đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș seamus-flaherty-aldous-huxley.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:58:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Aldous Huxley Author: Seamus Flaherty Date: 2021 Language: en Topics: Social Anarchism Source: https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/13569317.2021.1912880?journalCode=cjpi20
This article shows that in the years between 1937 and 1962 Aldous Huxley
adopted a species of anarchism. It demonstrates, first, how in espousing
gradualism and pacifism, in stressing the significance of education and
meditation as agents of social change, in seeking to construct
intentional communities in the here and now, as well as build on
pre-existing examples of âanarchy in actionâ such as consumer and
producer cooperatives, in taking a measured view of the state, not
rejecting the institution on principle, but only its coercive form, and
in making sex central to his vision of utopia as an essential ingredient
of a happy and sustainable life, Huxley anticipated the ânewâ anarchism
of the postwar era. Second, it argues that, in rejecting notions of
ânormalâ subjectivity, in seeing the human subject as fundamentally
irrational, in viewing power as coextensive with society itself, as a
relationship that can only be managed as opposed to abolished, in
repudiating grand theory or metanarratives in favour of
âmicro-politicsâ, and in viewing science as both epistemologically
flawed and potentially oppressive, Huxley anticipated postanarchism.
Despite his reluctance to adopt a label, it is the contention of this
article that Huxley ought to be considered a social anarchist.
In 2010, Saul Newman used the term postanarchism to describe the
political philosophy which emerged from his reformulation of classical
anarchism in the light of poststructuralist theory.1 What Newmanâs
reformulation entailed was, in essence, the revision of classical
anarchism in three key areas. First, Newman repudiated the ambition of
classical anarchism to turn itself into a science. Instead, he argued
that contemporary anarchists ought to âextend the anarchist critique of
political authority to the epistemological authority of science.â2
Second, Newman claimed that the operation of power was poorly understood
in classical anarchism. Citing Michel Foucault, Newman argued that
classical anarchism failed to acknowledge that âpower is everywhere
because it comes from everywhereâ and that power, furthermore, will â in
one form or another â âalways be with usâ.3 Third, then, Newman declared
that postanarchism involved relinquishing classical anarchismâs
âontological foundation in a certain humanist and Enlightenment
conception of the subjectââthe subject, that is, âunderstood in terms of
an innate goodness and rationalityâ.4 According to Newman, after Freud
and psychoanalysis, it is clear that ârevolution must go âall the wayâ
down to the psycheâ.5
There can be no doubt that Newmanâs critique of classical anarchism is
somewhat schematic. The very term âclassical anarchismâ essentializes
what was a rich and pluralistic intellectual tradition; and many
âclassical anarchistsâ simply do not conform to Newmanâs ahistorical
collective portrait.6 A perhaps even more egregious error, however, is
the lacuna in Newmanâs work of discussion of the ânewâ anarchism of the
mid-to-late twentieth century, namely the anarchist political
philosophies advanced by Herbert Read, George Woodcock, Alex Comfort,
Colin Ward, and Paul Goodman, among others. For from the 1940s onwards
these thinkers theorized about some of postanarchismâs chief tenets.
Like Newman, they, too, were preoccupied with questions of power and
psychology, and, between them, they developed sophisticated answers to
previous social anarchismsâ perceived shortcomings in each of these
areas.7 The purpose of this article is not to criticize postanarchism;
nor is it to discuss the ways in which Read, Woodcock, Comfort, Ward,
and Goodman in some ways foreshadowed it, thus bringing into question
the label Newman and others have applied to their own insights.8 Rather,
what this article seeks to achieve is to establish Aldous Huxley as both
a forebear of the ânewâ anarchism and in less pronounced, but not
insignificant, ways as a forerunner of postanarchism too. This article
will show how Huxley not only anticipated the ânewâ anarchism, setting
out a pragmatic anarchist political philosophy in Ends and Means,
Huxleyâs âpractical cookery book of reformâ published in 1937, but how
Huxley also posited ideas about epistemology, power, and ontology that
map loosely onto Newmanâs.9 The article argues that Huxleyâs novel
Island (1962) can be legitimately read as a profound social anarchist
political tract, with affinities to both ânewâ anarchism and
postanarchism. Huxley was ultimately a kind of ânewâ anarchist. But, by
1962, he had encroached, idiosyncratically, on a number of postanarchist
themes. In its analysis of Huxleyâs political thought the article adopts
a morphological approach to political ideologies derived from Michael
Freedenâs work on methodology. It identifies a set of core social
anarchist concepts as well as a set of adjacent concepts, which, in
their shifting relationship to one another, account for the existence of
diversity and change within social anarchist ideology.10 Section 1
charts Huxleyâs political trajectory from the 1920s. Section 2 engages
with conceptual issues and establishes the criterion on which Huxley can
properly be referred to as an anarchist. Sections 3 and 4 reconstruct
Huxleyâs anarchist views as they are set out in Ends and Means, while
sections 5 and 6 perform the same task for Island.
Of the forty-nine books Aldous Huxley (1894â1963) wrote, there are two
in particular for which he is most widely known: The Doors of Perception
(1954), Huxleyâs account of the effects of mescalin, and Brave New
World, Huxleyâs somewhat slippery dystopia of 1932.11 In Brave New
World, Huxley envisioned a future where eugenics has been embraced and
the principle of mass production has been applied to biology; where the
human species has been divided between Alphas and Betas, a multi-layered
aristocracy who have an exclusive monopoly on âhigh grade workâ, and
Gammas, Deltas, and Epsilons, worker castes which are conditioned to
like the work they have got to do; where Neo-Pavlovian conditioning has
likewise abolished the love of books and nature; where the family is a
defunct institution; where promiscuous sex is the norm; where citizens
of the world state are preserved from having emotions with the aid of a
pleasuredrug; where individuality is almost unknown; and where the
polity is governed by Ten World Controllers.12 The world stateâs motto,
we learn in chapter one, is âCommunity, Identity, Stabilityâ, and we are
brought to understand that comfort and happiness can only be realized at
the expense of beauty, democracy, liberty, and truth.13 During the 1920s
and early-1930s, Huxley was not an anarchist. On the contrary, a keen
devotee of the work of the American journalist and Nietzschean opponent
of mass democracy, H. L. Mencken, and the elite theory formulated by the
Italian economist and sociologist, Vilfredo Pareto, Huxleyâs politics
were of an aristocratic authoritarian kind.14 It was not that Huxley did
not sympathize with the working classesâas an undergraduate at Oxford,
Huxley had been a member of the Balliol Fabian Group; in 1919, he urged
a friend to âvote Labour, our only hopeâ; and in 1926, he described his
political views as âFabian and mildly labouriteâ.15 It was merely that
Huxley believed that a more egalitarian kind of society could only be
delivered and maintained by âsome strong and intelligent central
authorityâ.16 Although Huxley confessed that Brave New World started out
as a parody of H. G. Wellsâ anti-utopian utopianism â specifically,
Wellsâ utopia of 1923 Men Like Gods â Huxleyâs relationship with Wells
was ambivalent, and he accepted Wellsâ notion of the Samurai,
describing, in 1934, the formation of a non-hereditary aristocracy as âa
piece of strictly practical politics.â17 Yet, by 1937, Huxleyâs
political views had decisively shifted. The transformation had been
gradual, but from that point on Huxley was â broadly speaking â an
anarchist.18 In the foreword to the 1946 reprint of Brave New World,
Huxley explained that the author of his ambiguous dystopia was an
âamused, Pyrrhonic aestheteâ.19 âTodayâ, he went on, âI feel no wish to
demonstrate that sanity is impossible.â20 In Brave New World, the
character of John is presented with two alternatives: âan insane life in
Utopia,â as Huxley put it, âor the life of a primitive in an Indian
village, a life more human in some respects, but in others hardly less
queer and abnormal.â21 âIf I was to rewrite this book,â wrote the new
Huxley â the post-personal crisis Huxley and confidante of Gerald Heard,
no longer the âamused, Pyrrhonic aestheteâ of 1932 â âI would offer the
Savage a third alternative ... In this community economics would be
decentralist and Henry-Georgian, politics Kropotkinesque and
cooperative.â22 This was not a throwaway remark. For Huxley had, in
fact, been collecting ârelevant informationâ to âfind a satisfactory
technique for giving practical realization to the ideal of philosophic
anarchismâ since 1938, at the latest; and in Island, as we shall see,
Huxley finally executed the ambition.23 Huxleyâs anarchism can be dated
to 1937. While there are indeed differences between the two texts,
Island is best understood as a fictionalized account of his non-fiction
work Ends and Means: more considered in some respects, certainly; but
ultimately the latter text, written in 1937, provides the foundation for
the former. Although he was a pacifist, during the Spanish Civil War â
along with Ethel Mannin and Herbert Read â Huxley praised the
anarchists. But it was surely not Huxleyâs positive comments about the
anarchists in Spain alone that induced Emma Goldman, the anarchist
activist and philosopher, to write Huxley in 1938: âI was delighted to
see that you are so close to the ideas that I have fought for all my
life. It is so rarely that one finds in England men or women dedicated
to a truly libertarian idealâ.24 That Goldman should describe Huxley in
these terms suggests that she was familiar with Ends and Means, and it
is indicative that she, as a pillar of the international anarchist
movement, should approve so effusively of what she read. Yet Huxley did
not self-describe as an anarchist â unlike his friend Bertrand Russell â
which raises the question on what basis can we justifiably attribute the
label anarchist to him?25
Anarchism is a notoriously difficult ideology to identify and explain.26
The diversity among the thinkers to whom the label has been applied
makes it hard to isolate a coherent set of principles which unites them.
To circumvent this problem, some scholars have opted to settle for a
single common denominator, or âanarchist minimumâ, usually identified as
either antagonism towards the state or the rejection of all coercion.27
Others, however, have sought to bypass the issue by arguing simply that
non-socialist anarchism is not, properly speaking, anarchism at all.28
This article is concerned only with social anarchism. Benjamin Franks
identifies social anarchists by âfour key concepts that have remained
consistently core and stable since the nineteenth centuryâ: first,
social anarchists reject the state and state-like bodies, which
distinguishes them from social democrats; second, social anarchists
reject âcapitalism as a coercive set of norms and practicesâ; third,
social anarchists adopt âa fluid conception of the self in which oneâs
identity is inherently linked to socio-historical context and
relationships with others,â which distinguishes them from egoists; and
fourth, social anarchists recognize that âthe means used have to
prefigure anarchist goals,â which separates them from the
consequentialism of orthodox Marxists.29 By this criterion, Huxley, in
his maturity, was an anarchist. First, for example, Huxley proclaimed in
Ends and Means that the âpolitical road to a better society is ...
decentralisation and responsible self-governmentâ.30 If the state is
âthe instrument by which the ruling class preserves its privilegesâ and
enables âparanoiacs to satisfy their lust for power and carry out their
dreams of gloryâ, he concurred with the anarchist ambition to abolish
it.31 Huxley argued, second, that the principle of âself-government for
allâ is âincompatible with capitalism and state Socialismâ where
authoritarian management prevails.32 Third, Huxley believed not only
that âeconomic statusâ was responsible for âdifferences in outlook, in
ways of living, thinking, feeling, and judgingâ, but that the
transcendence of personality itself was desirable.33 Finally, Huxley
argued that the âend cannot justify the meansâ.34 He reproduced the
Dutch anarchist Bart de Ligtâs dictum, âThe more violence, the less
revolutionâ, and recommended instead the construction âhere and nowâ of
âsmall working models of the better societyâ.35 If, however, Huxley was
indeed a social anarchist, he was a social anarchist of a very definite
kind. Huxleyâs anarchism did not look back to the social anarchisms of
Proudhon, Bakunin, Kropotkin, or Tolstoy, but looked forward rather to
the ânewâ anarchism of Read, Woodcock, Comfort, Ward, and Goodman. What,
above all, distinguished the ânewâ anarchism from antecedent social
anarchisms was its pragmatic, or practical, ethos.36 While it shared the
four key concepts of social anarchism, as adumbrated above, the ânewâ
anarchism, as Benjamin J. Pauli has shown, had five key emphases, which
serve to distinguish it as a distinct strand within the larger social
anarchist ideological family. First, ânewâ anarchists endorsed
evolutionary means. They embraced the principle of ânon-violenceâ and
saw revolution not as an event, but as a process. Second, ânewâ
anarchists adopted a âdefensive posture towards society no less than the
stateâ. They explored social hierarchies and relations of domination
beyond a one-dimensional Marxisant model based on the concept of
class.37 Third, ânewâ anarchists stressed the significance of education
as an agent of social change. Fourth, ânewâ anarchists held a more
complex view of the state than their predecessors. They sought to
âstrike a balance between spontaneity and planningâ.38 And fifth, ânewâ
anarchists sought to âreclaim the concept of utopia from figures like
Karl Popperâ who equated âthe term with totalitarianism and
authoritarian social engineering.â39 The ânewâ anarchism altered the
microstructure of the ideology of social anarchism in significant ways.
It readjusted the arrangement not of its core concepts but of its
adjacent ones, eschewing concepts such as class war, revolution, and
vertical relations of domination which often feature prominently in
other social anarchisms. As we shall see, Huxley was an anarchist in
this particular facet of the social anarchist tradition, condemned as
âmilitant liberalismâ by its anarchist detractors and inherently
conservative, as Ward and Goodman acknowledged, in its strategy.40
Huxleyâs version of it, though, was not imitative; rather, in advancing
his social anarchist programme in Ends and Means in 1937, Huxley was the
pioneer. However, much more so than other ânewâ anarchists, Huxley also
anticipated aspects of postanarchism, another distinct hybrid within the
social anarchist ideological tradition.41
In Ends and Means, Huxley nonchalantly claimed that there is, and has
been for nearly thirty centuries, âa very general agreementâ about âthe
goal of human effortâ, namely that the Golden Age to which the prophets,
from Isaiah to Marx, have looked forward will be an age of âliberty,
peace, justice and brotherly loveâ.42 According to Huxley, however,
there was no such consensus about the roads which led to that goal. He
isolated two broad strategies for the realization of utopia. There were
those, first, who thought in terms of âsocial machinery and large-scale
organisationâ, whether that entailed economic reform, military conquest,
or armed revolution.43 While secondly, there were those who believed
that âdesirable social changes can be brought about most effectively by
changing the individuals who compose societyâ, whether that be by means
of education, psychoanalysis, applied behaviourism or religion.44 Huxley
rejected all dualisms, arguing in Island that âWisdom never puts enmity
anywhereâ.45 But Huxley strongly favoured the latter strategy, adopting,
in ânewâ and postanarchist fashion, a view of politics which equated the
personal with the political.46 He established as his ideal individual
the ânonattachedâ person.47 For Huxley, the non-attached person is
neither attached to their bodily sensations and lusts nor to their
cravings for power and possessions; they are neither attached to their
hatred and anger nor to their exclusive loves; they are neither attached
to their fame, wealth, or social position nor to science, art,
speculation or philanthropy. The non-attached person is, in short,
neither attached to the self nor the mere âthings of this worldâ,
finding meaning, instead, in a âscientific-mystical conception of the
worldâ which establishes âcommunion between the soul and the integrating
principle of the universeâ. They are conscious of their own
insignificance and see beauty in their âoneness with ultimate realityâ,
renouncing their apparent separateness from others and the universe at
large.48
Huxley opined that the âpractice of non-attachment entails the practice
of all of the virtuesâ, imposing âupon those who would practice it the
adoption of an intensely positive attitude towards the worldâ.49
However, instead of advancing towards the ideal goal of the just society
of non-attached persons imbued with the virtues of love, compassion, and
understanding, Huxley believed that âmost of the peoples of the worldâ
were, on the contrary, ârapidly moving away from itâ.50 Progress, which
for Huxley meant progress in âcharityâ, or humanitarianism, had ceased.
Europe, in particular, had regressed to a state in which torture and
state-organized atrocity was responded to with equanimity, and truth was
treated with contempt. Huxley anticipated that technological progress
would accelerate charityâs demise, merely providing a âmore efficient
means for going backwardâ.51 He reacted not by seeking to manipulate the
structure of society into such a form where the individual will practice
non-attachment simply because they will be preserved from temptation to
do otherwise; rather, pointing to the behaviour of the British in India
to demonstrate the fragility of a humanitarianism held together by
custom and circumstance alone â culminating, apparently, in the Amritsar
massacre of 1919 â Huxley argued that âthere must be more than a mere
deflection of evilâ, evil must be suppressed at its source, âin the
individual will.â52 To that end, Huxley advocated a form of formal
education âfor freedom and responsibilityâ â as opposed, that is, to the
extant type âfor bullying and subordinationâ â and self-education
through religious meditation.53 Huxley did not reject large-scale
political and economic reform. But he insisted on the importance of
recognizing its limitations. Huxley harboured no illusions about the
capacity of most human beings to attain a state of âenlightenmentâ, a
term he used to connote the realization of the limits of human
potential. But as a way of diminishing evil in the individual will, if
not extinguishing it completely, Huxley stressed the significance of
education. Unlike Read, âa convinced Freudianâ, who then âtransferred
his allegiance to Jungâ, and perhaps the most enthusiastic advocate of
the transformative capacity of education among the ânewâ anarchists,
Huxley was wary of attributing too much explanatory power to the
âconditioning process which takes place in childhoodâ.54 Huxley argued,
however, that it was no fortuitous accident that the decline of
democracy in the inter-war years should coincide âexactly with the rise
to manhood and political power of the second generation of the
compulsorily educated proletariatâ.55 For the âstrict, authoritarian
discipline of state schoolsâ constituted, he claimed, a âtraining for
life in a hierarchical, militarised society, in which people are
abjectly obedient to their superiors and inhuman to their inferiorsâ.56
Huxley therefore proposed an experimental kind of education outside the
reach of the state, where the pedagogical ambition was not passive
obedience, but rather the production of intelligent men and women ready
to pass judgement on traditional notions of duty.57 For Huxley, in an
age of unbridled propaganda, to which the individual in dictatorial
countries was subject from infancy, and to which the individual in
democratic countries was also vulnerable (developing psychological
habits of political and cultural consumption akin to drug addiction), it
was necessary to build up resistance to âsuggestionâ. This could be
achieved in two ways: first, by teaching children âto rely on their own
internal resources and not to depend on incessant stimulation from
withoutâ; and second, by training children âto subject the devices of
the propagandists to critical analysisâ, creating, in effect,
communities of critical theorists, self-aware and eternally vigilant
about potential threats to their liberty.58
Huxley, in other words, mirrored the ânewâ anarchists in viewing the
question of liberty as inseparable from that of education, and, like the
ânewâ anarchists, Huxley sought a holistic kind of education, which
catered not only for the mind but for the body and the emotions too.
Ever seeking examples of âanarchy in actionâ, Huxley drew attention to
the âhopeful attempt to enlarge the scope and humanise the character of
academic educationâ undertaken by A. E. Morgan at Antioch College, where
periods of study were alternated with periods of âlabour in the factory,
the office, the farmâeven the prison and the asylumâ, in an effort to
integrate the cognitive, conative, and the affective.59 The second
method, then, by which Huxley envisioned transforming the human subject,
bringing them to the ideal state of non-attachment, was religious.
Rejecting the claims of science to have a âcomplete picture of realityâ,
by 1937 Huxley was effectively a mysticist.60 An arbitrary abstraction
from reality is not reality itself, he argued, and science, while useful
in its own given sphere, was not competent to âdescribe and explain the
non-measurable, purely qualitative aspects of realityâ, like âaesthetic
and moral valuesâ and âreligious experiences and intuitionsâ.61 Huxley
regarded religion as, in part, a system of education, by means of which,
first, it was possible for individuals to âmake desirable changes in
their own personalities and, at one remove, in societyâ; and, second, to
âheighten consciousness and so establish more adequate relations between
themselves and the universe of which they are parts.â62
Huxleyâs account of the means of social change, as laid out above,
expected a lot from the individual, laying Huxley open to the charge of
having embraced a âmilitantâ, or ânaĂŻveâ, liberalism â or âliberalism
gone wildâ â rather than social anarchism.63 But in Ends and Means
Huxley did not neglect the phenomenon of class, remarking that, while in
theory, under the present dispensation, the workers âmay be the subjects
of a democratic stateâ, âin practice they spend the whole of their
working lives as the subjects of a petty tyrantâ.64 Huxley may not have
seen the working class as a revolutionary agent, but he was not blind to
class oppression. He sought in Ends and Means to find practical ways to
end it. Beyond changing the individual, Huxley elaborated a series of
practical steps in Ends and Means to bring a form of social anarchism
into existence. Stressing the compatibility of collective ownership and
authoritarian management, Huxley reversed in Ends and Means his earlier
enthusiasm for economic planning.65 In its place, Huxley advocated,
first, extending to other industries âthe principle of the limitation of
profit and of supervision by the state in the public interestâ as it
then applied to the Port of London Authority, the London Passenger
Transport Board, the Electricity Board, and the BBC. He called these
âmixed concernsâ, since management retained its autonomy.66 Second, and
more importantly, Huxley prescribed âextending the application of the
popularly approved principlesâ of co-operation.67 Echoing Wardâs later
injunction for anarchists to make use of the forms of organization
ârooted in the experience of everyday lifeâ, which operate âside by side
with, and in spite of, the dominant authoritarian trends of our societyâ
â friendly societies, self-help therapeutic groups, housing
co-operatives, squats and free schools â in building anarchism, rather
than abstractly positing the need for revolution, Huxley argued that
âprinciples already accepted should be taken over and applied to a wider
fieldâ.68 To increase the number of co-operatives which âalready exist
and work very wellâ, he posited, âwould not seem like a revolutionary
actâ.69 But, in âits effects, it would be revolutionary; for it would
result in a profound modification of the existing systemâ.70 Like most
ânewâ anarchists, Huxley objected to the use of violent means for
revolutionary ends on the grounds that violence was immoral and
counter-productive; progress in charity could not be achieved by âmeans
that are essentially uncharitableâ, he wrote.71 Huxley also sought to
account for human conservatism, which is âa factâ, he claimed, âin any
given historical situationâ.72 This ontological position helps to
explain why Huxley refrained from going much further, faster; first,
anarchism had to be made respectable. Thus, taking a range of examples
which included Gandhiâs strategy of non-violent revolution in South
Africa and India, Huxley argued that ânon-violence can prove its value
pragmatically â by workingâ, whereas violence only begets more violence;
while Huxley deployed the same kind of pragmatic analysis in his defence
of industrial democracy, commending it on the basis that it can be seen
to work.73 Drawing on the French trade unionist Hyacinthe Dubreuilâs
book, A Chance for Everybody: A Liberal Basis for the Organization of
Work, Huxley insisted that selfgovernment within factories was
demonstrably efficient. Adopting Dubreuilâs recommendations, Huxley
argued that even the largest industries could be organized âso as to
consist of a series of self-governing, yet co-ordinated groups of, at
the outside, thirty members. Within the industryâ, he explained, âeach
one of such groupsâ could âact as a kind of sub-contractor, undertaking
to perform so much of such and such a kind of work for such and such a
sumâ.74 It would be left to the group itself to determine how its
earnings should be divided, to preserve discipline within its ranks, and
to elect its representatives, or delegates. This kind of industrial
democracy was not only efficient, he averred, it also âeducates those
who belong to it in the practice of co-operation and
mutual-responsibilityâ.75 For Huxley â echoing a typical anarchist
concern â the size of the units of selfgovernment was important.76
Distinguishing between the psychology of the group and the crowd, Huxley
argued that if the units of self-government are smaller than the optimum
size (of around ten to thirty), âthey will fail to develop that
emotional field which gives to group activity its characteristic
qualityâ, namely, the sense of belonging, in an intelligent way, âwhile
the available quantity of pooled information and experience will be
inadequateâ.77 If, meanwhile, they are larger than the optimum size
âthere will be a danger of their relapsing into the crowdâs sub-human
stupidityâ â the flight from self, downwards, into âthe darkness of
sub-human emotionalism and panic animalityâ.78 Huxley deplored the
decline of community and the community sense engendered by capitalism,
technological progress, and centralized professionalism. Modernity,
Huxley argued, had âreduced the number of physical contactsâ between
members of a community and impoverished their âspiritual relationsâ,
making âmanifestations of local charity and mutual aidâ increasingly
rare.79 The direct, industrial democracy he envisioned would compensate
for that lack. What was also important for Huxley was that this kind of
industrial self-government solved the problem of human heterogeneity in
its application to democracy. For while Huxley believed that âpractice
in self-governmentâ was an âindispensable element in the curriculum of
manâs moral and psychological educationâ, he did not accept that people
were equally endowed with the capacity to sustain an interest in
âlong-range, large-scale political issuesâ.80 Following the work of the
American psychologist, William Sheldon, Huxley isolated a number of
human types â somatotonic, viscerotonic, and cerebrotonic â separated by
temperament and âdifferences of intellectual abilityâ.81 Huxley opined
that it is the responsibility of the large-scale social reformer to
arrange the structure of society in such a way that bridges are built
between âincommensurable psychological universesâ.82 Industrial
democracy is therefore not only a good in itself, on this reading; it
also furnishes people with âshort-range, small-scale interestsâ with the
opportunity to âfind scope for their kind of political abilitiesâ.83 In
Ends and Means, Huxleyâs main quibble with anarchism was semantic. To be
sure, Huxley did not seek to dispense with organization: he was not
anti-state, as such; the state still had useful functions to perform.
For example, while Huxley sought to decentralize â neutralizing
bureaucracy and making relations between people as direct as they
possibly could be â in any complex society, he argued, âthere must be
some organisation responsible for co-ordinating the activities of the
various constituent groupsâ.84 There must also âbe a bodyâ, he
continued, âwhich is delegated the power of acting in the name of the
society as a wholeâ.85 For Huxley, however, like the ânewâ anarchists,
the state in this form was not oppressive, hence his willingness to find
some name other than âstateâ for it.86 This was administrative
representation rather than political representation. It involved a mere
delegation of power instead of a fundamental transfer of power. It is
therefore consistent with social anarchism. Yet Huxleyâs other political
proposal did involve representation, which most anarchists view as
inherently oppressive. Motivated by the desire to ensure that a ruling
oligarchy did not gain control of the necessary social machinery during
the initial stages of a new regime of decentralization and
self-government, Huxley argued that administrative obstacles ought to be
put in the way of the âindividual of consuming ambitionâ.87 Just as
Rousseau complained how philosophers had âtransported into the state of
nature concepts formed in societyâ, namely need, greed, oppression,
desire and pride, Huxley explained the prevalence of ambitious
individuals by the value contemporary society assigned to individual
ambition, and, with the right kind of education, he expected to see
their numbers diminish.88 Yet, in the meantime, Huxley advocated forming
institutes of chartered business managers, chartered politicians, and
chartered administrators akin to the institution of Chartered
Accountants, with its self-government, rules and responsibilities, as a
way to exclude ambitious individuals from positions of leadership. Thus,
having seemingly discarded it, in Ends and Means Huxley let the Samurai
in through the back door. Evidence of Huxleyâs residual elitism is also
apparent elsewhere. Clearly Huxley did not share the a priori trust in
the individual, characteristic of some strands of social anarchism.89 On
the contrary, he remained a sceptic. Through ignorance, fear, kinship,
or mere habit or inertia, âmost men and womenâ, Huxley wrote, âare
prepared to tolerate the intolerableâ.90 He saw human nature as plastic,
capable of being âmade to assume the most bewilderingly diverseâ and
âamazingly improbable formsâ.91 Cooperation, accordingly, neither ran
with or against its grain. But, in the first instance, true âanarchy in
actionâ would be enacted by enlightened elites. If the âmaterialâ with
which anarchists must deal is ârecalcitrantâ, then prior to the changes
in personality wrought by education and politico-economic restructuring
social anarchism must be pioneered by the comparatively small number of
individuals who accept it in theory in advance. Huxley identified
associations of like-minded individuals organized as intentional
communities in which direct democracy is practised and property is held
in common as a decisive agent of social change. By âbehaving
differentlyâ, by establishing new relationships between human beings and
making a success of it, such intentional communities would not only
modify the existing social and economic order for the better, they had
the further merit of having propagandistic value.92 âThe fact that a
theory has actually worked is a better recommendation for its
soundnessâ, Huxley wrote, âthan any amount of ingenious dialecticsâ.93
Yet that did not prevent Huxley from engaging in dialectical ingenuity
in Island, his literary utopia of 1962, in which he outlined his
conception of a feasible social anarchist society.
The first thing to say about Huxleyâs Island is that Pala, the utopian
island community Huxley imagined, should not be interpreted as Huxleyâs
unblemished ideal society. Pala, rather, is intentionally flawed, hence
the epigraph Huxley borrowed from Aristotle: âIn framing an ideal we may
assume what we wish, but should avoid impossibilitiesâ.94 Pala has a
history. It is convoluted and contingent, and artefacts from its past
remain. Contrary to Huxleyâs actual political ambitions, Pala is
therefore a constitutional monarchy. The second thing one ought to note
about Island is that it is ultimately a melancholic, or pessimistic,
work.95 âPala was completely viableâ, Huxley has the insightful but
Machiavellian character Mr Bahu explain, âuntil about 1905â.96 By 1962,
however, it seemed to Huxley that no ideal society could resist the
inevitable cultural, economic, and military incursions of an
increasingly globalized, and increasingly psychologically unhinged,
external world. If a social anarchist society was still practically
conceivable in the 1930s or even in the immediate postwar years, for
Huxley, in 1962, it was now conceivable only on an abstract plane.
Island thus concludes with a coup dâĂ©tat, that is, with the overthrow of
Palaâs experiment in social anarchism. Over the years Huxley became
âless and less âliteraryâ: he repudiated âart-for-artâs sakeâ, sought
forms that âwere primarily vehicles for ideasâ, and, by 1952, thought of
himself as âan essayist who sometimes writes novelsâ.97 The ideas
advanced in Island had been in gestation for thirty years. In Nicholas
Murrayâs words, they were âthe Summa of all his beliefs about the world,
about human potential, about the meaning and purpose of lifeâ.98 Huxley
was right to regard Island as âa serious contribution to social
thoughtâ.99 Huxleyâs utopia dramatized the social anarchist principles
he first established in Ends and Means, it embodied new ânewâ anarchist
themes, and it offered considered views on a number of postanarchist
topics. Beginning with the economic and political arrangements in
Huxleyâs utopia, Pala is a society of co-operators. They are neither
capitalists nor state socialists. There is, however, private property.
It is not a community of goods. Pala has a monetary economy, and
inequality, up to a point, is permitted; it is possible for anyone to
become âfour or five times as rich as the averageâ.100 What Pala has
abolished is âcut throatâ competition.101 In its place, it has
substituted âcooperative techniques for buying and selling and
profit-sharing and financingâ.102 Its borrowing and lending system is
modelled on the credit unions established by Wilhelm Raiffeisen in
Germany in the nineteenth century. Efforts are pooled, friendly
agreements established, and bureaucracy is kept to a bare minimum.
Seeking to adapt their economy and technology to human beings, rather
than viceversa, Pala has only industrialized in spots. The Palanese
reject the consumerism of the outside world. They find meaning, instead,
in nature, personal relationships, and exercise of the body. They rotate
their jobs, sampling âall kinds of workâ, and set no store by the
principle of maximum efficiency.103 The equation they use to represent
their social arrangements and aspirations is as follows: âElectricity
minus heavy industry plus birth control equals democracy and plentyâ.104
True to Huxleyâs conception of the good society as set out in Ends and
Means, Pala is âa federation of self-governing units, geographical
units, professional units, economic units â so,â Huxley has the
character Dr Robert explain in the novel, âthereâs plenty of scope for
small-scale initiative and democratic leaders, but no place for any kind
of dictator at the head of a centralized governmentâ.105 There is no
army since the Palanese are pacifists. Palanese society is composed of
âvoluntary associationsâ.106 Here, Huxleyâs chief innovation was the
concept of the âMutual Adoption Clubâ, or MAC.107 In Island, Huxley
disbanded the nuclear family, favouring instead âan inclusive,
unpredestined and voluntary familyâ model.108 The MAC is composed of
twenty âpairs of fathers and mothers, eight or nine ex-fathers and
ex-mothers, and forty or fifty assorted children of all agesâ.109 This
formed a direct, face-to-face community and the basic building block of
Palanese society. Just as the ânewâ anarchists envisioned âa mass of
societies rather than a mass societyâ, Huxley has his imagined Palanese
sociologists speak of a âhybridisation of micro-culturesâ produced by
the system of autonomous MACs.110 Yet Pala still has a Cabinet, a House
of Representatives, and a Privy Council. âThe state has to exist, of
courseâ, we learn from Palaâs Under-Secretary of Education.111 Pala is
not therefore without its judges and policeman. However, since so few
crimes are committed they are few in number, and crime is primarily
dealt with not through the state but through the criminalâs MAC. The
judge decides whether the accused person is innocent or guilty.
Thereafter, group therapy, rather than punishment, is provided within
the MAC, which assumes âgroup responsibility for the delinquentâ.112 The
reason why so few crimes are committed in Pala is because the Palanese
are a remarkably well-adjusted people. They are alert to the smallest of
details about what is required to make a psychologically healthy human
being and how to keep them that way, attending to items such as what
they eat, how they make love, what they see and hear, and how they feel
about being who they are. As children they are treated as individuals
with unique needs and experiences, and methods have been devised to
bring Palanese boys and girls of widely differing and conflictual
temperaments to âunderstand and tolerate one anotherâ.113 The Palanese
practise meditation, which they supplement with the use of a
hallucinogenic drug which serves to liberate them from âbondage to the
egoâ.114 The ordinary response to the so-called âmoksha-medicineâ is
âfull-blown mystical experienceâ, a sense of the merging of the
individual with the whole, âlimitless compassion, fathomless mystery and
meaningâ, not to mention âinexpressible joyâ.115 Palanese culture is, in
short, built on the principles of friendliness, trust, and compassion,
decency, reason, and liberty, and, for the most part, Palanese people
behave accordingly. The Palanese are keen to stress that âPala isnât
Eden or the Land of Cockayneâ.116 But the Palanese are a happy,
freedom-loving people, richly endowed with insight about the human
condition. They are therefore tolerant and largely conflict-free, thus
the state as an instrument of physical coercion is almost entirely
inoperative. It is, for the most part, a state only in name.
In the same way that Ward stressed that people consent to be ruled not
only because of fear but also because, more often than not, people
âsubscribe to the same values of their governorsâ, Huxleyâs utopians
choose âto behave in a sensible and realistic wayâ.117 They are aided in
this not only by their ethical principles, politico-economic
arrangements, and by the Buddhist religion they cleave to, but also by
the sexual mores they have adopted. Huxley, like Orwell, recognized the
political utility of sex, and while the Palanese are not the promiscuous
citizens of Huxleyâs earlier dystopia, where âeveryone belongs to
everyone elseâ, their Buddhism âis shot through and through with
Tantraâ.118 In Island Huxley takes up Freudâs notion that, instead of a
sexuality concentrated on the genitals, the sexuality of children is
âdiffused throughout the whole organismâ.119 It is a sexuality which,
for cultural reasons, was ceded as children grew up. The Palanese
commitment to Tantric sex is âthe organised attempt to regain that
paradiseâ lost.120 Huxley has his utopians observe the age-old
injunction to make love not war. Huxley appreciated how sexual pleasure
and psychological well-being coincide and dramatized this phenomenon in
the novel. The satisfying and meaningful sex enjoyed by the Palanese
also serves to negate their appetite for possessions. Thus, ten years
prior to the publication of Comfortâs implicitly anarchist handbook on
sexual conduct, The Joy of Sex (1972), Huxley acknowledged âthe central
importance of unanxious, responsible and happy sexuality in the lives of
normal peopleâ.121 Where Huxley dissented from Comfort was in his
repudiation of the notion of ânormalâ subjectivity. For Huxley,
âeverybodyâs different from everybody elseâ.122 Essentialist categories
in psychology, Huxley has the character Dr MacPhail report, are
âhopelessly inadequateâ.123 Neither Freudism, Behaviourism, or any other
system of psychology, could account for âthe roulette wheel of
heredityâ, with its production of different constitutions, anatomies,
biochemistries, and temperamentsâ. Human beings, Dr MacPhail avers, âare
much less reliable as laboratory animals than dogsâ.124 Like Newman and
other postanarchists, Huxley thought of subjectivity as an
âindeterminite field of possibilities, potentialities and often
conflicting desires and drivesâ.125 The view that Huxley attributes to
Western psychiatrists, that, âa normal human being is one who can have
an orgasm and is adjusted to his societyâ, is treated with derision by
the Palanese.126 âItâs unimaginable!â, the nurse attending to the
central protagonist, Will Farnaby, announces. âNo question about what
you do with your orgasms. No question about the quality of your feelings
and thoughts and perceptions. And then what about the society youâre
supposed to be adjusted to?â127 âIn the country of the insaneâ, Huxley
has Mr Bahu observe âthe integrated man doesnât become kingâ. On the
contrary, âhe gets lynchedâ.128 Huxley was a humanist in the sense that
he believed in reason, virtue, and human agency.129 But, at the same
time, he considered the individuals who peopled the dysfunctional
societies â both Affluent and economically depressed â that he had known
in his life and reading as âless than humanâ.130 Huxley anticipated the
postanarchists in arguing that âWe cannot reason ourselves out of our
basic irrationality. All we can do is to learn the art of being
irrational in a reasonable wayâ.131 Even for the Palanese âto become
fully humanâ is only an ambition.132 Huxley, then, formulated ideas
which would not be out of place among the postmodern advocates of
anti-psychiatry. He also mirrored Foucault and Foucaultâs postanarchist
admirers in his consideration of âthe problems of powerâ.133 Huxley
believed, like Newman, that domination can be most effectively countered
âby engaging with, rather than denying, powerâ.134 He, too, observed
that the operation of power is âfar more complex and differentiatedâ
than anarchists have typically allowed for.135 In Island, Huxley uses Dr
Robert as a vehicle to argue that while Lord Acton âwas altogether
admirableâ as a political theorist, as âa practical psychologist he was
altogether absentâ.136 Huxley has Dr Robert claim, in assent with Acton
that it is obvious that due to its propensity to corrupt, power âhas to
be curbed on the legal and political levelsâ.137 But âitâs also
obviousâ, he goes on, âthat there must be prevention on the individual
level. On the level of instinct and emotion, the muscles and the
bloodâ.138 For Huxley, the problems of power confront us on every level
of organization, âfrom national governments to nurseries and
honeymooning couplesâ.139 That is to say, power takes both vertical and
horizontal forms; it is coextensive with society itself. In addition to
the âGreat Leadersâ, there are âthe millions of small-scale tyrants and
persecutors, all the mute inglorious Hitlers, the village Napoleons, the
Calvins and Torquemadas of the familyâ.140 Like Newman, Huxley argued
that power cannot be abolished. Power, and the ambition to acquire it,
is, on the contrary, perennial. Yet, while there is no âfinal liberation
from powerâ, Huxley concurred with Newman, what is possible is âan
ongoing modificationâ of power relations.141 The Palanese have thus not
only adopted the principle of non-attachment as a mode of ethical
living, they also seek to harness the power generated by the
power-hungry, setting it âto work in some useful wayâ, or else
preventing it from doing harm to others.142 They are âonly half
convincedâ by psychoanalytic approaches to questions of power that
explain it as a âmatter of mother and toilet-training, of early
conditioning and traumatic environmentsâ.143 According to Huxley, there
was also innate predisposition, or biochemistry, to consider. The
Palanese identify two species of power-loving individual: Peter Pans and
Muscle People. Peter Pans are children, primarily boys, who grow up too
late. Envious and hateful, they are incapable of either competing or
cooperating. âThe most recent, as well as the best and biggestâ, Dr
Robert explains, âwas Adolf Hitlerâ.144 Muscle Men, by contrast, are
predestined by shape to extraversion, always feeling impelled âto Do
Somethingâ, and ânever inhibited by doubts or qualms, by sympathy or
sensibilityâ.145 The âsupreme example of the delinquent Muscle Manâ,
Huxley has Dr Robert note, is Stalin.146 In Pala, Peter Pans are ânever
given a chance to work up an appetite for powerâ.147 Reaching for a
remarkably illiberal solution for Peter Panic delinquency, which does
not easily square with his other liberal, anti-essentialist and
anti-determinist, pronouncements about the human subject, Huxley has his
utopians test for the condition between the ages of four-and -a-half and
five. Those who test positive are treated biomedically. Muscle Men, on
the other hand, are âcuredâ in less starkly sinister ways. First, Palaâs
social and political arrangements offer them few opportunities for
bullying their families or domineering on a larger scale. Second, Muscle
Men are trained to be âaware and sensitiveâ.148 They are taught to
âenjoy the commonplaces of everyday existenceâ.149 And third, the
Palanese âcanaliseâ their love of power, as Huxley put it, deflecting it
âaway from people and on to thingsâ.150 Muscle Men are âgiven all kinds
of difficult tasks to performâstrenuous and violent tasks that exercise
their muscles and satisfy their craving for dominationâ.151 By embracing
essentialism and determinism in constructing categories of power-loving
individual and, in the case of Peter Pans in particular, positing a
coercive solution to the problem, Huxley may have erred in his
anticipation of postanarchism. However, that anticipation revealed
itself again in his strident rejection of grand theory, or
metanarratives.
In Ends and Means, Huxley poured scorn on the notion of the
âhistoricalâ, or âhistorical necessityâ, deployed by grand theorists
such as Hegel and exploited by every modern tyranny, âFascist, Nazi, and
Communist alikeâ.152 He argued that âto work for it is to co-operate
with the powers of darkness against the lightâ.153 âThe real is not the
rationalâ, Huxley averred, and âhistoricalnessâ is not a valueâ.154 Just
as postanarchists are âsuspicious of ideals that function to coerce
individuals into subordinating themselves to a larger causeâ, Huxley
denounced the âhistoricalâ as liberty-denying, as almost, in fact,
âunmitigatedly evilâ.155 Huxley exhibited the same kind of resistance to
abstraction found among postanarchists. He was a nominalist, who
deplored âthe invincible tendency to reduce the diverse to the
identicalâ.156 Like postanarchists, Huxley, accordingly, did not seek to
make a science of his anarchism.157 Rather, Huxley was a moralist and
the social anarchism he envisioned was contingent; it could only be
accomplished by rational â or âreasonably irrationalâ â human agents.
Thus, instead of a historically determined product of a clash between
forces and relations of production and the class struggle to which that
clash gives rise, the social anarchist society created in Pala is the
result of chance and intelligent human activity â the gradual
implementation of a pragmatic social policy devised by one highly
intelligent and adventurous, non-conforming Scottish surgeon, Dr Andrew,
and a Palanese monarch of intellect and refinement, âa man not only of
deep religious convictions ... but also of deep religious experience and
spiritual insightâ.158 Needless to say, this form of transition to a
social anarchist society was not a model that Huxley expected others to
follow. Rather, it was a unique thought-experiment, appropriate to
Islandâs literary form. Huxley was a proponent of âmicro-politicsâ, a
type of political thinking centred on the specific.159 He may have
reserved a special place for the role of the individual in history, but
only local circumstances and local knowledge could determine its
particular efficacy and dictate an appropriate course of action. Huxley
was not entirely averse to the âsociologistâs eye-viewâ of the world,
the view, namely, of the pattern-discerner and conceptmaker. But it
must, he insisted, be complemented by training in receptivity, that is,
it must be combined with the epistemological habits of âthe alertly
passive insight-receiverâ.160 Science, Huxley averred, is handicapped by
the tradition-bound concepts and classificatory schemes adopted by its
practitioners.161 In conformity with postanarchists, he was sensitive to
âscienceâs power effectsâ.162 Science was never politically neutral. It
was both suffused with unconscious bias and tied up with power claims.
In anticipation of Newmanâs proposal, Huxley formulated an anarchism
without âdeep foundations in science and rationality; an anarchismâ â
distinct from many earlier iterations â that, as we have seen, âdid not
make universal claims about human nature, natural laws or an unfolding
rationality immanent in social progressâ.163 While Huxley may have been
inconsistent in his anti-essentialism, rejecting the idea of ânormalâ
subjectivity while recycling biomedical essentialist ideas derived from
William Sheldonâs determinist psychological schema, Huxley was still
closer to postanarchism than most other ânewâ anarchists, maintaining a
heightened sensitivity to the omnipresence of power and expressly
rejecting scientism and metanarratives.
Although Huxley did not self-describe as an anarchist, in 1938 he
replied to Emma Goldman that the libertarian ideal she propounded was
âthe only satisfactory and even the only practical political creed for
anyone who is not a conservative reactionaryâ.164 But by 1962, Huxley
was more pessimistic. It seemed to him that the prospects for such a
libertarian ideal were not promising. Yet if Island is essentially a
melancholic utopia, ending with the overthrow of Huxleyâs imagined
society, it is nonetheless a social anarchist work of political
philosophy, with affinities to both ânewâ anarchism and postanarchism.
This article has shown how, between 1937 and 1962, Huxley embraced
pragmatic anarchism. It has demonstrated how in espousing gradualism and
pacifism, in stressing the significance of education and self-care, or
meditation, as agents of social change, in seeking to construct
intentional communities in the here and now, as well as build on
pre-existing examples of âanarchy in actionâ such as consumer and
producer cooperatives, in taking a measured view of the state, not
rejecting the institution on principle, but only its coercive form, and
in making sex central to his vision of utopia as an essential ingredient
of a happy and sustainable life, Huxley anticipated the ânewâ anarchism
of Read, Woodcock, Comfort, Ward, and Goodman. In rejecting notions of
ânormalâ subjectivity, in seeing the human subject as fundamentally
irrational rather than rational, in viewing power as coextensive with
society itself, as a relationship that can only be managed as opposed to
abolished, in repudiating grand theory or metanarratives in favour of
âmicro-politicsâ, and in viewing science as both epistemologically
flawed and potentially oppressive, Huxley anticipated the postanarchism
of Newman and others. It is the contention of this article that, despite
his reluctance to adopt a label, Huxley should be considered a social
anarchist, suspended somewhere between these two sub-ideological
hybrids. If Huxley started out as a ânewâ anarchist in 1937, by 1962 he
had begun to encroach â loosely and idiosyncratically â on postanarchist
themes. This article also demonstrates the malleability of political
ideologies. It has shown how social anarchism is a broad tradition. It
comprises a number of sub-ideological hybrids including ânewâ anarchism
and postanarchism which, while maintaining the ideologyâs conceptual
core have, over time, reordered and reprioritized its adjacent concepts.
It is precisely this, moreover â the process of rearranging an
ideologyâs micro-structure â that, as Freeden explains, âprovides the
basis for im
7. See C. Honeywell, A British Anarchist Tradition: Herbert Read, Alex
Comfort and Colin Ward (New York: Continuum, 2011); C. Honeywell,
âBridging the Gaps: Twentieth-Century AngloâAmerican Anarchist Thoughtâ,
in R. Kinna (Ed.) The Continuum Companion to Anarchism (London:
Continuum, 2012), pp. 111â139; and B. J. Pauli, âThe New Anarchism in
Britain and the US: towards a richer understanding of post-war anarchist
thoughtâ, Journal of Political Ideologies, 20, No. 2 (2015), pp.
133â155. 8. Drawing on distinctly different sources postanarchismâs
originality has been questioned before. See, for example, G. Kuhn,
âAnarchism, Postmodernity, and Poststructuralismâ, in R. Amster, A.
DeLeon, L. A. Fernandez, A. J. Nocella, II., and D. Shannon (Eds)
Contemporary Anarchist Studies: An Introductory Anthology of Anarchy in
the Academy (New York: Routledge, 2009), p. 21. 9. A. Huxley, Ends and
Means: An Enquiry into the Nature of Ideals and into the Methods
employed for their Realization (London: Chatto & Windus, 1937), p. 8.
10. See M. Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual
Approach (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), above all, pp. 13â136; and for
a prĂ©cis, M. Freeden, âThe Morphological Analysis of Ideologyâ, in M.
Freeden, L. Tower Sargent, and M. Stears (Eds) The Oxford Handbook of
Political Ideologies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp.
115â137. 11. See N. Murray, Aldous Huxley: An English Intellectual
(London: Little, Brown, 2002), p. 401. For analysis of Brave New World
see R. S. Baker, Brave New World: History, Science, Dystopia (Boston:
Twayne, 1990); G. Claeys, Dystopia: A Natural History (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2016), Ch. 6; P. Edgerly Firchow, The End of Utopia: A
Study of Aldous Huxleyâs Brave New World (Cranbury, NJ: Associated
University Press, 1984); D. G. Izzo and K. Kirkpatrick (Eds), Huxleyâs
Brave New World: Essays (Jefferson, North Carolina: McFarland and
Company, 2008); and Jonathan Greenberg and Nathan Waddell (Eds), Brave
New World: Contexts and Legacies (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan,
2016). 12. Huxley, Brave New World (London: Penguin, 1974), p. 175. 13.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 15. 14. See D. Bradshaw, âIntroductionâ and
âChroniclers of Folly: Huxley and H. L. Menckenâ, in D. Bradshaw (Ed.)
The Hidden Huxley: Contempt and Compassion for the Masses 1920â36
(London: Faber and Faber, 1994), pp. viiâ30. 15. Bradshaw, ibid, pp.
viiiâix; Murray, Huxley, op. cit., Ref. 11, pp. 110, 181. 16. A. Huxley,
âThe Victory of Art over Humanityâ, in Bradshaw (Ed.), op. cit., Ref.
14, p. 83. 17. Quoted in D. Bradshaw, âOpen Conspirators: Huxley and H.
G. Wellsâ, in Bradshaw (Ed.), op. cit., Ref. 14, p. 41. 18. Huxley is
not widely regarded as such. But David Goodway, from whom this article
borrows, did see Huxley as an anarchist, in particular, as a
âforerunnerâ of the ânew anarchismâ, as I have also posited here.
Anarchist Seeds Beneath the Snow: Left Libertarian Thought and British
Writers from William Morris to Colin Ward (Liverpool: Liverpool
University Press, 2006), p. 232. George Woodcock, too, regarded Huxley
as an anarchist. Dawn and the Darkest Hour: A Study of Aldous Huxley
(London: Faber and Faber, 1972), pp. 211â212; and G. Woodcock (Ed.), The
Anarchist Reader (Glasgow: Fontana, 1977), p. 52; and Murray claimed,
somewhat less precisely, that Huxleyâs âlater vision was a world
organised around the principles of classical anarchismâ, Huxley, p. 258.
By contrast, Alessandro Maurini fails to make this connection in his
monograph, Aldous Huxley: The Political Thought of a Man of Letters
(Lanham, Md: Lexington Books, 2017). That said, Mauriniâs study, which
claims Huxleyâs mature political thought is best understood as âa
pacifist and ecological communitarianismâ, is instructive. Maurini,
ibid., p. ix, as is Ronald Lee Ziglerâs, The Educational Prophecies of
Aldous Huxley: The Visionary Legacy of Brave New World, Ape and Essence,
and Island (New York: Routledge, 2015). 19. Huxley, Brave New World, op.
cit., Ref. 12, p. 8. 20. Huxley, Ibid. 21. Huxley, Ibid., p. 7. 22.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 8. 23. Quoted in Goodway, Anarchist Seeds, op. cit.,
Ref. 18, p. 229. 24. Quoted in Goodway, Ibid.aginative inventiveness in
political thinkingâ.165 And Huxley was nothing if not imaginatively
inventive.
Notes 1. S. Newman, The Politics of Postanarchism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2010). For a helpful survey of postanarchism see B.
Franks, âPostanarchism: a critical assessmentâ, Journal of Political
Ideologies, 12, No. 2 (2007), pp. 127â145. 2. S. Newman, âPostanarchism:
a politics of antiâpoliticsâ, Journal of Political Ideologies, 16, No. 3
(2011), p. 318. 3. Newman, Ibid., pp. 320, 321. 4. Newman, Ibid., p.
321. 5. Newman, Ibid., p. 322. Classical anarchism, for instance, did
not account for the phenomenon of voluntary servitude, Newman objected.
6. This is of course somewhat ironic, given postanarchismâs
postmodernist and poststructuralist origins. For historicist criticism
of postanarchism see M. S. Adams and N. J. Jun, âPolitical theory and
history: the case of anarchismâ, Journal of Political Ideologies, 20,
no. 3 (2015), pp. 244â262. It should, however, be added here that in
Newmanâs most recent book he no longer uses the term classical
anarchism. Postanarchism (Cambridge: Polity, 2016). I use it here only
for the purpose of exposition of Newmanâs original theory. âTraditionalâ
is also often used synonymously. That, too, is rejected here as lacking
analytic and historical precision.
25. Russell did not consistently selfâdescribe as such, but he was known
to use the hybrid, âaristocratic anarchismâ. Goodway, ibid., p. 31. For
Russellâs âanarchist tendenciesâ see P. Ironside, The Social and
Political Thought of Bertrand Russell: The Development of an
Aristocratic Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996),
Ch. 6. 26. B. Franks, âAnarchismâ, in Freeden, Tower Sargent, and Stears
(Eds) Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies, op. cit., Ref. 10, p.
385. 27. See B. Franks, âIdeological hybrids: the contrary case of Tory
anarchismâ, Journal of Political Ideologies, 21, no. 2 (2016), p. 162.
28. Franks, Ibid., p. 163. Others still have argued that, âanarchism is
not really an ideology, but rather a point of intersection of several
ideologiesâ, or, put slightly differently, that the âthinnessâ of its
core âbegs the question whether the allegiance of the two modesâ â
individualist and socialistââis not primarily to libertarianism and to
the socialist family respectively.â D. Miller, Anarchism (London: J. M.
Dent, 1984), p. 3; Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory, op. cit.,
Ref. 10., p. 312. 29. Franks, âAnarchismâ, in Freeden, Sargent, and
Steers (Eds), op. cit., Ref. 26, p. 390. 30. Huxley, Ends and Means, op.
cit., Ref. 9, p. 63. 31. Huxley, Ibid., p. 70. 32. Huxley, Ibid., p. 85.
33. A. Huxley, âAbroad in Englandâ, in Bradshaw (Ed.), op. cit., Ref.
14, p. 51; Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, pp. 255, 326â327.
34. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 8. 35. Huxley, Ibid.,
pp. 25, 128. 36. See R. Kinnaâs analysis in Anarchism: A Beginnerâs
Guide (Oxford: Oneworld, 2005), pp. 142â147. Kinna uses the epithet
âpractical anarchistsâ. 37. Pauli, âNew Anarchismâ, op. cit., Ref. 7, p.
140. 38. Pauli, Ibid., p. 146. 39. Pauli, Ibid., p. 145. 40. Pauli,
Ibid., p. 138. Postanarchism, it is worth remarking here, has also been
censured as ânaĂŻve liberalismâ for its rejection of economic
reductivism, attention to the individual, and consequent downgrading of
class. Franks, âPostanarchismâ, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 136. 41. What,
above all, distinguishes postanarchism from ânewâ anarchism is
postanarchismâs explicit rejection of scientism and meta-narratives and
its sustained preoccupation with horizontal relations of power.
Postanarchism is also internally diverse. See T. May, The Political
Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism (Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania
University Press, 1994); D. Rouselle, and S. Evren (Eds), Postanarchism:
A Reader (London: Pluto Books, 2011); and L. Call, Postmodern Anarchism
(Lanham: Lexington Books, 2002). 42. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit.,
Ref. 9, p. 1. 43. Huxley, Ibid. 44. Huxley, Ibid. 45. A. Huxley, Island
(London: Vintage, 2005), p. 193. 46. Murray, Huxley, op. cit., Ref. 11,
p. 305. 47. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 3. 48. Huxley,
Ibid., pp. 4, 286, 300. 49. Huxley, Ibid., p. 4. 50. Huxley, Ibid., p.
6. 51. Huxley, Ibid., p. 8. Ends and Means âdisplays an astonishing
awareness ... of what was really happening in the Germany and Russia of
that timeâ, wrote R. B. Schmerl. âAldous Huxleyâs social criticismâ,
Chicago Review, 13, no. 1 (1959), p. 46. Living in Italy in the 1920s,
Huxley experienced the rise of fascism first-hand. For Huxleyâs
knowledge of the Bolshevik regime see Claeys, Dystopia, op. cit., Ref.
11, p. 371. 52. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 24. 53.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 185. 54. Goodway, Anarchist Seeds, op. cit., Ref. 18,
p. 197. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 177. For the
broader literature on Read see, M. Adams, Kropotkin, Read, and the
Intellectual History of British Anarchism: Between Reason and
Romanticism (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2015); J. King, The Last Modern: A
Life of Herbert Read (New York: St. Martinâs Press, 1990); D. Goodway
(Ed.), Herbert Read Reassessed (Liverpool: Liverpool University Press,
1998); M. Paraskos, Rereading Read: New Views on Herbert Read (London:
Freedom Press, 2008); and G. Woodcock, Herbert Read: The Stream and the
Source (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 2008). 55. Huxley, Ends and Means,
op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 184. 56. Huxley, Ibid., p. 182. 57. Although Huxley
is not mentioned, the broad topic is covered in J. Suissa, Anarchism and
Education: A Philosophical Perspective (London: PM Press, 2010). 58.
Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, pp. 212, 214. See also, G.
Pritchard, âModelling Power in Anarchist Perspectiveâ, Anarchist
Studies, 28, No. 1 (2020), p. 18. Pritchard describes critical thinking
as the âhighest and most important form of power-fromâwithinâ. 59.
âAnarchy in actionâ is Colin Wardâs phrase for instances of anarchism
already present in society. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9,
pp. 202, 203. 60. See J. Deery, Aldous Huxley and the Mysticism of
Science (London: Macmillan, 1996); and M. Birnbaum, âAldous Huxleyâs
Quest for Values: A Study in Religious Syncretismâ, in R. E. Kuehn (Ed.)
Aldous Huxley: A Collection of Critical Essays (Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice Hall, 1974), pp. 46â63. 61. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit.,
Ref. 9, pp. 268â269. 62. Huxley, Ibid., p. 225. 63. Todd May, âIs
post-structuralist political theory anarchist?â, Philosophy and Social
Criticism, 15, no. 2 (1989), p. 171. 64. Huxley, Ends and Means, op.
cit., Ref. 9, p. 75. 65. Huxley, âAbroad in Englandâ, in Bradshaw (Ed.),
op. cit., Ref. 14, pp. 62â63. 66. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref.
9, pp. 48â49, 85. 67. Huxley, Ibid., p. 49. 68. Quoted in S. White,
âMaking anarchism respectable? The social philosophy of Colin Wardâ,
Journal of Political Ideologies, 12, No. 1 (2007), p. 15; Huxley, Ends
and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 30. For Ward, see also C. Levy (Ed.),
Colin Ward: Life, Times, and Thought (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2013).
69. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 85. 70. Huxley, Ibid.
71. Huxley, Ibid., p. 25. 72. Huxley, Ibid., p. 30. 73. Huxley, Ibid.,
p. 140. 74. Huxley, Ibid., p. 74. 75. Huxley, Ibid., p. 75. 76.
Honeywell, âBridging the Gapsâ, in Kinna (Ed.), op. cit., Ref. 7, p.
127. 77. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 74. 78. Huxley,
Ibid., p. 72. 79. Huxley, Ibid., p. 78. 80. Huxley, Ibid., p. 76. 81.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 168. 82. Huxley, Ibid. 83. Huxley, Ibid., p. 77. 84.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 70. 85. Huxley, Ibid. 86. Huxley, Ibid. 87. Huxley,
Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 175. 88. J. J. Rousseau, A
Discourse on Inequality (London: Penguin, 1984), p. 78. 89. May, âIs
Poststructuralist Political Theory Anarchist?â, op. cit., Ref. 63, p.
171. 90. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 56. 91. Huxley,
Ibid., p. 20. 92. White, âMaking anarchism respectable?â, op. cit., Ref.
68, p. 12.
93. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 129. 94. Huxley,
Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 6. 95. Claeys, Dystopia, op. cit., Ref.
11. p. 387. 96. Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 58. 97. Huxley,
Ibid., pp. 153, 161. 98. Murray, Huxley, op. cit., Ref. 11, p. 444. 99.
Quoted in Goodway, Anarchist Seeds, op. cit., Ref. 18, p. 235. It is
markedly undervalued as a novel, however. Frank Kermode, for example,
described Island as âone of the worst novels ever writtenâ. Yet,
regardless of its literary credentials, Goodway correctly notes that
âIsland has attracted astonishingly little attentionâ. Quoted in
Goodway, Ibid., pp. 234, 236. 100. Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p.
146. 101. Huxley, Ibid., p. 145. 102. Huxley, Ibid. 103. Huxley, Ibid.,
p. 148. 104. Huxley, Ibid., p. 144. 105. Huxley, Ibid., p. 146. 106.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 171. 107. Huxley, Ibid., p. 90. 108. Huxley, Ibid.
109. Huxley, Ibid. 110. Quoted in May, âIs Poststructuralist Political
Theory Anarchist?â, op. cit., Ref. 63, p. 170; Huxley, Island, op. cit.,
Ref. 45, p. 91. 111. Huxley, ibid., p. 202. 112. Huxley, Ibid., p. 155.
113. Huxley, Ibid., p. 206. 114. Huxley, Ibid., p. 137. 115. Huxley,
Ibid., p. 138. 116. Huxley, Ibid., p. 191. 117. C. Ward, Anarchy in
Action (London: Freedom Press, 1982), p. 15; Huxley, Island, op. cit.,
Ref. 45, p. 82. 118. For Orwell, sexual abstinence and the propensity
for fanaticism are intimately connected, hence in Nineteen Eighty-Four
sex is instrumentalized by the state. Sexual desire is sublimated into
loyalty to the party. G. Orwell, Nineteen EightyâFour (London: Penguin,
1989), pp. 68â71; Huxley, Brave New World, op. cit., Ref. 12, p. 42;
Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 75. 119. Huxley, ibid., p. 77.
120. Huxley, Ibid., p. 77. 121. A. Comfort, The Joy of Sex (London:
Mitchell Beazley, 2002), p. 7. For Comfort see A. E. Salmon, Alex
Comfort (Boston, MA: Twayne, 1978). And for the parallels between Huxley
and Comfort see D. Goodway, âAldous Huxley and Alex Comfort: A
Comparisonâ, in H. G. Klaus and S. Knight (Eds) âTo Hell with Cultureâ:
Anarchism and TwentiethâCentury English Literature (Cardiff: University
of Wales Press, 2005), pp. 111â125. 122. Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref.
45, p. 202. 123. Huxley, Ibid., p. 119. 124. Huxley, Ibid., pp. 119,
117. 125. Newman, âPostanarchismâ, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 321. 126.
Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, pp. 69â70. 127. Huxley, Ibid., p. 70.
128. Huxley, Ibid., p. 68. 129. âHumanismâ, as Thomas Swann correctly
argues, âis an incredibly vague term and commonly subject to imprecise
and improper useâ. The way in which Newman and other postanarchists
define it is as a theory that attributes both rationality to all human
beings as well as teleology; the notion, that is, of âliving up toâ
something essential. In this sense of the term Huxley is not a humanist.
For Huxley, if there is something essential in human nature it is only a
set of animal drives and instincts. To be âhumanâ is simply to learn as
best we can how to manage them. T. Swann, âAre Postanarchists Right to
Call Classical Anarchisms âHumanistâ?â, in B. Franks and M. Wilson (Eds)
Anarchism and Moral Philosophy (London: Palgrave, 2010), pp. 227, 232.
130. Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 98. 131. Huxley, Ibid., p.
171. 132. Huxley, Ibid., p. 141. 133. Huxley, Ibid., p. 149. 134. S.
Newman, âAnarchism and the politics of ressentimentâ, Theory and Event,
4, no. 3 (2000).
. For a discussion of anarchism and power from an analytical philosophy
perspective see M. Taylor, Community, Anarchy and Liberty (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1982). 135. Newman, âPostanarchismâ, op.
cit., Ref. 2, p. 319. 136. Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 155.
137. Huxley, Ibid. 138. Huxley, Ibid. Here, too, Huxley paralleled
Comfort. In 1950, Comfort wrote Authority and Delinquency in the Modern
State: A Study in the Psychology of Power. Goodway referred to it as
Comfortâs âtreatise on Actonâs dictum ... for the conditions of the
midâtwentieth centuryâ. Anarchist Seeds, op. cit., Ref. 18, p. 251. 139.
Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 149. 140. Huxley, Ibid., pp.
149â150. 141. Newman, âPostanarchismâ, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 321. 142.
Huxley, Island, op. cit., Ref. 45, p. 150. 143. Huxley, Ibid. 144.
Huxley, Ibid., p. 151. 145. Huxley, Ibid., p. 152. 146. Huxley, Ibid.,
p. 154. 147. Huxley, Ibid. 148. Huxley, Ibid. 149. Huxley, Ibid. 150.
Huxley, Ibid. 151. Huxley, Ibid. 152. Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit.,
Ref. 9, p. 67. 153. Huxley, Ibid., p. 69. 154. Huxley, Ibid., pp. 29,
69. 155. May, âIs Post-Structuralist Political Theory Anarchist?â, op.
cit., Ref. 63, p. 170; Huxley, Ends and Means, op. cit., Ref. 9, p. 69.
156. Huxley, Ends and Means, ibid., p. 12. 157. This also true of many
ânewâ anarchists, but ânewâ anarchists are typically less sceptical
about the epistemological validity of science. 158. Huxley, Island, op.
cit., Ref. 45, p. 123. 159. May, âIs Poststructuralist Political Theory
Anarchist?â, op. cit., Ref. 63, p. 176. 160. Huxley, Island, op. cit.,
Ref. 45, pp. 218, 219. 161. Huxleyâs views on science are elaborated in
A. Huxley, Science, Liberty and Peace (London: Chatto & Windus, 1950);
and A. Huxley, Literature and Science (New York: Harper & Row, 1963).
162. Newman, âPostanarchismâ, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 318. 163. Newman,
Ibid. 164. Quoted in Goodway, Anarchist Seeds, op. cit., Ref. 18, p.
229. 165. Freeden, âMorphological Analysis of Ideologyâ, op. cit., Ref.
10, p. 117.
Disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by
the author(s).