đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș ken-knabb-the-joy-of-revolution.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:52:52. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Joy of Revolution
Author: Ken Knabb
Date: 1997
Language: en
Topics: situationist, situationist international, Utopia, violence, work
Source: Retrieved on September 18, 2010 from http://www.bopsecrets.org/PS/joyrev.htm
Notes: First published in Public Secrets: Collected Skirmishes of Ken Knabb (1997).

Ken Knabb

The Joy of Revolution

Chapter 1: Some Facts of Life

“We can comprehend this world only by contesting it as a whole... The

root of the prevailing lack of imagination cannot be grasped unless one

is able to imagine what is lacking, that is, what is missing, hidden,

forbidden, and yet possible, in modern life.”

— Situationist International [1]

Utopia or bust

Never in history has there been such a glaring contrast between what

could be and what actually exists.

It’s hardly necessary to go into all the problems in the world today —

most of them are widely known, and to dwell on them usually does little

more than dull us to their reality. But even if we are “stoic enough to

endure the misfortunes of others,” the present social deterioration

ultimately impinges on us all. Those who don’t face direct physical

repression still have to face the mental repressions imposed by an

increasingly mean, stressful, ignorant and ugly world. Those who escape

economic poverty cannot escape the general impoverishment of life.

And even life at this pitiful level cannot continue for long. The

ravaging of the planet by the global development of capitalism has

brought us to the point where humanity may become extinct within a few

decades.

Yet this same development has made it possible to abolish the system of

hierarchy and exploitation that was previously based on material

scarcity and to inaugurate a new, genuinely liberated form of society.

Plunging from one disaster to another on its way to mass insanity and

ecological apocalypse, this system has developed a momentum that is out

of control, even by its supposed masters. As we approach a world in

which we won’t be able to leave our fortified ghettoes without armed

guards, or even go outdoors without applying sunscreen lest we get skin

cancer, it’s hard to take seriously those who advise us to beg for a few

reforms.

What is needed, I believe, is a worldwide participatory-democracy

revolution that would abolish both capitalism and the state. This is

admittedly a big order, but I’m afraid that nothing less can get to the

root of our problems. It may seem absurd to talk about revolution; but

all the alternatives assume the continuation of the present system,

which is even more absurd.

Stalinist “communism” and reformist “socialism” are merely variants

of capitalism

Before going into what this revolution would involve and responding to

some typical objections, it should be stressed that it has nothing to do

with the repugnant stereotypes that are usually evoked by the word

(terrorism, revenge, political coups, manipulative leaders preaching

self-sacrifice, zombie followers chanting politically correct slogans).

In particular, it should not be confused with the two principal failures

of modern social change, Stalinist “communism” and reformist

“socialism.”

After decades in power, first in Russia and later in many other

countries, it has become obvious that Stalinism is the total opposite of

a liberated society. The origin of this grotesque phenomenon is less

obvious. Trotskyists and others have tried to distinguish Stalinism from

the earlier Bolshevism of Lenin and Trotsky. There are differences, but

they are more of degree than of kind. Lenin’s The State and Revolution,

for example, presents a more coherent critique of the state than can be

found in most anarchist writings; the problem is that the radical

aspects of Lenin’s thought merely ended up camouflaging the Bolsheviks’

actual authoritarian practice. Placing itself above the masses it

claimed to represent, and with a corresponding internal hierarchy

between party militants and their leaders, the Bolshevik Party was

already well on its way toward creating the conditions for the

development of Stalinism while Lenin and Trotsky were still firmly in

control.[2]

But we have to be clear about what failed if we are ever going to do any

better. If socialism means people’s full participation in the social

decisions that affect their own lives, it has existed neither in the

Stalinist regimes of the East nor in the welfare states of the West. The

recent collapse of Stalinism is neither a vindication of capitalism nor

proof of the failure of “Marxist communism.” Anyone who has ever

bothered to read Marx (most of his glib critics obviously have not) is

aware that Leninism represents a severe distortion of Marx’s thought and

that Stalinism is a total parody of it. Nor does government ownership

have anything to do with communism in its authentic sense of common,

communal ownership; it is merely a different type of capitalism in which

state-bureaucratic ownership replaces (or merges with) private-corporate

ownership.

The long spectacle of opposition between these two varieties of

capitalism hid their mutual reinforcement. Serious conflicts were

confined to proxy battles in the Third World (Vietnam, Angola,

Afghanistan, etc.). Neither side ever made any real attempt to overthrow

the enemy in its own heartland. (The French Communist Party sabotaged

the May 1968 revolt; the Western powers, which intervened massively in

countries where they were not wanted, refused to send so much as the few

antitank weapons desperately needed by the 1956 Hungarian insurgents.)

Guy Debord noted in 1967 that Stalinist state-capitalism had already

revealed itself as merely a “poor cousin” of classical Western

capitalism, and that its decline was beginning to deprive Western rulers

of the pseudo-opposition that reinforced them by seeming to represent

the sole alternative to their system. “The bourgeoisie is in the process

of losing the adversary that objectively supported it by providing an

illusory unification of all opposition to the existing order” (The

Society of the Spectacle, §§110–111).

Although Western leaders pretended to welcome the recent Stalinist

collapse as a natural victory for their own system, none of them had

seen it coming and they now obviously have no idea what to do about all

the problems it poses except to cash in on the situation before it

totally falls apart. The monopolistic multinational corporations that

proclaim “free enterprise” as a panacea are quite aware that free-market

capitalism would long ago have exploded from its own contradictions had

it not been saved despite itself by a few New Deal-style pseudosocialist

reforms.

Those reforms (public services, social insurance, the eight-hour day,

etc.) may have ameliorated some of the more glaring defects of the

system, but in no way have they led beyond it. In recent years they have

not even kept up with its accelerating crises. The most significant

improvements were in any case won only by long and often violent popular

struggles that eventually forced the hands of the bureaucrats: the

leftist parties and labor unions that pretended to lead those struggles

have functioned primarily as safety valves, coopting radical tendencies

and greasing the wheels of the social machine.

As the situationists have shown, the bureaucratization of radical

movements, which has degraded people into followers constantly

“betrayed” by their leaders, is linked to the increasing

spectacularization of modern capitalist society, which has degraded

people into spectators of a world over which they have no control — a

development that has become increasingly glaring, though it is usually

only superficially understood.

Taken together, all these considerations point to the conclusion that a

liberated society can be created only by the active participation of the

people as a whole, not by hierarchical organizations supposedly acting

on their behalf. The point is not to choose more honest or “responsive”

leaders, but to avoid granting independent power to any leaders

whatsoever. Individuals or groups may initiate radical actions, but a

substantial and rapidly expanding portion of the population must take

part if a movement is to lead to a new society and not simply to a coup

installing new rulers.

Representative democracy versus delegate democracy

I won’t repeat all the classic socialist and anarchist critiques of

capitalism and the state; they are already widely known, or at least

widely accessible. But in order to cut through some of the confusions of

traditional political rhetoric, it may be helpful to summarize the basic

types of social organization. For the sake of clarity, I will start out

by examining the “political” and “economic” aspects separately, though

they are obviously interlinked. It is as futile to try to equalize

people’s economic conditions through a state bureaucracy as it is to try

to democratize society while the power of money enables the wealthy few

to control the institutions that determine people’s awareness of social

realities. Since the system functions as a whole it can be fundamentally

changed only as a whole.

To begin with the political aspect, roughly speaking we can distinguish

five degrees of “government”:

The present society oscillates between (4) and (5), i.e. between overt

minority rule and covert minority rule camouflaged by a façade of token

democracy. A liberated society would eliminate (4) and (5) and would

progressively reduce the need for (2) and (3).

I’ll discuss the two types of (2) later on. But the crucial distinction

is between (3) and (4).

In representative democracy people abdicate their power to elected

officials. The candidates’ stated policies are limited to a few vague

generalities, and once they are elected there is little control over

their actual decisions on hundreds of issues — apart from the feeble

threat of changing one’s vote, a few years later, to some equally

uncontrollable rival politician. Representatives are dependent on the

wealthy for bribes and campaign contributions; they are subordinate to

the owners of the mass media, who decide which issues get the publicity;

and they are almost as ignorant and powerless as the general public

regarding many important matters that are determined by unelected

bureaucrats and independent secret agencies. Overt dictators may

sometimes be overthrown, but the real rulers in “democratic” regimes,

the tiny minority who own or control virtually everything, are never

voted in and never voted out. Most people don’t even know who they are.

In delegate democracy, delegates are elected for specific purposes with

very specific limitations. They may be strictly mandated (ordered to

vote in a certain way on a certain issue) or the mandate may be left

open (delegates being free to vote as they think best) with the people

who have elected them reserving the right to confirm or reject any

decision thus taken. Delegates are generally elected for very short

periods and are subject to recall at any time.

In the context of radical struggles, delegate assemblies have usually

been termed “councils.” The council form was invented by striking

workers during the 1905 Russian revolution (soviet is the Russian word

for council). When soviets reappeared in 1917, they were successively

supported, manipulated, dominated and coopted by the Bolsheviks, who

soon succeeded in transforming them into parodies of themselves: rubber

stamps of the “Soviet State” (the last surviving independent soviet,

that of the Kronstadt sailors, was crushed in 1921). Councils have

nevertheless continued to reappear spontaneously at the most radical

moments in subsequent history, in Germany, Italy, Spain, Hungary and

elsewhere, because they represent the obvious solution to the need for a

practical form of nonhierarchical popular self-organization. And they

continue to be opposed by all hierarchical organizations, because they

threaten the rule of specialized elites by pointing to the possibility

of a society of generalized self-management: not self-management of a

few details of the present setup, but self-management extended to all

regions of the globe and all aspects of life.

But as noted above, the question of democratic forms cannot be separated

from their economic context.

Irrationalities of capitalism

Economic organization can be looked at from the angle of work:

And from the angle of distribution:

Though it’s possible for goods or services produced by wage labor to be

given away, or for those produced by volunteer or cooperative labor to

be turned into commodities for sale, for the most part these levels of

work and distribution tend to correspond with each other. The present

society is predominately (3): the forced production and consumption of

commodities. A liberated society would eliminate (3) and as far as

possible reduce (2) in favor of (1).

Capitalism is based on commodity production (production of goods for

profit) and wage labor (labor power itself bought and sold as a

commodity). As Marx pointed out, there is less difference between the

slave and the “free” worker than appears. Slaves, though they seem to be

paid nothing, are provided with the means of their survival and

reproduction, for which workers (who become temporary slaves during

their hours of labor) are compelled to pay most of their wages. The fact

that some jobs are less unpleasant than others, and that individual

workers have the nominal right to switch jobs, start their own business,

buy stocks or win a lottery, disguises the fact that the vast majority

of people are collectively enslaved.

How did we get in this absurd position? If we go back far enough, we

find that at some point people were forcibly dispossessed: driven off

the land and otherwise deprived of the means for producing the goods

necessary for life. (The famous chapters on “primitive accumulation” in

Capital vividly describe this process in England.) As long as people

accept this dispossession as legitimate, they are forced into unequal

bargains with the “owners” (those who have robbed them, or who have

subsequently obtained titles of “ownership” from the original robbers)

in which they exchange their labor for a fraction of what it actually

produces, the surplus being retained by the owners. This surplus

(capital) can then be reinvested in order to generate continually

greater surpluses in the same way.

As for distribution, a public water fountain is a simple example of true

communism (unlimited accessibility). A public library is an example of

true socialism (free but regulated accessibility).

In a rational society, accessibility would depend on abundance. During a

drought, water might have to be rationed. Conversely, once libraries are

put entirely online they could become totally communistic: anyone could

have free instant access to any number of texts with no more need to

bother with checking out and returning, security against theft, etc.

But this rational relation is impeded by the persistence of separate

economic interests. To take the latter example, it will soon be

technically possible to create a global “library” in which every book

ever written, every film ever made and every musical performance ever

recorded could be put online, potentially enabling anyone to freely tap

in and obtain a copy (no more need for stores, sales, advertising,

packaging, shipping, etc.). But since this would also eliminate the

profits from present-day publishing, recording and film businesses, far

more energy is spent concocting complicated methods to prevent or charge

for copying (while others devote corresponding energy devising ways to

get around such methods) than on developing a technology that could

potentially benefit everyone.

One of Marxïżœïżœïżœs merits was to have cut through the hollowness of political

discourses based on abstract philosophical or ethical principles (“human

nature” is such and such, all people have a “natural right” to this or

that) by showing how social possibilities and social awareness are to a

great degree limited and shaped by material conditions. Freedom in the

abstract means little if almost everybody has to work all the time

simply to assure their survival. It’s unrealistic to expect people to be

generous and cooperative when there is barely enough to go around

(leaving aside the drastically different conditions under which

“primitive communism” flourished). But a sufficiently large surplus

opens up wider possibilities. The hope of Marx and other revolutionaries

of his time was based on the fact that the technological potentials

developed by the Industrial Revolution had finally provided an adequate

material basis for a classless society. It was no longer a matter of

declaring that things “should” be different, but of pointing out that

they could be different; that class domination was not only unjust, it

was now unnecessary.

Was it ever really necessary? Was Marx right in seeing the development

of capitalism and the state as inevitable stages, or might a liberated

society have been possible without this painful detour? Fortunately, we

no longer have to worry about this question. Whatever possibilities

there may or may not have been in the past, present material conditions

are more than sufficient to sustain a global classless society.

The most serious drawback of capitalism is not its quantitative

unfairness — the mere fact that wealth is unequally distributed, that

workers are not paid the full “value” of their labor. The problem is

that this margin of exploitation (even if relatively small) makes

possible the private accumulation of capital, which eventually reorients

everything to its own ends, dominating and warping all aspects of life.

The more alienation the system produces, the more social energy must be

diverted just to keep it going — more advertising to sell superfluous

commodities, more ideologies to keep people bamboozled, more spectacles

to keep them pacified, more police and more prisons to repress crime and

rebellion, more arms to compete with rival states — all of which

produces more frustrations and antagonisms, which must be repressed by

more spectacles, more prisons, etc. As this vicious circle continues,

real human needs are fulfilled only incidentally, if at all, while

virtually all labor is channeled into absurd, redundant or destructive

projects that serve no purpose except to maintain the system.

If this system were abolished and modern technological potentials were

appropriately transformed and redirected, the labor necessary to meet

real human needs would be reduced to such a trivial level that it could

easily be taken care of voluntarily and cooperatively, without requiring

economic incentives or state enforcement.

It’s not too hard to grasp the idea of superseding overt hierarchical

power. Self-management can be seen as the fulfillment of the freedom and

democracy that are the official values of Western societies. Despite

people’s submissive conditioning, everyone has had moments when they

rejected domination and began speaking or acting for themselves.

It’s much harder to grasp the idea of superseding the economic system.

The domination of capital is more subtle and self-regulating. Questions

of work, production, goods, services, exchange and coordination in the

modern world seem so complicated that most people take for granted the

necessity of money as a universal mediation, finding it difficult to

imagine any change beyond apportioning money in some more equitable way.

For this reason I will postpone more extensive discussion of the

economic aspects till later in this text, when it will be possible to go

into more detail.

Some exemplary modern revolts

Is such a revolution likely? The odds are probably against it. The main

problem is that there is not much time. In previous eras it was possible

to imagine that, despite all humanity’s follies and disasters, we would

somehow muddle through and perhaps eventually learn from past mistakes.

But now that social policies and technological developments have

irrevocable global ecological ramifications, blundering trial and error

is not enough. We have only a few decades to turn things around. And as

time passes, the task becomes more difficult: the fact that basic social

problems are scarcely even faced, much less resolved, encourages

increasingly desperate and delirious tendencies toward war, fascism,

ethnic antagonism, religious fanaticism and other forms of mass

irrationality, deflecting those who might potentially work toward a new

society into merely defensive and ultimately futile holding actions.

But most revolutions have been preceded by periods when everyone scoffed

at the idea that things could ever change. Despite the many discouraging

trends in the world, there are also some encouraging signs, not least of

which is the widespread disillusionment with previous false

alternatives. Many popular revolts in this century have already moved

spontaneously in the right direction. I am not referring to the

“successful” revolutions, which are without exception frauds, but to

less known, more radical efforts. Some of the most notable examples are

Russia 1905, Germany 1918–19, Italy 1920, Asturias 1934, Spain 1936–37,

Hungary 1956, France 1968, Czechoslovakia 1968, Portugal 1974–75 and

Poland 1980–81; many other movements, from the Mexican revolution of

1910 to the recent anti-apartheid struggle in South Africa, have also

contained exemplary moments of popular experimentation before they were

brought under bureaucratic control.

No one is in any position to dismiss the prospect of revolution who has

not carefully examined these movements. To ignore them because of their

“failure” is missing the point.[3] Modern revolution is all or nothing:

individual revolts are bound to fail until an international chain

reaction is triggered that spreads faster than repression can close in.

It’s hardly surprising that these revolts did not go farther; what is

inspiring is that they went as far as they did. A new revolutionary

movement will undoubtedly take new and unpredictable forms; but these

earlier efforts remain full of examples of what can be done, as well as

of what must be avoided.

Some common objections

It’s often said that a stateless society might work if everyone were

angels, but due to the perversity of human nature some hierarchy is

necessary to keep people in line. It would be truer to say that if

everyone were angels the present system might work tolerably well

(bureaucrats would function honestly, capitalists would refrain from

socially harmful ventures even if they were profitable). It is precisely

because people are not angels that it’s necessary to eliminate the setup

that enables some of them to become very efficient devils. Lock a

hundred people in a small room with only one air hole and they will claw

each other to death to get to it. Let them out and they may manifest a

rather different nature. As one of the May 1968 graffiti put it, “Man is

neither Rousseau’s noble savage nor the Church’s depraved sinner. He is

violent when oppressed, gentle when free.”

Others contend that, whatever the ultimate causes may be, people are now

so screwed up that they need to be psychologically or spiritually healed

before they can even conceive of creating a liberated society. In his

later years Wilhelm Reich came to feel that an “emotional plague” was so

firmly embedded in the population that it would take generations of

healthily raised children before people would become capable of a

libertarian social transformation; and that meanwhile one should avoid

confronting the system head-on since this would stir up a hornet’s nest

of ignorant popular reaction.

Irrational popular tendencies do sometimes call for discretion. But

powerful though they may be, they are not irresistible forces. They

contain their own contradictions. Clinging to some absolute authority is

not necessarily a sign of faith in authority; it may be a desperate

attempt to overcome one’s increasing doubts (the convulsive tightening

of a slipping grip). People who join gangs or reactionary groups, or who

get caught up in religious cults or patriotic hysteria, are also seeking

a sense of liberation, connection, purpose, participation, empowerment.

As Reich himself showed, fascism gives a particularly vigorous and

dramatic expression to these basic aspirations, which is why it often

has a deeper appeal than the vacillations, compromises and hypocrisies

of liberalism and leftism.

In the long run the only way to defeat reaction is to present more

forthright expressions of these aspirations, and more authentic

opportunities to fulfill them. When basic issues are forced into the

open, irrationalities that flourished under the cover of psychological

repression tend to be weakened, like disease germs exposed to sunlight

and fresh air. In any case, even if we don’t prevail, there is at least

some satisfaction in fighting for what we really believe, rather than

being defeated in a posture of hesitancy and hypocrisy.

There are limits on how far one can liberate oneself (or raise liberated

children) within a sick society. But if Reich was right to note that

psychologically repressed people are less capable of envisioning social

liberation, he failed to realize how much the process of social revolt

can be psychologically liberating. (French psychiatrists are said to

have complained about a significant drop in the number of their

customers in the aftermath of May 1968!)

The notion of total democracy raises the specter of a “tyranny of the

majority.” Majorities can be ignorant and bigoted, there’s no getting

around it. The only real solution is to confront and attempt to overcome

that ignorance and bigotry. Keeping the masses in the dark (relying on

liberal judges to protect civil liberties or liberal legislators to

sneak through progressive reforms) only leads to popular backlashes when

sensitive issues eventually do come to the surface.

Examined more closely, however, most instances of majority oppression of

minorities turn out to be due not to majority rule, but to disguised

minority rule in which the ruling elite plays on whatever racial or

cultural antagonisms there may be in order to turn the exploited masses’

frustrations against each other. When people get real power over their

own lives they will have more interesting things to do than to persecute

minorities.

So many potential abuses or disasters are evoked at any suggestion of a

nonhierarchical society that it would be impossible to answer them all.

People who resignedly accept a system that condemns millions of their

fellow human beings to death every year in wars and famines, and

millions of others to prison and torture, suddenly let their imagination

and their indignation run wild at the thought that in a self-managed

society there might be some abuses, some violence or coercion or

injustice, or even merely some temporary inconvenience. They forget that

it is not up to a new social system to solve all our problems; it merely

has to deal with them better than the present system does — not a very

big order.

If history followed the complacent opinions of official commentators,

there would never have been any revolutions. In any given situation

there are always plenty of ideologists ready to declare that no radical

change is possible. If the economy is functioning well, they will claim

that revolution depends on economic crises; if there is an economic

crisis, others will just as confidently declare that revolution is

impossible because people are too busy worrying about making ends meet.

The former types, surprised by the May 1968 revolt, tried to

retrospectively uncover the invisible crisis that their ideology insists

must have been there. The latter contend that the situationist

perspective has been refuted by the worsened economic conditions since

that time.

Actually, the situationists simply noted that the widespread achievement

of capitalist abundance had demonstrated that guaranteed survival was no

substitute for real life. The periodic ups and downs of the economy have

no bearing on that conclusion. The fact that a few people at the top

have recently managed to siphon off a yet larger portion of the social

wealth, driving increasing numbers of people into the streets and

terrorizing the rest of the population lest they succumb to the same

fate, makes the feasibility of a postscarcity society less evident; but

the material prerequisites are still present.

The economic crises held up as evidence that we need to “lower our

expectations” are actually caused by over-production and lack of work.

The ultimate absurdity of the present system is that unemployment is

seen as a problem, with potentially labor-saving technologies being

directed toward creating new jobs to replace the old ones they render

unnecessary. The problem is not that so many people don’t have jobs, but

that so many people still do. We need to raise our expectations, not

lower them.[4]

Increasing dominance of the spectacle

Far more serious than this spectacle of our supposed powerlessness in

the face of the economy is the greatly increased power of the spectacle

itself, which in recent years has developed to the point of repressing

virtually any awareness of pre-spectacle history or anti-spectacle

possibilities. Debord’s Comments on the Society of the Spectacle (1988)

goes into this new development in detail:

In all that has happened over the last twenty years, the most important

change lies in the very continuity of the spectacle. What is significant

is not the refinements of the spectacle’s media instrumentation, which

had already attained a highly advanced stage of development; it is quite

simply that spectacular domination has succeeded in raising an entire

generation molded to its laws... Spectacular domination’s first priority

was to eradicate historical knowledge in general, beginning with

virtually all information and rational commentary on the most recent

past... The spectacle makes sure that people are unaware of what is

happening, or at least that they quickly forget whatever they may have

become aware of. The more important something is, the more it is hidden.

Nothing in the last twenty years has been so thoroughly shrouded with

official lies as May 1968... The flow of images carries everything

before it, and it is always someone else who controls this simplified

digest of the perceptible world, who decides where the flow will lead,

who programs the rhythm of what is shown into an endless series of

arbitrary surprises that leaves no time for reflection ... isolating

whatever is presented from its context, its past, its intentions and its

consequences... It is thus hardly surprising that children are now

starting their education with an enthusiastic introduction to the

Absolute Knowledge of computer language while becoming increasingly

incapable of reading. Because reading requires making judgments at every

line; and since conversation is almost dead (as will soon be most of

those who knew how to converse) reading is the only remaining gateway to

the vast realms of pre-spectacle human experience.

In the present text I have tried to recapitulate some basic points that

have been buried under this intensive spectacular repression. If these

matters seem banal to some or obscure to others, they may at least serve

to recall what once was possible, in those primitive times a few decades

ago when people had the quaint, old-fashioned notion that they could

understand and affect their own history.

While there is no question that things have changed considerably since

the sixties (mostly for the worse), our situation may not be quite as

hopeless as it seems to those who swallow whatever the spectacle feeds

them. Sometimes it only takes a little jolt to break through the stupor.

Even if we have no guarantee of ultimate victory, such breakthroughs are

already a pleasure. Is there any greater game around?

Chapter 2: Foreplay

“An individual cannot know what he really is until he has realized

himself through action... The interest the individual finds in something

is already the answer to the question of whether he should act and what

should be done.”

— Hegel, The Phenomenology of Spirit

Personal breakthroughs

Later on I will try to answer some more of the perennial objections. But

as long as the objectors remain passive, all the arguments in the world

will never faze them, and they will continue to sing the old refrain:

“It’s a nice idea, but it’s not realistic, it goes against human nature,

it’s always been this way...” Those who don’t realize their own

potential are unlikely to recognize the potential of others.

To paraphrase that very sensible old prayer, we need the initiative to

solve the problems we can, the patience to endure the ones we can’t, and

the wisdom to know the difference. But we also need to bear in mind that

some problems that can’t be solved by isolated individuals can be solved

collectively. Discovering that others share the same problem is often

the beginning of a solution.

Some problems can, of course, be solved individually, through a variety

of methods ranging from elaborate therapies or spiritual practices to

simple commonsense decisions to correct some mistake, break some harmful

habit, try something new, etc. But my concern here is not with purely

personal makeshifts, worthwhile though they may be within their limits,

but with moments where people move “outward” in deliberately subversive

ventures.

There are more possibilities than appear at first sight. Once you refuse

to be intimidated, some of them are quite simple. You can begin

anywhere. And you have to begin somewhere — do you think you can learn

to swim if you never go in the water?

Sometimes a little action is needed to cut through excessive verbiage

and reestablish a concrete perspective. It needn’t be anything

momentous; if nothing else comes to mind, some rather arbitrary venture

may suffice — just enough to shake things up a bit and wake yourself up.

At other times it’s necessary to stop, to break the chain of compulsive

actions and reactions. To clear the air, to create a little space free

from the cacophony of the spectacle. Just about everyone does this to

some degree, out of instinctive psychological self-defense, whether by

practicing some form of meditation, or by periodically engaging in some

activity that effectively serves the same purpose (working in one’s

garden, taking a walk, going fishing), or simply by pausing to take a

deep breath amid their daily round, coming back for a moment to the

“quiet center.” Without such a space it is difficult to get a sane

perspective on the world, or even simply to keep one’s own sanity.

One of the methods I have found most useful is to put things in writing.

The advantage is partly psychological (some problems lose their power

over us by being set out where we can see them more objectively), partly

a matter of organizing our thoughts so as to see the different factors

and choices more clearly. We often maintain inconsistent notions without

becoming aware of their contradictions until we try putting them down on

paper.

I have sometimes been criticized for exaggerating the importance of

writing. Many matters can, of course, be dealt with more directly. But

even nonverbal actions require thinking about, talking about, and

usually writing about, if they are to be effectively carried out,

communicated, debated, corrected.

(In any case, I don’t claim to cover everything; I am merely discussing

certain points about which I feel I have something to say. If you think

I have failed to address some important topic, why don’t you do it

yourself?)

Critical interventions

Writing enables you to work out your ideas at your own pace, without

worrying about oratorical skills or stage fright. You can make a point

once and for all instead of having to constantly repeat yourself. If

discretion is necessary, a text can be issued anonymously. People can

read it at their own pace, stop and think about it, go back and check

specific points, reproduce it, adapt it, refer others to it. Talking may

generate quicker and more detailed feedback, but it can also disperse

your energy, prevent you from focusing and implementing your ideas.

Those in the same rut as you may resist your efforts to escape because

your success would challenge their own passivity.

Sometimes you can best provoke such people by simply leaving them behind

and pursuing your own course. (“Hey, wait for me!”) Or by shifting the

dialogue to a different level. A letter forces both writer and addressee

to work out their ideas more clearly. Copies to others concerned may

enliven the discussion. An open letter draws in even more people.

If you succeed in creating a chain reaction in which more and more

people read your text because they see others reading it and heatedly

discussing it, it will no longer be possible for anyone to pretend to be

unaware of the issues you have raised.[5]

Suppose, for example, that you criticize a group for being hierarchical,

for allowing a leader to have power over members (or followers or fans).

A private talk with one of the members might merely meet with a series

of contradictory defensive reactions with which it is fruitless to

argue. (“No, he’s not really our leader... And even if he is, he’s not

authoritarian... And besides, what right do you have to criticize?”) But

a public critique forces such contradictions into the open and puts

people in a crossfire. While one member denies that the group is

hierarchical, a second may admit that it is and attempt to justify this

by attributing superior insight to the leader. This may cause a third

member to start thinking.

At first, annoyed that you have disturbed their cozy little scene, the

group is likely to close ranks around the leader and denounce you for

your “negativity” or “elitist arrogance.” But if your intervention has

been acute enough, it may continue to sink in and have a delayed impact.

The leader now has to watch his step since everyone is more sensitive to

anything that might seem to confirm your critique. In order to

demonstrate how unjustified you are, the members may insist on greater

democratization. Even if the particular group proves impervious to

change, its example may serve as an object lesson for a wider public.

Outsiders who might otherwise have made similar mistakes can more easily

see the pertinence of your critique because they have less emotional

investment.

It’s usually more effective to criticize institutions and ideologies

than to attack individuals who merely happen to be caught up in them —

not only because the machine is more crucial than its replaceable parts,

but because this approach makes it easier for individuals to save face

while dissociating themselves from the machine.

But however tactful you may be, there’s no getting around the fact that

virtually any significant critique will provoke irrational defensive

reactions, ranging from personal attacks on you to invocations of one or

another of the many fashionable ideologies that seem to demonstrate the

impossibility of any rational consideration of social problems. Reason

is denounced as cold and abstract by demagogues who find it easier to

play on people’s feelings; theory is scorned in the name of practice...

Theory versus ideology

To theorize is simply to try to understand what we are doing. We are all

theorists whenever we honestly discuss what has happened, distinguish

between the significant and the irrelevant, see through fallacious

explanations, recognize what worked and what didn’t, consider how

something might be done better next time. Radical theorizing is simply

talking or writing to more people about more general issues in more

abstract (i.e. more widely applicable) terms. Even those who claim to

reject theory theorize — they merely do so more unconsciously and

capriciously, and thus more inaccurately.

Theory without particulars is empty, but particulars without theory are

blind. Practice tests theory, but theory also inspires new practice.

Radical theory has nothing to respect and nothing to lose. It criticizes

itself along with everything else. It is not a doctrine to be accepted

on faith, but a tentative generalization that people must constantly

test and correct for themselves, a practical simplification

indispensable for dealing with the complexities of reality.

But hopefully not an oversimplification. Any theory can turn into an

ideology, become rigidified into a dogma, be twisted to hierarchical

ends. A sophisticated ideology may be relatively accurate in certain

respects; what differentiates it from theory is that it lacks a dynamic

relation to practice. Theory is when you have ideas; ideology is when

ideas have you. “Seek simplicity, and distrust it.”

Avoiding false choices and elucidating real ones

We have to face the fact that there are no foolproof gimmicks, that no

radical tactic is invariably appropriate. Something that is collectively

possible during a revolt may not be a sensible option for an isolated

individual. In certain urgent situations it may be necessary to urge

people to take some specific action; but in most cases it is best simply

to elucidate relevant factors that people should take into account when

making their own decisions. (If I occasionally presume to offer direct

advice here, this is for convenience of expression. “Do this” should be

understood as “In some circumstances it may be a good idea to do this.”)

A social analysis need not be long or detailed. Simply “dividing one

into two” (pointing out contradictory tendencies within a given

phenomenon or group or ideology) or “combining two into one” (revealing

a commonality between two apparently distinct entities) may be useful,

especially if communicated to those most directly involved. More than

enough information is already available on most issues; what is needed

is to cut through the glut in order to reveal the essential. Once this

is done, other people, including knowledgeable insiders, will be spurred

to more thorough investigations if these are necessary.

When confronted with a given topic, the first thing is to determine

whether it is indeed a single topic. It’s impossible to have any

meaningful discussion of “Marxism” or “violence” or “technology” without

distinguishing the diverse senses that are lumped under such labels.

On the other hand, it can also be useful to take some broad, abstract

category and show its predominant tendencies, even though such a pure

type does not actually exist. The situationists’ Student Poverty

pamphlet, for example, scathingly enumerates all sorts of stupidities

and pretensions of “the student.” Obviously not every student is guilty

of all these faults, but the stereotype serves as a focus around which

to organize a systematic critique of general tendencies. By stressing

qualities most students have in common, the pamphlet also implicitly

challenges those who claim to be exceptions to prove it. The same

applies to the critique of “the pro-situ” in Debord and Sanguinetti’s

The Real Split in the International — a challenging rebuff of followers

perhaps unique in the history of radical movements.

“Everyone is asked their opinion about every detail in order to prevent

them from forming one about the totality” (Vaneigem). Many issues are

such emotionally loaded tar-babies that anyone who reacts to them

becomes entangled in false choices. The fact that two sides are in

conflict, for example, does not mean that you must support one or the

other. If you cannot do anything about a particular problem, it is best

to clearly acknowledge this fact and move on to something that does

present practical possibilities.[6]

If you do decide to choose a lesser evil, admit it; don’t add to the

confusion by whitewashing your choice or demonizing the enemy. If

anything, it’s better to do the opposite: to play devil’s advocate and

neutralize compulsive polemical delirium by calmly examining the strong

points of the opposing position and the weaknesses in your own. “A very

popular error: having the courage of one’s convictions; the point is to

have the courage for an attack on one’s convictions!” (Nietzsche).

Combine modesty with audacity. Remember that if you happen to accomplish

anything it is on the foundation of the efforts of countless others,

many of whom have faced horrors that would make you or me crumple into

submission. But don’t forget that what you say can make a difference:

within a world of pacified spectators even a little autonomous

expression will stand out.

Since there are no longer any material obstacles to inaugurating a

classless society, the problem has been essentially reduced to a

question of consciousness: the only thing that really stands in the way

is people’s unawareness of their own collective power. (Physical

repression is effective against radical minorities only so long as

social conditioning keeps the rest of the population docile.) Hence a

large element of radical practice is negative: attacking the various

forms of false consciousness that prevent people from realizing their

positive potentialities.

The insurrectionary style

Both Marx and the situationists have often been ignorantly denounced for

such negativity, because they concentrated primarily on critical

clarification and deliberately avoided promoting any positive ideology

to which people could passively cling. Because Marx pointed out how

capitalism reduces our lives to an economic rat-race, “idealistic”

apologists for this state of affairs accuse him of “reducing life to

materialistic concerns” — as if the whole point of Marx’s work was not

to help us get beyond our economic slavery so that our more creative

potentials can flower. “To call on people to give up their illusions

about their condition is to call on them to give up a condition that

requires illusions... Criticism plucks the imaginary flowers from the

chain not in order that man shall continue to bear that chain without

fantasy or consolation, but so that he will throw off the chain and

pluck the living flower” (“Introduction to a Critique of Hegel’s

Philosophy of Right”).

Accurately expressing a key issue often has a surprisingly powerful

effect. Bringing things out into the open forces people to stop hedging

their bets and take a position. Like the dexterous butcher in the Taoist

fable whose knife never needed sharpening because he always cut between

the joints, the most effective radical polarization comes not from

strident protest, but from simply revealing the divisions that already

exist, elucidating the different tendencies, contradictions, choices.

Much of the situationists’ impact stemmed from the fact that they

articulated things that most people had already experienced but were

unable or afraid to express until someone else broke the ice. (“Our

ideas are in everybody’s mind.”)

If some situationist texts nevertheless seem difficult at first, this is

because their dialectical structure goes against the grain of our

conditioning. When this conditioning is broken they don’t seem so

obscure (they were the source of some of the most popular May 1968

graffiti). Many academic spectators have floundered around trying

unsuccessfully to resolve the various “contradictory” descriptions of

the spectacle in The Society of the Spectacle into some single,

“scientifically consistent” definition; but anyone engaged in contesting

this society will find Debord’s examination of it from different angles

eminently clear and useful, and come to appreciate the fact that he

never wastes a word in academic inanities or pointless expressions of

outrage.

The dialectical method that runs from Hegel and Marx to the

situationists is not a magic formula for churning out correct

predictions, it is a tool for grappling with the dynamic processes of

social change. It reminds us that social concepts are not eternal; that

they contain their own contradictions, interacting with and transforming

each other, even into their opposites; that what is true or progressive

in one context may become false or regressive in another.[7]

A dialectical text may require careful study, but each new reading

brings new discoveries. Even if it influences only a few people

directly, it tends to influence them so profoundly that many of them end

up influencing others in the same way, leading to a qualitative chain

reaction. The nondialectical language of leftist propaganda is easier to

understand, but its effect is usually superficial and ephemeral;

offering no challenge, it soon ends up boring even the stupefied

spectators for whom it is designed.

As Debord put it in his last film, those who find what he says too

difficult would do better to blame their own ignorance and passivity,

and the schools and society that have made them that way, than to

complain about his obscurity. Those who don’t have enough initiative to

reread crucial texts or to do a little exploration or a little

experimentation for themselves are unlikely to accomplish anything if

they are spoonfed by someone else.

Radical film

Debord is in fact virtually the only person who has made a truly

dialectical and antispectacular use of film [see Guy Debord’s Films].

Although would-be radical filmmakers often give lip service to Brechtian

“distanciation” — the notion of encouraging spectators to think and act

for themselves rather than sucking them into passive identification with

hero or plot — most radical films still play to the audience as if it

were made up of morons. The dimwitted protagonist gradually “discovers

oppression” and becomes “radicalized” to the point where he is ready to

become a fervent supporter of “progressive” politicians or a loyal

militant in some bureaucratic leftist group. Distanciation is limited to

a few token gimmicks that allow the spectator to think: “Ah, a Brechtian

touch! What a clever fellow that filmmaker is! And how clever am I to

recognize such subtleties!” The radical message is usually so banal that

it is obvious to virtually anyone who would ever go to see such a film

in the first place; but the spectator gets the gratifying impression

that other people might be brought up to his level of awareness if only

they could be got to see it.

If the spectator has any uneasiness about the quality of what he is

consuming, it is assuaged by the critics, whose main function is to read

profound radical meanings into practically any film. As with the

Emperor’s New Clothes, no one is likely to admit that he wasn’t aware of

these supposed meanings until informed of them, for fear that this would

reveal him as less sophisticated than the rest of the audience.

Certain films may help expose some deplorable condition or convey some

sense of the feel of a radical situation. But there is little point in

presenting images of a struggle if both the images and the struggle are

not criticized. Spectators sometimes complain that a film portrays some

social category (e.g. women) inaccurately. This may be true insofar as

the film reproduces certain false stereotypes; but the usually implied

alternative — that the filmmaker “should have presented images of women

struggling against oppression” — would in most cases be equally false to

reality. Women (like men or any other oppressed group) have in fact

usually been passive and submissive — that’s precisely the problem we

have to face. Catering to people’s self-satisfaction by presenting

spectacles of triumphant radical heroism only reinforces this bondage.

Oppressionism versus playfulness

To rely on oppressive conditions to radicalize people is unwise; to

intentionally worsen them in order to accelerate this process is

unacceptable. The repression of certain radical projects may

incidentally expose the absurdity of the ruling order; but such projects

should be worthwhile for their own sake — they lose their credibility if

they are merely pretexts designed to provoke repression. Even in the

most “privileged” milieus there are usually more than enough problems

without needing to add to them. The point is to reveal the contrast

between present conditions and present possibilities; to give people

enough taste of real life that they’ll want more.

Leftists often imply that a lot of simplification, exaggeration and

repetition is necessary in order to counteract all the ruling propaganda

in the other direction. This is like saying that a boxer who has been

made groggy by a right hook will be restored to lucidity by a left hook.

People’s consciousness is not “raised” by burying them under an

avalanche of horror stories, or even under an avalanche of information.

Information that is not critically assimilated and used is soon

forgotten. Mental as well as physical health requires some balance

between what we take in and what we do with it. It may sometimes be

necessary to force complacent people to face some outrage they are

unaware of, but even in such cases harping on the same thing ad nauseam

usually accomplishes nothing more than driving them to escape to less

boring and depressing spectacles.

One of the main things that keeps us from understanding our situation is

the spectacle of other people’s apparent happiness, which makes us see

our own unhappiness as a shameful sign of failure. But an omnipresent

spectacle of misery also keeps us from seeing our positive potentials.

The constant broadcasting of delirious ideas and nauseating atrocities

paralyzes us, turns us into paranoids and compulsive cynics.

Strident leftist propaganda, fixating on the insidiousness and

loathsomeness of “oppressors,” often feeds this delirium, appealing to

the most morbid and mean-spirited side of people. If we get caught up in

brooding on evils, if we let the sickness and ugliness of this society

pervade even our rebellion against it, we forget what we are fighting

for and end up losing the very capacity to love, to create, to enjoy.

The best “radical art” cuts both ways. If it attacks the alienation of

modern life, it simultaneously reminds us of the poetic potentialities

hidden within it. Rather than reinforcing our tendency to wallow in

self-pity, it encourages our resilience, enables us to laugh at our own

troubles as well as at the asininities of the forces of “order.” Some of

the old IWW songs and comic strips are good examples, even if the IWW

ideology is by now a bit musty. Or the ironic, bittersweet songs of

Brecht and Weill. The hilarity of The Good Soldier Svejk is probably a

more effective antidote to war than the moral outrage of the typical

antiwar tract.

Nothing undermines authority like holding it up to ridicule. The most

effective argument against a repressive regime is not that it is evil,

but that it is silly. The protagonists of Albert Cossery’s novel La

violence et la dérision, living under a Middle-Eastern dictatorship,

plaster the walls of the capital with an official-looking poster that

praises the dictator to such a preposterous degree that he becomes a

laughingstock and is forced to resign out of embarrassment. CossĂ©ry’s

pranksters are apolitical and their success is perhaps too good to be

true, but somewhat similar parodies have been used with more radical

aims (e.g. the Li I-Che coup mentioned on page 304 [A Radical Group in

Hong Kong]). At demonstrations in Italy in the 1970s the Metropolitan

Indians (inspired perhaps by the opening chapter of Lewis Carroll’s

Sylvie and Bruno: “Less Bread! More Taxes!”) carried banners and chanted

slogans such as “Power to the Bosses!” and “More work! Less pay!”

Everyone recognized the irony, but it was harder to dismiss with the

usual pigeonholing.

Humor is a healthy antidote to all types of orthodoxy, left as well as

right. It’s highly contagious and it reminds us not to take ourselves

too seriously. But it can easily become a mere safety valve, channeling

dissatisfaction into glib, passive cynicism. Spectacle society thrives

on delirious reactions against its most delirious aspects. Satirists

often have a dependent, love-hate relation with their targets; parodies

become indistinguishable from what they are parodying, giving the

impression that everything is equally bizarre, meaningless and hopeless.

In a society based on artificially maintained confusion, the first task

is not to add to it. Chaotic disruptions usually generate nothing but

annoyance or panic, provoking people to support whatever measures the

government takes to restore order. A radical intervention may at first

seem strange and incomprehensible; but if it has been worked out with

sufficient lucidity, people will soon understand it well enough.

The Strasbourg scandal

Imagine being at Strasbourg University at the opening of the school year

in fall 1966, among the students, faculty and distinguished guests

filing into an auditorium to hear a commencement address. You find a

little pamphlet placed on each seat. A program? No, something about “the

poverty of student life.” You idly open it up and start to read: “It is

pretty safe to say that the student is the most universally despised

creature in France, apart from the policeman and the priest...” You look

around and see that everyone else is also reading it, reactions ranging

from puzzlement or amusement to shock and outrage. Who is responsible

for this? The title page reveals that it is published by the Strasbourg

Student Union, but it also refers to “the Situationist International,”

whatever that might be...

What made the Strasbourg scandal different from some college prank, or

from the confused and confusing capers of groups like the Yippies, was

that its scandalous form conveyed an equally scandalous content. At a

moment when students were being proclaimed as the most radical sector of

society, this text was the only one that put things into perspective.

But the particular poverties of students just happened to be the point

of departure; equally scathing texts could and should be written on the

poverty of every other segment of society (preferably by those who know

them from inside). Some have in fact been attempted, but none have

approached the lucidity and coherence of the situationist pamphlet, so

concise yet so comprehensive, so provocative yet so accurate, moving so

methodically from a specific situation through increasingly general

ramifications that the final chapter presents the most pithy existing

summary of the modern revolutionary project. (See SI Anthology, pp.

204–212, 319–337 [On the Poverty of Student Life and Our Goals and

Methods in the Strasbourg Scandal].)

The situationists never claimed to have single-handedly provoked May

1968 — as they said, they predicted the content of the revolt, not the

date or location. But without the Strasbourg scandal and the subsequent

agitation by the SI-influenced Enragés group (of which the more well

known March 22^(nd) Movement was only a belated and confused imitation)

the revolt might never have happened. There was no economic or

governmental crisis, no war or racial antagonism destabilizing the

country, nor any other particular issue that might have fostered such a

revolt. There were more radical worker struggles going on in Italy and

England, more militant student struggles in Germany and Japan, more

widespread countercultural movements in the United States and the

Netherlands. But only in France was there a perspective that tied them

all together.

Carefully calculated interventions like the Strasbourg scandal must be

distinguished not only from confusionistic disruptions, but also from

merely spectacular exposés. As long as social critics confine themselves

to contesting this or that detail, the spectacle-spectator relation

continually reconstitutes itself: if such critics succeed in

discrediting existing political leaders, they themselves often become

new stars (Ralph Nader, Noam Chomsky, etc.) whom slightly more aware

spectators admiringly rely on for a continuing flow of shocking

information that they rarely do anything about. The milder exposés get

the audience to root for this or that faction in intragovernmental power

struggles; the more sensational ones feed people’s morbid curiosity,

sucking them into consuming more articles, news programs and docudramas,

and into interminable debates about various conspiracy theories. Most

such theories are obviously nothing but delirious reflections of the

lack of critical historical sense produced by the modern spectacle,

desperate attempts to find some coherent meaning in an increasingly

incoherent and absurd society. In any case, as long as things remain on

the spectacular terrain it hardly matters whether any of these theories

are true: those who keep watching to see what comes next never affect

what comes next.

Certain revelations are more interesting because they not only open up

significant issues to public debate, but do so in a manner that draws

lots of people into the game. A charming example is the 1963 “Spies for

Peace” scandal in England, in which a few unknown persons publicized the

location of a secret bomb shelter reserved for members of the

government. The more vehemently the government threatened to prosecute

anyone who reproduced this “state secret” information which was no

longer secret from anyone, the more creatively and playfully it was

disseminated by thousands of groups and individuals (who also proceeded

to discover and invade several other secret shelters). Not only did the

asininity of the government and the insanity of the nuclear war

spectacle became evident to everyone, the spontaneous human chain

reaction provided a taste of a quite different social potential.

The poverty of electoral politics

“Since 1814 no Liberal government had come in except by violence.

CĂĄnovas was too intelligent not to see the inconvenience and the danger

of that. He therefore arranged that Conservative governments should be

succeeded regularly by Liberal governments. The plan he followed was,

whenever an economic crisis or a serious strike came along, to resign

and let the Liberals deal with it. This explains why most of the

repressive legislation passed during the rest of the century was passed

by them.”

— Gerald Brenan, The Spanish Labyrinth

The best argument in favor of radical electoral politics was made by

Eugene Debs, the American socialist leader who in 1920 received nearly a

million votes for president while in prison for opposing World War I:

“If the people don’t know enough to know who to vote for, they’re not

going to know who to shoot at.” On the other hand, the workers during

the 1918–19 German revolution were confused about who to shoot at

precisely by the presence of “socialist” leaders in the government who

were working overtime to repress the revolution.

In itself, voting is of no great significance one way or the other

(those who make a big deal about refusing to vote are only revealing

their own fetishism). The problem is that it tends to lull people into

relying on others to act for them, distracting them from more

significant possibilities. A few people who take some creative

initiative (think of the first civil rights sit-ins) may ultimately have

a far greater effect than if they had put their energy into campaigning

for lesser-evil politicians. At best, legislators rarely do more than

what they have been forced to do by popular movements. A conservative

regime under pressure from independent radical movements often concedes

more than a liberal regime that knows it can count on radical support.

If people invariably rally to lesser evils, all the rulers have to do in

any situation that threatens their power is to conjure up a threat of

some greater evil.

Even in the rare case when a “radical” politician has a realistic chance

of winning an election, all the tedious campaign efforts of thousands of

people may go down the drain in one day because of some trivial scandal

discovered in his personal life, or because he inadvertently says

something intelligent. If he manages to avoid these pitfalls and it

looks like he might win, he tends to evade controversial issues for fear

of antagonizing swing voters. If he actually gets elected he is almost

never in a position to implement the reforms he has promised, except

perhaps after years of wheeling and dealing with his new colleagues;

which gives him a good excuse to see his first priority as making

whatever compromises are necessary to keep himself in office

indefinitely. Hobnobbing with the rich and powerful, he develops new

interests and new tastes, which he justifies by telling himself that he

deserves a few perks after all his years of working for good causes.

Worst of all, if he does eventually manage to get a few “progressive”

measures passed, this exceptional and usually trivial success is held up

as evidence of the value of relying on electoral politics, luring many

more people into wasting their energy on similar campaigns to come.

As one of the May 1968 graffiti put it, “It’s painful to submit to our

bosses; it’s even more stupid to choose them!”

Referendums on particular issues are less susceptible to the

precariousness of personalities; but the results are often no better

since the issues tend to be posed very simplistically, and any measure

that threatens powerful interests can usually be defeated by the

influence of money and mass media.

Local elections sometimes offer people a more realistic chance to affect

policies and keep tabs on elected officials. But even the most

enlightened communities cannot insulate themselves from the

deterioration of the rest of the world. If a city manages to preserve

desirable cultural or environmental features, these very advantages put

it under increasing economic pressure. The fact that human values have

been given precedence over property values ultimately causes enormous

increases in the latter (more people will want to invest or move there).

Sooner or later this property-value increase overpowers the human

values: local policies are overruled by high courts or by state or

national governments, outside money is poured into municipal elections,

city officials are bribed, residential neighborhoods are demolished to

make room for highrises and freeways, rents skyrocket, the poorer

classes are forced out (including the diverse ethnic groups and artistic

bohemians who contributed to the city’s original liveliness and appeal),

and all that remains of the earlier community are a few isolated sites

of “historical interest” for tourist consumption.

Reforms and alternative institutions

Still, “acting locally” may be a good place to start. People who feel

that the global situation is hopeless or incomprehensible may

nevertheless see a chance to affect some specific local matter. Block

clubs, co-ops, switchboards, study groups, alternative schools, free

health clinics, community theaters, neighborhood newspapers,

public-access radio and television stations and many other kinds of

alternative institutions are worthwhile for their own sake, and if they

are sufficiently participatory they may lead to broader movements. Even

if they don’t last very long, they provide a temporary terrain for

radical experimentation.

But always within limits. Capitalism was able to develop gradually

within feudal society, so that by the time the capitalist revolution

cast off the last vestiges of feudalism, most of the mechanisms of the

new bourgeois order were already firmly in place. An anticapitalist

revolution, in contrast, cannot really build its new society “within the

shell of the old.” Capitalism is far more flexible and all-pervading

than was feudalism, and tends to coopt any oppositional organization.

Nineteenth-century radical theorists could still see enough surviving

remnants of traditional communal forms to suppose that, once the

overarching exploitive structure was eliminated, they might be revived

and expanded to form the foundation of a new society. But the global

penetration of spectacular capitalism in the present century has

destroyed virtually all forms of popular control and direct human

interaction. Even the more modern efforts of the sixties counterculture

have long been integrated into the system. Co-ops, crafts, organic

farming and other marginal enterprises may produce better quality goods

under better working conditions, but those goods still have to function

as commodities on the market. The few successful ventures tend to evolve

into ordinary businesses, with the founding members gradually assuming

an ownership or managerial role over the newer workers and dealing with

all sorts of routine commercial and bureaucratic matters that have

nothing to do with “preparing the ground for a new society.”

The longer an alternative institution lasts, the more it tends to lose

its volunteer, experimental, nothing-to-lose character. Permanent paid

staffs develop a vested interest in the status quo and avoid rocking the

boat for fear of offending supporters or losing their government or

foundation funding. Alternative institutions also tend to demand too

much of the limited free time people have, bogging them down, robbing

them of the energy and imagination to confront more general issues.

After a brief period of participation most people get burned out,

leaving the work to the dutiful types or to leftists trying to make an

ideological point. It may sound nice to hear about people forming block

clubs, etc., but unless a real local emergency comes up you may not want

to attend interminable meetings to listen to your neighbors’ complaints,

or otherwise commit yourself to matters you don’t really care about.

In the name of realism, reformists limit themselves to pursuing

“winnable” objectives, yet even when they win some little adjustment in

the system it is usually offset by some other development at another

level. This doesn’t mean that reforms are irrelevant, merely that they

are insufficient. We have to keep resisting particular evils, but we

also have to recognize that the system will keep generating new ones

until we put an end to it. To suppose that a series of reforms will

eventually add up to a qualitative change is like thinking we can get

across a ten-foot chasm by a series of one-foot hops.

People tend to assume that because revolution involves much greater

change than reforms, it must be more difficult to bring about. In the

long run it may actually be easier, because in one stroke it cuts

through so many petty complications and arouses a much greater

enthusiasm. At a certain point it becomes more practical to start fresh

than to keep trying to replaster a rotten structure.

Meanwhile, until a revolutionary situation enables us to be truly

constructive, the best we can do is be creatively negative —

concentrating on critical clarification, leaving people to pursue

whatever positive projects may appeal to them but without the illusion

that a new society is being “built” by the gradual accumulation of such

projects.

Purely negative projects (e.g. abolition of laws against drug use,

consensual sex and other victimless crimes) have the advantage of

simplicity, immediately benefiting virtually everyone (except for that

symbiotic duo, organized crime and the crime-control industry) while

requiring little if any followup work once they are successful. On the

other hand, they provide little opportunity for creative participation.

The best projects are those that are worthwhile for their own sake while

simultaneously containing an implicit challenge to some fundamental

aspect of the system; projects that enable people to participate in

significant issues according to their own degree of interest, while

tending to open the way to more radical possibilities.

Less interesting, but still worthwhile, are demands for improved

conditions or more equal rights. Even if such projects are not in

themselves very participatory, they may remove impediments to

participation.

Least desirable are mere zero-sum struggles, where one group’s gain is

another’s loss.

Even in the latter case the point is not to tell people what they should

do, but to get them to realize what they are doing. If they are

promoting some issue in order to recruit people, it is appropriate to

expose their manipulative motives. If they believe they are contributing

to radical change, it may be useful to show them how their activity is

actually reinforcing the system in some way. But if they are really

interested in their project for its own sake, let them go for it.

Even if we disagree with their priorities (fundraising for the opera,

say, while the streets are filled with homeless people) we should be

wary of any strategy that merely appeals to people’s guilt, not only

because such appeals generally have a negligible effect but because such

moralism represses healthy positive aspirations. To refrain from

contesting “quality of life” issues because the system continues to

present us with survival emergencies is to submit to a blackmail that no

longer has any justification. “Bread and roses” are no longer mutually

exclusive.[8]

“Quality of life” projects are in fact often more inspiring than routine

political and economic demands because they awaken people to richer

perspectives. Paul Goodman’s books are full of imaginative and often

amusing examples. If his proposals are “reformist,” they are so in a

lively, provocative way that provides a refreshing contrast to the

cringing defensive posture of most present-day reformists, who confine

themselves to reacting to the reactionaries’ agenda. (“We agree that it

is essential to create jobs, fight crime, keep our country strong; but

moderate methods will accomplish this better than the conservatives’

extremist proposals.”)

Other things being equal, it makes sense to concentrate one’s energy on

issues that are not already receiving public attention; and to prefer

projects that can be done cleanly and directly, as opposed to those that

require compromises, such as working through government agencies. Even

if such compromises don’t seem too serious, they set a bad precedent.

Reliance on the state almost always backfires (commissions designed to

root out bureaucratic corruption themselves develop into new corrupt

bureaucracies; laws designed to thwart armed reactionary groups end up

being used primarily to harass unarmed radicals).

The system is able to kill two birds with one stone by maneuvering its

opponents into offering “constructive solutions” to its own crises. It

in fact needs a certain amount of opposition to warn it of problems, to

force it to rationalize itself, to enable it to test its instruments of

control, and to provide excuses to impose new forms of control.

Emergency measures imperceptibly become standard procedures as

regulations that might ordinarily be resisted are introduced during

situations of panic. The slow, steady rape of the human personality by

all the institutions of alienated society, from school and factory to

advertising and urbanism, is made to seem normal as the spectacle

focuses obsessively on sensational individual crimes, manipulating

people into law-and-order hysteria.

Political correctness, or equal opportunity alienation

Above all, the system thrives when it can deflect social contestation

into squabbles over privileged positions within it.

This is a particularly thorny area. All social inequalities need to be

challenged, not only because they are unfair, but because as long as

they remain they can be used to divide people. But attaining equal wage

slavery or equal opportunity to become a bureaucrat or a capitalist

hardly amounts to any victory over bureaucratic capitalism.

It is both natural and necessary that people defend their own interests;

but if they try do so by identifying too exclusively with some

particular social group they tend to lose sight of the larger picture.

As increasingly fragmented categories scramble over the crumbs allotted

to them, they get caught up in petty mutual-blame games and the notion

of abolishing the whole hierarchical structure is forgotten. People who

are normally quick to denounce the slightest hint of derogatory

stereotyping get carried away into lumping all men or all whites as

“oppressors,” then wonder why they run up against such powerful

backlashes among the vast majority of the latter, who are quite aware

that they have little real power over their own lives, much less over

anyone else’s.

Aside from the reactionary demagogues (who are pleasantly surprised to

find “progressives” providing them with such easy targets for ridicule)

the only people who actually benefit from these internecine squabbles

are a few careerists struggling for bureaucratic posts, government

grants, academic tenure, publishing contracts, commercial clienteles or

political constituencies at a time when there is increasingly limited

space at the trough. Sniffing out “political incorrectness” enables them

to bash rivals and critics and reinforce their own positions as

recognized specialists or spokespeople of their particular fragment. The

various oppressed groups that are foolish enough to accept such

spokespeople get nothing but the bittersweet thrill of self-righteous

resentment and a ludicrous official terminology reminiscent of Orwell’s

Newspeak.[9]

There is a crucial, though sometimes subtle, distinction between

fighting social evils and feeding on them. People are not empowered by

being encouraged to wallow in their own victimhood. Individual autonomy

is not developed by taking refuge in some group identity. Equal

intelligence is not demonstrated by dismissing logical reasoning as a

“typical white male tactic.” Radical dialogue is not fostered by

harassing people who don’t conform to some political orthodoxy, much

less by striving to get such orthodoxy legally enforced.

Nor is history made by rewriting it. We do need to free ourselves from

uncritical respect for the past and to become aware of the ways it has

been distorted. But we have to recognize that despite our disapproval of

past prejudices and injustices, it is unlikely that we would have done

any better had we ourselves lived under the same conditions. Applying

present-day standards retroactively (smugly correcting earlier authors

every time they use the formerly conventional masculine forms, or trying

to censor Huckleberry Finn because Huck doesn’t refer to Jim as a

“person of color”) only reinforces the historical ignorance that the

modern spectacle has been so successful in fostering.

Drawbacks of moralism and simplistic extremism

A lot of this nonsense stems from the false assumption that being

radical implies living up to some moral “principle” — as if no one could

work for peace without being a total pacifist, or advocate the abolition

of capitalism without giving away all their money. Most people have too

much common sense to actually follow such simplistic ideals, but they

often feel vaguely guilty that they don’t. This guilt paralyzes them and

makes them more susceptible to blackmail by leftist manipulators (who

tell us that if we don’t have the courage to martyrize ourselves, we

must uncritically support those who do). Or they try to repress their

guilt by disparaging others who seem even more compromised: a manual

laborer may take pride in not selling out mentally like a professor; who

perhaps feels superior to an ad designer; who may in turn look down on

someone who works in the arms industry...

Turning social problems into personal moral issues deflects attention

from their potential solution. Trying to change social conditions by

charity is like trying to raise the sea level by dumping buckets of

water in the ocean. Even if some good is accomplished by altruistic

actions, to rely on them as a general strategy is futile because they

will always be the exception. Most people naturally look out first for

themselves and for those closest to them. One of the merits of the

situationists was to have cut through the traditional leftist appeal to

guilt and self-sacrifice by stressing that the primary reason to make a

revolution is for ourselves.

“Going to the people” in order to “serve” or “organize” or “radicalize”

them usually leads to manipulation and often meets with apathy or

hostility. The example of others’ independent actions is a far stronger

and healthier means of inspiration. Once people begin to act on their

own they are in a better position to exchange experiences, to

collaborate on equal terms and, if necessary, to ask for specific

assistance. And when they win their own freedom it’s much harder to take

it back from them. One of the May 1968 graffitists wrote: “I’m not a

servant of the people (much less of their self-appointed leaders) — let

the people serve themselves.” Another put it even more succinctly:

“Don’t liberate me — I’ll take care of that.”

A total critique means that everything is called into question, not that

everything must be totally opposed. Radicals often forget this and get

caught up in outbidding each other with increasingly extremist

assertions, implying that any compromise amounts to selling out or even

that any enjoyment amounts to complicity with the system. Actually,

being “for” or “against” some political position is just as easy, and

usually just as meaningless, as being for or against some sports team.

Those who proudly proclaim their “total opposition” to all compromise,

all authority, all organization, all theory, all technology, etc.,

usually turn out to have no revolutionary perspective whatsoever — no

practical conception of how the present system might be overthrown or

how a postrevolutionary society might work. Some even attempt to justify

this lack by declaring that a mere revolution could never be radical

enough to satisfy their eternal ontological rebelliousness.

Such all-or-nothing bombast may temporarily impress a few spectators,

but its ultimate effect is simply to make people blasé. Sooner or later

the contradictions and hypocrisies lead to disillusionment and

resignation. Projecting their own disappointed delusions onto the world,

the former extremists conclude that all radical change is hopeless and

repress the whole experience; or perhaps even flip to some equally silly

reactionary position.

If every radical had to be a Durruti we might as well forget it and

devote ourselves to more realizable concerns. But being radical does not

mean being the most extreme. In its original sense it simply means going

to the root. The reason it is necessary to strive for the abolition of

capitalism and the state is not because this is the most extreme goal

imaginable, but because it has unfortunately become evident that nothing

less will do.

We need to find out what is both necessary and sufficient; to seek

projects that we are actually capable of doing and realistically likely

to do. Anything beyond this is just hot air. Many of the oldest and

still most effective radical tactics — debates, critiques, boycotts,

strikes, sit-ins, workers councils — caught on precisely because they

are at once simple, relatively safe, widely applicable, and open-ended

enough to lead to broader possibilities.

Simplistic extremism naturally seeks the most extremist foil for itself.

If all problems can be attributed to a sinister clique of “total

fascists,” everything else will seem comfortingly progressive by

comparison. Meanwhile the actual forms of modern domination, which are

usually more subtle, proceed unnoticed and unopposed.

Fixating on reactionaries only reinforces them, makes them seem more

powerful and more fascinating. “It matters little if our opponents mock

us or insult us, if they represent us as clowns or criminals; the

essential thing is that they talk of us, preoccupy themselves with us”

(Hitler). Reich pointed out that “by drilling people to hate the police

one only strengthens police authority and invests it with mystic power

in the eyes of the poor and the helpless. The strong are hated but also

feared and envied and followed. This fear and envy felt by the

‘have-nots’ accounts for a portion of the political reactionaries’

power. One of the main objectives of the rational struggle for freedom

is to disarm reactionaries by exposing the illusionary character of

their power” (People in Trouble).

The main problem with compromising is not so much moral as practical:

it’s difficult to attack something when we ourselves are implicated in

it. We hedge our critiques lest others criticize us in turn. It becomes

harder to think big, to act boldly. As has often been noted, many of the

German people acquiesced to Nazi oppression because it began fairly

gradually and was at first directed mainly at unpopular minorities

(Jews, Gypsies, Communists, homosexuals); by the time it began affecting

the general population, they had become incapable of doing anything

about it.

In hindsight it’s easy to condemn those who capitulated to fascism or

Stalinism, but it’s unlikely that most of us would have done any better

had we been in the same position. In our daydreams, picturing ourself as

a dramatic personage faced with a clear-cut choice in front of an

appreciative audience, we imagine that we would have no trouble making

the right decision. But the situations we actually face are usually more

complex and obscure. It’s not always easy to know where to draw the

line.

The point is to draw it somewhere, stop worrying about guilt and blame

and self-justification, and take the offensive.

Advantages of boldness

This spirit is well exemplified by those Italian workers who have gone

on strike without making any demands whatsoever. Such strikes are not

only more interesting than the usual bureaucratic union negotiations,

they may even be more effective: the bosses, uncertain of how far they

have to go, frequently end up offering much more than the strikers would

have dared to demand. The latter can then decide on their next move

without having committed themselves to anything in return.

A defensive reaction against this or that social symptom at best wins

some temporary concession on the specific issue. Aggressive agitation

that refuses to limit itself exerts far more pressure. Faced with

widespread, unpredictable movements like the sixties counterculture or

the May 1968 revolt — movements calling everything in question,

generating autonomous contestations on many fronts, threatening to

spread throughout the whole society and too vast to be controlled by

cooptable leaders — rulers hasten to clean up their image, pass reforms,

raise wages, release prisoners, declare amnesties, initiate peace talks

— anything in the hope of preempting the movement and reestablishing

their control. (The sheer unmanageability of the American

counterculture, which was spreading deeply into the army itself,

probably played as great a role as the explicit antiwar movement in

forcing the end of the Vietnam war.)

The side that takes the initiative defines the terms of the struggle. As

long as it keeps innovating, it also retains the element of surprise.

“Boldness is virtually a creative power... Whenever boldness meets

hesitation it already has a significant advantage because the very state

of hesitation implies a loss of equilibrium. It is only when it

encounters cautious foresight that it is at a disadvantage” (Clausewitz,

On War). But cautious foresight is quite rare among those who run this

society. Most of the system’s processes of commodification,

spectacularization and hierarchization are blind and automatic:

merchants, media and leaders merely follow their natural tendencies to

make money or grab audiences or recruit followers.

Spectacle society is often the victim of its own falsifications. As each

level of bureaucracy tries to cover for itself with padded statistics,

as each “information source” outbids the others with more sensational

stories, and as competing states, governmental departments and private

companies each launch their own independent disinformation operations

(see chapters 16 and 30 of Debord’s Comments on the Society of the

Spectacle), even the exceptional ruler who may have some lucidity has a

hard time finding out what is really happening. As Debord observes

elsewhere in the same book, a state that ends up repressing its own

historical knowledge can no longer conduct itself strategically.

Advantages and limits of nonviolence

“The whole history of the progress of human liberty shows that all

concessions yet made to her august claims have been born of struggle...

If there is no struggle there is no progress. Those who profess to favor

freedom and yet deprecate agitation, are men who want crops without

plowing up the ground. They want rain without thunder and lightning.

They want the ocean without the awful roar of its many waters. The

struggle may be a moral one; or it may be a physical one; or it may be

both moral and physical, but it must be a struggle. Power concedes

nothing without a demand. It never did and it never will.”

— Frederick Douglass

Anyone with any knowledge of history is aware that societies do not

change without stubborn and often savage resistance by those in power.

If our ancestors had not resorted to violent revolt, most of those who

now self-righteously deplore it would still be serfs or slaves.

The routine functioning of this society is far more violent than any

reaction against it could ever be. Imagine the outrage that would greet

a radical movement that executed 20,000 opponents; that’s a conservative

estimate of the number of children that the present system allows to

starve to death each day. Vacillations and compromises allow this

ongoing violence to drag on indefinitely, ultimately causing a thousand

times more suffering than a single decisive revolution.

Fortunately a modern, genuinely majority revolution would have

relatively little need for violence except to neutralize those elements

of the ruling minority who try to violently maintain their own power.

Violence is not only undesirable in itself, it generates panic (and thus

manipulability) and promotes militaristic (and thus hierarchical)

organization. Nonviolence entails more open and democratic organization;

it tends to foster composure and compassion and to break the miserable

cycle of hatred and revenge.

But we have to avoid making a fetish out of it. The common retort, “How

can you work for peace with violent methods?” is no more logical than it

would be to tell a drowning man that if he wants to get to dry land he

must avoid touching water. Striving to resolve “misunderstandings”

through dialogue, pacifists forget that some problems are based on

objective conflicts of interest. They tend to underestimate the malice

of enemies while exaggerating their own guilt, berating themselves even

for their “violent feelings.” The seemingly personal practice of

“bearing witness” actually reduces the activist to a passive object,

“another person for peace” who (like a soldier) puts her body on the

line while abdicating personal investigation or experimentation. Those

who want to undermine the notion of war as exciting and heroic must get

beyond such a cringing, beggarly notion of peace. Defining their

objective as survival, peace activists have had little to say to those

who are fascinated by global annihilation precisely because they are

sick of an everyday life reduced to mere survival, who see war not as a

threat but as a welcome deliverance from a life of boredom and constant

petty anxiety.

Sensing that their purism would not hold up under the test of reality,

pacifists usually remain deliberately ignorant about past and present

social struggles. Though often capable of intensive study and stoic

self-discipline in their personal spiritual practices, they seem to feel

that a Reader’s Digest level of historical and strategical knowledge

will suffice for their ventures into “social engagement.” Like someone

hoping to eliminate injurious falls by abolishing the law of gravity,

they find it simpler to envision a never-ending moral struggle against

“greed,” “hatred,” “ignorance,” “bigotry,” than to challenge the

specific social structures that actually reinforce such qualities. If

pressed, they sometimes complain that radical contestation is a very

stressful terrain. It is indeed, but this is a strange objection to hear

from those whose spiritual practices claim to enable people to confront

problems with detachment and equanimity.

There’s a wonderful moment in Uncle Tom’s Cabin: As a Quaker family is

helping some slaves escape to Canada, a Southern slave catcher appears.

One of the Quakers points a shotgun at him and says, “Friend, thee isn’t

wanted here.” I think that’s just the right tone: not caught up in

hatred, or even contempt, but ready to do what is necessary in a given

situation.

Reactions against oppressors are understandable, but those who get too

caught up in them risk becoming mentally as well as materially enslaved,

chained to their masters by “bonds of hate.” Hatred of bosses is partly

a projection of people’s self-hatred for all the humiliations and

compromises they have accepted, stemming from their secret awareness

that bosses ultimately exist only because the bossed put up with them.

Even if there is some tendency for the scum to rise to the top, most

people in positions of power don’t act much differently than would

anyone else who happened to find themselves in the same position, with

the same new interests, temptations and fears.

Vigorous retaliation may teach enemy forces to respect you, but it also

tends to perpetuate antagonisms. Forgiveness sometimes wins over

enemies, but in other cases it simply gives them a chance to recover and

strike again. It’s not always easy to determine which policy is best in

which circumstances. People who have suffered under particularly vicious

regimes naturally want to see the perpetrators punished; but too much

revenge sends a message to other present and future oppressors that they

may as well fight to the death since they have nothing to lose.

But most people, even those who have been most blamably complicitous

with the system, will tend to go whichever way the wind blows. The best

defense against counterrevolution is not to be preoccupied with sniffing

out people’s past offenses or potential future betrayals, but to deepen

the insurgence to the point that everyone is drawn in.

Chapter 3: Climaxes

“As soon as the relations of exploitation and the violence that

underlies them are no longer concealed by the mystical veil, there is a

breakthrough, a moment of clarity, the struggle against alienation is

suddenly revealed as a ruthless hand-to-hand fight with naked power,

power exposed in its brute force and its weakness, a vulnerable giant

... sublime moment when the complexity of the world becomes tangible,

transparent, within everyone’s grasp.”

— Raoul Vaneigem, Basic Banalities (SI Anthology, p. 93 [Revised Edition

p. 121])

Causes of social breakthroughs

It’s hard to generalize about the immediate causes of radical

breakthroughs. There have always been plenty of good reasons to revolt,

and sooner or later instabilities will arise where something has to

give. But why at one moment and not another? Revolts have often occurred

during periods of social improvement, while worse conditions have been

endured with resignation. If some have been provoked by sheer

desperation, others have been touched off by relatively trivial

incidents. Grievances that have been patiently accepted as long as they

seemed inevitable may suddenly seem intolerable once it appears possible

to remove them. The meanness of some repressive measure or the asininity

of some bureaucratic blunder may bring home the absurdity of the system

more clearly than a steady accumulation of oppressions.

The system’s power is based on people’s belief in their powerlessness to

oppose it. Normally this belief is well founded (transgress the rules

and you are punished). But when for one reason or another enough people

begin to ignore the rules that they can do so with impunity, the whole

illusion collapses. What was thought to be natural and inevitable is

seen to be arbitrary and absurd. “When no one obeys, no one commands.”

The problem is how to reach this point. If only a few disobey, they can

easily be isolated and repressed. People often fantasize about wonderful

things that might be achieved “if only everyone would agree to do such

and such all at once.” Unfortunately, social movements don’t usually

work that way. One person with a six-gun can hold off a hundred unarmed

people because each one knows that the first six to attack will be

killed.

Of course some people may be so infuriated that they attack regardless

of risk; and their apparent determination may even save them by

convincing those in power that it’s wiser to give in peacefully than to

be overwhelmed after arousing even more hatred against themselves. But

it is obviously preferable not to depend on acts of desperation, but to

seek forms of struggle that minimize risk until a movement has spread so

far that repression is no longer feasible.

People living under particularly repressive regimes naturally begin by

taking advantage of whatever rallying points already exist. In 1978 the

Iranian mosques were the only place people could get away with

criticizing the Shah’s regime. Then the huge demonstrations called by

Khomeini at 40-day intervals began providing the safety of numbers.

Khomeini thus became recognized as a general symbol of opposition, even

by those who were not his followers. But tolerating any leader, even as

a mere figurehead, is at best a temporary measure that should be

abandoned as soon as more independent action becomes possible — as did

those Iranian oil workers who by fall 1978 felt they had enough leverage

to strike on days different from those called for by Khomeini.

The Catholic Church in Stalinist Poland played a similarly ambiguous

role: the state used the Church to help control the people, but the

people also used the Church to help them get around the state.

Fanatical orthodoxy is sometimes the first step toward more radical

self-expression. Islamic fundamentalists may be extremely reactionary,

but by getting used to taking events in their own hands they complicate

any return to “order” and may even, if disillusioned, become genuinely

radical — as happened with some of the similarly fanatical Red Guards

during the Chinese “Cultural Revolution,” when what was originally a

mere ploy by Mao to lever out some of his bureaucratic rivals eventually

led to uncontrolled insurgency by millions of young people who took his

antibureaucratic rhetoric seriously.[10]

Postwar upheavals

If someone proclaimed: “I am the greatest, strongest, noblest,

cleverest, and most peace-loving person in the world,” he would be

considered obnoxious, if not insane. But if he says precisely the same

things about his country he is looked upon as an admirably patriotic

citizen. Patriotism is extremely seductive because it enables even the

most miserable individual to indulge in a vicarious collective

narcissism. The natural nostalgic fondness for one’s home and

surroundings is transformed into a mindless cult of the state. People’s

fears and resentments are projected onto foreigners while their

frustrated aspirations for authentic community are mystically projected

onto their own nation, which is seen as somehow essentially wonderful

despite all its defects. (“Yes, America has its problems; but what we

are fighting for is the real America, what America really stands for.”)

This mystical herd-consciousness becomes almost irresistible during war,

smothering virtually all radical tendencies.

Yet patriotism has sometimes played a role in triggering radical

struggles (e.g. Hungary 1956). And even wars have sometimes led to

revolts in the aftermath. Those who have borne the greatest share of the

military burden, supposedly in the name of freedom and democracy, may

return home to demand a fairer share for themselves. Seeing historic

struggle in action and acquiring the habit of dealing with obstacles by

destroying them, they may be less inclined to believe in a changeless

status quo.

The dislocations and disillusionments produced by World War I led to

uprisings all over Europe. If World War II did not do the same, it was

because genuine radicalism had since been destroyed by Stalinism,

fascism and reformism; because the victors’ rationales for the war,

though full of lies as always, were more credible than usual (the

defeated enemies were more obvious villains); and because this time the

victors had taken care to work out the postwar reestablishment of order

in advance (eastern Europe was handed over to Stalin in exchange for his

guaranteeing the docility of the French and Italian Communist Parties

and his abandonment of the insurgent Greek CP). Nevertheless the global

jolt of the war was sufficient to open the way for an autonomous

Stalinist revolution in China (which Stalin had not wanted, as this

threatened his exclusive domination of the “socialist camp”) and to give

a new impetus to the anticolonial movements (which the European colonial

powers naturally did not want, though they were eventually able to

retain the more profitable aspects of their domination through the sort

of economic neocolonialism that the United States was already

practicing).

Faced with the prospect of a postwar power vacuum, rulers often

collaborate with their ostensible enemies in order to repress their own

people. At the end of the Franco-German war of 1870–71 the victorious

German army helped surround the Paris Commune, enabling the French

rulers to crush it more easily. As Stalin’s army approached Warsaw in

1944 it called on the people of the city to rise against the Nazi

occupiers, then waited outside the city for several days while the Nazis

wiped out the thus-exposed independent elements which might later have

resisted the imposition of Stalinism. We have recently seen a similar

scenario in the de facto Bush-Saddam alliance in the aftermath of the

Gulf war, when, after calling on the Iraqi people to rise against

Saddam, the American military systematically massacred Iraqi conscripts

retreating from Kuwait (who, if they had regained their country, would

have been ripe for revolt) while leaving Saddam’s elite Republican

Guards intact and free to crush the immense radical uprisings in

northern and southern Iraq.[11]

In totalitarian societies the grievances are obvious but revolt is

difficult. In “democratic” societies struggles are easier, but the goals

are less clear. Controlled largely by subconscious conditioning or by

vast, seemingly incomprehensible forces (“the state of the economy”) and

offered a wide range of apparently free choices, it’s difficult for us

to grasp our situation. Like a flock of sheep, we’re herded in the

desired direction, but allowed enough room for individual variations to

enable us to preserve an illusion of independence.

Impulses toward vandalism or violent confrontation can often be seen as

attempts to break through this frustrating abstractness and come to

grips with something concrete.

Just as the first organization of the classical proletariat was

preceded, during the end of the eighteenth century and the beginning of

the nineteenth, by a period of isolated “criminal” acts aimed at

destroying the machines of production that were depriving people of

their work, we are presently witnessing the first appearance of a wave

of vandalism against the machines of consumption that are just as

certainly depriving us of our life. In both cases the significance

obviously does not lie in the destruction itself, but in the

rebelliousness which could potentially develop into a positive project

going to the point of reconverting the machines in a way that increases

people’s real power over their lives. (SI Anthology, p. 82 [Revised

Edition p. 108] [The Bad Days Will End].)

(Note that last sentence, incidentally: To point out a symptom of social

crisis, or even to defend it as an understandable reaction, does not

necessary imply recommending it as a tactic.)

Many other triggers of radical situations could be enumerated. A strike

may spread (Russia 1905); popular resistance to some reactionary threat

may overflow official bounds (Spain 1936); people may take advantage of

token liberalization in order to push further (Hungary 1956,

Czechoslovakia 1968); exemplary small group actions may catalyze a mass

movement (the early civil rights sit-ins, May 1968); a particular

outrage may be seen as the last straw (Watts 1965, Los Angeles 1992);

the sudden collapse of a regime may leave a power vacuum (Portugal

1974); some special occasion may bring people together in such numbers

that it’s impossible to prevent them from expressing their grievances

and aspirations (Tiananmen Square 1976 and 1989); etc.

But social crises involve so many imponderables that it is rarely

possible to predict them, much less provoke them. In general it seems

best to pursue projects we are personally most drawn to, while trying to

remain aware enough to quickly recognize significant new developments

(dangers, urgent tasks, favorable opportunities) that call for new

tactics.

Meanwhile, we can move on to examine some of the crucial stages in

radical situations once they do get started.

Effervescence of Radical Situations

A radical situation is a collective awakening. At one extreme it may

involve a few dozen people in a neighborhood or workplace; at the other

it shades into a full-fledged revolutionary situation involving millions

of people. It’s not a matter of numbers, but of open-ended public

dialogue and participation. The incident at the beginning of the1964

Free Speech Movement (FSM) is a classic and particularly beautiful

example. As police were about to take away an arrested civil rights

activist on the university campus in Berkeley, a few students sat down

in front of the police car; within a few minutes hundreds of others

spontaneously followed their example, surrounding the car so it could

not move. For the next 32 hours the car roof was turned into a platform

for freewheeling debate. The May 1968 occupation of the Sorbonne created

an even more radical situation by drawing in much of the nonstudent

Parisian population; the workers’ occupation of factories throughout

France then turned it into a revolutionary situation.

In such situations people become much more open to new perspectives,

readier to question previous assumptions, quicker to see through the

usual cons. Every day some people go through experiences that lead them

to question the meaning of their lives; but during a radical situation

practically everyone does so all at once. When the machine grinds to a

halt, the cogs themselves begin wondering about their function.

Bosses are ridiculed. Orders are ignored. Separations are broken down.

Personal problems are transformed into public issues; public issues that

seemed distant and abstract become immediate practical matters. The old

order is analyzed, criticized, satirized. People learn more about

society in a week than in years of academic “social studies” or leftist

“consciousness raising.” Long repressed experiences are revived.[12]

Everything seems possible — and much more is possible. People can hardly

believe what they used to put up with in “the old days.” Even if the

outcome is uncertain, the experience is often seen as worthwhile for its

own sake. “If we only have enough time ...” wrote one May 1968

graffitist; to which a couple others responded: “In any case, no

regrets!” and “Already ten days of happiness.”

As work comes to a halt, rat-race commuting is replaced by leisurely

circulation, passive consumption by active communication. Strangers

strike up lively discussions on street corners. Debates continue round

the clock, new arrivals constantly replacing those who depart for other

activities or to try to catch a few hours of sleep, though they are

usually too excited to sleep very long. While some people succumb to

demagogues, others start making their own proposals and taking their own

initiatives. Bystanders get drawn into the vortex, and go through

astonishingly rapid changes. (A beautiful example from May 1968: The

director of the national Odéon Theater was at first dismayed at its

being taken over by the radical crowds; but after taking in the

situation for a few minutes, he came forward and exclaimed: “Yes! Now

that you have it, keep it, never give it up — burn it rather than do

that!”)

Of course, not everyone is immediately won over. Some people simply lay

low, anticipating the time when the movement will subside and they can

recover their possessions or their positions, and take their revenge.

Others waver, torn between desire for change and fear of change. An

opening of a few days may not be enough to break a lifetime of

hierarchical conditioning. The disruption of habits and routines can be

disorienting as well as liberating. Everything happens so fast it’s easy

to panic. Even if you manage to keep calm, it’s not easy to grasp all

the factors in play quickly enough to determine the best thing to do,

which may appear obvious in hindsight. One of the main purposes of the

present text is to point out certain typical recurring patterns so that

people can be prepared to recognize and exploit such opportunities

before it’s too late.

Radical situations are the rare moments when qualitative change really

becomes possible. Far from being abnormal, they reveal how abnormally

repressed we usually are; they make our “normal” life seem like

sleepwalking. Yet of the vast number of books that have been written

about revolutions, few have much to say about such moments. Those

dealing with the most radical modern revolts are usually merely

descriptive, perhaps giving a hint of what such experiences feel like

but seldom providing any useful tactical insights. Studies of bourgeois

and bureaucratic revolutions are generally even less relevant. In such

revolutions, where the “masses” played only a temporary supporting role

for one leadership or another, their behavior could to a large degree be

analyzed like the motions of physical masses, in terms of the familiar

metaphors of rising and ebbing tides, pendulum swings from radicality to

reaction, etc. But an antihierarchical revolution requires people to

cease being homogenous, manipulable masses, to get beyond the

subservience and unconsciousness that make them subject to this sort of

mechanistic predictability.

Popular self-organization

During the sixties it was widely felt that the best way to foster such

demassification was to form “affinity groups”: small associations of

close friends with compatible lifestyles and perspectives. Such groups

do have many obvious advantages. They can decide on a project and

immediately carry it out; they are difficult to infiltrate; and when

necessary they can link up with others. But even leaving aside the

various pitfalls to which most of the sixties affinity groups soon

succumbed, there’s no getting around the fact that some matters require

large-scale organization. And large groups will soon revert to accepting

some sort of hierarchy unless they manage to organize themselves in a

manner that renders leaders unnecessary.

One of the simplest ways for a large gathering to begin organizing

itself is for those who have something to say to line up or sign up,

with each person allowed a certain time within which they can talk about

anything they want. (The Sorbonne assembly and the FSM gathering around

the police car each established a three-minute limit, occasionally

extended by popular acclaim.) Some of the speakers will propose specific

projects that will precipitate smaller, more workable groups. (“I and

some others intend to do such and such; anyone who wants to take part

can join us at such and such time and place.”) Others will raise issues

involving the general aims or ongoing functioning of the assembly

itself. (Whom does it include? When will it meet again? How will urgent

new developments be dealt with in the interim? Who will be delegated to

deal with specific tasks? With what degree of accountability?) In this

process the participants will soon see what works and what doesn’t — how

strictly delegates need to be mandated, whether a chairperson is needed

to facilitate discussion so that everyone isn’t talking at once, etc.

Many modes of organization are possible; what is essential is that

things remain open, democratic and participatory, that any tendency

toward hierarchy or manipulation is immediately exposed and rejected.

Despite its naïveté and confusions and lack of rigorous delegate

accountability, the FSM is a good example of the spontaneous tendencies

toward practical self-organization that arise in a radical situation.

Some two dozen “centrals” were formed to coordinate printing, press

releases, legal assistance, to rustle up food, speaker systems and other

necessary supplies, or to locate volunteers who had indicated their

skills and availability for different tasks. Phone trees made it

possible to contact over twenty thousand students on short notice.

But beyond mere questions of practical efficiency, and even beyond the

ostensible political issues, the insurgents were breaking through the

whole spectacular façade and getting a taste of real life, real

community. One participant estimated that within a few months he had

come to know, at least as a nodding acquaintance, two or three thousand

people — this at a university that was notorious for “turning people

into numbers.” Another movingly wrote: “Confronting an institution

apparently and frustratingly designed to depersonalize and block

communication, neither humane nor graceful nor responsive, we found

flowering in ourselves the presence whose absence we were at heart

protesting.”[13]

A radical situation must spread or fail. In exceptional cases a

particular location may serve as a more or less permanent base, a focus

for coordination and a refuge from outside repression. (Sanrizuka, a

rural region near Tokyo that was occupied by local farmers during the

1970s in an effort to block the construction of a new airport, was so

stubbornly and successfully defended for so many years that it came to

be used as a headquarters for diverse struggles all over Japan.) But a

fixed location facilitates manipulation, surveillance and repression,

and being stuck with defending it inhibits people’s freedom to move

around. Radical situations are always characterized by a lot of

circulation: while some people converge to key locations to see what’s

happening, others fan out to spread the contestation to other areas.

A simple but essential step in any radical action is for people to

communicate what they are actually doing and why. Even if what they have

done is very limited, such communication is in itself exemplary: besides

spreading the game to a wider field and inciting others to join in, it

cuts through the usual reliance on rumors, news media and self-appointed

spokespeople.

It’s also a crucial step in self-clarification. A proposal to issue a

collective communiqué presents concrete alternatives: Who do we want to

communicate with? For what purpose? Who is interested in this project?

Who agrees with this statement? Who disagrees? With which points? This

may lead to a polarization as people see the different possibilities of

the situation, sort out their own views, and regroup with like-minded

persons to pursue diverse projects.

Such polarization clarifies matters for everyone. Each tendency remains

free to express itself and to test its ideas in practice, and the

results can be discerned more clearly than if contradictory strategies

were mixed together in some lowest-common-denominator compromise. When

people see a practical need for coordination, they will coordinate; in

the mean time, the proliferation of autonomous individuals is far more

fruitful than the superficial, top-down “unity” for which bureaucrats

are always appealing.

Large crowds sometimes enable people to do things that would be

imprudent if undertaken by isolated individuals; and certain collective

actions, such as strikes or boycotts, require people to act in concert,

or at least not to go against a majority decision. But many other

matters can be dealt with directly by individuals or small groups.

Better to strike while the iron is hot than to waste time trying to

argue away the objections of masses of spectators who are still under

the sway of manipulators.

The situationists in May 1968

Small groups have every right to choose their own collaborators:

specific projects may require specific abilities or close accord among

the participants. A radical situation opens up broader possibilities

among a broader range of people. By simplifying basic issues and cutting

through habitual separations, it renders masses of ordinary people

capable of carrying out tasks they could not even have imagined the week

before. In any case, the self-organized masses are the only ones who can

carry out those tasks — no one else can do it on their behalf.

What is the role of individual radicals in such a situation? It is clear

that they must not claim to represent or lead the people. On the other

hand, it is absurd to declare, in the name of avoiding hierarchy, that

they should immediately “dissolve into the masses” and cease putting

forward their own views or initiating their own projects. They should

hardly do less than the ordinary “mass” individuals, who have to express

their views and initiate their projects or nothing at all would happen.

In practice those radicals who claim to be afraid of “telling people

what to do” or of “acting in place of the workers” generally end up

either doing nothing or disguising their endless reiterations of their

ideology as “reports of discussions among some workers.”

The situationists and Enragés had a considerably more lucid and

forthright practice during May 1968. During the first three or four days

of the Sorbonne occupation (14–17 May) they openly expressed their views

on the tasks of the assembly and of the general movement. On the basis

of those views one of the Enragés, René Riesel, was elected to the first

Sorbonne Occupation Committee, and he and his fellow delegates were

reelected the following day.

Riesel and one other delegate (the rest apparently slipped away without

fulfilling any of their responsibilities) endeavored to carry out the

two policies he had advocated: maintaining total democracy in the

Sorbonne and disseminating the most widespread appeals for occupying the

factories and forming workers councils. But when the assembly repeatedly

allowed its Occupation Committee to be overridden by various unelected

leftist bureaucracies and failed to affirm the call for workers councils

(thereby denying the workers the encouragement to do what the assembly

itself was doing in the Sorbonne), the Enragés and situationists left

the assembly and continued their agitation independently.

There was nothing undemocratic about this departure: the Sorbonne

assembly remained free to do whatever it wanted. But when it failed to

respond to the urgent tasks of the situation and even contradicted its

own pretensions of democracy, the situationists felt that it had no

further claim to be considered a focal point of the most radical

possibilities of the movement. Their diagnosis was confirmed by the

subsequent collapse of any pretense of participatory democracy at the

Sorbonne: after their departure the assembly had no more elections and

reverted to the typical leftist form of self-appointed bureaucrats

running things over the heads of passive masses.

While this was going on among a few thousand people in the Sorbonne,

millions of workers were occupying their factories throughout the

country. (Hence the absurdity of characterizing May 1968 as a “student

movement.”) The situationists, the EnragĂ©s and a few dozen other

councilist revolutionaries formed the Council for Maintaining the

Occupations (CMDO) with the aim of encouraging those workers to bypass

the union bureaucrats and directly link up with each other in order to

realize the radical possibilities their action had already opened

up.[14]

Workerism is obsolete, but workers’ position remains pivotal

“Virtuous indignation is a powerful stimulant, but a dangerous diet.

Keep in mind the old proverb: anger is a bad counsellor... Whenever your

sympathies are strongly stirred on behalf of some cruelly ill used

person or persons of whom you know nothing except that they are ill

used, your generous indignation attributes all sorts of virtues to them,

and all sorts of vices to those who oppress them. But the blunt truth is

that ill used people are worse than well used people.”

— George Bernard Shaw, The Intelligent Woman’s Guide to Socialism and

Capitalism

“We shall abolish slaves because we can’t stand the sight of them.”

— Nietzsche

Fighting for liberation does not imply applauding the traits of the

oppressed. The ultimate injustice of social oppression is that it is

more likely to debase the victims than to ennoble them.

A lot of traditional leftist rhetoric stemmed from obsolete work-ethic

notions: the bourgeois were bad because they didn’t do productive work,

whereas the worthy proletarians deserved the fruits of their labor, etc.

As labor has become increasingly unnecessary and directed to

increasingly absurd ends, this perspective has lost whatever sense it

may once have had. The point is not to praise the proletariat, but to

abolish it.

Class domination hasn’t gone away just because a century of leftist

demagogy has made some of the old radical terminology sound pretty

corny. While phasing out certain kinds of traditional blue-collar labor

and throwing whole sectors of the population into permanent

unemployment, modern capitalism has proletarianized almost everyone

else. White-collar workers, technicians, and even middle-class

professionals who formerly prided themselves on their independence

(doctors, scientists, scholars) are increasingly subject to the crassest

commercialization and even to virtually assembly-line style

regimentation.

Less than 1% of the global population owns 80% of the world’s land. Even

in the supposedly more egalitarian United States, economic disparity is

extreme and constantly growing more extreme. Twenty years ago the

average CEO salary was 35 times that of the average production worker;

today it’s 120 times as much. Twenty years ago the richest half-percent

of the American population owned 14% of the total private wealth; they

now own 30% of it. But such figures do not convey the full extent of

this elite’s power. The “wealth” of the lower and middle classes is

almost entirely devoted to covering their day-to-day expenses, leaving

little or nothing for investment at any significant, socially empowering

level. A magnate who owns as little as five or ten percent of a

corporation will usually be able to control it (due to the apathy of the

unorganized mass of small stockholders), thus wielding as much power as

if he owned the whole thing. And it only takes a few major corporations

(whose directorates are closely interlinked with each other and with

upper government bureaucracies) to buy out, wipe out or marginalize

smaller independent competitors and effectively control the key

politicians and media.

The omnipresent spectacle of middle-class prosperity has concealed this

reality, especially in the United States where, because of its

particular history (and despite the violence of many of its past class

conflicts), people are more naĂŻvely oblivious to class divisions than

anywhere else in the world. The wide variety of ethnicities and the

multitude of complex intermediate gradations has buffered and blurred

the fundamental distinction between top and bottom. Americans own so

many commodities that they fail to notice that someone else owns the

whole society. Except for those at the very bottom, who can’t help

knowing better, they generally assume that poverty is the fault of the

poor, that any enterprising person has plenty of opportunity, that if

you can’t make a satisfactory living in one place you can always make a

fresh start somewhere else. A century ago, when people could just pick

up and head further west, this belief had some foundation; the

persistence of nostalgic frontier spectacles obscures the fact that

present conditions are quite different and that we no longer have

anywhere else to go.

The situationists sometimes used the term proletariat (or more

precisely, the new proletariat) in a broadened sense, to refer to “all

those who have no power over their own lives and know it.” This usage

may be rather loose, but it has the merit of stressing the fact that

society is still divided into classes, and that the fundamental division

is still between the few who own and control everything and the rest who

have little or nothing to exchange but their own labor power. In some

contexts it may be preferable to use other terms, such as “the people”;

but not when this amounts to indiscriminately lumping exploiters with

exploited.

The point is not to romanticize wage laborers, who, not surprisingly,

considering that the spectacle is designed above all to keep them

deluded, are often among the most ignorant and reactionary sectors of

society. Nor is it a matter of scoring points to see who is most

oppressed. All forms of oppression must be contested, and everyone can

contribute to this contestation — women, youth, unemployed, minorities,

lumpens, bohemians, peasants, middle classes, even renegades from the

ruling elite. But none of these groups can achieve a definitive

liberation without abolishing the material foundation of all these

oppressions: the system of commodity production and wage labor. And this

abolition can be achieved only through the collective self-abolition of

wage laborers. They alone have the leverage not only to directly bring

the whole system to a stop, but to start things up again in a

fundamentally different way.[15]

Nor is it a matter of giving anyone special privileges. Workers in

essential sectors (food, transportation, communications, etc.) who have

rejected their capitalist and union bosses and begun to self-manage

their own activities will obviously have no interest in holding on to

the “privilege” of doing all the work and every interest in inviting

everyone else, whether nonworkers or workers from obsolete sectors (law,

military, sales, advertising, etc.), to join them in the project of

reducing and transforming it. Everyone who takes part will share in the

decisionmaking; the only ones left out will be those who remain on the

sidelines claiming special privileges.

Traditional syndicalism and councilism have tended to take the existing

division of labor too much for granted, as if people’s lives in a

postrevolutionary society would continue to center around fixed jobs and

workplaces. Even within the present society such a perspective is

becoming increasingly obsolete: as most people work at absurd and

frequently only temporary jobs without in any way identifying with them,

while many others don’t work on the wage market at all, work-related

issues become merely one aspect of a more general struggle.

At the beginning of a movement it may be appropriate for workers to

identify themselves as such. (“We, the workers of such and such company,

have occupied our workplace with such and such aims; we urge workers in

other sectors to do likewise.”) The ultimate goal, however, is not the

self-management of existing enterprises. For, say, media workers to have

control over the media just because they happen to work there would be

almost as arbitrary as the present control by whoever happens to own

them. Workers’ management of the particular conditions of their work

will need to be combined with community management of matters of general

concern. Housewives and others working in relatively separated

conditions will need to develop their own forms of organization to

enable them to express their own particular interests. But potential

conflicts of interest between “producers” and “consumers” will be

quickly superseded when everyone becomes directly involved in both

aspects; when workers councils interlink with neighborhood and community

councils; and when fixed work positions fade through the obsoleting of

most jobs and the reorganization and rotation of those that remain

(including housework and child care).

The situationists were certainly right to strive for the formation of

workers councils during the May 1968 factory occupations. But it should

be noted that those occupations were triggered by actions of largely

nonworker youth. The post-1968 situationists tended to fall into a sort

of workerism (though a resolutely anti-work-ethic one), seeing the

proliferation of wildcat strikes as the major indicator of revolutionary

possibilities while paying less attention to developments on other

terrains. Actually, blatant union sellouts often force into wildcat

struggles workers who are in other respects not particularly radical;

and on the other hand, people can resist the system in many other ways

besides strikes (including avoiding wage labor as much as possible in

the first place). The situationists rightly recognized collective

self-management and individual “radical subjectivity” as complementary

and equally essential aspects of the revolutionary project, but without

quite succeeding in bringing them together (though they certainly came

closer than did the surrealists, who tried to link cultural and

political revolt simply by declaring their fervent adhesion to one or

another version of Bolshevik ideology).[16]

Wildcats and sitdowns

Wildcat strikes do present interesting possibilities, especially if the

strikers occupy their workplace. Not only does this make their position

more secure (it prevents lockouts and scabbing, and the machines and

products serve as hostages against repression), it brings everyone

together, virtually guaranteeing collective self-management of the

struggle and hinting at the idea of self-managing the whole society.

Once the usual operation has been stopped, everything takes on a

different ambience. A drab workplace may be transfigured into an almost

sacred space that is jealously guarded against the profane intrusion of

bosses or police. An observer of the 1937 sitdown strike in Flint,

Michigan, described the strikers as “children playing at a new and

fascinating game. They had made a palace out of what had been their

prison.” (Quoted in Sidney Fine’s Sit-Down: The General Motors Strike of

1936–1937.) Though the aim of the strike was simply to win the right to

unionize, its organization was virtually councilist. During the six

weeks that they lived in their factory (using car seats for beds and

cars for closets) a general assembly of all 1200 workers met twice daily

to determine policies regarding food, sanitation, information,

education, complaints, communication, security, defense, sports and

recreation, and to elect accountable and frequently rotated committees

to implement them. There was even a Rumor Committee, whose purpose was

to counteract disinformation by tracking down the source and checking

the validity of every rumor. Outside the factory, strikers’ wives took

care of rounding up food and organizing pickets, publicity, and liaison

with workers in other cities. Some of the bolder ones organized a

Women’s Emergency Brigade which had a contingency plan to form a buffer

zone in case of a police attack on the factories. “If the police want to

fire then they’ll just have to fire into us.”

Unfortunately, although workers retain a pivotal position in some

crucial areas (utilities, communication, transportation), workers in

many other sectors have less leverage than they used to. Multinational

companies usually have large reserves and can wait it out or shift

operations to other countries, while workers have a hard time holding

out without wages coming in. Far from threatening anything essential,

many present-day strikes are mere appeals to postpone shutting down

obsolete industries that are losing money. Thus, while the strike

remains the most basic worker tactic, workers must also devise other

forms of on-the-job struggle and find ways to link up with struggles on

other terrains.

Consumer strikes

Like worker strikes, consumer strikes (boycotts) depend on both the

leverage they can exert and the support they can enlist. There are so

many boycotts in favor of so many causes that, except for a few based on

some glaringly clear moral issue, most of them fail. As is so often the

case in social struggles, the most fruitful consumer strikes are those

in which people are fighting directly for themselves, such as the early

civil rights boycotts in the South or the “self-reduction” movements in

Italy and elsewhere in which whole communities have decided to pay only

a certain percentage of utility bills or mass transit fares. A rent

strike is a particularly simple and powerful action, but it’s difficult

to achieve the degree of unity necessary to get one started except among

those who have nothing to lose; which is why the most exemplary

challenges to the fetish of private property are being made by homeless

squatters.

In what might be called reverse boycotts, people sometimes join in

supporting some popular institution that is threatened. Raising money

for a local school or library or alternative institution is usually

fairly banal, but such movements occasionally generate a salutary public

debate. In 1974 striking reporters took over a major South Korean

newspaper and began publishing exposés of government lies and

repression. In an effort to bankrupt the paper without having to openly

suppress it, the government pressured all the advertisers to remove

their ads from the paper. The public responded by buying thousands of

individual ads, using their space for personal statements, poems,

quotations from Tom Paine, etc. The “Freedom of Speech Support Column”

soon filled several pages of each issue and circulation increased

significantly before the paper was finally suppressed.

But consumer struggles are limited by the fact that consumers are at the

receiving end of the economic cycle: they may exert a certain amount of

pressure through protests or boycotts or riots, but they don’t control

the mechanisms of production. In the above-mentioned Korean incident,

for example, the public participation was only made possible by the

workers’ takeover of the paper.

A particularly interesting and exemplary form of worker struggle is what

is sometimes called a “social strike” or “giveaway strike,” in which

people carry on with their jobs but in ways that prefigure a free social

order: workers giving away goods they have produced, clerks

undercharging customers, transportation workers letting everyone ride

free. In February 1981 11,000 telephone workers occupied exchanges

throughout British Columbia and carried on all phone services without

charge for six days before being maneuvered out by their union. Besides

winning many of their demands, they seem to have had a delightful

time.[17] One can imagine ways of going further and becoming more

selective, such as blocking business and government calls while letting

personal calls go through free. Postal workers could do likewise with

mail; transportation workers could continue to ship necessary goods

while refusing to transport police or troops...

But this type of strike would make no sense for that large majority of

workers whose jobs serve no sensible purpose. (The best thing that such

workers can do is to publicly denounce the absurdity of their own work,

as some ad designers nicely did during May 1968.) Moreover, even useful

work is often so parcelized that isolated groups of workers can

implement few changes on their own. And even the small minority who

happen to produce finished and salable products (as did the workers who

in 1973 took over the bankrupt Lip watch factory in Besançon, France,

and started running it for themselves) usually remain dependent on

commercial financing and distribution networks. In the exceptional case

where such workers make a go of it on their own, they simply become one

more capitalist company; more often, their self-management innovations

merely end up rationalizing the operation for the benefit of the owners.

A “Strasbourg of the factories” might occur if workers finding

themselves in a Lip-type situation use the facilities and publicity it

gives them to go farther than the Lip workers (who were struggling

simply to save their jobs) by calling on others to join them in

superseding the whole system of commodity production and wage labor. But

this is unlikely to happen until there is a sufficiently widespread

movement to enlarge people’s perspectives and offset the risks — as in

May 1968, when most of the factories of France were occupied:

What could have happened in May 1968

If, in a single large factory, between 16 May and 30 May, a general

assembly had constituted itself as a council holding all powers of

decision and execution, expelling the bureaucrats, organizing its

self-defense and calling on the strikers of all the enterprises to link

up with it, this qualitative step could have immediately brought the

movement to the ultimate showdown... A very large number of enterprises

would have followed the course thus discovered. This factory could

immediately have taken the place of the dubious and in every sense

eccentric Sorbonne of the first days and have become the real center of

the occupations movement: genuine delegates from the numerous councils

that already virtually existed in some of the occupied buildings, and

from all the councils that could have imposed themselves in all the

branches of industry, would have rallied around this base. Such an

assembly could then have proclaimed the expropriation of all capital,

including state capital; announced that all the country’s means of

production were henceforth the collective property of the proletariat

organized in direct democracy; and appealed directly (by finally seizing

some of the telecommunications facilities, for example) to the workers

of the entire world to support this revolution. Some people will say

that such a hypothesis is utopian. We answer: It is precisely because

the occupations movement was objectively at several moments only an hour

away from such a result that it spread such terror, visible to everyone

at the time in the impotence of the state and the panic of the so-called

Communist Party, and since then in the conspiracy of silence concerning

its gravity. [SI Anthology, pp. 234–235 [Revised Edition pp. 299–300]

(Beginning of an Era).]

What prevented this from happening was above all the labor unions, in

particular the largest one in the country: the Communist Party-dominated

CGT. Inspired by the rebellious youth who had fought the police in the

streets and taken over the Sorbonne and other public buildings, ten

million workers ignored their unions and occupied virtually all the

factories and many of the offices in the country, launching the first

wildcat general strike in history. But most of these workers were

unclear enough as to what to do next that they allowed the union

bureaucracy to insinuate itself into the movement it had tried to

prevent. The bureaucrats did everything they could to brake and fragment

the movement: calling brief token strikes; setting up phony

“rank-and-file” organizations composed of loyal Party members; seizing

control of the loudspeaker systems; rigging elections in favor of

returning to work; and most crucially, locking the factory gates in

order to keep workers isolated from each other and from the other

insurgents (on the pretext of “guarding against outside provocateurs”).

The unions then proceeded to negotiate with the employers and the

government a package of wage and vacation bonuses. This bribe was

emphatically rejected by a large majority of the workers, who had the

sense, however confused, that some more radical change was on the

agenda. In early June, de Gaulle’s presenting the carrot/stick

alternative of new elections or civil war finally intimidated many

workers into returning to work. There were still numerous holdouts, but

their isolation from each other enabled the unions to tell each group

that all the others had resumed work, so that they would believe they

were alone and give up.

Methods of confusion and cooption

As in May 1968, when the more developed countries are threatened with a

radical situation, they usually rely on confusion, concessions, curfews,

distractions, disinformation, fragmentation, preemption, postponement

and other methods of diverting, dividing and coopting the opposition,

reserving overt physical repression as a last resort. These methods,

which range from the subtle to the ludicrous,[18] are so numerous that

it would be impossible here to mention more than a few.

A common method of confusing the issues is to distort the apparent

alignment of forces by projecting diverse positions onto a linear,

left-versus-right schema, implying that if you are opposed to one side

you must be in favor of the other. The communism-versus-capitalism

spectacle served this purpose for over half a century. Since the recent

collapse of that farce, the tendency has been to declare a centrist

pragmatic global consensus, with any opposition being lumped with

lunatic-fringe “extremisms” (fascism and religious fanaticism on the

right, terrorism and “anarchy” on the left).

One of the classic divide-and-rule methods has been discussed earlier:

encouraging the exploited to fragment into a multitude of narrow group

identities, which can be manipulated into directing their energies into

squabbling with each other. Conversely, opposed classes can be lumped

together by patriotic hysteria and other means. Popular fronts, united

fronts and similar coalitions serve to obscure fundamental conflicts of

interest in the name of joint opposition to a common enemy

(bourgeoisie + proletariat versus a reactionary regime;

military-bureaucratic strata + peasantry versus foreign domination). In

such coalitions the upper group generally has the material and

ideological resources to maintain its control over the lower group,

which is tricked into postponing self-organized action on its own behalf

until it’s too late. By the time victory has been attained over the

common enemy, the upper group has had time to consolidate its power

(often in a new alliance with elements of the defeated enemy) in order

to crush the radical elements of the lower group.

Any vestige of hierarchy within a radical movement will be used to

divide and undermine it. If there are no cooptable leaders, a few will

be created by intensive media exposure. Leaders can be privately

bargained with and held responsible for their followers; once they are

coopted, they can establish similar chains of command beneath them,

enabling a large mass of people to be brought under control without the

rulers having to deal with all of them openly and simultaneously.

Cooption of leaders serves not only to separate them from the people,

but also divides the people among themselves — some seeing the cooption

as a victory, others denouncing it, others hesitating. As attention

shifts from participatory actions to the spectacle of distant

leader-celebrities debating distant issues, most people become bored and

disillusioned. Feeling that matters are out of their hands (perhaps even

secretly relieved that somebody else is taking care of them), they

return to their previous passivity.

Another method of discouraging popular participation is to emphasize

problems that seem to require specialized expertise. A classic instance

was the ploy of certain German military leaders in 1918, at the moment

when the workers and soldiers councils that emerged in the wake of the

German collapse at the end of World War I potentially had the country in

their hands:

On the evening of November 10, when the Supreme Command was still at

Spa, a group of seven enlisted men presented themselves at headquarters.

They were the ‘Executive Committee’ of the Supreme Headquarters

Soldiers’ Council. Their demands were somewhat unclear, but obviously

they expected to play a role in the command of the Army during its

retreat. At the very least they wanted the right to countersign the

Supreme Command’s orders and to insure that the field army was not used

for any counterrevolutionary purpose. The seven soldiers were

courteously received by a Lieutenant Colonel Wilhelm von Faupel, who had

been carefully rehearsed for the occasion... Faupel led the delegates

into the Supreme Command’s map room. Everything was laid out on a

gigantic map which occupied one wall: the huge complex of roads, railway

lines, bridges, switching points, pipelines, command posts and supply

dumps — the whole an intricate lace of red, green, blue and black lines

converging into narrow bottlenecks at the crucial Rhine bridges...

Faupel then turned to them. The Supreme Command had no objection to the

soldiers’ councils, he said, but did his hearers feel competent to

direct the general evacuation of the German Army along these lines of

communication? ... The disconcerted soldiers stared uneasily at the

immense map. One of them allowed that this was not what they had really

had in mind — ‘This work can well be left to the officers.’ In the end,

the seven soldiers willingly gave the officers their support. More than

this, they practically begged the officers to retain command... Whenever

a soldiers’ council delegation appeared at Supreme Headquarters, Colonel

Faupel was trotted out to repeat his earlier performance; it always

worked. [Richard Watt, The Kings Depart: Versailles and the German

Revolution.]

Terrorism reinforces the state

Terrorism has often served to break the momentum of radical situations.

It stuns people, turns them back into spectators anxiously following the

latest news and speculations. Far from weakening the state, terrorism

seems to confirm the need to strengthen it. If terrorist spectacles fail

to spontaneously arise when it needs them, the state itself may produce

them by means of provocateurs. (See Sanguinetti’s On Terrorism and the

State and the last half of Debord’s Preface to the Fourth Italian

Edition of “The Society of the Spectacle.”)

A popular movement can hardly prevent individuals from carrying out

terrorist or other thoughtless actions, actions that may sidetrack and

destroy it as surely as if they were the work of a provocateur. The only

solution is to create a movement with such consistently forthright and

nonmanipulative tactics that everyone will recognize individual

stupidities or police provocations for what they are.

An antihierarchical revolution can only be an “open conspiracy.”

Obviously some things require secrecy, especially under the more

repressive regimes. But even in such cases the means should not be

inconsistent with the ultimate goal: the supersession of all separate

power through the conscious participation of everyone. Secrecy often has

the absurd result that the police are the only ones who know what is

happening, and are thus able to infiltrate and manipulate a radical

group without anyone else being aware of it. The best defense against

infiltration is to make sure there’s nothing of any importance to

infiltrate, i.e. that no radical organization wields any separate power.

The best safety is in numbers: once thousands of people are openly

involved, it hardly matters if a few spies are among them.

Even in small group actions safety often lies in maximum publicity. When

some of the Strasbourg scandal participants started to get cold feet and

suggested toning things down, Mustapha Khayati (the SI delegate who was

the main author of the Student Poverty pamphlet) pointed out that the

safest course would not be to avoid offending the authorities too much —

as if they would be grateful for being only moderately and hesitantly

insulted! — but to perpetrate such a widely publicized scandal that they

wouldn’t dare retaliate.

The ultimate showdown

To get back to the May 1968 factory occupations, suppose that the French

workers had rejected the bureaucratic maneuvers and established a

councilist network throughout the country. What then?

In such an eventuality, civil war would naturally have been

inevitable... Armed counterrevolution would certainly have been launched

immediately. But it would not have been certain of winning. Some of the

troops would obviously have mutinied; the workers would have figured out

how to get weapons, and they certainly would not have built any more

barricades — a good form of political expression at the beginning of the

movement, but obviously ridiculous strategically... Foreign intervention

would have inevitably followed ... probably beginning with NATO forces,

but with the direct or indirect support of the Warsaw Pact. But then

everything would once again have hinged on the European proletariat:

double or nothing. [SI Anthology, p. 235 [Revised Edition pp. 300–301]

(Beginning of an Era).]

Roughly speaking, the significance of armed struggle varies inversely

with the degree of economic development. In the most underdeveloped

countries social struggles tend to be reduced to military struggles,

because without arms there is little that the impoverished masses can do

that will not hurt them more than the rulers, especially when their

traditional self-sufficiency has been destroyed by a one-crop economy

geared for export. (But even if they win militarily, they can usually be

overpowered by foreign intervention or pressured into compliance with

the global economy, unless parallel revolutions elsewhere open up new

fronts.)

In more developed countries armed force has relatively less

significance, though it can, of course, still be an important factor at

certain critical junctures. It is possible, though not very efficient,

to force people to do simple manual labor at gunpoint. It is not

possible to do this with people who work with paper or computers within

a complex industrial society — there are too many opportunities for

troublesome yet untraceable “mistakes.” Modern capitalism requires a

certain amount of cooperation and even semicreative participation from

its workers. No large enterprise could function for a day without its

workers’ spontaneous self-organization, reacting to unforeseen problems,

compensating for managers’ mistakes, etc. If workers engage in a

“work-to-rule” strike in which they do nothing more than strictly follow

all the official regulations, the whole operation will be slowed down or

even brought to a complete halt (forcing the managers, who are unable to

openly condemn such strictness, into the amusingly awkward position of

having to hint to the workers that they should get on with their work

without being quite so rigorous). The system survives only because most

workers are relatively apathetic and, in order not to cause trouble for

themselves, cooperate enough to keep things going.

Isolated revolts may be repressed one at a time; but if a movement

spreads fast enough, as in May 1968, a few hundred thousand soldiers and

police can hardly do anything in the face of ten million striking

workers. Such a movement can be destroyed only from the inside. If the

people don’t know what they need to do, arms can scarcely help them; if

they do know, arms can scarcely stop them.

Only at certain moments are people “together” enough to revolt

successfully. The more lucid rulers know that they are safe if they can

only disperse such threats before they develop too much momentum and

self-awareness, whether by direct physical repression or by the various

sorts of diversion mentioned above. It hardly matters if the people

later find out that they were tricked, that they had victory in their

hands if they had only known it: once the opportunity has passed, it’s

too late.

Ordinary situations are full of confusions, but matters are generally

not so urgent. In a radical situation things are both simplified and

speeded up: the issues become clearer, but there is less time to resolve

them.

The extreme case is dramatized in a famous scene in Eisenstein’s

Potemkin. Mutinous sailors, heads covered by a tarp, have been lined up

to be shot. Guards aim their rifles and are given the order to fire. One

of the sailors cries out: “Brothers! Do you realize who you are

shooting?” The guards waver. The order is given again. After a

suspenseful hesitation the guards lower their weapons. They help the

sailors to raid the armory, together they turn against the officers, and

the battle is soon won.

Note that even in this violent showdown the outcome is more a matter of

consciousness than of brute power: once the guards come over to the

sailors, the fight is effectively over. (The remainder of Eisenstein’s

scene — a drawn-out struggle between an officer villain and a martyrized

revolutionary hero — is mere melodrama.) In contrast to war, in which

two distinct sides consciously oppose each other, “class struggle is not

just a battle waged against an external enemy, the bourgeoisie; it is

equally the struggle of the proletariat against itself: against the

devastating and degrading effects of the capitalist system on its class

consciousness” (Lukács, History and Class Consciousness). Modern

revolution has the peculiar quality that the exploited majority

automatically wins as soon as it becomes collectively aware of the game

it is playing. The proletariat’s opponent is ultimately nothing but the

product of its own alienated activity, whether in the economic form of

capital, the political form of party and union bureaucracies, or the

psychological form of spectacular conditioning. The rulers are such a

tiny minority that they would be immediately overwhelmed if they had not

managed to bamboozle a large portion of the population into identifying

with them, or at least into taking their system for granted; and

especially into becoming divided against each other.

The tarp, which dehumanizes the mutineers, making it easier for the

guards to shoot them, symbolizes this divide-and-rule tactic. The

“Brothers!” shout represents the countertactic of fraternization.

While fraternization refutes lies about what is happening elsewhere, its

greatest power probably stems from the emotional effect of direct human

encounter, which reminds soldiers that the insurgents are people not

essentially different from themselves. The state naturally tries to

prevent such contact by bringing in troops from other regions who are

unfamiliar with what has taken place and who, if possible, don’t even

speak the same language; and by quickly replacing them if they

nevertheless become too contaminated by rebellious ideas. (Some of the

Russian troops sent in to crush the 1956 Hungarian revolution were told

that they were in Germany and that the people confronting them in the

streets were resurgent Nazis!)

In order to expose and eliminate the most radical elements, a government

sometimes deliberately provokes a situation that will lead to an excuse

for violent repression. This is a dangerous game, however, because, as

in the Potemkin incident, forcing the issue may provoke the armed forces

to come over to the people. From the rulers’ standpoint, the optimum

strategy is to brandish just enough of a threat that there is no need to

risk the ultimate showdown. This worked in Poland in 1980–81. The

Russian bureaucrats knew that to invade Poland might bring about their

own downfall; but the constantly hinted threat of such an invasion

successfully intimidated the radical Polish workers, who could easily

have overthrown the state, into tolerating the persistence of

military-bureaucratic forces within Poland. The latter were eventually

able to repress the movement without having to call in the Russians.

Internationalism

“Those who make revolutions half way only dig their own graves.” A

revolutionary movement cannot attain some local victory and then expect

to peacefully coexist with the system until it’s ready to try for a

little more. All existing powers will put aside their differences in

order to destroy any truly radical popular movement before it spreads.

If they can’t crush it militarily, they’ll strangle it economically

(national economies are now so globally interdependent that no country

would be immune from such pressure). The only way to defend a revolution

is to extend it, both qualitatively and geographically. The only

guarantee against internal reaction is the most radical liberation of

every aspect of life. The only guarantee against external intervention

is the most rapid internationalization of the struggle.

The most profound expression of internationalist solidarity is, of

course, to make a parallel revolution in one’s own country (1848,

1917–1920, 1968). Short of this, the most urgent task is at least to

prevent counterrevolutionary intervention from one’s own country, as

when British workers pressured their government not to support the slave

states during the American Civil War (even though this meant greater

unemployment due to lack of cotton imports); or when Western workers

struck and mutinied against their governments’ attempts to support the

reactionary forces during the civil war following the Russian

revolution; or when people in Europe and America opposed their

countries’ repression of anticolonial revolts.

Unfortunately, even such minimal defensive efforts are few and far

between. Positive internationalist support is even more difficult. As

long as the rulers remain in control of the most powerful countries,

direct personal reinforcement is complicated and limited. Arms and other

supplies may be intercepted. Even communications sometimes don’t get

through until it’s too late.

One thing that does get through is an announcement that one group is

relinquishing its power or claims over another. The 1936 fascist revolt

in Spain, for example, had one of its main bases in Spanish Morocco.

Many of Franco’s troops were Moroccan and the antifascist forces could

have exploited this fact by declaring Morocco independent, thereby

encouraging a revolt at Franco’s rear and dividing his forces. The

probable spread of such a revolt to other Arab countries would at the

same time have diverted Mussolini’s forces, which were supporting

Franco, to defend Italy’s North African possessions. But the leaders of

the Spanish Popular Front government rejected this idea for fear that

such an encouragement of anticolonialism would alarm France and England,

from whom they were hoping for aid. Needless to say this aid never came

anyway.[19]

Similarly, if, before the Khomeiniists had been able to consolidate

their power, the insurgent Iranians in 1979 had supported total autonomy

for the Kurds, Baluchis and Azerbaijans, this would have won them as

firm allies of the most radical Iranian tendencies and might have spread

the revolution to the adjacent countries where overlapping portions of

those peoples live, while simultaneously undermining the Khomeiniist

reactionaries in Iran.

Encouraging others’ autonomy does not imply supporting any organization

or regime that might take advantage of it. It’s simply a matter of

leaving the Moroccans, the Kurds, or whomever to work out their own

affairs. The hope is that the example of an antihierarchical revolution

in one country will inspire others to contest their own hierarchies.

It’s our only hope, but not an entirely unrealistic one. The contagion

of a genuinely liberated movement should never be underestimated.

Chapter 4: Rebirth

“It will, of course, be said that such a scheme as is set forth here is

quite impractical, and goes against human nature. This is perfectly

true. It is impractical, and it goes against human nature. This is why

it is worth carrying out, and that is why one proposes it. For what is a

practical scheme? A practical scheme is either a scheme that is already

in existence, or a scheme that could be carried out under existing

conditions. But it is exactly the existing conditions that one objects

to; and any scheme that could accept these conditions is wrong and

foolish. The conditions will be done away with, and human nature will

change. The only thing that one really knows about human nature is that

it changes. Change is the one quality we can predicate of it. The

systems that fail are those that rely on the permanency of human nature,

and not on its growth and development.”

— Oscar Wilde, The Soul of Man Under Socialism

Utopians fail to envision postrevolutionary diversity

Marx considered it presumptuous to attempt to predict how people would

live in a liberated society. “It will be up to those people to decide

if, when and what they want to do about it, and what means to employ. I

don’t feel qualified to offer them any advice on this matter. They will

presumably be at least as clever as we are” (letter to Kautsky, 1

February 1881). His modesty in this regard compares favorably with those

who accuse him of arrogance and authoritarianism while themselves not

hesitating to project their own fancies into pronouncements as to what

such a society can or cannot be.

It is true, however, that if Marx had been a little more explicit about

what he envisioned, it would have been that much more difficult for

Stalinist bureaucrats to pretend to be implementing his ideas. An exact

blueprint of a liberated society is neither possible nor necessary, but

people must have some sense of its nature and feasibility. The belief

that there is no practical alternative to the present system is one of

the things that keeps people resigned.

Utopian speculations can help free us from the habit of taking the

status quo for granted, get us thinking about what we really want and

what might be possible. What makes them “utopian” in the pejorative

sense that Marx and Engels criticized is the failure to take present

conditions into consideration. There is usually no serious notion of how

we might get from here to there. Ignoring the system’s repressive and

cooptive powers, utopian authors generally envision some simplistic

cumulative change, imagining that, with the spread of utopian

communities or utopian ideas, more and more people will be inspired to

join in and the old system will simply collapse.

I hope the present text has given some more realistic ideas of how a new

society might come about. In any case, at this point I am going to jump

ahead and do a little speculating myself.

To simplify matters, let us assume that a victorious revolution has

spread throughout the world without too much destruction of basic

infrastructures, so that we no longer need to take into consideration

problems of civil war, threats of outside intervention, the confusions

of disinformation or the delays of massive emergency reconstruction, and

can examine some of the issues that might come up in a new,

fundamentally transformed society.

Though for clarity of expression I will use the future tense rather than

the conditional, the ideas presented here are simply possibilities to

consider, not prescriptions or predictions. If such a revolution ever

happens, a few years of popular experimentation will change so many of

the variables that even the boldest predictions will soon seem laughably

timid and unimaginative. All we can reasonably do is try to envision the

problems we will confront at the very beginning and some of the main

tendencies of further developments. But the more hypotheses we explore,

the more possibilities we will be prepared for and the less likely we

will be to unconsciously revert to old patterns.

Far from being too extravagant, most fictional utopias are too narrow,

generally being limited to a monolithic implementation of the author’s

pet ideas. As Marie Louise Berneri notes in the best survey of the field

(Journey Through Utopia), “All utopias are, of course, the expression of

personal preferences, but their authors usually have the conceit to

assume that their personal tastes should be enacted into laws; if they

are early risers the whole of their imaginary community will have to get

up at four o’clock in the morning; if they dislike women’s make-up, to

use it is made a crime; if they are jealous husbands infidelity will be

punished by death.”

If there is one thing that can be confidently predicted about the new

society, it is that it will be far more diverse than any one person’s

imagination or any possible description. Different communities will

reflect every sort of taste — aesthetic and scientific, mystical and

rationalist, hightech and neoprimitive, solitary and communal,

industrious and lazy, spartan and epicurean, traditional and

experimental — continually evolving in all sorts of new and

unforeseeable combinations.[20]

Decentralization and coordination

There will be a strong tendency toward decentralization and local

autonomy. Small communities promote habits of cooperation, facilitate

direct democracy, and make possible the richest social experimentation:

if a local experiment fails, only a small group is hurt (and others can

help out); if it succeeds it will be imitated and the advantage will

spread. A decentralized system is also less vulnerable to accidental

disruption or to sabotage. (The latter danger, however, will probably be

negligible in any case: it’s unlikely that a liberated society will have

anywhere near the immense number of bitter enemies that are constantly

produced by the present one.)

But decentralization can also foster hierarchical control by isolating

people from each other. And some things can best be organized on a large

scale. One big steel factory is more energy-efficient and less damaging

to the environment than a smelting furnace in every community.

Capitalism has tended to overcentralize in some areas where greater

diversity and self-sufficiency would make more sense, but its irrational

competition has also fragmented many things that could more sensibly be

standardized or centrally coordinated. As Paul Goodman notes in People

or Personnel (which is full of interesting examples of the pros and cons

of decentralization in various present-day contexts), where, how and how

much to decentralize are empirical questions that will require

experimentation. About all we can say is that the new society will

probably decentralize as much as possible, but without making a fetish

of it. Most things can be taken care of by small groups or local

communities; regional and global councils will be limited to matters

with broad ramifications or significant efficiencies of scale, such as

environmental restoration, space exploration, dispute resolution,

epidemic control, coordination of global production, distribution,

transportation and communication, and maintenance of certain specialized

facilities (e.g. hightech hospitals or research centers).

It is often said that direct democracy may have worked well enough in

the old-fashioned town meeting, but that the size and complexity of

modern societies make it impossible. How can millions of people each

express their own viewpoint on every issue?

They don’t need to. Most practical matters ultimately come down to a

limited number of options; once these have been stated and the most

significant arguments have been advanced, a decision can be reached

without further ado. Observers of the 1905 soviets and the 1956

Hungarian workers councils were struck by the brevity of people’s

statements and the rapidity with which decisions were arrived at. Those

who spoke to the point tended to get delegated; those who spouted hot

air got flak for wasting people’s time.

For more complicated matters, committees can be elected to look into

various possibilities and report back to the assemblies about the

ramifications of different options. Once a plan is adopted, smaller

committees can continue to monitor developments, notifying the

assemblies of any relevant new factors that might suggest modifying it.

On controversial issues multiple committees reflecting opposing

perspectives (e.g. protech versus antitech) might be set up to

facilitate the formulation of alternative proposals and dissenting

viewpoints. As always, delegates will not impose any decisions (except

regarding the organization of their own work) and will be elected on a

rotating and recallable basis, so as to ensure both that they do a good

job and that their temporary responsibilities don’t go to their heads.

Their work will be open to public scrutiny and final decisions will

always revert to the assemblies.

Modern computer and telecommunication technologies will make it possible

for anyone to instantly check data and projections for themselves, as

well as to widely communicate their own proposals. Despite current hype,

such technologies do not automatically promote democratic participation;

but they have the potential to facilitate it if they are appropriately

modified and put under popular control.[21]

Telecommunications will also render delegates less necessary than during

previous radical movements, when they functioned to a great extent as

mere bearers of information back and forth. Diverse proposals could be

circulated and discussed ahead of time, and if an issue was of

sufficient interest council meetings could be hooked up live with local

assemblies, enabling the latter to immediately confirm, modify or

repudiate delegate decisions.

But when the issues are not particularly controversial, mandating will

probably be fairly loose. Having arrived at some general decision (e.g.

“This building should be remodeled to serve as a daycare center”), an

assembly might simply call for volunteers or elect a committee to

implement it without bothering with detailed accountability.

Safeguards against abuses

Idle purists can always envision possible abuses. “Aha! Who knows what

subtle elitist maneuvers these delegates and technocratic specialists

may pull off!” The fact remains that large numbers of people cannot

directly oversee every detail at every moment. Any society has to rely

to some extent on people’s good will and common sense. The point is that

abuses are far less possible under generalized self-management than

under any other form of social organization.

People who have been autonomous enough to inaugurate a self-managed

society will naturally be alert to any reemergence of hierarchy. They

will note how delegates carry out their mandates, and rotate them as

often as practicable. For some purposes they may, like the ancient

Athenians, choose delegates by lot so as to eliminate the

popularity-contest and deal-making aspects of elections. In matters

requiring technical expertise they will keep a wary eye on the experts

until the necessary knowledge is more widely disseminated or the

technology in question is simplified or phased out. Skeptical observers

will be designated to sound the alarm at the first sign of chicanery. A

specialist who provides false information will be quickly found out and

publicly discredited. The slightest hint of any hierarchical plot or of

any exploitive or monopolistic practice will arouse universal outrage

and be eliminated by ostracism, confiscation, physical repression or

whatever other means are found necessary.

These and other safeguards will always be available to those worried

about potential abuses, but I doubt if they will often be necessary. On

any serious issue people can insist on as much mandating or monitoring

as they want to bother with. But in most cases they will probably give

delegates a reasonable amount of leeway to use their own judgment and

creativity.

Generalized self-management avoids both the hierarchical forms of the

traditional left and the more simplistic forms of anarchism. It is not

bound to any ideology, even an “antiauthoritarian” one. If a problem

turns out to require some specialized expertise or some degree of

“leadership,” the people involved will soon find this out and take

whatever steps they consider appropriate to deal with it, without

worrying about whether present-day radical dogmatists would approve. For

certain uncontroversial functions they might find it most convenient to

appoint specialists for indefinite periods of time, removing them only

in the unlikely event that they abuse their position. In certain

emergency situations in which quick, authoritative decisions are

essential (e.g. fire-fighting) they will naturally grant to designated

persons whatever temporary authoritarian powers are needed.

Consensus, majority rule and unavoidable hierarchies

But such cases will be exceptional. The general rule will be consensus

when practicable, majority decision when necessary. A character in

William Morris’s News from Nowhere (one of the most sensible, easygoing

and down-to-earth utopias) gives the example of whether a metal bridge

should be replaced by a stone one. At the next Mote (community assembly)

this is proposed. If there is a clear consensus, the issue is settled

and they proceed to work out the details of implementation. But

if a few of the neighbors disagree to it, if they think that the beastly

iron bridge will serve a little longer and they don’t want to be

bothered with building a new one just then, they don’t count heads that

time, but put off the formal discussion to the next Mote; and meantime

arguments pro and con are flying about, and some get printed, so that

everybody knows what is going on; and when the Mote comes together again

there is a regular discussion and at last a vote by show of hands. If

the division is a close one, the question is again put off for further

discussion; if the division is a wide one, the minority are asked if

they will yield to the more general opinion, which they often, nay, most

commonly do. If they refuse, the question is debated a third time, when,

if the minority has not perceptibly grown, they always give way; though

I believe there is some half-forgotten rule by which they might still

carry it on further; but I say, what always happens is that they are

convinced, not perhaps that their view is the wrong one, but they cannot

persuade or force the community to adopt it.

Note that what enormously simplifies cases like this is that there are

no longer any conflicting economic interests — no one has any means or

any motive to bribe or bamboozle people into voting one way or the other

because he happens to have a lot of money, or to control the media, or

to own a construction company or a parcel of land near a proposed site.

Without such conflicts of interest, people will naturally incline to

cooperation and compromise, if only to placate opponents and make life

easier for themselves. Some communities might have formal provisions to

accommodate minorities (e.g. if, instead of merely voting no, 20%

express a “vehement objection” to some proposal, it must pass by a 60%

majority); but neither side will be likely to abuse such formal powers

lest it be treated likewise when the situations are reversed. The main

solution for repeated irreconcilable conflicts will lie in the wide

diversity of cultures: if people who prefer metal bridges, etc.,

constantly find themselves outvoted by Morris-type arts-and-crafts

traditionalists, they can always move to some neighboring community

where more congenial tastes prevail.

Insistence on total consensus makes sense only when the number of people

involved is relatively small and the issue is not urgent. Among any

large number of people complete unanimity is rarely possible. It is

absurd, out of worry over possible majority tyranny, to uphold a

minority’s right to constantly obstruct a majority; or to imagine that

such problems will go away if we leave things “unstructured.”

As was pointed out in a well-known article many years ago (Jo Freeman’s

“The Tyranny of Structurelessness”), there’s no such thing as a

structureless group, there are simply different types of structures. An

unstructured group generally ends up being dominated by a clique that

does have some effective structure. The unorganized members have no

means of controlling such an elite, especially when their

antiauthoritarian ideology prevents them from admitting that it exists.

Failing to acknowledge majority rule as a backup when unanimity is not

attainable, anarchists and consensists are often unable to arrive at

practical decisions except by following those de facto leaders who are

skilled at maneuvering people into unanimity (if only by their capacity

to endure interminable meetings until all the opposition has got bored

and gone home). Fastidiously rejecting workers councils or anything else

with any taint of coercion, they themselves usually end up settling for

far less radical lowest-common-denominator projects.

It’s easy to point out shortcomings in the workers councils of the past,

which were, after all, just hurried improvisations by people involved in

desperate struggles. But if those brief efforts were not perfect models

to blindly imitate, they nevertheless represent the most practical step

in the right direction that anyone has come up with so far. Riesel’s

article on councils (SI Anthology, pp. 270–282 [Revised Edition pp.

348–362]) discusses the limitations of these old movements, and rightly

stresses that council power should be understood as the sovereignty of

the popular assemblies as a whole, not merely of the councils of

delegates they have elected. Some groups of radical workers in Spain,

wishing to avoid any ambiguity on this latter point, have referred to

themselves as “assemblyists” rather than “councilists.” One of the CMDO

leaflets (SI Anthology, p. 351 [Revised Edition p. 444] [Address to All

Workers]) specifies the following essential features of councilist

democracy:

them

liberated life

Once these features are recognized and implemented, it will make little

difference whether people refer to the new form of social organization

as “anarchy,” “communalism,” “communist anarchism,” “council communism,”

“libertarian communism,” “libertarian socialism,” “participatory

democracy” or “generalized self-management,” or whether its various

overlapping components are termed “workers councils,” “antiwork

councils,” “revolutionary councils,” “revolutionary assemblies,”

“popular assemblies,” “popular committees,” “communes,” “collectives,”

“kibbutzes,” “bolos,” “motes,” “affinity groups,” or anything else.

(“Generalized self-management” is unfortunately not very catchy, but it

has the advantage of referring to both means and goal while being free

of the misleading connotations of terms like “anarchy” or “communism.”)

In any case, it’s important to remember that large-scale formal

organization will be the exception. Most local matters can be handled

directly and informally. Individuals or small groups will simply go

ahead and do what seems appropriate in any given situation

(“adhocracy”). Majority rule will merely be a last resort in the

progressively diminishing number of cases in which conflicts of interest

cannot otherwise be resolved.

A nonhierarchical society does not mean that everyone magically becomes

equally talented or must participate equally in everything; it simply

means that materially based and reinforced hierarchies have been

eliminated. Although differences of abilities will undoubtedly diminish

when everyone is encouraged to develop their fullest potentials, the

point is that whatever differences remain will no longer be transformed

into differences of wealth or power.

People will be able to take part in a far wider range of activities than

they do now, but they won’t have to rotate all positions all the time if

they don’t feel like it. If someone has a special taste and knack for a

certain task, others will probably be happy to let her do it as much as

she wants — at least until someone else wants a shot at it. “Independent

specializations” (monopolistic control over socially vital information

or technologies) will be abolished; open, nondominating specializations

will flourish. People will still ask more knowledgeable persons for

advice when they feel the need for it (though if they are curious or

suspicious they will always be encouraged to investigate for

themselves). They will still be free to voluntarily submit themselves as

students to a teacher, apprentices to a master, players to a coach or

performers to a director — remaining equally free to discontinue the

relation at any time. In some activities, such as group folksinging,

anyone can join right in; others, such as performing a classical

concerto, may require rigorous training and coherent direction, with

some people taking leading roles, others following, and others being

happy just to listen. There should be plenty of opportunity for both

types. The situationist critique of the spectacle is a critique of an

excessive tendency in present society; it does not imply that everyone

must be an “active participant” twenty-four hours a day.

Apart from the care necessary for mental incompetents, the only

unavoidable enforced hierarchy will be the temporary one involved in

raising children until they are capable of managing their own affairs.

But in a safer and saner world children could be given considerably more

freedom and autonomy than they are now. When it comes to openness to the

new playful possibilities of life, adults may learn as much from them as

vice versa. Here as elsewhere, the general rule will be to let people

find their own level: a ten-year-old who takes part in some project

might have as much say in it as her adult co-participants, while a

nonparticipating adult will have none.

Self-management does not require that everyone be geniuses, merely that

most people not be total morons. It’s the present system that makes

unrealistic demands — pretending that the people it systematically

imbecilizes are capable of judging between the programs of rival

politicians or the advertising claims of rival commodities, or of

engaging in such complex and consequential activities as raising a child

or driving a car on a busy freeway. With the supersession of all the

political and economic pseudoissues that are now intentionally kept

incomprehensible, most matters will turn out not to be all that

complicated.

When people first get a chance to run their own lives they will

undoubtedly make lots of mistakes; but they will soon discover and

correct them because, unlike hierarchs, they will have no interest in

covering them up. Self-management does not guarantee that people will

always make the right decisions; but any other form of social

organization guarantees that someone else will make the decisions for

them.

Eliminating the roots of war and crime

The abolition of capitalism will eliminate the conflicts of interest

that now serve as a pretext for the state. Most present-day wars are

ultimately based on economic conflicts; even ostensibly ethnic,

religious or ideological antagonisms usually derive much of their real

motivation from economic competition, or from psychological frustrations

that are ultimately linked to political and economic repression. As long

as desperate competition prevails, people can easily be manipulated into

reverting to their traditional groupings and squabbling over cultural

differences they wouldn’t bother about under more comfortable

circumstances. War involves far more work, hardship and risk than any

form of constructive activity; people with real opportunities for

fulfillment will have more interesting things to do.

The same is true for crime. Leaving aside victimless “crimes,” the vast

majority of crimes are directly or indirectly related to money and will

become meaningless with the elimination of the commodity system.

Communities will then be free to experiment with various methods for

dealing with whatever occasional antisocial acts might still occur.

There are all sorts of possibilities. The persons involved might argue

their cases before the local community or a “jury” chosen by lot, which

would strive for the most reconciling and rehabilitating solutions. A

convicted offender might be “condemned” to some sort of public service —

not to intentionally unpleasant and demeaning shitwork administered by

petty sadists, which simply produces more anger and resentment, but to

meaningful and potentially engaging projects that might introduce him to

healthier interests (ecological restoration, for example). A few

incorrigible psychotics might have to be humanely restrained in one way

or another, but such cases would become increasingly rare. (The present

proliferation of “gratuitous” violence is a predictable reaction to

social alienation, a way for those who are not treated as real persons

to at least get the grim satisfaction of being recognized as real

threats.) Ostracism will be a simple and effective deterrent: the thug

who laughs at the threat of harsh punishment, which only confirms his

macho prestige, will be far more deterred if he knows that everyone will

give him the cold shoulder. In the rare case where that proves

inadequate, the variety of cultures might make banishment a workable

solution: a violent character who was constantly disturbing a quiet

community might fit in fine in some more rough-and-tumble, Wild

West-type region — or face less gentle retaliation.

Those are just a few of the possibilities. Liberated people will

undoubtedly come up with more creative, effective and humane solutions

than any we can presently imagine. I don’t claim that there will be no

problems, only that there will be far fewer problems than there are now,

when people who happen to find themselves at the bottom of an absurd

social order are harshly punished for their crude efforts to escape,

while those at the top loot the planet with impunity.

The barbarity of the present penal system is surpassed only by its

stupidity. Draconian punishments have repeatedly been shown to have no

significant effect on the crime rate, which is directly linked to levels

of poverty and unemployment as well as to less quantifiable but equally

obvious factors like racism, the destruction of urban communities, and

the general alienation produced by the commodity-spectacle system. The

threat of years in prison, which might be a powerful deterrent to

someone with a satisfying life, means little to those with no meaningful

alternatives. It is hardly very brilliant to slash already pitifully

inadequate social programs in the name of economizing, while filling

prisons with lifers at a cost of close to a million dollars each; but

like so many other irrational social policies, this trend persists

because it is reinforced by powerful vested interests.[22]

Abolishing money

A liberated society must abolish the whole money-commodity economy. To

continue to accept the validity of money would amount to accepting the

continued dominance of those who had previously accumulated it, or who

had the savvy to reaccumulate it after any radical reapportionment.

Alternative forms of “economic” reckoning will still be needed for

certain purposes, but their carefully limited scope will tend to

diminish as increasing material abundance and social cooperativity

render them less necessary.

A postrevolutionary society might have a three-tier economic setup along

the following lines:

without any accounting whatsoever.

“credits.”

Unlike money, credits will be applicable only to certain specified

goods, not to basic communal property such as land, utilities or means

of production. They will also probably have expiration dates to limit

any excessive accumulation.

Such a setup will be quite flexible. During the initial transition

period the amount of free goods might be fairly minimal — just enough to

enable a person to get by — with most goods requiring earning credits

through work. As time goes on, less and less work will be necessary and

more and more goods will become freely available — the tradeoff between

the two factors always remaining up to the councils to determine. Some

credits might be generally distributed, each person periodically

receiving a certain amount; others might be bonuses for certain types of

dangerous or unpleasant work where there is a shortage of volunteers.

Councils might set fixed prices for certain luxuries, while letting

others follow supply and demand; as a luxury becomes more abundant it

will become cheaper, perhaps eventually free. Goods could be shifted

from one tier to another depending on material conditions and community

preferences.

Those are just some of the possibilities.[23] Experimenting with

different methods, people will soon find out for themselves what forms

of ownership, exchange and reckoning are necessary.

In any case, whatever “economic” problems may remain will not be serious

because scarcity-imposed limits will be a factor only in the sector of

inessential “luxuries.” Free universal access to food, clothing,

housing, utilities, health care, transportation, communication,

education and cultural facilities could be achieved almost immediately

in the industrialized regions and within a fairly short period in the

less developed ones. Many of these things already exist and merely need

to be made more equitably available; those that don’t can easily be

produced once social energy is diverted from irrational enterprises.

Take housing, for example. Peace activists have frequently pointed out

that everyone in the world could be decently housed at less than the

cost of a few weeks of global military expenditure. They are no doubt

envisioning a fairly minimal sort of dwelling; but if the amount of

energy people now waste earning the money to enrich landlords and real

estate speculators was diverted to building new dwellings, everyone in

the world could soon be housed very decently indeed.

To begin with, most people might continue living where they are now and

concentrate on making dwellings available for homeless people. Hotels

and office buildings could be taken over. Certain outrageously

extravagant estates might be requisitioned and turned into dwellings,

parks, communal gardens, etc. Seeing this trend, those possessing

relatively spacious properties might offer to temporarily quarter

homeless people while helping them build homes of their own, if only to

deflect potential resentment from themselves.

The next stage will be raising and equalizing the quality of dwellings.

Here as in other areas, the aim will probably not be a rigidly uniform

equality (“everyone must have a dwelling of such and such

specifications”), but people’s general sense of fairness, with problems

being dealt with on a flexible, case-by-case basis. If someone feels he

is getting the short end of the stick he can appeal to the general

community, which, if the grievance is not completely absurd, will

probably bend over backward to redress it. Compromises will have to be

worked out regarding who gets to live in exceptionally desirable areas

for how long. (They might be shared around by lot, or leased for limited

periods to the highest bidders in credit auctions, etc.) Such problems

may not be solved to everyone’s complete satisfaction, but they will

certainly be dealt with much more fairly than under a system in which

accumulation of magic pieces of paper enables one person to claim

“ownership” of a hundred buildings while others have to live on the

street.

Once basic survival needs are taken care of, the quantitative

perspective of labor time will be transformed into a qualitatively new

perspective of free creativity. A few friends may work happily building

their own home even if it takes them a year to accomplish what a

professional crew could do more efficiently in a month. Much more fun

and imagination and love will go into such projects, and the resulting

dwellings will be far more charming, variegated and personal than what

today passes for “decent.” A nineteenth-century rural French mailman

named Ferdinand Cheval spent all his spare time for several decades

constructing his own personal fantasy castle. People like Cheval are

considered eccentrics, but the only thing unusual about them is that

they continue to exercise the innate creativity we all have but are

usually induced to repress after early childhood. A liberated society

will have lots of this playful sort of “work”: personally chosen

projects that will be so intensely engaging that people will no more

think of keeping track of their “labor time” than they would of counting

caresses during lovemaking or trying to economize on the length of a

dance.

Absurdity of most present-day labor

Fifty years ago Paul Goodman estimated that less than ten percent of the

work then being done would satisfy our basic needs. Whatever the exact

figure (it would be even lower now, though it would of course depend on

precisely what we consider basic or reasonable needs), it is clear that

most present-day labor is absurd and unnecessary. With the abolition of

the commodity system, hundreds of millions of people now occupied with

producing superfluous commodities, or with advertising them, packaging

them, transporting them, selling them, protecting them or profiting from

them (salespersons, clerks, foremen, managers, bankers, stockbrokers,

landlords, labor leaders, politicians, police, lawyers, judges, jailers,

guards, soldiers, economists, ad designers, arms manufacturers, customs

inspectors, tax collectors, insurance agents, investment advisers, along

with their numerous underlings) will all be freed up to share the

relatively few actually necessary tasks.

Add the unemployed, who according to a recent UN report now constitute

over 30% of the global population. If this figure seems large it is

because it presumably includes prisoners, refugees, and many others who

are not usually counted in official unemployment statistics because they

have given up trying to look for work, such as those who are

incapacitated by alcoholism or drugs, or who are so nauseated by the

available job options that they put all their energy into evading work

through crimes and scams.

Add millions of old people who would love to engage in worthwhile

activities but who are now relegated to a boring, passive retirement.

And teenagers and even younger children, who would be excitedly

challenged by many useful and educational projects if they weren’t

confined to worthless schools designed to instill ignorant obedience.

Then consider the large component of waste even in undeniably necessary

work. Doctors and nurses, for example, spend a large portion of their

time (in addition to filling out insurance forms, billing patients,

etc.) trying with limited success to counteract all sorts of socially

induced problems such as occupational injuries, auto accidents,

psychological ailments and diseases caused by stress, pollution,

malnutrition or unsanitary living conditions, to say nothing of wars and

the epidemics that often accompany them — problems that will largely

disappear in a liberated society, leaving health-care providers free to

concentrate on basic preventive medicine.

Then consider the equally large amount of intentionally wasted labor:

make-work designed to keep people occupied; suppression of labor-saving

methods that might put one out of a job; working as slowly as one can

get away with; sabotaging machinery to exert pressure on bosses, or out

of simple rage and frustration. And don’t forget all the absurdities of

“Parkinson’s Law” (work expands to fill the time available), the “Peter

Principle” (people rise to their level of incompetence) and similar

tendencies that have been so hilariously satirized by C. Northcote

Parkinson and Laurence Peter.

Then consider how much wasted labor will be eliminated once products are

made to last instead of being designed to fall apart or go out of style

so that people have to keep buying new ones. (After a brief initial

period of high production to provide everyone with durable, high-quality

goods, many industries could be reduced to very modest levels — just

enough to keep those goods in repair, or to occasionally upgrade them

whenever some truly significant improvement is developed.)

Taking all these factors into consideration, it’s easy to see that in a

sanely organized society the amount of necessary labor could be reduced

to one or two days per week.

Transforming work into play

But such a drastic quantitative reduction will produce a qualitative

change. As Tom Sawyer discovered, when people are not forced to work,

even the most banal task may become novel and intriguing: the problem is

no longer how to get people to do it, but how to accommodate all the

volunteers. It would be unrealistic to expect people to work full time

at unpleasant and largely meaningless jobs without surveillance and

economic incentives; but the situation becomes completely different if

it’s a matter of putting in ten or fifteen hours a week on worthwhile,

varied, self-organized tasks of one’s choice.

Moreover, many people, once they are engaged in projects that interest

them, will not want to limit themselves to the minimum. This will reduce

necessary tasks to an even more minuscule level for others who may not

have such enthusiasms.

There’s no need to quibble about the term work. Wage work needs to be

abolished; meaningful, freely chosen work can be as much fun as any

other kind of play. Our present work usually produces practical results,

but not the ones we would have chosen, whereas our free time is mostly

confined to trivialities. With the abolition of wage labor, work will

become more playful and play more active and creative. When people are

no longer driven crazy by their work, they will no longer require

mindless, passive amusements to recover from it.

Not that there’s anything wrong with enjoying trivial pastimes; it’s

simply a matter of recognizing that much of their present appeal stems

from the absence of more fulfilling activities. Someone whose life lacks

real adventure may derive at least a little vicarious exoticism from

collecting artifacts from other times and places; someone whose work is

abstract and fragmented may go to great lengths to actually produce a

whole concrete object, even if that object is no more significant than a

model ship in a bottle. These and countless other hobbies reveal the

persistence of creative impulses that will really blossom when given

free play on a broader scale. Imagine how people who enjoy fixing up

their home or cultivating their garden will get into recreating their

whole community; or how the thousands of railroad enthusiasts will jump

at the chance to rebuild and operate improved versions of the rail

networks that will be one of the main ways to reduce automobile traffic.

When people are subjected to suspicion and oppressive regulations, they

naturally try to get away with doing as little as possible. In

situations of freedom and mutual trust there is a contrary tendency to

take pride in doing the best job possible. Although some tasks in the

new society will be more popular than others, the few really difficult

or unpleasant ones will probably get more than enough volunteers,

responding to the thrill of the challenge or the desire for

appreciation, if not out of a sense of responsibility. Even now many

people are happy to volunteer for worthy projects if they have the time;

far more will do so once they no longer have to constantly worry about

providing for the basic needs of themselves and their families. At

worst, the few totally unpopular tasks will have to be divided up into

the briefest practicable shifts and rotated by lot until they can be

automated. Or there might be auctions to see if anyone is willing to do

them for, say, five hours a week in lieu of the usual workload of ten or

fifteen; or for a few extra credits.

Uncooperative characters will probably be so rare that the rest of the

population may just let them be, rather than bothering to pressure them

into doing their small share. At a certain degree of abundance it

becomes simpler not to worry about a few possible abuses than to enlist

an army of timekeepers, accountants, inspectors, informers, spies,

guards, police, etc., to snoop around checking every detail and

punishing every infraction. It’s unrealistic to expect people to be

generous and cooperative when there isn’t much to go around; but a large

material surplus will create a large “margin of abuse,” so that it won’t

matter if some people do a little less than their share, or take a

little more.

The abolition of money will prevent anyone from taking much more than

their share. Most misgivings about the feasibility of a liberated

society rest on the ingrained assumption that money (and thus also its

necessary protector: the state) would still exist. This money-state

partnership creates unlimited possibilities for abuses (legislators

bribed to sneak loopholes into tax laws, etc.); but once it is abolished

both the motives and the means for such abuses will vanish. The

abstractness of market relations enables one person to anonymously

accumulate wealth by indirectly depriving thousands of others of basic

necessities; but with the elimination of money any significant

monopolization of goods would be too unwieldy and too visible.

Whatever other forms of exchange there may be in the new society, the

simplest and probably most common form will be gift-giving. The general

abundance will make it easy to be generous. Giving is fun and

satisfying, and it eliminates the bother of accounting. The only

calculation is that connected with healthy mutual emulation. “The

neighboring community donated such and such to a less well off region;

surely we can do the same.” “They put on a great party; let’s see if we

can do an even better one.” A little friendly rivalry (who can create

the most delicious new recipe, cultivate a superior vegetable, solve a

social problem, invent a new game) will benefit everyone, even the

losers.

A liberated society will probably function much like a potluck party.

Most people enjoy preparing a dish that will be enjoyed by others; but

even if a few people don’t bring anything there’s still plenty to go

around. It’s not essential that everyone contribute an exactly equal

share, because the tasks are so minimal and are spread around so widely

that no one is overburdened. Since everyone is openly involved, there’s

no need for checking up on people or instituting penalties for

noncompliance. The only element of “coercion” is the approval or

disapproval of the other participants: appreciation provides positive

reinforcement, while even the most inconsiderate person realizes that if

he consistently fails to contribute he will start getting funny looks

and might not be invited again. Organization is necessary only if some

problem turns up. (If there are usually too many desserts and not enough

main dishes, the group might decide to coordinate who will bring what.

If a few generous souls end up bearing an unfair share of the cleanup

work, a gentle prodding suffices to embarrass others into volunteering,

or else some sort of systematic rotation is worked out.)

Now, of course, such spontaneous cooperation is the exception, found

primarily where traditional communal ties have persisted, or among

small, self-selected groups of like-minded people in regions where

conditions are not too destitute. Out in the dog-eat-dog world people

naturally look out for themselves and are suspicious of others. Unless

the spectacle happens to stir them with some sentimental human-interest

story, they usually have little concern for those outside their

immediate circle. Filled with frustrations and resentments, they may

even take a malicious pleasure in spoiling other people’s enjoyments.

But despite everything that discourages their humanity, most people, if

given a chance, still like to feel that they are doing worthy things,

and they like to be appreciated for doing them. Note how eagerly they

seize the slightest opportunity to create a moment of mutual

recognition, even if only by opening a door for someone or exchanging a

few banal remarks. If a flood or earthquake or some other emergency

arises, even the most selfish and cynical person often plunges right in,

working twenty-four hours a day to rescue people, deliver food and

first-aid supplies, etc., without any compensation but others’

gratitude. This is why people often look back on wars and natural

disasters with what might seem like a surprising degree of nostalgia.

Like revolution, such events break through the usual social separations,

provide everyone with opportunities to do things that really matter, and

produce a strong sense of community (even if only by uniting people

against a common enemy). In a liberated society these sociable impulses

will be able to flourish without requiring such extreme pretexts.

Technophobic objections

Present-day automation often does little more than throw some people out

of work while intensifying the regimentation of those who remain; if any

time is actually gained by “labor-saving” devices, it is usually spent

in an equally alienated passive consumption. But in a liberated world

computers and other modern technologies could be used to eliminate

dangerous or boring tasks, freeing everyone to concentrate on more

interesting activities.

Disregarding such possibilities, and understandably disgusted by the

current misuse of many technologies, some people have come to see

“technology” itself as the main problem and advocate a return to a

simpler lifestyle. How much simpler is debated — as flaws are discovered

in each period, the dividing line keeps getting pushed farther back.

Some, considering the Industrial Revolution as the main villain,

disseminate computer-printed eulogies of hand craftsmanship. Others,

seeing the invention of agriculture as the original sin, feel we should

return to a hunter-gatherer society, though they are not entirely clear

about what they have in mind for the present human population which

could not be sustained by such an economy. Others, not to be outdone,

present eloquent arguments proving that the development of language and

rational thought was the real origin of our problems. Yet others contend

that the whole human race is so incorrigibly evil that it should

altruistically extinguish itself in order to save the rest of the global

ecosystem.

These fantasies contain so many obvious self-contradictions that it is

hardly necessary to criticize them in any detail. They have questionable

relevance to actual past societies and virtually no relevance to present

possibilities. Even supposing that life was better in one or another

previous era, we have to begin from where we are now. Modern technology

is so interwoven with all aspects of our life that it could not be

abruptly discontinued without causing a global chaos that would wipe out

billions of people. Postrevolutionary people will probably decide to

reduce human population and phase out certain industries, but this can’t

be done overnight. We need to seriously consider how we will deal with

all the practical problems that will be posed in the interim.

If it ever comes down to such a practical matter, I doubt if the

technophobes will really want to eliminate motorized wheelchairs; or

pull the plug on ingenious computer setups like the one that enables

physicist Stephen Hawking to communicate despite being totally

paralyzed; or allow a woman to die in childbirth who could be saved by

technical procedures; or accept the reemergence of diseases that used to

routinely kill or permanently disable a large percentage of the

population; or resign themselves to never visiting or communicating with

people in other parts of the world unless they’re within walking

distance; or stand by while people die in famines that could be averted

through global food shipments.

The problem is that meanwhile this increasingly fashionable ideology

deflects attention from real problems and possibilities. A simplistic

Manichean dualism (nature is Good, technology is Bad) enables people to

ignore complex historical and dialectical processes; it’s so much easier

to blame everything on some primordial evil, some sort of devil or

original sin. What begins as a valid questioning of excessive faith in

science and technology ends up as a desperate and even less justified

faith in the return of a primeval paradise, accompanied by a failure to

engage the present system in any but an abstract, apocalyptical way.[24]

Technophiles and technophobes are united in treating technology in

isolation from other social factors, differing only in their equally

simplistic conclusions that new technologies are automatically

empowering or automatically alienating. As long as capitalism alienates

all human productions into autonomous ends that escape the control of

their creators, technologies will share in that alienation and will be

used to reinforce it. But when people free themselves from this

domination, they will have no trouble rejecting those technologies that

are harmful while adapting others to beneficial uses.

Certain technologies — nuclear power is the most obvious example — are

indeed so insanely dangerous that they will no doubt be brought to a

prompt halt. Many other industries which produce absurd, obsolete or

superfluous commodities will, of course, cease automatically with the

disappearance of their commercial rationales. But many technologies

(electricity, metallurgy, refrigeration, plumbing, printing, recording,

photography, telecommunications, tools, textiles, sewing machines,

agricultural equipment, surgical instruments, anesthetics, antibiotics,

among dozens of other examples that will come to mind), however they may

presently be misused, have few if any inherent drawbacks. It’s simply a

matter of using them more sensibly, bringing them under popular control,

introducing a few ecological improvements, and redesigning them for

human rather than capitalistic ends.

Other technologies are more problematic. They will still be needed to

some extent, but their harmful and irrational aspects will be phased

out, usually by attrition. If one considers the automobile industry as a

whole, including its vast infrastructure (factories, streets, highways,

gas stations, oil wells) and all its inconveniences and hidden costs

(traffic jams, parking, repairs, insurance, accidents, pollution, urban

destruction), it is clear that any number of alternative methods would

be preferable. The fact remains that this infrastructure is already

there. The new society will thus undoubtedly continue to use existing

automobiles and trucks for a few years, while concentrating on

developing more sensible modes of transportation to gradually replace

them as they wear out. Personal vehicles with nonpolluting engines might

continue indefinitely in rural areas, but most present-day urban traffic

(with a few exceptions such as delivery trucks, fire engines,

ambulances, and taxis for disabled people) could be superseded by

various forms of public transit, enabling many freeways and streets to

be converted to parks, gardens, plazas and bike paths. Airplanes will be

retained for intercontinental travel (rationed if necessary) and for

certain kinds of urgent shipments, but the elimination of wage labor

will leave people with time for more leisurely modes of travel — boats,

trains, biking, hiking.

Here, as in other areas, it will be up to the people involved to

experiment with different possibilities to see what works best. Once

people are able to determine the aims and conditions of their own work,

they will naturally come up with all sorts of ideas that will make that

work briefer, safer and more pleasant; and such ideas, no longer

patented or jealously guarded as “business secrets,” will rapidly spread

and inspire further improvements. With the elimination of commercial

motives, people will also be able to give appropriate weight to social

and environmental factors along with purely quantitative labor-time

considerations. If, say, production of computers currently involves some

sweatshop labor or causes some pollution (though far less than classic

“smokestack” industries), there’s no reason to believe that better

methods cannot be figured out once people set their minds to it — very

likely precisely through a judicious use of computer automation.

(Fortunately, the more repetitive the job, the easier it usually is to

automate.)

The general rule will be to simplify basic manufactures in ways that

facilitate optimum flexibility. Techniques will be made more uniform and

understandable, so that people with a minimal general training will be

able to carry out construction, repairs, alterations and other

operations that formerly required specialized training. Basic tools,

appliances, raw materials, machine parts and architectural modules will

probably be standardized and mass-produced, leaving tailor-made

refinements to small-scale “cottage industries” and the final and

potentially most creative aspects to the individual users. Once time is

no longer money we may, as William Morris hoped, see a revival of

elaborate “labor”-intensive arts and crafts: joyful making and giving by

people who care about their creations and the people for whom they are

destined.

Some communities might choose to retain a fair amount of (ecologically

sanitized) heavy technology; others might opt for simpler lifestyles,

though backed up by technical means to facilitate that simplicity or for

emergencies. Solar-powered generators and satellite-linked

telecommunications, for example, would enable people to live off in the

woods with no need for power and telephone lines. If earth-based solar

power and other renewable energy sources proved insufficient, immense

solar receptors in orbit could beam down a virtually unlimited amount of

pollution-free energy.

Most Third World regions, incidentally, lie in the sun belt where solar

power can be most effective. Though their poverty will present some

initial difficulties, their traditions of cooperative self-sufficiency

plus the fact that they are not encumbered with obsolete industrial

infrastructures may give them some compensating advantages when it comes

to creating new, ecologically appropriate structures. By drawing

selectively on the developed regions for whatever information and

technologies they themselves decide they need, they will be able to skip

the horrible “classic” stage of industrialization and capital

accumulation and proceed directly to postcapitalist forms of social

organization. Nor will the influence necessarily be all one way: some of

the most advanced social experimentation in history was carried out

during the Spanish revolution by illiterate peasants living under

virtually Third World conditions.

Nor will people in developed regions need to accept a drab transitional

period of “lowered expectations” in order to enable less developed

regions to catch up. This common misconception stems from the false

assumption that most present-day products are desirable and necessary —

implying that more for others means less for ourselves. In reality, a

revolution in the developed countries will immediately supersede so many

absurd commodities and concerns that even if supplies of certain goods

and services are temporarily reduced, people will still be better off

than they are now even in material terms (in addition to being far

better off in “spiritual” terms). Once their own immediate problems are

taken care of, many of them will enthusiastically assist less fortunate

people. But this assistance will be voluntary, and most of it will not

entail any serious self-sacrifice. To donate labor or building materials

or architectural know-how so that others can build homes for themselves,

for example, will not require dismantling one’s own home. The potential

richness of modern society consists not only of material goods, but of

knowledge, ideas, techniques, inventiveness, enthusiasm, compassion, and

other qualities that are actually increased by being shared around.

Ecological issues

A self-managed society will naturally implement most present-day

ecological demands. Some are essential for the very survival of

humanity; but for both aesthetic and ethical reasons, liberated people

will undoubtedly choose to go well beyond this minimum and foster a rich

biodiversity.

The point is that we can debate such issues open-mindedly only when we

have eliminated the profit incentives and economic insecurity that now

undermine even the most minimal efforts to defend the environment

(loggers afraid of losing their jobs, chronic poverty tempting Third

World countries to cash in on their rain forests, etc.).[25]

When humanity as a species is blamed for environmental destruction, the

specific social causes are forgotten. The few who make the decisions are

lumped with the powerless majority. Famines are seen as nature’s revenge

against overpopulation, natural checks that must be allowed to run their

course — as if there was anything natural about the World Bank and the

International Monetary Fund, which force Third World countries to

cultivate products for export rather than food for local consumption.

People are made to feel guilty for using cars, ignoring the fact that

auto companies (by buying up and sabotaging electric transit systems,

lobbying for highway construction and against railroad subsidies, etc.)

have created a situation in which most people have to have cars.

Spectacular publicity gravely urges everyone to reduce energy

consumption (while constantly inciting everyone to consume more of

everything), though we could by now have developed more than enough

clean and renewable energy sources if the fossil-fuel companies had not

successfully lobbied against devoting any significant research funding

to that end.

The point is not to blame even the heads of those companies — they too

are caught in a grow-or-die system that impels them to make such

decisions — but to abolish the setup that continually produces such

irresistible pressures.

A liberated world should have room both for human communities and for

large enough regions of undisturbed wilderness to satisfy most of the

deep ecologists. Between those two extremes I like to think that there

will be all sorts of imaginative, yet careful and respectful, human

interactions with nature. Cooperating with it, working with it, playing

with it; creating variegated interminglings of forests, farms, parks,

gardens, orchards, creeks, villages, towns.

Large cities will be broken up, spaced out, “greened,” and rearranged in

a variety of ways incorporating and surpassing the visions of the most

imaginative architects and city planners of the past (who were usually

limited by their assumption of the permanence of capitalism).

Exceptionally, certain major cities, especially those of some aesthetic

or historical interest, will retain or even amplify their cosmopolitan

features, providing grand centers where diverse cultures and lifestyles

can come together.[26]

Some people, drawing on the situationists’ early “psychogeographical”

explorations and “unitary urbanism” ideas, will construct elaborate

changeable decors designed to facilitate labyrinthine wanderings among

diverse ambiences — Ivan Chtcheglov envisioned “assemblages of castles,

grottos, lakes,” “rooms more conducive to dreams than any drug,” and

people living in their own personal “cathedrals” (SI Anthology, pp. 3–4

[Revised Edition p. 6] [Formulary for a New Urbanism]). Others may

incline more to the Far Eastern poet’s definition of happiness as living

in a hut beside a mountain stream.

If there aren’t enough cathedrals or mountain streams to go around,

maybe some compromises will have to be worked out. But if places like

Chartres or Yosemite are presently overrun, this is only because the

rest of the planet has been so uglified. As other natural areas are

revitalized and as human habitats are made more beautiful and

interesting, it will no longer be necessary for a few exceptional sites

to accommodate millions of people desperate to get away from it all. On

the contrary, many people may actually gravitate toward the most

miserable regions because these will be the “new frontiers” where the

most exciting transformations will be taking place (ugly buildings being

demolished to make way for experimental reconstruction from scratch).

The blossoming of free communities

The liberation of popular creativity will generate lively communities

surpassing Athens, Florence, Paris and other famous centers of the past,

in which full participation was limited to privileged minorities. While

some people may choose to be relatively solitary and self-sufficient

(hermits and nomads will be free to keep to themselves except for a few

minimal arrangements with nearby communities), most will probably prefer

the pleasure and convenience of doing things together, and will set up

all sorts of public workshops, libraries, laboratories, laundries,

kitchens, bakeries, cafés, health clinics, studios, music rooms,

auditoriums, saunas, gyms, playgrounds, fairs, flea markets (without

forgetting some quiet spaces to counterbalance all the socializing).

City blocks might be converted into more unified complexes, connecting

outer buildings with hallways and arcades and removing fences between

back yards so as to create larger interior park, garden or nursery

areas. People could choose among various types and degrees of

participation, e.g. whether to sign up for a couple days per month of

cooking, dishwashing or gardening entitling them to eat at a communal

cafeteria, or to grow most of their own food and cook for themselves.

In all these hypothetical examples it’s important to bear in mind the

diversity of cultures that will develop. In one, cooking might be seen

as a tedious chore to be minimized as much as possible and precisely

apportioned; in another it might be a passion or a valued social ritual

that will attract more than enough enthusiastic volunteers.

Some communities, like Paradigm III in Communitas (allowing for the fact

that the Goodmans’ schema still assumes the existence of money), may

maintain a sharp distinction between the free sector and the luxury

sector. Others may develop more organically integrated social patterns,

along the lines of Paradigm II of the same book, striving for maximum

unity of production and consumption, manual and intellectual activity,

aesthetic and scientific education, social and psychological harmony,

even at the cost of purely quantitative efficiency. The Paradigm III

style might be most appropriate as a initial transitional form, when

people are not yet used to the new perspectives and want some fixed

economic frame of reference to give them a sense of security against

potential abuses. As people get the bugs out of the new system and

develop more mutual trust, they will probably tend more toward the

Paradigm II style.

As in Fourier’s charming fantasies, but minus his eccentricities and

with much more flexibility, people will be able to engage in a variety

of pursuits according to elaborately interrelated affinities. A person

might be a regular member of certain ongoing groupings (affinity group,

council, collective, neighborhood, town, region) while only temporarily

taking part in various ad hoc activities (as people do today in clubs,

hobbyist networks, mutual-aid associations, political-issue groups and

barnraising-type projects). Local assemblies will keep tallies of offers

and requests; make known the decisions of other assemblies and the

current state of projects in progress or problems yet unresolved; and

form libraries, switchboards and computer networks to gather and

disseminate information of all kinds and to link up people with common

tastes. Media will be accessible to everyone, enabling them to express

their own particular projects, problems, proposals, critiques,

enthusiasms, desires, visions. Traditional arts and crafts will

continue, but merely as one facet of continuously creative lives. People

will still take part, with more zest than ever, in sports and games,

fairs and festivals, music and dancing, lovemaking and child raising,

building and remodeling, teaching and learning, camping and traveling;

but new genres and arts of life will also develop that we can now hardly

imagine.

More than enough people will gravitate to socially necessary projects,

in agronomy, medicine, engineering, educational innovation,

environmental restoration and so on, for no other reason than that they

find them interesting and satisfying. Others may prefer less utilitarian

pursuits. Some will live fairly quiet domestic lives; others will go in

for daring adventures, or live it up in feasts and orgies; yet others

may devote themselves to bird-watching, or exchanging zines, or

collecting quaint memorabilia from prerevolutionary times, or any of a

million other pursuits. Everyone can follow their own inclinations. If

some sink into a passive spectator existence, they’ll probably

eventually get bored and try more creative ventures. Even if they don’t,

that will be their affair; it won’t harm anyone else.

For anyone who finds the earthly utopia too insipid and really wants to

get away from it all, the exploration and colonization of the solar

system — perhaps eventually even migration to other stars — will provide

a frontier that will never be exhausted.

But so will explorations of “inner space.”

More interesting problems

An antihierarchical revolution will not solve all our problems; it will

simply eliminate some of the anachronistic ones, freeing us to tackle

more interesting problems.

If the present text seems to neglect the “spiritual” aspects of life,

this is because I wanted to stress some basic material matters that are

often overlooked. But these material matters are only the framework. A

liberated society will be based far more on joy and love and spontaneous

generosity than on rigid rules or egoistic calculations. We can probably

get a more vivid sense of what it might be like from visionaries like

Blake or Whitman than from pedantic debates about economic credits and

recallable delegates.

I suspect that once people’s basic material needs are generously taken

care of and they are no longer subjected to a constant barrage of

commercial titillation, most of them (after brief binges of

overindulgence in things they were previously deprived of) will find the

greatest satisfaction in relatively simple and uncluttered lifestyles.

The erotic and gustatory arts will undoubtedly be enrichened in many

ways, but simply as facets of full, rounded lives that also include a

wide range of intellectual, aesthetic and spiritual pursuits.

Education, no longer limited to conditioning young people for a narrow

role in an irrational economy, will become an enthusiastic lifelong

activity. In addition to whatever formal educational institutions there

may still be, people will have instant access via books and computers to

information on any subject they wish to explore, and they’ll be able to

get hands-on experience in all sorts of arts and skills, or to seek out

anyone for personal instruction or discussion — like the ancient Greek

philosophers debating in the public marketplace, or the medieval Chinese

monks wandering the mountains in search of the most inspiring Zen

master.

The aspects of religion that now serve as mere psychological escapes

from social alienation will fade away, but the basic questions that have

found more or less distorted expression in religion will remain. There

will still be pains and losses, tragedies and frustrations, people will

still face sickness, old age and death. And in the process of trying to

figure out what, if anything, it all means, and how to deal with it,

some of them will rediscover what Aldous Huxley, in The Perennial

Philosophy, refers to as the “highest common factor” of human

consciousness.

Others may cultivate exquisite aesthetic sensibilities like the

characters in Murasaki’s Tale of Genji, or develop elaborate

metacultural genres like the “glass bead games” in Hermann Hesse’s novel

(freed from the material limits that formerly confined such pursuits to

narrow elites).

I like to think that as these diverse pursuits are alternated, combined

and developed, there will be a general tendency toward the personal

reintegration envisioned by Blake, and toward the genuine “I-Thou”

relations envisioned by Martin Buber. A permanent spiritual revolution

in which joyous communion does not preclude rich diversity and “generous

contention.” Leaves of Grass, Whitman’s wishful thinking about the

potentialities of the America of his day, perhaps comes as close as

anything to conveying the expansive state of mind of such communities of

fulfilled men and women, ecstatically working and playing, loving and

loitering, strolling down the never-ending Open Road.

With the proliferation of continually developing and mutating cultures,

travel could once again become an unpredictable adventure. The traveler

could “see the cities and learn the ways of many different peoples”

without the dangers and disappointments faced by the wanderers and

explorers of the past. Drifting from scene to scene, from encounter to

encounter; but occasionally stopping, like those barely visible human

figures in Chinese landscape paintings, just to gaze into the immensity,

realizing that all our doings and sayings are just ripples on the

surface of a vast, unfathomable universe.

These are just a few hints. We aren’t limited to radical sources of

inspiration. All sorts of creative spirits of the past have manifested

or envisioned some of our almost unlimited possibilities. We can draw on

any of them as long as we take care to extricate the relevant aspects

from their original alienated context.

The greatest works do not so much tell us something new as remind us of

things we have forgotten. We all have intimations of what life can be

like at its richest — memories from early childhood, when experiences

were still fresh and unrepressed, but also occasional later moments of

love or camaraderie or enthusiastic creativity, times when we can’t wait

to get up in the morning to continue some project, or simply to see what

the new day will bring. Extrapolating from these moments probably gives

the best idea of what the whole world could be like. A world, as Whitman

envisions it,

Where the men and women think lightly of the laws,

Where the slave ceases, and the master of slaves ceases,

Where the populace rise at once against the never-ending audacity

of elected persons, ...

Where children are taught to be laws to themselves, and to depend

on themselves,

Where equanimity is illustrated in affairs,

Where speculations on the soul are encouraged,

Where women walk in public processions in the streets the same as

the men,

Where they enter the public assembly and take places the same as

the men ...

The main shapes arise!

Shapes of Democracy total, result of centuries,

Shapes ever projecting other shapes,

Shapes of turbulent manly cities,

Shapes of the friends and home-givers of the whole earth,

Shapes bracing the earth and braced with the whole earth.

 

[1] Ken Knabb (ed. and trans.), Situationist International Anthology

(Bureau of Public Secrets, 1981), p. 81 [Revised Edition pp. 106–107]

[Geopolitics of Hibernation]. Here and elsewhere I have sometimes

slightly modified my original SI Anthology translations.

[2] See Maurice Brinton’s The Bolsheviks and Workers’ Control:

1917–1921, Voline’s The Unknown Revolution, Ida Mett’s The Kronstadt

Uprising, Paul Avrich’s Kronstadt 1921, Peter Arshinov’s History of the

Makhnovist Movement, and Guy Debord’s The Society of the Spectacle

§§98–113. (These and most of the other texts cited in this book can be

obtained through the distributors listed at the end of the Situationist

Bibliography.)

[3] “The journalists’ and governments’ superficial references to the

‘success’ or ‘failure’ of a revolution mean nothing for the simple

reason that since the bourgeois revolutions no revolution has yet

succeeded: not one has abolished classes. Proletarian revolution has so

far not been victorious anywhere, but the practical process through

which its project manifests itself has already created at least ten

revolutionary moments of historic importance that can appropriately be

termed revolutions. In none of these moments was the total content of

proletarian revolution fully developed; but in each case there was a

fundamental interruption of the ruling socioeconomic order and the

appearance of new forms and conceptions of real life: variegated

phenomena that can be understood and evaluated only in their overall

significance, including their potential future significance... The

revolution of 1905 did not bring down the Czarist regime, it only

obtained a few temporary concessions from it. The Spanish revolution of

1936 did not formally suppress the existing political power: it arose,

in fact, out of a proletarian uprising initiated in order to defend that

Republic against Franco. And the Hungarian revolution of 1956 did not

abolish Nagy’s liberal-bureaucratic government. Among other regrettable

limitations, the Hungarian movement had many aspects of a national

uprising against foreign domination; and this national-resistance aspect

also played a certain, though less important, role in the origin of the

Paris Commune. The Commune supplanted Thiers’s power only within the

limits of Paris. And the St. Petersburg Soviet of 1905 never even took

control of the capital. All the crises cited here as examples, though

deficient in their practical achievements and even in their

perspectives, nevertheless produced enough radical innovations and put

their societies severely enough in check to be legitimately termed

revolutions.” (SI Anthology, pp. 235–236 [Revised Edition pp. 301–302]

[Beginning of an Era].)

[4] “We’re not interested in hearing about the exploiters’ economic

problems. If the capitalist economy is not capable of fulfilling

workers’ demands, that is simply one more reason to struggle for a new

society, one in which we ourselves have the decisionmaking power over

the whole economy and all social life.” (Portuguese airline workers, 27

October 1974.)

[5] The SI’s dissemination of a text denouncing an international

gathering of art critics in Belgium was a fine example of this: “Copies

were mailed to a large number of critics or given to them personally.

Others were telephoned and read all or part of the text. A group forced

its way into the Press Club where the critics were being received and

threw the leaflets among the audience. Others were tossed onto the

sidewalks from upstairs windows or from a car... In short, all steps

were taken to leave the critics no chance of being unaware of the text.”

(SI Anthology, p. 49 [Revised Edition pp. 60–61] [Action in Belgium].)

[6] “The absence of a revolutionary movement in Europe has reduced the

Left to its simplest expression: a mass of spectators who swoon with

rapture each time the exploited in the colonies take up arms against

their masters, and who cannot help seeing these uprisings as the epitome

of Revolution... Wherever there is a conflict they always see Good

fighting Evil, ‘total revolution’ versus ‘total reaction.’ ...

Revolutionary criticism begins beyond good and evil; it is rooted in

history and operates on the totality of the existing world. In no case

can it applaud a belligerent state or support the bureaucracy of an

exploitive state in the process of formation... It is obviously

impossible at present to seek a revolutionary solution to the Vietnam

war. It is first of all necessary to put an end to the American

aggression in order to allow the real social struggle in Vietnam to

develop in a natural way; i.e. to allow the Vietnamese workers and

peasants to rediscover their enemies at home: the bureaucracy of the

North and the propertied and ruling strata of the South. Once the

Americans withdraw, the Stalinist bureaucracy will seize control of the

whole country — there’s no getting around this... The point is not to

give unconditional (or even conditional) support to the Vietcong, but to

struggle consistently and uncompromisingly against American

imperialism.” (SI Anthology, pp. 195–196, 203 [Revised Edition pp.

252–253, 262] [Two Local Wars].)

[7] “In its mystified form, dialectics became the fashion in Germany

because it seemed to transfigure and glorify the existing state of

things. In its rational form it is a scandal and abomination to

bourgeois society and its doctrinaire professors, because in

comprehending the existing state of things it simultaneously recognizes

the negation of that state, its inevitable breaking up; because it sees

the fluid movement of every historically developed social form, and

therefore takes into account its transience as well as its momentary

existence; because it lets nothing impose on it, and is in its essence

critical and revolutionary.” (Marx, Capital.)

The split between Marxism and anarchism crippled both sides. The

anarchists rightly criticized the authoritarian and narrowly economistic

tendencies in Marxism, but they generally did so in an undialectical,

moralistic, ahistorical manner, contraposing various absolute dualisms

(Freedom versus Authority, Individualism versus Collectivism,

Centralization versus Decentralization, etc.) and leaving Marx and a few

of the more radical Marxists with a virtual monopoly on coherent

dialectical analysis — until the situationists finally brought the

libertarian and dialectical aspects back together again. On the merits

and flaws of Marxism and anarchism see The Society of the Spectacle

§§78–94.

[8] “What surfaced this spring in Zurich as a demonstration against the

closing of a youth center has crept across Switzerland, feeding on the

restlessness of a young generation anxious to break out of what they see

as a suffocating society. ‘We don’t want a world where the guarantee of

not dying of hunger is paid for by the certainty of dying of boredom,’

proclaim banners and spray-painted storefronts in Lausanne.” (Christian

Science Monitor, 28 October 1980.) The slogan is from Vaneigem’s The

Revolution of Everyday Life.

[9] For some hilarious examples see Henry Beard and Christopher Cerf’s

The Official Politically Correct Dictionary and Handbook (Villard,

1992): it’s often hard to tell which of the Correctspeak terms are

satirical and which have actually been seriously proposed or even

officially adopted and enforced. The only antidote to such delirium is a

lot of healthy guffaws.

[10] On the Cultural Revolution, see SI Anthology, pp. 185–194 [Revised

Edition pp. 240–251] [The Explosion Point of Ideology in China], and

Simon Leys’s The Chairman’s New Clothes.

[11] “As Shiites and Kurds battle the regime of Saddam Hussein and Iraqi

opposition parties try to patch together a democratic future, the United

States finds itself in the awkward position of, in effect, supporting

continuing one-party rule in Iraq. US government statements, including

those of President Bush, have stressed the desire to see Saddam Hussein

overthrown, but not to see Iraq broken apart by civil strife. At the

same time, Bush administration officials have insisted that democracy is

not currently a viable alternative for Iraq... This may account for the

fact that thus far, the administration has refused to meet with Iraqi

opposition leaders in exile ... ‘The Arabs and the US have the same

agenda,’ says a coalition diplomat. ‘We want Iraq in the same borders

and Saddam to disappear. But we will accept Saddam in Baghdad in order

to have Iraq as one state.’” (Christian Science Monitor, 20 March 1991.)

[12] “I am flabbergasted at the memory people retain of their own

revolutionary past. Present events have shaken that memory. Dates never

learned at school, songs never sung openly, are recalled in their

totality... The noise, the noise, the noise is still ringing in my ears.

The horns tooting in joy, the shouting, the slogans, the singing and

dancing. The doors of revolution seem open again, after forty-eight

years of repression. In that single day everything was replaced in

perspective. Nothing was god-given, all was man-made. People could see

their misery and their problems in a historical setting... A week has

passed, although it already feels like many months. Every hour has been

lived to the full. It is already difficult to remember what the papers

looked like before, or what people had then said. Hadn’t there always

been a revolution?” (Phil Mailer, Portugal: The Impossible Revolution?)

[13] One of the most powerful moments was when the sitdowners around the

police car averted a potentially violent confrontation with a mob of

fraternity hecklers by remaining totally silent for half an hour. With

the wind taken out of their sails, the hecklers became bored and

embarrassed, and eventually dispersed. Such collective silence has the

advantage of dissolving compulsive reactions on both sides; yet because

it is nonspecific it does this without the dubious content of many

slogans and songs. (Singing “We Shall Overcome” has also served to calm

people in difficult situations, but at the cost of sentimentalizing

reality.)

The best account of the FSM is David Lance Goines’s The Free Speech

Movement (Ten Speed Press, 1993).

[14] On May 1968 see SI Anthology, pp. 225–256, 343–352 [Revised Edition

pp. 288–325, 435–457] [The Beginning of an Era and May 1968 Documents],

and RenĂ© ViĂ©net’s EnragĂ©s and Situationists in the Occupation Movement.

Also recommended is Roger GrĂ©goire and Fredy Perlman’s Worker-Student

Action Committees, France May ’68 (Black and Red, 1969).

[15] “Labor will not only SHUT DOWN the industries, but Labor will

REOPEN, under the management of the appropriate trades, such activities

as are needed to preserve public health and public peace. If the strike

continues, Labor may feel led to avoid public suffering by reopening

more and more activities. UNDER ITS OWN MANAGEMENT. And that is why we

say that we are starting on a road that leads — NO ONE KNOWS WHERE!”

(Announcement on the eve of the 1919 Seattle general strike.) See Jeremy

Brecher’s Strike! (South End, 1972), pp. 101–114. More extensive

accounts are included in Root and Branch: The Rise of the Workers’

Movements and in Harvey O’Connor’s Revolution in Seattle, both currently

out of print.

[16] Raoul Vaneigem (who incidentally wrote a good brief critical

history of surrealism) represented the clearest expression of both

aspects. His little book De la grĂšve sauvage Ă  l’autogestion gĂ©nĂ©ralisĂ©e

(literally “From Wildcat Strike to Generalized Self-Management,” but

partially translated as Contributions to the Revolutionary Struggle)

usefully recapitulates a number of basic tactics during wildcat strikes

and other radical situations as well as various possibilities of

postrevolutionary social organization. Unfortunately it is also padded

with the inflated verbiage characteristic of Vaneigem’s post-SI

writings, attributing to worker struggles a Vaneigemist content that is

neither justified nor necessary. The radical-subjectivity aspect was

rigidified into a tediously repeated ideology of hedonism in Vaneigem’s

later books (The Book of Pleasures, etc.), which read like cotton-candy

parodies of the ideas he dealt with so trenchantly in his earlier works.

[17] “One day into this thing, and I’m tired, but compared to the

positive sensations that are passing through this place, fatigue doesn’t

stand a chance... Who will ever forget the look on management’s faces

when we tell them we are now in control, and their services are

obviously no longer needed... Everything as normal, except we don’t

collect phone bills... We’re also making friends from other departments.

Guys from downstairs are coming up to help out and learn our jobs...

We’re all flying... Sailing on pure adrenalin. It’s like we own the

bloody thing... The signs on the front door say, CO-OP TEL: UNDER NEW

MANAGEMENT — NO MANAGEMENT ALLOWED.” (Rosa Collette, “Operators Dial

Direct Action,” Open Road, Vancouver, Spring 1981.)

[18] “A South African company is selling an anti-riot vehicle that plays

disco music through a loudspeaker to soothe the nerves of would-be

troublemakers. The vehicle, already bought by one black nation, which

the company did not identify, also carries a water cannon and tear gas.”

(AP, 23 September 1979.)

[19] If this question had been openly posed to the Spanish workers (who

had already bypassed the vacillating Popular Front government by seizing

arms and resisting the fascist coup by themselves, and in the process

launched the revolution) they would probably have agreed to grant

Moroccan independence. But once they were swayed by political leaders —

including even many anarchist leaders — into tolerating that government

in the name of antifascist unity, they were kept unaware of such issues.

The Spanish revolution remains the single richest revolutionary

experience in history, though it was complicated and obscured by the

simultaneous civil war against Franco and by the sharp contradictions

within the antifascist camp — which, besides two or three million

anarchists and anarchosyndicalists and a considerably smaller contingent

of revolutionary Marxists (the POUM), included bourgeois republicans,

ethnic autonomists, socialists and Stalinists, with the latter in

particular doing everything in their power to repress the revolution.

The best comprehensive histories are Pierre BrouĂ© and Emile TĂ©mime’s

Revolution and the War in Spain and Burnett Bolloten’s The Spanish

Revolution (the latter is also substantially incorporated in Bolloten’s

monumental final work, The Spanish Civil War). Some good first-hand

accounts are George Orwell’s Homage to Catalonia, Franz Borkenau’s The

Spanish Cockpit, and Mary Low and Juan Breá’s Red Spanish Notebook.

Other books worth reading include Vernon Richards’s Lessons of the

Spanish Revolution, Murray Bookchin’s To Remember Spain, Gerald Brenan’s

The Spanish Labyrinth, Sam Dolgoff’s The Anarchist Collectives, Abel

Paz’s Durruti: The People Armed, and Victor Alba and Stephen Schwartz’s

Spanish Marxism versus Soviet Communism: A History of the P.O.U.M.

[20] P.M.’s Bolo’bolo (1983; new edition: Semiotext(e), 1995) has the

merit of being one of the few utopias that fully recognize and welcome

this diversity. Leaving aside its flippancies and idiosyncrasies and its

rather unrealistic notions about how we might get there, it touches on a

lot of the basic problems and possibilities of a postrevolutionary

society.

[21] Although the so-called networking revolution has so far been

limited mainly to increased circulation of spectator trivia, modern

communications technologies continue to play an important role in

undermining totalitarian regimes. Years ago the Stalinist bureaucracies

had to cripple their own functioning by restricting the availability of

photocopy machines and even typewriters lest they be used to reproduce

samizdat writings. The newer technologies are proving even more

difficult to control:

“The conservative Guangming Daily reported new enforcement measures

targeted at an estimated 90,000 illegal fax machines in Beijing. Chinese

analysts say the regime fears that the proliferation of fax machines is

allowing information to flow too freely. Such machines were used

extensively during student demonstrations in 1989 that resulted in a

military crackdown... In the comfort of their own homes in Western

capitals, such as London, oppositionists can tap out messages to

activists in Saudi Arabia who, by downloading via Internet in their own

homes, no longer have to fear a knock on the door in the middle of the

night... Every taboo subject from politics to pornography is spreading

through anonymous electronic messages far beyond the government’s iron

grip... Many Saudis find themselves discussing religion openly for the

first time. Atheists and fundamentalists regularly slug it out in Saudi

cyberspace, a novelty in a country where the punishment for apostasy is

death... But banning the Internet is not possible without removing all

computers and telephone lines... Experts claim that for those willing to

work hard enough to get it, there is still little any government can do

to totally deny access to information on the Internet. Encrypted e-mail

and subscribing to out-of-country service providers are two options

available to net-savvy individuals for circumventing current Internet

controls... If there is one thing repressive East Asian governments fear

more than unrestricted access to outside media sources, it is that their

nations’ competitiveness in the rapidly growing information industry may

be compromised. Already, protests have been voiced in the business

communities of Singapore, Malaysia, and China that censoring the

Internet may, in the end, hamper those nations’ aspirations to be the

most technologically advanced on the block.” (Christian Science Monitor,

11 August 1993, 24 August 1995 and 12 November 1996.)

[22] “In the post-Cold War era politicians have discovered crime-baiting

as a substitute for red-baiting. Just as the fear of communism propelled

the unimpeded expansion of the military-industrial complex,

crime-baiting has produced the explosive growth of the

correctional-industrial complex, also known as the crime-control

industry. Those who disagree with its agenda of more prisons are branded

criminal sympathizers and victim betrayers. Since no politician will

risk the ‘soft on crime’ label, an unending spiral of destructive

policies is sweeping the country... Repression and brutalization will be

further promoted by the institutions that are the primary beneficiaries

of such policies. As California increased its prison population from

19,000 to 124,000 over the past 16 years, 19 new prisons were built.

With the increase in prisons, the California Correctional Peace Officers

Association (CCPOA), the guards’ union, emerged as the state’s most

powerful lobby... As the percentage of the state budget devoted to

higher education has fallen from 14.4 percent to 9.8 percent, the share

of the budget for corrections has risen from 3.9 percent to 9.8 percent.

The average salary and benefits for prison guards in California exceeds

$55,000 — the highest in the nation. This year the CCPOA, along with the

National Rifle Association, has directed its substantial war chest to

promote the passage of the ‘three strikes, you’re out’ initiative that

would triple the current size of California’s prison system. The same

dynamics that evolved in California will certainly result from Clinton’s

crime bill. As more resources are poured into the crime-control

industry, its power and influence will grow.” (Dan Macallair, Christian

Science Monitor, 20 September 1994.)

[23] Other possibilities are presented in considerable detail in

Workers’ Councils and the Economics of a Self-Managed Society (London

Solidarity’s edition of a Socialisme ou Barbarie article by Cornelius

Castoriadis). This text is full of valuable suggestions, but I feel that

it assumes more centering around work and workplace than will be

necessary. Such an orientation is already somewhat obsolete and will

probably become much more so after a revolution.

Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel’s Looking Forward: Participatory

Economics for the Twenty First Century (South End, 1991) also includes a

number of useful points on self-managed organization. But the authors

assume a society in which there is still a money economy and the

workweek is only slightly reduced (to around 30 hours). Their

hypothetical examples are largely modeled on present-day worker co-ops

and the “economic participation” envisaged includes voting on marketing

issues that will be superseded in a noncapitalist society. As we will

see, such a society will also have a far shorter workweek, reducing the

need to bother with the complicated schemes for equal rotation among

different types of jobs that occupy a large part of the book.

[24] Fredy Perlman, author of one of the most sweeping expressions of

this tendency, Against His-story, Against Leviathan! (Black and Red,

1983), provided his own best critique in his earlier book about C.

Wright Mills, The Incoherence of the Intellectual (Black and Red, 1970):

“Yet even though Mills rejects the passivity with which men accept their

own fragmentation, he no longer struggles against it. The coherent

self-determined man becomes an exotic creature who lived in a distant

past and in extremely different material circumstances... The main drift

is no longer the program of the right which can be opposed by the

program of the left; it is now an external spectacle which follows its

course like a disease... The rift between theory and practice, thought

and action, widens; political ideals can no longer be translated into

practical projects.”

[25] Isaac Asimov and Frederick Pohl’s Our Angry Earth: A Ticking

Ecological Bomb (Tor, 1991) is among the more cogent summaries of this

desperate situation. After demonstrating how inadequate current policies

are for dealing with it, the authors propose some drastic reforms that

might postpone the worst catastrophes; but such reforms are unlikely to

be implemented as long as the world is dominated by the conflicting

interests of nation-states and multinational corporations.

[26] For a wealth of suggestive insights on the advantages and drawbacks

of different types of urban communities, past, present and potential, I

recommend two books: Paul and Percival Goodman’s Communitas and Lewis

Mumford’s The City in History. The latter is one of the most penetrating

and comprehensive surveys of human society ever written.