💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › errico-malatesta-science-and-social-reform.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:43:14. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Science and Social Reform Author: Errico Malatesta Date: 1913 Language: en Topics: science, scientific socialism, Marxism Source: The Method of Freedom: An Errico Malatesta Reader, edited by Davide Turcato, translated by Paul Sharkey. Notes: Man! (San Francisco) 3, no. 2 [recte 3] (March 1935), translated by Eli J. Boche. Originally published as “Scienza e riforma sociale,” Volontà (Ancona) 1, no. 29 (27 December 1913).
The great scientific discoveries of the nineteenth century and the
victorious criticism which science made against the lies and the errors
of religions, had the effect upon progressive spirits, of making them
enthusiastic admirers if not intelligent and patient cultivators, of
science. These progressives exaggerated the importance of science by
attributing to it the power to solve and understand everything; they
made of science a new religion.
Social reformers of every kind that is, of every kind which, by whatever
means and ends, wished to modify the existing social order believed
themselves obliged to found their aspirations upon Science. Similarly,
the conservatives also, when they saw that religious faith was
vacillating and that it was no longer sufficient to keep the people in
subjection, sought to justify the existing regime by means of science.
It was verily a state of intellectual intoxication (not yet vanished)
which caused the loss of a clear concept of nature and of the methods
and scope of science, and it was to the utter detriment of scientific
truth and social action.
Hardly anyone was saved; and if we anarchists were saved from the
ridiculousness of calling ourselves scientific anarchists, it was
perhaps only because the adjective “scientific” had already been taken
and rendered antipathetic by Marxian socialism. In fact, many of our
Comrades (and among them some of the most deserving and illustrious)
actually maintained that Anarchism is a deduction consolidated with
scientific truths, and, furthermore, that it is nothing but the
application of the mechanical conception of the universe to human
interests.[1]
Meanwhile, the fact that they remain anarchists even while science
progresses and changes, demonstrates the fallacy of their scientific-ism
and demonstrates likewise, that their anarchism is derived from their
sentiments and not from their scientific convictions. But, in spite of
their professed objectivism, in practice they will not admit facts or
accept theories which seem to contradict their anarchical aspirations.
And, if they had not had the opportunity to pursue scientific studies,
or science did not exist and human knowledge had remained in the state
in which it was centuries ago,[2] they would probably be anarchists just
the same because, being good and sensible men, they would suffer because
of human sorrows and would want to find a remedy and because, being
proud and just men, they would rebel against oppression and would want
complete liberty for themselves and for all. In addition they recognize
the quality of conscious anarchism in that immense majority of Comrades
who do not know science, and, when they do propaganda work, they do just
as we do, that is, they seek to awaken in men the sentiments of personal
dignity and love of others; they strive to excite the passion for
liberty and justice; they speak of general well-being and of human
brotherhood; they bring to light the social ills and they arouse the
desire to destroy them; and they do not wait until the people have
studied mathematics, astronomy, and chemistry.
The study of the sciences is an excellent thing and we will speak later
of those things which they serve. But to pretend that anarchism (and the
same holds true for socialism or any other human aspiration) is a
scientific deduction and especially, therefore, a consequence of one of
those vast cosmogonical hypotheses in which philosophy takes such great
delight, is a thing which is false per se and is pernicious because of
the consequent effect it can have upon the intellectual development of
individuals and upon their capacity as combatants.
The idea of a personal god, creator of all things, which is the oldest,
the most ingenuous, and the most grossly absurd of these hypotheses, has
done immense harm because it has accustomed people to believing without
understanding and, by suffocating the spirit of examination, it has made
intellectual slaves, well prepared to support political and economic
slavery.
But do not scientific hypotheses do the same when they are presented as
firm facts and as motives for actions, to those who know little or
nothing of science and who are therefore in no position to judge? Some
vague notions of scientific facts, more or less true, and the knowledge
of a few strange words, are not enough to make of a man a scientist or
even one who knows what he is talking about or who can choose from among
the things that he is told.
For the public in general Moses and Haeckel are equally mythical figures
and the belief in the monism of the one rather than in the genesis of
the other just because it happens to be in style in the present
environment, does not make one any the less ignorant, any the less
superstitious, or any the less religious.[3] And to speak to the
unbelievers of atoms, ions, and electrons (which are only hypotheses for
explaining and binding certain categories of fact—convenient hypotheses
useful to the ends of scientific research, but, nevertheless, only
hypotheses, simple mental concepts, and not at all positive discoveries,
pace friend Cassisa)[4]—to speak, I say, without adequate preparation,
of mysterious and incomprehensible things to one who does not
understand, is the same as to speak of god and of angels. It means the
teaching of words as things and the accustoming of the mind to
contenting itself with affirmations which it can neither understand, nor
prove, nor define.
This would be only a change in religion because it would still be a
religion in the sense of blind submission to a revealed truth, which can
be neither controlled nor comprehended. If it were true that anarchy is
a scientific truth, then there would be no real anarchists except the
very few scientists who would call themselves such; all we others would
constitute a non-conscious herd which would blindly follow a few holy
men who had been initiated into the reasons for faith!
Nor is there any difference in the moral deductions or in the social
applications which can be obtained out of the various cosmogonical
theories. The priests had God say the things which were convenient to
them and they used him as a medium for justifying and strengthening the
dominion of the victors.
However, in the course of history there was no lack of rebels who, in
the name of God, preached justice and equality. It is said that
everything occurs by the will of God and that, therefore, we must accept
with resignation our own position. But it can also be said that
rebellion is holy since it does occur and hence must be willed by God.
It can also be said that, if God is the common father, we are all
brothers and ought, therefore, to be equal. In sum, this idea may be
turned in any manner, to suit any taste—for example, we know that
Mazzini invented God of goodness, of love, and of progress, who was
entirely different from the ferocious God of Pius IX.
Bakunin used to say that, if God exists, men can have neither liberty
nor dignity. Another might say—and many, in fact, have said it—that if
all is matter, if everything is subject to natural laws, the will is an
illusion, liberty a chimera and man nothing but an automaton.
So it is that, if the convictions and the moral aspirations are based
upon the mobile foundations of philosophic hypotheses, they are always
uncertain and mutable. Like the catholic who, basing his conduct upon
belief in God, is left without any moral criterion as soon as his faith
is shaken, so the anarchist, if he were really an anarchist because of
scientific convictions, would have to continually consult the latest
bulletins of the Academy of Science in order to determine whether he can
continue to be an anarchist.
Cassisa furnishes an example of how, by means of philosophy, the
simplest and most evident things can be confounded. According to him,
“the principle of property is based upon the false belief in creation
from nothing.” I, truly, do not understand what he wants to say: but it
seems to me that if, before having a revolution and expropriating the
holders of social wealth, we must first attend to nothing but the
question of the origin of the world, then the capitalists may sleep in
tranquility! Oh, isn’t it much more simple, much more comprehensible, to
say that, however the world may have been formed, it is here and ought
to serve the needs of all, and to incite the workers to take it and to
work it on their own account, and to no longer permit themselves to be
despoiled by those who, by violence or fraud, have made themselves the
owners?
---
If then, from the clouds of philosophy, we descend to the more solid
domain of the positive sciences and of the so-called social sciences, we
find here, too, that they can serve to defend the most diverse political
regimes, the most contradictory social aspirations. From the immense
heap of more of less established facts, each one chooses those which
support his own position, and each one formulates theories which in
reality, become programs, desires, and objectives which he proposes and
which he, deluding himself as well as others, calls scientific truths.
In the interpretation of the facts of natural history, in anthropology,
in the philosophy of history, in political economy, and in every phase
of sociology, at every turning of a page we come upon dubious
affirmations which say “it is” when they should say “it ought to be” or,
better, “I wish it were.” The result is that scientific, objective, and
impartial investigation suffers; the social struggle passes from the
ardent field of passion and interest which are its very own, to
degenerate itself in the chattering of the academicians and the pedants.
Science gathers facts, classifies them, and, when it finds that these
facts are necessary and that they necessarily reproduce themselves every
time the same conditions are set up, formulates natural laws. The latter
are, for this reason, nothing but affirmations that under given
conditions certain definite phenomena occur. But this does not tell man
what to desire, whether he should love or hate, be good or bad, just or
unjust. Goodness, justice, and right are concepts which science ignores
completely.
Science tends to delimit the field between fatalism and free will. The
more science advances the more powerful does man become because he
learns what are the the necessary conditions which he must fulfill in
order to be able to execute his will. But this will, executed or not,
remains an extra scientific force with its own origins and its own
tendencies.
Toxology teaches us the physiology of poisons, but it does not tell us
whether we should use the acquired knowledge to poison or to cure
people. Mechanics discovers the laws of equilibrium and of the
resistance of materials, it teaches us to build bridges, steamships, and
aeroplanes, but it does not tell us whether it is better to build the
bridge where it may serve the greed of a proprietor, or where it may
serve the interests of all; it does not tell us whether ships and planes
should be used to carry soldiers and to hurl bombs upon the people or to
spread throughout the world, civility, well-being, and brotherhood.
Science is a weapon that can serve for good or for evil; but it ignores
completely the idea of good or evil.
So then, we are not anarchists, because sciences tell us to be: we are,
instead, anarchists because, among other reasons, we want everyone to be
able to enjoy the advantages and the joys that science can procure for
us.
[1] The implicit but obvious reference is to the theories of Peter
Kropotkin.
[2] The words from “science did” to “knowledge had” were missing from
the English version. They have been added on the basis of the Italian
original.
[3] Ernst Haeckel (1834–1919) was a German scientist who promoted and
popularized Darwin’s theories. His philosophical monism proposed the
unity of organic and physical nature, including social phenomena and
mental processes.
[4] In the article “L’Anarchia è atea” (Anarchy is atheistic), which
appeared in the previous issue of VolontĂ , the anarchist Gian Salvatore
Cassisa had taken issue with Malatesta on religion and science. Taking a
strongly positivistic stance, he had maintained that Anarchy was the
synthesis of a new “scientific civilization.”