hard to

imagine a positive use for nuclear weaponry, for example, or for

biological and chemical weapons. But primitivists have a long way to go

to convince the public that technology invariably entails coercive

social relations (“invariably” is a word that merits some reflection

here). They also have a long way to go to convince us that people like

physicist Stephen Hawking should be left to die (in Social Darwinian

fashion) simply because they require technology to live. As well, John

Zerzan’s reading glasses would have to be cast aside in a primitivist

society, as would the lens-crafting technology that enables others with

eyesight as bad as his to see.

Let us not play around with these concepts idly. When primitivists

advocate eliminating technology, they advocate the wholesale slaughter

or starvation of billions, of humans worldwide.

No Agriculture

Zerzanite and Green Anarchy primitivists would prevent the domestication

of food and animals as well. Domestication of crops began around 12,000

years ago in the Near East, marking the shift from nomadic

hunter-gatherer lifestyles — which most primitivists like — to more

sedentary, settled social formations, which most primitivists dislike.

According to the Green Anarchy collective, growing crops “was the first

mistake in the series leading to modernity.”

“Agriculture must be overcome, as domestication,” Zerzan writes in “On

the Transition: Postscript to Future Primitive.” Rather than enjoy huge,

equitably distributed agricultural surpluses, as classical anarchists

like Peter Kropotkin would have for humanity, primitivists would have

people form into hunter-gatherer units and forage for wild, naturally

occurring fruits and vegetables. This immediately presents a dilemma, as

John Johnson notes in Imagine in “Zerzan-Buffoon”: what if a rebellious

hunter-gatherer “thought, ‘Hey, I like strawberries; I sure wish there

was a way to get them more regularly than just having to stumble across

them in the wild’”? In order to preserve primitivist society,

primitivist police would have to root out this kind of dissidence

immediately. Cultivation of crops would have to be banned.

Again, let us reflect soberly on the consequences of the belief that

agriculture ought to be eliminated: Deprived of agriculture, the

majority of the global population would immediately perish.

Given these three criteria alone, it is clear that no existing society

could be called primitivist. In fact, it is not clear that any culture

we have knowledge of accords to such strict ideals. Societies lacking

language, agriculture, and technology are few and far between. Even the

living, non-industrial tribes that primitivists regularly cite in their

analyses-such as the !Kung Bushmen of Africa (see Future Primitive,

Perlman’s Against His-story, or Bob Black’s “Primitive Affluence,” for

example) — speak a type of language. And even if the !Kung do not employ

technology as primitivists define it (an important distinction, since

primitivists define it to suit their agenda), or domesticate animals,

there are other respects in which aspects of theirs and other tribal

lifestyles are not anarchistic or desirable for others.

4. Realities of Tribal Lifeways

According to anthropologist Lorna Marshall, whose research on the !Kung

has been reported by the primitivist-beloved Marshall Sahlins, “Except

for food and water (important exceptions!) ... they all had what they

needed or could make what they needed.” Marshall’s notation that food

and water can be “important exceptions” to primitive “affluence” is well

taken. Fifth Estate’s George Bradford compassionately concedes that

“primal humans” are “capable of experiencing occasional hunger” but

reassures us that they “sometimes [chose] hunger to enhance

interrelatedness, to play, or to see visions.” It remains to be seen how

well the primitivist notion of “hunger as a means of play” will catch on

with the modern public.

Furthermore, anthropologist Edwin Wilemsen notes that living !Kung

cultural practices observed by anthropologists such as Marshall Sahlins

or Lorna Marshall are themselves the product of millennia of adaptation:

the !Kung used to hunt elephants, practiced horticulture and other types

of farming, and had skirmishes with chiefdoms in eastern Africa that

drove them into their current habitat (the Kalahari Desert), where they

are observed by contemporary researchers. This is contrary to what Fredy

Perlman implies in a statement that “the !Kung people miraculously

survived into our own exterminating age.” Of course, it is technically

true that the !Kung have survived, as have Native Americans and

Aborigines, but Perlman implies the !Kung are a kind of living

anachronism whose tribal ways preserve life in “the natural state.” As

well, University of Illinois-Chicago anthropologist Lawrence H. Keeley

notes that the !Kung “homicide rate from 1920 to 1955 was four times

that of the United States and twenty to eighty times that of major

industrial nations during the 1950s and 1960s.” Far from representing a

pristine picture of “primitive man,” in other words, !Kung society, as

any other, has changed over the centuries to adapt to changing needs.

This all underscores the point that existing hunter-gatherer tribes do

not necessarily provide a window back into time.

In this regard, amateur primitivist pseudo-anthropology warrants a

strong caution from Kenneth L. Feder, a practicing anthropologist at

Central Connecticut State University. He writes that knowledge of early

human “social systems — how they related to each other within groups,

how they defined ‘family,’ who they considered suitable mates-is,

perhaps, forever out of reach. We are relegated to using living primates

or hunting and gathering groups of human beings, neither of whom should

be considered all that reliable as models for prehistoric hominid

behavior.” But trifles such as scientific knowledge do not prevent the

Green Anarchy collective from proclaiming that prior to 8,000 B.C.E. “a

natural state of anarchy ... had prevailed for about 2 million years.”

Thanks to research by other historians, archaeologists, and

anthropologists, we know that other non-industrialized peoples besides

the !Kung did not always live in egalitarian social formations, either.

For example, he 500 nations that existed in North America before 1500

represented a diversity of cultural, political, and economic systems.

Some native societies were resolutely patriarchal, such as the Powhatan

Confederacy that settlers at Jarnestown, Virginia encountered in the

1600s. Others incorporated matriarchal and democratic aspects of

governance into tribal life; Iroquois women, for example, made most of

the important decisions in their society. (A matriarchal society, it is

important to remember, is still of course a hierarchical society.)

Moreover, Native Americans domesticated corn and tobacco, eventually

teaching Europeans how to grow them. These facts are important for those

attempting an honest evaluation of non-European tribal lifeways. It is

impossible to abstract the estimated 12,000 native cultures of the “New

World” before 1492 into one composite “noble savage” or “primitive man”

type.

Of course, native tribes did not live in a nation-state system such as

Europeans developed, nor did they have property rights as Europeans

conceived of them. However, natives did fight back when they felt

settlers encroached too far inland. In other words, many tribes

apparently held some basic notions of territoriality, evidenced not only

in skirmishes with Europeans but in inter-tribal conflicts as well.

Most, if not all, native societies practiced some type of religion. The

rich variety of Native American creation myths is known to many.

Anarchism, by contrast, has traditionally posited atheism — in fact,

antitheism — as the only belief system congruent with the scientific

understanding of reality. This is also quite opposed to primitivist icon

Ted Kaczynski’s belief in “the Grandfather Rabbit, the grandfather who

was responsible for the existence of all other rabbits.” Kaczynski notes

this supernatural being “was able to disappear, [and] that is why you

couldn’t catch him and why you would never see him.... Every time I shot

a snowshoe rabbit [in the wild], I would always say ‘thank you

Grandfather Rabbit.”’ Similar pagan beliefs (or delusions) were widely

held by other hunter-gatherer cultures.

Of course, this does not mean that anarchists wish to forcibly impose

atheism on others. In an anarchist society, people would be free to

believe whatever they wanted. But an anarchist society worthy of the

name would not allow those holding religious beliefs to impose them upon

others, nor would religious beliefs be allowed to influence decisions of

production and distribution. Although individual belief in mystical

forces would be tolerated, most anarchists would probably continue to

criticize the irrationality of those who believed in the supernatural.

The cultural climate of most Native American societies was far from

atheist or irreligious; in fact, tribal belief systems often served to

legitimize the unequal distribution of power between tribal members, and

permeated almost every aspect of everyday life.

Before European influence, many native systems of exploitation were

already in place, as well. The Mexica (Aztec) Indians of Central

America, for example, who began as roving bands of mercenaries, had by

1400 established a broad empire centered on the worship of the war god

Huitzilopochtli. The Mexica exacted tribute from subjugated villages and

sacrificed as many as 20,000 humans per year to their imperial deity.

The Incas built an empire in South America that was even larger than

that of their Central American cousins. Of course, European societies

were (and are) bloodier on a mass scale, and certainly more expansive,

as history has clearly shown. These are facts that need not be forgotten

in any honest evaluation of other social systems. But neither should

they lead us to idealize other social systems.

Zerzan and other primitivists often claim that pre-civilized social

groups enjoyed lifestyles of ease, relatively free from disease and

hardship. For example, the Green Anarchy collective writes, “Prior to

civilization there generally existed ... strong health and robusticity.”

Before European civilization, however, it is not clear that many natives

always enjoyed either, let alone both. Historians James L. Roark, Sarah

Stage, and others write: “At one site in western Kentucky, which dates

to about 2500 to 2000 BC, archaeologists found enough burials to allow

them to calculate that the life expectancy at birth for these Woodland

people was slightly over 18 years.” According to estimates by

researchers at the UCLA Gerontology Research Group, Homo sapiens’

average life expectancy 50,000 years ago was 10 years, owing to death by

disease, predators and accidents. In addition, hunter-gatherers

developed other ailments associated with their lifestyles: at one

Hopewell site dating to about 100 B.C.E., excavations revealed that

hunters “tended to have arthritis of the elbow associated with stress to

the elbow joint from using spear throwers.” Of course, in a primitivist

society such painful conditions would simply have to be endured.

Additionally, the mound-building peoples of the Mississippian culture

developed forms of hierarchy and domination as well:

One Cahokia burial mound [dating to approx. 1000 C.E.] suggests the

authority a great chief exercised. One man — presumably the chief — was

buried with the dismembered bodies of several people, perhaps enemies or

slaves; three men and three women of high status, perhaps the chiefs

relatives; four men, perhaps servants or guards, whose heads and hands

had been cut off; and fifty young women between the ages of -eighteen

and twenty-three who had evidently been strangled. Such a mass sacrifice

shows the power a Cahokian chief wielded and the obedience he commanded.

In Running on Emptiness, Zerzan claims, ‘The foraging Comanche

maintained their non-violent ways for centuries before the European

invasion, becoming violent only upon contact with marauding

civilization.” But in War Before Civilization, according to John

Johnson, anthropologist Lawrence H. Keeley produces evidence that

“Contrary to arguments that tribal violence increased after contact with

Europeans, the percentage of burials in coastal British Columbia bearing

evidence of violent traumas was actually lower after European contact

(13 percent from 1774 to 1874) than the very high levels (20 to 32

percent) evidenced in prehistoric periods.” Additionally, it is known

that even without European help Comanches harassed Wichita settlements

in present-day Texas into the 18^(th) century. The Wichita had

themselves moved to the Red River area by the 1700s to escape hostile

Osage Indians in the Midwest.

A side note is in order before continuing: Some primitivists may protest

that focusing on the less-than-romantic realities of native tribal

history “plays into the hands of” those who unjustly oppressed the

American Indians. That is, by stating that natives engaged in

internecine warfare or were mostly patriarchal, etc., one is merely

“playing into the hands of’ European conquerors, who highlighted native

“savagery” in order to oppress them. This “plays into the hands of’-type

argumentation stunts many discussions on the left, and so it is worth

quoting George Orwell, who wrote:

Whenever A and B are in opposition to one another, anyone who attacks or

criticises A is accused of aiding and abetting B. And it is often true,

objectively and on a short-term analysis, that he is making things

easier for B. Therefore, say the supporters of A, shut up and don’t

criticize: or at least criticize ‘constructively,’ which in practice

always means favourably. And from this it is only a short step to

arguing that the suppression and distortion of known facts is the

highest duty of a journalist.

For purposes of argument, we could say that Orwell’s “A” above

represents primitivism, while “B” represents apologists for European

exploitation. (Of course, the argument of this pamphlet is on the side

of neither A [primitivism] nor B [European exploitation], but rather on

the side of “C” [an anarchist society].)

It is very important to recognize the stupidity and destructiveness of

the “if you’re not with us, you’re on the side of our enemies”

accusation. In the first place, a moment’s reflection reveals that both

sides in a dispute can easily hurl this canard at those who refuse to

side with them. It also introduces an absurd contradiction: if both

sides are correct that “if you’re not with us, you’re on the side of our

enemies,” those who refuse to take either side are guilty of

simultaneously taking both sides. In practice, the only purpose of this

accusation is to intimidate critics and to silence dissent. (It’s very

disturbing that anyone who calls him or herself an anarchist would ever

stoop to such slimy tactics.)

Getting back to the question of the characteristics of primitive

societies, it is known that European conquerors were far more brutal in

their rape and plunder of native lands than almost any native societies

ever were to each other. This fact, however, need not distort any

accurate depiction of what tribal lifeways were really like. We deserve

an honest picture of events; we gain no real understanding by filtering

them through ideological biases. And from such an honest picture, we can

admit that there were many, many admirable things about native

societies, but that few, if any, represent desirable alternatives to our

current social situation, much less alternatives that conform to

anarchist ideals of direct democracy and the removal of religious

authoritarianism from the public sphere.

The Green Anarchy Collective shifts course, however, and argues that,

despite the primitivist citation of many native societies, the only

truly ) acceptable primitive societies were in fact those that existed

before the invention of writing approximately 1 1,000 years ago. In

other words, the prehistoric societies of non-literate peoples are those

that primitivists really wish to model their utopia on. (Again, see the

Zerzan, Blair, and Green Anarchy document “Notes on Primitivism.”) Some

other primitivists do not wish to recede this far into the past (“only

to the Iron Age,” say some), but for the moment, it is worth studying

the Zerzanian/Green Anarchy contention.

So, what did prehistoric human social formations actually look like?

What were the values of prehistoric hominids, and around what principles

— if any — was their social life organized? Without the written record,

their social ideas remain largely a mystery. It is unfortunate that

Emory University historian Michael P. Roark, et. al., have to remind us

that “[no documents chronicle [prehistoric] births and deaths, comings

and goings, victories and defeats. No diaries chart their daily lives.

No letters record their thoughts and emotions. No songs or stories

capture their musings about who they were and what was important to

them.”

Of course, elementary concessions to logic do not impede primitivist

fantasy. Referring to ways of life that existed in the dark eras of

human prehistory, John Zerzan complains in Future Primitive that

nowadays Neanderthals are “much-maligned.” Contrary to the strong health

and “robusticity” primitivists attribute to the Neanderthal,

anthropologists Christopher Stringer and Clive Gamble note, “The high

incidence of degenerative joint disease in Neanderthals is perhaps not

surprising given what we know of the hard lives they led and the wear

and tear this would have produced on their bodies. But the prevalence of

serious injuries is more surprising, and indicates just how dangerous

life was, even for those who did not manage to reach ‘old age’ in

Neanderthal societies.” As well, it is important to remember that prior

to their becoming extinct more than 30,000 years ago, according to Ian

Tattersall, curator of physical anthropology at the American Museum of

Natural History in New York City, “[p]hysical differences in the

Neanderthal species were so distinct that they would have represented a

completely separate species from homo sapiens.” There was also “no

biologically meaningful exchange of genes between the two species.” In

other words, anatomically modern humans (homo sapiens) coexisted with

Neanderthals in Europe as a different species, and did not develop from

them, as some primitivists ignorantly insinuate. “[M]odern humans are

the sole surviving twig on a branching bush produced by evolution,”

Tattersall reminds us. “We’re not the pinnacle of a ladder that our

ancestors climbed, but an altogether different experiment.” In fact,

Zerzan’s “much-maligned” and genetically different species, the

Neanderthal, is thought by many anthropologists to have been wiped out

through warfare with homo sapiens (the Cro-Magnon) — that is, our direct

ancestors — despite the naive, speculative Green Anarchist statement

that “civilization inaugurated warfare.”

If primitivists wish to posit a certain conception of social

organization as ideal for the future of humanity, then let them do so.

But to say humans have already lived in anarchist societies in the sense

imagined by the classical anarchist tradition is untenable. To

misrepresent the scientific record, to conjure out of the past examples

for which evidence is sketchy at best, to speculate wildly about how

prehistoric humans lived and to assert such speculations as fact — this

is to commit nothing less than fraud. In this regard, primitive

pseudoscientific ramblings resemble those of T.D.Lysenko, the Soviet

geneticist and agricultural commissar, who attempted to make nature’s

laws appear to conform to the ideological biases of Leninism, often by

falsifying his data. Very much like fundamentalist Christians opposed to

the theory of evolution, ideology-driven primitivists play with the

paleo-anthropological record, discarding data that conflicts with their

predetermined conclusions.

Doubtless, it is valuable to trace the origins of warfare, the state,

and other forms of violent domination. Anarchists since Peter Kropotkin

have done this. Nevertheless, Columbia University anthropologist Morton

H. Fried reports, “There are no authentic written records from which the

development of a pristine state can be directly read.” Coercive

hierarchical structures are generally thought to have arisen through

control over nascent agricultural surpluses, aided by religious beliefs

and ultimately a sacerdotal caste that legitimized inequality. It seems

perverse to suggest that, rather than eliminating the unjust social

relationships that remove food surpluses from public use, we get rid of

the food surpluses themselves! But again, that is what many primitivists

want.

Also, only the most misinformed could agree with the wildly untenable

primitivist claim that in prehistory — that is, history for which there

is no written record — humans lived in “a state of natural anarchy...for

about 2 million years.” And even if it could be proven that they did

(and it cannot), what would this mean for us now?

Regardless of what human societies did for the two million-year period

for which scant knowledge exists, whether what happened was admirable or

atrocious, we still find ourselves in the present dealing with forms of

oppression that exist now. That hominids have the capacity to live in

stateless societies was well known before primitivists took to

photocopiers and the Internet to remind us. So, too, has history told us

of the human capacity for cruelty and violence — two things not limited

to technological civilizations. These facts shed light on the human

condition, but they do not dictate our future. The past suggests that a

statist society is not inevitable, but it also does not necessarily tell

us what is to be done in the modern era. The past defines

possibilities,’ but it is still up to humans in the present to decide

what their future will look like. From the data we have, it seems clear

that the hunter-gatherer lifestyle of the earliest hominids would not be

a viable, much less desirable, option for many.

5. Primitivist Attacks on Anarchism

Not content simply to attack the fields of anthropology and history, or

the reader’s intelligence, primitivists also rail against the tradition

they claim to be a part of — the anarchist tradition. In an article in

the pretentiously titled Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, for

example, John Zerzan complains of “an anarchy dominated by the

productionist/ workerist/ syndicalist perspectives of...Murray Bookchin

and Noam Chomsky.” “George Bradford” groans that primitivism’s enemies

are “corporate engineers and leftist/syndicalist critics,” amazingly

equating the two. The especially noxious Feral Faun/David Watkins claims

that “anarcho-syndicalists embrace the values essential to capitalism,”

while the Green Anarchy Collective writes at Z-Net that “nsofar as

anarchists cling to the left and define themselves in its terms (e.g.

anarcho-syndicalists) they will go nowhere.” A recent issue of

primitivist-friendly [i]A:AJODA also devoted much space to polemics

against anarcho-communism and “organizationalism,” as well.

Anarcho-syndicalism, of course, was the highly organized revolutionary

strategy of the great anarchist movements in Spain, Mexico, Cuba,

Argentina, and elsewhere. Prominent anarcho-syndicalists, living and

dead, include Rudolf Rocker, Noam Chomsky, Sam Dolgoff, Diego Abad de

Santillan, Gregory Maximoff, Bueneventura Durutti, and Emile Pouget.

Prominent anarcho-communists have included Alexander Berkman, Errico

Malatesta, Emma Goldman, Nestor Makhno, and Peter Kropotkin. Others that

have worked within this tradition include Mikhail Bakunin, Daniel

Guerin, Murray Bookchin, Janet Biehl, and Albert Meltzer. In other

words, this is the mainstream of anarchism. According to primitive

thinkers, however, the anarchist tradition is wrong. (And if it is so

wrong, then one wonders why they feel the need to attach themselves to

it.)

In Against His-story, Perlman berates those who advocate the

self-management thesis. “They would supplant the state with a network of

computer centers, factories, and mines coordinated ‘by the workers

themselves’ or by an Anarchist union,” he warns. “They would not call

this arrangement a State. The name-change would exorcise the beast,”

Perlman incredibly states. He sees no difference whatsoever between a

hierarchical, authoritarian society based on violence, in which nearly

everyone who works must follow orders in an almost military manner, and

a society in which people freely and collectively control their own work

lives, and in which no government intrudes into our private lives.

In stating that anarcho-syndicalists merely want a name-change, Perlman

echoes the worst anarcho-capitalist polemicists, who state that an

anarchist syndicate is really “a state by another name.” That is,

apparently any organized group of people with some type of

decision-making structure is a “state.” By this logic, aren’t

primitivist groups also states? The self-management thesis that Perlman

attacks is at root a thesis of human self-determination; that is, it

asserts that workers and their communities should have decision-making

power over resources and structures (mines, computer centers, etc.) in

their area. Do primitivists not believe in this? If primitivists do not

believe that communities should be self-managed — that is, managed by

the people living in them — then how shall decisions affecting the

collectivity be coordinated within them? The desire for self-management

says nothing about the decisions communities will make, such as whether

to continue to utilize or close up mines — only that control will be

shifted to worker and community hands, and away from capitalists and

politicians.

Perlman’s characterization is wrong, but not unique.

Primitivists regularly advance two notions when defending their views

against anarchists. One is that, no matter how many primitive screeds

are read, anyone who objects to primitivism “does not understand it” or

“has not read enough about it.” Presumably, to understand primitivism is

to agree with it. (It’s common for devout members of religious groups to

make the same claim, which highlights the similarities between

primitivists and religionists.) Primitivists seem not to be able to

grasp the possibility that one could disagree with their views precisely

because they are understood.

The second notion is that, although they allow themselves the freedom to

polemicize viciously against traditional anarchists, they cannot be

criticized in turn. Anarchist criticism of their views is “divisive,”

“sectarian,” or “uncomradely.” Anarchists are routinely presented with

the pathetic sight of primitivists and post-leftists viciously attacking

classical anarchism, only to thereafter run behind the black flag and

claim “but we’re all in this together” when the fire is returned. In the

world of primitive thinking, only primitive thoughts deserve to be

advanced.

In fact, those who can access the Internet or who have the time and

money to read many current anarchist periodicals are probably familiar

with the growing gulf between primitivism and the tendency within the

anarchist movement that maintains a class-struggle, but not

anti-technological, approach. Primitivism claims hostility to

traditional left ideas, as evidenced by dour rants about “workerists”

above, including those embodied in the classical anarchist tradition.

“Post-leftists,” as anti-left primitivists prefer to be called, derive

their appellation in the main from the book Anarchy After Leftism,

written by known police informant and attorney Bob Black. In A:AJODA #48

(Fall-Winter 1999–2000), John Zerzan wrote under the “Post-Left

Anarchy!” forum, identifying his brand of primitivism as a form of

post-leftist thought.

The division within the anarchist movement between primitivists and

other anarchists is particular to the U.S., where hipsters often claim

any number of bizarre ideas under a rubric of “anarchism” to lend them a

fashionable sheen. Where the anarchist movement exists elsewhere,

however, one finds it informed with classical anarchist ideas of class

struggle and self-management. These same working class aspects of the

anarchist movement, however, are often derided by American primitivists

as reformist or “leftist.” For them, leftism is quite as bad as

rightism.

Of course, anarchists have always criticized the authoritarian left,

because anarchists have always criticized authoritarianism. For

instance, Voline’s The Unknown Revolution and Emma Goldman’s My

Disillusionment in Russia are two well-known examples of the anarchist

critique of Leninist tyranny. The fate of the anarchist Spanish CNT-FAI

at the hands of the Stalinist, nominally leftist Partido Comunista

Espanola is known by most anarchists. Anarchist criticism of the

practices of authoritarian leftists has come as much from actual

experience as from theoretical disagreement. Bakunin and Marx debated

constantly, defining for many the splits between libertarian and

authoritarian leftism, and it’s silly and dishonest to pretend that

these differences are nonexistent or trivial.

The Green Anarchy Collective writes at Z-Net: “The two main failed and

exhausted means or approaches towards change in recent times have been

liberalism and leftism.... Technology, production, hierarchy;

government, ecological destruction, and ideas like ‘progress’ continue

to go unquestioned by most who would identify with the left.” The Green

Anarchist proclamation to the contrary, traditional anarchists like

Peter Kropotkin situated anarchism at the left wing of the socialist

movement. Like Bakunin, Kropotkin believed that anarchism was a form of

socialism, and that “socialism without liberty is slavery and

brutality.”

Additionally, primitivists often denigrate anarcho-syndicalists as

secret Marxist-Leninists (or even fascists!) who would reveal themselves

truly as such if ever they “gained power.” This is a rather curious

charge, given that the social designs advanced by anarcho-syndicalists

are designed to make it impossible that anyone could “gain power” over

others.

The primitivists’ chief complaint is that “workerist” anarchists

romanticize work, while primitivists want to abolish it.

Anarcho-syndicalists hold work on a sort of mystical pedestal,

primitivists say, refusing to acknowledge that humans are more than

simple “workers.” (Actually, the problem is that anarcho-syndicalists do

see that humans are more than mere workers, but that capitalists don’t!)

Most direct of the primitivist assaults on anarcho-syndicalism is Feral

Faun’s “The Bourgeois Origins of Anarcho-Syndicalism,” available on the

web (at

www.insurgentdesire.org.uk

) and as a pamphlet. Feral Watkins, published in A: AJODA and Fifth

Estate, absurdly claims in his piece that “anarcho-syndicalists embrace

the values essential to capitalism” and that anarcho-syndicalists do

this “maybe even more than the bourgeoisie.” How it is possible for

those other than the actual bourgeoisie to do this is not explained; by

definition, the bourgeoisie are the guardians and source of bourgeois

values. If anarcho-syndicalists do this “maybe even more” than their

bosses — the bourgeoisie — then anarcho-syndicalists are a great danger

indeed. It means they are even more reactionary than the actual power

holders in this system!

The essay’s main point is that “anarcho-syndicalism reflects bourgeois

ideology” and that “values upheld by anarcho-syndicalists do not

significantly differ from those of the more radical of the bourgeois

liberal theorists, and their project, upon examination, proves to be

merely the extension of the liberal project.” It is unclear what

Faun/Watkins means by “merely an extension of the liberal project,” save

that this is supposed to be bad. Indeed, most anarchists agree that the

birth of anarchism owed much to the Enlightenment. “With the development

of industrial capitalism,” Noam Chomsky writes in Daniel Guerin’s

Anarchism, “a new and unanticipated system of injustice, it is

libertarian socialism that has preserved and extended the radical

humanist message of the Enlightenment and the classical liberal ideals

that were perverted into an ideology to sustain the emerging social

order.” Anarchists do not deny that power-holders pay lip service to

Enlightenment ideals while engaging in behavior that contradicts them.

Overall, Faun/Watkins’ critique of anarcho-syndicalism is a good example

of the primitivist critique of class struggle anarchism. To Feral Faun

and other primitivists, anarcho-syndicalism was never an authentic

revolutionary tendency to begin with. How could anarcho-syndicalism ever

be revolutionary if it has “bourgeois origins”?

Indeed, Faun’s essay castigates the behavior of the Spanish CNT during

the Revolution of 1936 as “truly disgusting.” Neglecting the fact that

it was only some members of the CNT that made (easy-to-see-in-hindsight)

mistakes, even those anarchists that do not consider themselves

anarcho-syndicalists are inclined to agree that if ever there was an

anarchist revolution, it was in Spain in the late 1930s. But not for

Faun and other primitivists. To them, the broad working class movement

against Spanish fascism was itself bourgeois, “maybe even more”

bourgeois than the bourgeois resistance itself, representing no real

libertarian alternative for the Spanish people, even if it was what a

majority of them preferred. According to the primitive take on the

conflict, what the workers themselves wanted in the face of Franco’s

dictatorship was a delusion, a “workerist” hell “even more” bourgeois

than capitalism. This being the case, surely for the primitivists the

defeat and attendant slaughter of the “bourgeois” Spanish anarchists was

a relief, as no consistent anarchist could ever want a system set up by

those “maybe even more” bourgeois than the capitalist class.

Ironically, Feral Watkins introduces his essay with a brief depiction of

the historical development of capitalism that could have come from the

pages of Marx. He refers to the period of “liberal bourgeois”

revolutions in the late 17^(th) to early 19^(th) centuries. “This period

was the uprising of the bourgeoisie against the feudal system and the

power of the Catholic Church,” Faun informs us. The irony in Faun’s

description lies not in the fact that it is incorrect — in fact, it is

accurate to say that the revolutions of this period did upset old feudal

orders and replace aristocracies with sham, bourgeois democracies — but

because it shows that, try as they may, primitive post-leftists cannot

escape a left-wing analysis.

Anti-left primitivists assail anarcho-syndicalists for engaging in an

analysis that they say is mired in musty old leftist terms and concepts,

for example. Feral Faun’s interpretation of the liberal bourgeois

revolutions of the Enlightenment, however, is pretty much straight up

historical materialism (Marxism, in other words). Ironically, without

leftist concepts buttressing them, primitivists could not write their

“anti-left” diatribes. Likewise, Faun repeatedly uses terms like

“bourgeoisie” that also reek of ancient leftism. Most modern anarchists

refuse such terms precisely because they reek of Old Guard, Party

dogmatism. (Rather than speak of the ”bourgeoisie,” for example, many

anarchists find it more useful to note the operations of multi-nationals

and the corporate elite.)

Faun then makes one of the more horrible mistakes in his essay: he

claims that “the defining quality of capitalism, as compared with other

economic systems, is not the existence of capitalists but the production

of excess capital allowing for continued economic expansion.” It is true

that the defining quality of capitalism is not the existence of

capitalists — but neither is it the “production of excess capital.” It

is the fact of capital — of class property — itself. If capitalism is

anything, it is the existence of capital. It is not the “excess

production” of it. “Capital” is itself a form of property that

presupposes a certain distribution of power: the power of some to

control and dispose of the things others must have access to in order to

survive. “Capital” is an authoritarian relationship between individuals,

and this authoritarian relation is precisely the defining aspect of

capitalism for anarchists. If the “production of excess capital” is the

defining quality for primitivists, and not the authoritarianism that is

inherent in “capital” itself, then in what sense are primitivists

anarchists?

Now, if by “production of excess capital” Feral Watkins really meant

“extraction of surplus value,” then again he is not engaging in a

primitivist analysis but simply an old Marxist one. If, however, he

really means that capitalism is defined as production of excess capital,

then we have to ask: what is the significance of this production of

“excess capital,” and who is I such production bad for? And, for that

matter, how much capital is the “right” amount of capital to be piled up

before “production of excess capital” begins?

For capitalists, there is no such thing as an excess of capital. They

can never have enough. And they can certainly not be sated to a degree

where they feel they have an “excess” of it. After all, that is what

makes them capitalists. The more, the better. For them, there is always

a shortage, no matter how much they have, and that is what drives them

to expand their businesses and to accumulate ever more. There is no

“excess” in their logic. Rather, there is always slightly less than is

needed to sate their appetite.

For workers, however, who labor under the command of capitalists, the

term “excess of capital” is a redundancy. The mere fact of capital is an

excess. Its simple existence is a superfluity. Capitalism breeds excess

because it is itself excess. From the working class point of view, the

existence of capitalists is excessive and unnecessary; capitalists are a

superfluous class of people whose elimination (as a class — not as

individuals!) would increase efficiency and freedom. But then, the

primitivists have no working class point of view. In fact, they show

disdain to the idea that there is a meaningfully distinct working class

perspective. (Of course, primitivists do slip up and refer to a “working

class” fairly often, but it is not informed with any definite meaning;

it is used in the same casual sense that The New York Times might

occasionally refer to an American “working class.”)

It may seem as if we are splitting hairs here, in the critique of how

Faun defines capitalism. But Faun’s failure to grasp the simple

authoritarian dynamic that makes “capital” what it is reveals the

poverty of the primitivist philosophy. Anarchists see private property

in the means of production — “capital” — as a manifestation of the

broader problem of authoritarianism. To anarchists, the particular type

of authoritarianism that capital represents is itself the defining

characteristic of capitalism. If for primitivists the defining

characteristic is simply an “excess production” of privately owned means

of production, then they have no meaningful anti-authoritarian analysis

of our current economic system.

Faun claims that anarcho-syndicalists have core values in common with

capitalists. The “values which are essential to capitalist expansion are

production and progress,” he says. “Anarcho-syndicalists embrace...these

capitalist values,” he maintains. Zerzan and others make similar

arguments, claiming that leftists blindly adhere to notions of progress

as well. “Production” and “progress” taken out of context, however,

could apply to almost anything. The question is, for anarchists,

production of what and under what conditions? And, similarly, progress

towards what? It is not enough to say that “production and progress”

themselves are absolutely good or bad, devoid of context.

Production that satisfies the greatest amount of human need with the

least human expenditure is a worthy goal for anarcho-syndicalists.

Production that fattens profit margins the handsomest, with the least

attending social responsibility, is what business owners value. These

are radically different priorities. Capitalists believe in progress

towards whatever will help them make money: technological progress that

eliminates paid or potentially dissident labor is hailed as “progress.”

Disemployment and environmental ruin are “progress.”

But to anarcho-syndicalists, this is the opposite of progress; to

anarcho-syndicalists, “progress” is meaningful to the extent innovations

occur that help feed, house, clothe, etc., the greatest number of humans

with the least amount of human labor, the least use of natural

resources, and the least amount of environmental damage. Innovations

that expand the scope of human freedom and aid in worker self-management

(i.e., human self-determination), are seen as progressive. Capitalists

have no interest in this sort of progress, as it is not profitable.

Primitivists do not acknowledge this obvious, basic distinction, as to

do so would deprive them of a useful straw man.

“Essential to production and progress is work,” Faun continues, “and so

the bourgeois highly value work — and, contrary to the image painted by

‘radical’ labor propagandists, it is not uncommon for capitalists to

work many more hours than industrial workers, but it’s organizational

rather than productive work”

Police informants may also work many more hours than industrial workers,

but this is not the sort of work that anarcho-syndicalists value. Again,

it is not simply work as an absolute that is valued, but the kind of

work. “What type of work is it, and to what ends is it being conducted?”

the anarcho-syndicalist asks. There is work that is harmful to the

working class — such as the “work” of exploitation and of managing — and

there is work that is productive and useful to society. The latter sort

of work is valued by anarcho-syndicalists. The work of ruling and

exploiting is not.

“Those who manage to avoid work are the moral scum of capitalist society

— parasites off the working people,” Faun writes, stating also that

anarcho-syndicalism views shirkers in the same light. Those who do

absolutely no 9-to-5 type work in our current system may or may not be

acting in a manner that is conducive to revolutionary goals, however.

Most anarcho-syndicalists would rather someone not work at all, than

work as a capitalist or as a police informant, for example. A hatred of

work in our current system is understandable; indeed, it is this hatred

that fuels the anarcho-syndicalist desire for revolutionary change. This

is hatred of work as it must be conducted in the statist/capitalist

system wherein the mass of people work to enrich a few at the expense of

themselves, their talents, and their own self-actualization.

Work in a primitivist society would consist of foraging, hunting,

gathering, cooking, seeking or constructing shelter, etc. Just as

primitivists claim they would not force anyone to engage in this sort of

work, leaving idlers to go it alone or die, so too would

anarcho-syndicalists not force anyone to work in a post-capitalist

order. But in an anarcho-syndicalist society, surpluses would be more

likely to abound, thereby enabling non-workers to be cared for. In the

primitivist utopia, surpluses would be guaranteed not to exist — indeed,

they are posited as authoritarian — leaving many to suffer and die.

(Remember, primitivists claim that “the emergence of surplus ...

invariably [my emphasis] involves property and an end to unconditional

sharing” — surpluses are therefore to be avoided, not welcomed.)

Anarcho-syndicalists can also envision a time when work is shorter, more

pleasant, more efficient, and more productive than it is now, leaving

plenty of time for leisure, if work itself is not counted by workers as

being indistinguishable from leisure activity. The primitivist notion,

much like the capitalist’s, is that people require external compulsion

to work. Without such external compulsion, primitivists say, no one

would want to work in mines or do other unsavory jobs. Kropotkin

addressed this old canard in “Anarchist Communism”:

As to the childish question, repeated for fifty years: “Who would do

disagreeable work?” frankly I regret that none of our savants has ever

been brought to do it, be it for only one day in his life. If there is

still work which is really disagreeable in itself, it is only because

our scientific men have never cared to consider the means of rendering

it less so: they have always known that there were plenty of starving

men who would do it for a few pence a day.

Work can be made more pleasant when the bosses are chased out and when

workers themselves administer their workplaces; all resources previously

controlled by capitalists would be in the hands of the public.

Primitivists who do not wish to work in such a society would not be

forced to do so, and it would be up to individual communities to decide

whether to give primitive idlers portions of a surplus they did not help

produce. (Of course, given that such a society could only occur through

a revolution stressing principles of solidarity and mutual aid, it is

likely that primitivist non-workers would indeed find themselves

supported by their despised workerist cousins.) Until such a state of

affairs, however, anarcho-syndicalism places no special blame on people

who try to avoid work, unless they do so in a manner that unduly hurts

their working class brethren. Anarchists believe that the most important

work to be done in the period we are in now is the work of organizing

people to overthrow the state-subsidized capitalist system.

Feral Watkins refers to Chaz Bufe’s “Listen, Anarchist!” as evidence of

how anarchists feel about those who try to avoid work in our society.

Bufe mentions that anarchists who intentionally try to get on public

assistance as a means of living a work-free, “anarchist” lifestyle are

not acting in a manner that is most beneficial for achieving

revolutionary change. To primitivists and lifestylists in general,

Bufe’s comment must come across as a paternalistic admonition of

slackers, echoing Republican anti-welfare rhetoric, with its obsessive

insistence that people everywhere do the responsible and moral thing of

getting a job. In fact, this is the general attitude that primitivists

attribute to anarcho-syndicalism and the labor movement as a whole. [1]

Bufe’s comments and the anarcho-syndicalist position are not congruent

with Watkins’ estimation of them, however. In one sense, it is more

helpful to anarcho-syndicalist goals for anarchists to have jobs, as

they can attempt to organize their place of work along non-hierarchical

lines. In this sense, it is helpful for anarchists to go into the

workplace much as community organizers go into neighborhoods they wish

to organize. The tragedy is, of course, that for most anarchists work is

not an organizing choice, but a necessity of life. Radical unions are

dependent upon workers organizing within their industry for the eventual

expropriation of capital from private hands.

The desire by some lumpenproles to scam their way onto the welfare rolls

also represents a type of escapism. No one is saying that what small,

paltry welfare programs exist in the US should be destroyed, or anything

like that (quite the contrary). But carving out an individual, work-free

lifestyle is not revolutionary, nor will it lead to any substantial

revolutionary change. Bosses can live with workers dropping out of the

rat race; they cannot live with workers actively organizing on the shop

floor. Indeed, the great anarchist revolutions of Spain, the Ukraine,

Mexico, and elsewhere, were not guided by some rousing vision of

dropping out of the rat race. Welfare escapism is.

“The only real problem they have with the capitalist system is who’s in

charge,” Feral Faun continues, referring to anarcho-syndicalists. Zerzan

agrees, writing, “Self-managed factories and other forms of

productionism and specialization are now widely understood as no advance

at all.” (“Widely understood”? By whom?) Anarcho-syndicalists would

“prefer the One Big Capitalist,” Faun writes, “the international union

of working people, rather than various individuals, corporations and

states to be in charge. But the basic structure would be the same.”

Here Faun/Watkins mocks the I.W.W. and its and its notion of the “One

Big Union.” But when Faun scoffs at the “international union of working

people” he also denigrates global working class unity itself! Indeed,

Faun’s analysis is not “workerist” at all. Far from it. It is, in fact,

anti-worker. The fear of the “one big capitalist” is exactly the

anarchist critique of Leninism and other forms of statist socialism.

That is, statist socialists seek to replace a number of capitalists with

one large capitalist in the form of the state. But anarcho-syndicalists

want neither one big capitalist (the state) or many capitalists to

choose from: they want a self-managed economy where the people doing the

actual work are calling the shots. That is not capitalism, let alone

something that is conducive to the formation of “One Big Capitalist.”

Feral Watkins’ insistence that it somehow is only reinforces the fact

that he and other primitivists have no understanding of the basic social

dynamic that underpins capitalism.

“[T]he bourgeois liberal is content to get rid of priests and kings, and

the anarcho-syndicalist throws in presidents and bosses,” Faun says.

“But the factories remain intact, the stores remain intact (though the

syndicalists may call them distribution centers), the family remains

intact — the entire social system remains intact.”

And would families not remain intact if primitivists had their way?

Faun’s insistence is that since physical structures, like stores, remain

standing, somehow oppressive social relations must exist as well. Like

Karl Marx’s flawed belief that the “steam mill gives you the industrial

capitalist,” Faun believes that the store will give you the boss. That

is, the physical existence of buildings somehow brings about authority

figures. Faun does not trouble us with an explanation of how this is so

— he leaves us to take it on his good word.

In fact, whether or not the stores remain intact would be the

prerogative of workers and their communities. When Faun posits that

anarcho-syndicalists want things to continue the same as before, but

simply self-managed, he betrays a deep misunderstanding of the principle

of self-management, as does Perlman, above. Anarcho-syndicalism is the

belief that workers know best about how their labor is to be used — if

at all — and that they, and not theorists, should decide what to do at

the actual point of production.

And, believe it or not, anarcho-syndicalists do not wish to deprive

primitivists of any opportunity to get back to nature. If, in a

post-revolutionary society, groups of primitivists wanted to leave and

lead a lifestyle they’d consider more attuned to man’s natural

inclinations, they would certainly be free to do so. As they’d look in

disdain over their shoulders at the “workerist” anarchist civilization

they have left, they could delight in pursuing the very hard work of

foraging and constructing shelter for themselves, deluding themselves

that that is not itself work — albeit a hard sort of work not aided by

the machinery that anarchists back in the hi-tech society have

expropriated from capitalist rule. In the end, the primitivist will be

working much harder than his “workerist” cousin, no matter how hard he

may try to convince himself that he has liberated himself from toil.

6. The Bloody Side of Primitivism

Simple theoretical ineptitude is one thing. But there is also a far

darker side to primitive thought.

On December 11, 1985, California store owner Hugh Scrutton tried to

remove what he thought was a road hazard from his store’s parking lot.

As he picked up the object, which resembled a piece of wood with nails

driven through it, an explosion drove metal shards into his heart and

ripped off his right hand, killing him. Scrutton was the first of three

victims to die from Unabomber attacks.

“They ain’t innocent,” Zerzan told a reporter. “Which isn’t to say that

I’m totally at ease with blowing them to pieces. Part of me is. And part

of me isn’t.” In Running on Emptiness, Zerzan evinces his sympathy

differently: “I offered the hope, if not the prediction, that TK [Ted

Kaczynski] might at some point also be considered in a more positive

light for his resistance to industrial civilization.” Kaczynski, Zerzan

claims, “decided he had to kill people to bring up this suppressed point

of view. And he forced them [the media] to publish it. The point here is

not whether he was justified or not, but merely the level of denial

[that culture and technology are bad.]”

According to Kaczynski at primitivism.com, “When things break down,

there is going to be violence and this does raise a question. I don’t

know if I exactly want to call it a moral question, but the point is

that for those who realize the need to do away with the

techno-industrial system, if you work for its collapse, in effect you

are killing a lot of people.” In the article “When Non-Violence is

Suicide,” Kaczynski urges activists to prepare for combat, painting a

hypothetical scenario to compel us towards this end: In Kaczynski-Land,

the parable goes, post-revolutionary farmers (i.e., cropdomesticators)

are confronted by marauders, who wish to rape a primitivists’ female

friend. “Mick, grab that bitch over there before she gets away. She got

[sic] a nice ass,” Kaczynski has the imaginary bandits saying. “We’ll

all screw her tonight.” Lovely stuff.

In A:AJODA, which published Kaczynski’s first prison interview, Lawrence

Jarach complains, “There are many prejudiced caricatures and objections

concerning primitivism; for example that its proponents want to ‘go back

to the Stone Age’ ....” In fact, Jarach says, “[a]s far as I can tell,

most primitivists only want to go back as far as the Iron Age,” putting

the primitivist golden era at around 1000 B.C.E., well after the

establishment of the written word and crop surpluses, and when Middle

Eastern kingdoms held sway. According to the non-partisan Population

Resource Bureau, “Estimates of average life expectancy in Iron Age

France have been put at only 10 or 12 years. Under these conditions, the

birth rate would have to be about 80 per 1,000 people just for the

species to survive.” That’s some Golden Age.

Jarach delineates a depressingly diverse number of primitivist theories

currently in circulation: some are associated with Zerzan and “green

anarchism”; another revolves around the misanthropy of Earth

First!-style Deep Ecology [2]; and yet at least one more comes from the

Perlman/ Bradford/Fifth Estate sector. Jarach says the criticism that

constructing a primitivist society “would result in an immediate mass

die-off of thousands — if not millions — of humans” is a mere

“dismissal” from those who do not want to spend time trying to

understand the many forms of primitivism he has laid out for us. Jarach

then asks Zerzan if, in fact, “millions will die immediately” if

primitivists had their way. “Perhaps the key word in your question is

‘immediately,”’ Zerzan carefully responds. “In other words, if the whole

prevailing apparatus vanished instantly somehow, millions probably would

die.” The solution is apparently to slowly dismantle

technology-something that would not bring about mass death immediately,

it is true, but gradually. The rest of Zerzan’s answer is a non-answer.

(“People are already dying,” he says — a fact known to most, and in fact

the reason many of us are anarchists, as we wish to prevent widespread

death!)

Tragically, the most fanatic segments of the primitivist movement

welcome human death. Though they do not practice Kaczynski-style

homicide in mass numbers, they thrill at large-scale epidemics that

might reduce the population of the earth. In a May 1, 1987 edition of

the Earth First! paper, for example, “Miss Ann Thropy” argued that AIDS

is a “good” thing, and said that if that “epidemic didn’t exist, radical

environmentalists would have to invent one.”

That a hunter-gatherer or even an Iron Age society could not support

massive population centers is a fact recognized by most primitivists. To

achieve their objective of a primitive society, therefore, like the

Khmer Rouge, they hold that the population must be more evenly

distributed across the earth. As Marx and Engels wrote in The Communist

Manifesto, revolutionaries should work to establish a “gradual abolition

of the distinction of town and country, by a more equitable distribution

of the population over the country.” Manifesto.” [3] Marxist-style

population dispersal advocated by “post-left” thinkers is an odd thing

indeed, not to mention an old thing — a prime example of their borrowing

from past authoritarians.

In “Notes on Primitivism,” Zerzan and the Green Anarchy Collective

repeat deep ecologist-style warnings that within “the last 200 years the

human population growth curve has shifted from the normal mammal ‘s’

shape to the more viral ‘j’ shape.” The association of humanity with a

“viral” infection is common to deep ecology, which regards humanity as a

disease upon the planet. (To wit: Earth First! co-founder David

Foreman’s statement “We are a cancer on nature.”) Playing with the

analogy further, the primitivists warn that “this increase is much like

that of viruses (which is to consume the host until both the virus and

the host are dead).”

Wisely, primitivists usually stop short of actually advocating mass

killing, even if individual primitivists like Ted Kaczynski have already

attempted it. “[W]e aren’t suggesting a strategy to deal with this

[population growth],” the Green Anarchy Collective wisely adds. “[W]e

just think there is data about the situation that should be known” —

presumably so that others, too, may ruminate and also not suggest a

strategy to deal with it.

In his “Primitive Thought” supplement to Listen, Anarchist! Chaz Bufe

says that the idea that “population lies at the root of every

environmental problem” is on “a par with the simplistic belief that

‘technology’ is the sole cause of environmental destruction.” The

Malthusian doctrine that asserts population growth will, at some point

in the future, outstrip available resources has been used to justify the

most callous government policies against the poor. Better to let people

die off if they will be a burden on the planet or others, the logic

goes. In fact, if the global population is increasing at an alarming

rate, we already know several of the reasons why this is so: 1)

Religious authoritarianism that urges people in poorer countries to

marry young and be fruitful, and to avoid sinful contraceptives. 2)

Right-wing policy makers that outlaw abortion (even though, for the

poor, there is always a de facto ban on expensive abortion procedures),

“morning after”-type abortion pills, and sex education in schools. 3)

Destructive neoliberal globalization policies that keep the third world

in poverty, leading families to produce more offspring so that they may

gain more income-earners for their household. Malthus’ notion that there

is a “surplus population” sadly merits a reminder that there is no human

being that is surplus to his or her family, or to the human project. It

is disappointing that some have to be reminded that no human being is

superfluous.

If a primitive life is so desirable, be it of a Stone Age or Iron Age

type, then why haven’t primitivists attempted to live this way? In fact,

the failure of primitivists to pursue the establishment of

hunter-gatherer societies reveals how clearly undesirable many

primitivists really feel such societies are. “Does Zerzan live like

that?” Peter Fenton asked in a 1999 issue of Scope magazine. “No way.

‘It’s too daunting a task,’ he admits.” Likewise, some primitivists live

off public assistance and/or the generosity of friends, never attempting

a break with civilized comforts.

Unlike anarcho-syndicalists or anarcho-communists, primitivists could

attempt to live their preferred lifestyle in our world now. Jon

Krakauer’s book Into the Wild presents academician Gene Rosellini’s

attempt to live a primitive lifestyle in the wilds of Canada. “I was

interested in knowing if it was possible to be independent of modern

technology,” he told Anchorage Daily News reporter Debra McKinney. “I

began my adult life with the hypothesis that it would be possible to

become a Stone Age native.” He “purged his life of all but the most

primitive tools, which he fashioned from native materials with his own

hands,” Krakauer writes. For ten years, Rossellini toughed it out.

Eventually, however, he gave up: “I would say I realistically

experienced the physical, mental and emotional reality of the Stone Age.

But to borrow a Buddhist phrase, eventually came a setting face-to-face

with pure reality. I learned that it is not possible for human beings as

we know them to live off the land.” In 1991, Rosellini was found dead in

his shack, a suicide victim.

Ted Kaczynski’s attempt at primitive living is well known, as well.

Kaczynski’s situation, however, presents the reality that many

primitivists are in fact not content simply to live in isolation, but

seek to strike out at the civilization that is around them. Primitivists

claim that “techno-industrial civilization” would inevitably encroach on

their enclaves due to its ceaseless, internal drive to expand outward.

This is why primitivists do not want anarcho-syndicalists or others to

enjoy a high-tech society — their contention is that if any remnants of

“techno-industrial civilization” remain — even if it is in anarchist

hands — they and the Earth will still be threatened. Again, primitivists

ascribe “techno-industrialism” a will of its own, proclaiming its

ability to do things independent of human agency (see the “Frankenstein

monster” and “Earthwrecker” comment made by primitivists cited [in

chapter 3]). Latent in this assertion is also the unproven belief that

“techno-industrial society” would always be ecologically unsustainable.

This is the logic that impels primitivists to strike out violently

against those they see as “technologism’s” advocates. In the primitive

mindset, such people literally threaten their lives; therefore, killing

them is a type of self-defense.

Interestingly, primitivists have also worked it out to have things both

ways. On the one hand, some say “it will do no good” to leave

civilization at this point, because civilization would eventually

encroach upon them. This provides them carte blanche to enjoy the

Internet, microwaved food, cell phones, and medical care. But at the

same time they ruminate on how much better life would be without such

amenities. Again, it seems primitivists want everyone else to go

primitive first. The notion that “there is no place to go now that is

free of civilization” provides an excuse to indulge in hi-tech gadgets

and other luxuries until “society breaks down.” Like Marxist

determinists, primitivists seem to believe that sooner or later society

will crash under its own weight, with or without them, so there’s no

harm in indulging themselves in its pleasures in the meantime.

However, one is led to a bloody conclusion once one adopts the flawed

premises of primitive thought. In conflating “industrialism” or

“techno-industrial civilization” with the market forces of capitalism,

primitivists insist it is a matter of ecological survival to destroy all

machinery, whether humans require it for life (as in medical care or

water purification devices) or not. For primitivists, elimination of

capitalist profit motives still leaves the Frankenstein monster of

technology unharmed; they preach that the monster will continue to grow

blindly, like a cancer, even if no capitalists control it. In the end,

the primitivist imperative is an all-out war not so much against

coercive social relations, as anarchism is, as against physical

structures that they say have their own prerogatives. Replacing

authoritarian social relations with egalitarian social relations will do

no good, they believe; physical infrastructure must be ruined as well.

This is a major part of their broader aim of destroying all

civilization.

In contrast, let us as anarchists propose the establishment of a

civilization worthy of the name. As Kropotkin once noted, “Competition

is the law of the jungle, but cooperation is the law of civilization.”

We should seek to establish a society and culture that is, in every

sense of the word, civilized. Statist capitalism provides no civility

for billions the world over. Wars, poverty, the eradication of native

peoples, unjust distribution of workers’ produce, debt bondage, and

crime — this is the legacy of our authoritarian era. Instead, anarchists

should work to create a society that replaces such widespread incivility

with a world that is thoroughly, and to every degree, civil.

7. Appendix: On Decoding Primitivist Babble

Notes on the Conflations of Primitive Thought (A Guide to Decoding

Primitivist Babble)

Conflation of Civilization and Coercive Social Relations

“Civilization is the fountainhead of all dominations: patriarchy,

division of labor, domestication of life, warfare, on down the line to

its present ghastly fullness,” Zerzan, Blair, and the Green Anarchy

Collective assert.

In fact, patriarchy, warfare, and forms of division of labor existed

before civilization — not to mention irrational page/religious thought.

See Keeley’s War Before Civilization, for example, or anthropologist

Robert B. Edgerton’s Sick Societies.

Conflation of Technology and Coercive Social Relations

“Technology is more of a process or concept than a static form. It is a

complex system involving division of labor, resource extraction, and

exploitation for the benefit of those who implement its process,”

Zerzan, Blair, and the Green Anarchy Collective inform us.

This view was addressed earlier. Needless to say, the primitive view

that technology constitutes an array of coercive relations is not shared

by anthropologists, who define technology as the application of science

or technical methods to problem-solving. That is not to say that

coercive relations involving the use of technology don’t exist, only

that technology isn’t the source of them. Humans are. The onus is on

primitivists to demonstrate that technology is invariably predicated on

coercive or environmentally hostile relations.

Conflation of “Industrialism” and Capitalism

Primitivists generally ascribe to their concept of “industrialism” all

the features of statist capitalism — but additionally (and incredibly)

attribute to it a sovereign will, suggesting that it acts independent of

human control. The “industrial system” would work to destroy humanity

and the earth even if it were the collective property of an anarchist

society (“self-managed”), in their view.

Conflation of Poverty and Freedom

Primitivists wish humanity to live like earlier hominids — that is, in

poverty, by today’s standards. They confer praise on those who live

“down-shifted” lifestyles (much like Kalle Lasn and his Adbusters

troupe) and approve of those who choose to become squatters and

dumpster-divers. They dispute the notion that primitive living amounts

to a poverty lifestyle because, they claim, early hominids enjoyed a

type of “primitive affluence” (in radically different conditions than

our own, of course).

This brings to mind a Saturday Night Live sketch in which comedian Jon

Lovitz complained that he couldn’t get a date, whereupon he turned to

the camera and urged women, “Lower your standards!” That is what

primitivists urge for the rest of us — not just for the super rich, mind

you, but for modest working class families. Traditionally, of course,

anarchists have sought a collective raising of living standards, with

redistribution from the rich downward to the rest of us.

Radically reducing living standards to meet a primitivist notion of

“affluence” seems Orwellian. While it is true that some non-industrial

peoples, such as the Chumash Indians of California, were lucky enough to

happen upon a naturally abundant environment (whereupon they ceased to

be hunter-gatherers, settled, and began crop-domestication), other

pre-civilized peoples did not fare so well, and roamed endlessly in

search of food, driven by a base need for survival. That all primitive

peoples for over two million years enjoyed “affluence” is not only

wildly speculative, it plainly contradicts anthropological knowledge.

Conflation of Group Decision Making and Statecraft

Primitivists and post-leftist allies (note: not all post-leftists are

primitivists) often sneer at anything “organizational.” They falsely

associate decision making structures of groups with the running of the

state, often conflating, for example, union democracy with statecraft.

This ignores the essence of the state: coercion and violence. Anarchists

argue that organization is essential to social survival, but that

coercion and violence are not, and that organizations can and do exist

that are not coercive or authoritarian. Primitivists ignore this

essential distinction and argue that all organizations are

authoritarian, thought they’re hard put to say why. Thus, by their own

logic, the Green Anarchy and Fifth Estate collectives are statist and

authoritarian and should be disbanded. Why they have thus far not

followed their own logic is a mystery.

Conflation of Organization and Authoritarians (or “Leninism”)

Statist capitalists have often said that “anarchist organization” is an

oxymoron. Statists are unable to imagine any type of organization that

is not authoritarian, steeped as they are in authoritarian ideas about

how groups must be run. Amazingly, many primitivists agree, and so hope

to do away with organization! Echoing the worst of post-leftist

rhetoric, some primitivists have incredibly suggested that no

institution should be allowed to exist for more than a decade or so,

even if members of the institution democratically decide they’d like the

operation to continue (and even if the rest of the community has no

problem with the institution continuing). A collectively run farm would

in this case have to be shut down after several years, lest it become an

evil “entrenched institution” — even if the community and farm workers

objected.

It’s also worth mentioning that primitivists routinely ignore the well

known distinguishing characteristics of Leninism (vanguard parties,

retention of the government in the form of a “workers’ state,” a

controlling party central committee, government control of all aspects

of life, especially work life, etc., etc.) and throw the term around

merely as a form of abuse, as a form of name calling, much in the manner

of right-wingers who label anyone who disagrees with them as a

“communist.”

Conflation of Unions per se with “Mediating Structures of

Oppression”

A common primitivist canard is that all unions are simply mediating

structures of exploitation (“the left-wing of capital”) between bosses

and wage slaves. This notion owes much to postmodern theory, which

asserts that any social relation arising in a hegemonic system is

automatically “tainted” by virtue of its birth there. That is, anything

brought about in an oppressive society will be oppressive, no matter

what its actual character is. Some radical Maoists have extended this to

include sexual relations between men and women. (All sex is exploitative

of women in capitalism, they say, no matter what.) In fact, there is

much truth to the notion that capitalism (or any authoritarian system)

skews relations between human beings. But the idea that all groups in

capitalism “mediate” capitalist oppression would have to apply to

primitivist groups as well. Eventually, one ends up with a pessimistic

picture in which every progressive organization is innately oppressive,

thereby eliminating hope for meaningful social change!

Of course, I’m not denying the fact that business unions of the AFL-CIO

variety often act in ways that are extremely detrimental to workers. The

labor aristocracy of the AFL-CIO does tend to create a caste of officers

who live at the expense of dues-paying workers, and who develop class

interests in opposition to them. But this does not mean all forms of

working class mutual aid in the workplace merely “mediate” exploitation!

Radically democratic unions are possible, as the IWW, early CIO, CNT,

and many independent unions have shown.

Even the primitivists who concede that some types of unions are

revolutionary (and they usually concede this only when they’re

absolutely pressed) are rarely to be found actually supporting such

unions or organizing for them. Most primitivists instead choose a

“zero-work” attitude and leave labor organizing to others.

Conflation of Economics and Competition

“It seems evident that industrialization and the factories could not be

gotten rid of instantly, but equally clear that their liquidation must

be pursued with all the vigor behind the rush of break-out. Such

enslavement of people and nature must disappear forever, so that words

like production and economy will have no meaning.”

— John Zerzan, “On the Transition — Postscript to Future Primitive.”

Even hunter-gatherer social groups had economic systems-that is, systems

of production and distribution. They produced tools and weapons, and

distributed the foods they gathered or killed. There is in fact an

implied primitivist type of economy in all primitivist works, whether

they choose to acknowledge this or not. Fredy Perlman, for example,

refers to Marshall Sahlins’ “Stone Age Economics.” Economics will

continue to exist as long as human beings exist.

In the end, the question boils down to what kind of economy we want —

one that’s controlled by those spending their work lives in it, or one

controlled by insatiable parasites (capitalists).

Likewise, the question that we as anarchists are faced with is what kind

of anarchist movement we want — one that looks often — ugly,

authoritarian social reality in the eye, with the aim of transforming it

into something better, something that will result in freer, happier

lives for ourselves and all of our brothers and sisters on planet Earth,

or one that wastes its time fantasizing about a non-existent Golden Age,

and that would result in the deaths of billions if its precepts were

followed.

The choice is ours.

 

[1] Editors Note: In fact, I see little ethical difference between

capitalists who live off the labor of others and welfare-primitivists

such as Watkins/Faun who likewise deliberately live off stolen [by the

government] labor. The money they receive doesn’t fall off trees — it’s

taken from the pay of those who work. I consider both parasites, and

worse, parasites who spit on those whose labor they live off. — CB

[2] Many, probably most, Earth Firsters have abandoned the misanthropic

“deep ecology” views expounded by Earth First! co-founder, “Republican

environmentalist” Dave Foreman, in the 1980s.

[3] Point 9 of the 10-point program recorded at the end of Section 2 of

the Manifesto.