š¾ Archived View for library.inu.red āŗ file āŗ harry-baecker-technology-science-and-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:44:49. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
ā”ļø Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Technology, Science and Anarchism Author: Harry Baecker Language: en Topics: science, technology, The Raven Source: Retrieved on 1 January 1999 from http://www.tao.ca/~freedom/scien.html Notes: From The Raven 24 pp. 296ā302
It has always been a great temptation to give an intensive definition of
man. Our ancestors were so bemused by their own philosophical
capabilities, and by the, to them, evident lack of these in the rest of
the fauna that they characterised themselves as homo sapiens. You and I
have inherited that noble appellation without any effort on our part. Of
late we have had other attempts at definition, homo ludens by Huizinga,
āman the time-builderā by Korzybski. The former emphasised the
importance of non-purposeful activity, play, in the development of those
activities we consider more worthy and important; the latter
characterised man by his ability to symbolise experience and thereby
transmit it to other members of the species far distant in time and
space. Korzybskiās definition is, by the way, extensive, as given in his
Manhood of Humanity.
I too have a chip on my shoulder, and as one of the mad ogres of modern
times, a technologist, a blind self-abasing servant of the machine, I
reject intensive definitions and choose to present my own extensive one
of man, an outgrowth of that of Korzybski, and I choose the label homo
aedificans, āman the builderā, to hang onto my definition. Intensive
definitions should be left to metaphysics, so it is up to me to make it
credible that my definition is extensive. The instructions for
verification of the definition are as follows:
āObserve the surface of this planet for at least one revolution round
its primary in sufficient detail to resolve features one hundred
millionth of its circumference in extent. You will observe several
lifeforms that produce artefacts from the material in their environment.
Further observation will show that in the case of all but one of these
lifeforms a given lifeform produces but one type of artefact and that
only within a sharply limited ecological framework. However, the
residual lifeform will be observed to produce a multiplicity of
artefacts and may be seen to produce the same artefact our of varying
environmental material by appropriate intermediary processes. If you
were to extend the period of your observations to a hundred revolutions
round the primary you would observe that no change has occurred in the
range of artefacts produced by the lifeforms except again in the case of
the one lifeform previously noted. Some artefacts previously produced by
this lifeform wil no longer be produced, some will be made out of
entirely different environmental material, and a large number of
artefacts not previously produced will now be noted. If you were to
improve the resolution of detail of your observations by a linear factor
of one hundred you will observe a class of artefact that may be deduced
to be symbolisations, abstractions, of other artefacts, of events, or of
actions of the lifeform. The lifeform you have particularised by your
observations is called man.ā
This definition of man says nothing of heart or soul, of art or
intellect. It is ignoble, you may say. Perhaps. But it is verifiable, it
is devoid of private assumptions and comprises only directives for the
performance of actions that will lead to the recognition of the species
under discussion. It identifies man as the sole maker of gadgets and
widgets on this planet, that is, by his technologies.
A few years ago such a definition might even have been challenged as
totally inadequate by archaeologists and hominid palaeontologists who
had developed an evolutionary sequence largely derived from the cranial
capacity of the pre-sapiens remains found. Recent years have seen the
excavation of many more archaeological sites in many more parts of the
planet and it has become clear cranial capacity is a secondary
development. The record now shows that tool-using and tool-making goes
much further back in our ancestry than had previously been supposed and,
what is more important, that each stage of cranial development is
preceded by a change in the skeleton structure of the limbs giving
greater manipulative skill, and the archaeological record confirms that
our ancestors immediately used the new skill to make more refined tools,
before their cranial capacity had increased. The gadget is the father of
wisdom.
A persistent thread in anarchist and libertarian writing, as elsewhere
is the denigration of modern technology and the expression of a thirst
for the simple life, the natural life. It is presupposed that if man can
slough off his concern for things he will behave more nobly towards his
fellow men. The proponents of this sort of argument point to āthe simple
happinessā of various primitive societies. There are several answers to
this view. Firstly, the range of expectations is much narrower in such
societies and therefore so are the expressions of discontent. Secondly,
it is no great achievement for a society the majority of whose members
are malarial or ridden by deficiency diseases to be placid, and content
with the simple fact of being alive. If you expect your children to die
in the first year of life and if you have no great life expectancy then
there is little inducement to be ambitious or to carve out an empire.
Thirdly, the technological accomplishments of some of these societies
put our own engineers to shame. Within the strict limitations of their
arctic environment the Eskimo have exploited its resources and invented
gadgets that have no equal. They have no word for āwarā because they are
too busy making and using gadgets to keep alive.
In conjunction with the arguments about the simplicity of life is that
about the natural life. Usually this is assumed to be pastoral,
horticultural or agricultural. I fail to see what is so natural about
any of these. They are as artificial as the construction of nuclear
reactors. The only natural habits for man would be to wander unclothed
and without constructed shelter, without fire, gathering herbs and
fruits to eat raw and catching small animals with his bare hands to gnaw
raw, and most certainly without any language to use to communicate with
his fellows. All else are constructs of a social technology of very
great complexity. No natural lifer would admit conditions as primitive
as these I have just described as his ideal. But none can adduce reasons
why his utopia should be permitted to indulge in the degree of
artificiality he feels to be desirable whilst forbidding other
artificialities.
I must, of course, put up my own version of what is ānaturalā for man.
It is to manipulate his environment to facilitate, directly or
indirectly, the survival of himself and his species, the survival value
of his actions depending on his current apprehension of reality. A
corollary of this view is that stasis is inconceivable for humanity. And
a survey of human history will quickly confirm that change is not
something facing us now, from which we can retreat into some golden era
of the past, but that it is a part of all we know of ourselves, a normal
condition of the race, and that it has always been with us.
The agrarian utopia can only succeed in an environment so devoid of
natural resources that innovation and invention are impossible, where
the struggle to survive by present means is so intense as to preclude
the spare time and energy requisite to the devising of other means.
Under more favourable circumstances the utopia of this type is
self-destroying if stocked with healthy human stock, it will invent and
innovate its way from subsistence to technological exuberance Invention
and innovation will not be confined to the arts or philosophy or the
love of oneās fellow man, there is no evidence that these can be
independent of material activity, and indeed there is overwhelmlng
evidence that the humanitarian must be preceded by the technician, to
prepare an environment in which the race can afford the graces of life.
And if man succeeds in creating an environment in which he can exist
without inventive effort then he will be dead. When curiosity and
questing cease the end has come. Why should this curiosity be exercised
upon the material world and not upon the finer delights of metaphysics,
charity and love? Because we live in this material world it is our
world, it is the raw material out of which we can fashion our lives of
our own choosing, if we have the will and the comprehension to do so.
Remember the men who are regarded as the two greatest artists ever, da
Vinci and Michelangelo. First and foremost they were manipulators of
materials, technicians, engineers. First they had to invent the paints
and other materials of their art, to devise the engineering rules for
their sculpture and architecture. They commanded the material world, and
comprehended it as best as they were able. Their art was based on the
foremost advances of the technology of their day. Today the castrate
artist hides his incomprehension of the world he inhabits behind flabby
talk of art and is impotent in the face of reality, the human race has
outgrown him, he is retarded in his development. In a frenzy of imagined
superiority he had abdicated his right to fashion the materials of our
daily lives, and then has the childish petulance to blame others for his
own futility.
The relevance of this view of the world to the anarchist discussion is
at least threefold. In the first place, it is a view held, usually
inarticulately and even unconsciously, by very many people in positions
of effective control in our culture. The task of the anarchist
propagandist does not begin with attempts to persuade these people of
the validity of the anarchist standpoint. The difficulty is far more
fundamental, it is incumbent upon the anarchist to discover the common
basis of discourse from which he can address the technologist. To the
anarchist it may be a self-evident truth that āman if born free, and
everywhere he is in chainsā. It is not. It is a metaphysical, not
practical, statement. It requires the exhibition of examples of the
states of freedom and bondage.
Man is born free. But unless he is subjected to the most rigorous social
discipline in his youth not even an anarchist is likely to claim him as
a comrade. For infant man must learn a language, and learn it correctly.
By correctly I mean that he must learn to frame his own communication in
such a way that he conveys whatever he wants to convey to others, and at
the same time learns to pay attention to the communications of others so
as to apprehend their meaning. By the time he has achieved fluency of
expression a manās ānatural freedomā has been severely circumscribed by
society. It is a very simple practical affair. If you wish to be a
member of society you must obey the rules, if you ignore the rules you
remain outside society for you are bereft of the means of communication.
You can babble as much as you like about freedom, but your babbling will
be couched in terms that obey the strict social rules if you wish your
effusions to have any effect.
So, maybe, man is born free. But unless he loses his freedom he ceases
to be a man. It is even doubtful that abstract thought is possible for
us without the use of linguistic symbolism. The hermit is indebted to
generations of social effort for the language in which he postulates his
withdrawal. Without the cultural apparatus that your ancestors and your
fellows have provided by laborious toil you, individual man, are less
than nothing. You have not even the instincts that enable most animals
to live, you depend for your survival upon the accumulated effort of the
race.
Comrades, you see your problem!
The second problem for the anarchist in an expanding society is that of
education. In an earlier issue of this journal it was asserted that
anarchist education must not compel the child to learn subjects that it
does not spontaneously wish to follow. I hope that the writers were not
prepared to make a few points of safety in a technical environment an
elective subject. For instance, do not touch live electric mains. Now if
these points are neglected we have, of course, solved the problem of
overpopulation brilliantly. If we do make personal and public safety
compulsory, but make the background subjects elective we have made
witchcraft the basis of our society. For without thorough comprehension
of the ālaws of natureā, of science, such safety precautions are just
witchcraft, or the edicts of a vengeful god. You will not get a free and
open society if the basis of the elemental rules of survival is not
understood by those upon whom they are enjoined. Further, unless a
citizen is somehow made aware of the existence of fields of human
knowledge and experience and ignorence then he has no chance to be
interested in them. You cannot look for an answer before you know that
there is a question. A fully elective education would be a disaster for
the child.
The third problem is that of authority. This is allied to the previous
one. In a technical society decisions must be made and directives must
be issued if the society is to exist at all. For instance, if
automobiles are desired then a rule of the road must be established and
rigourously enforced. We cannot choose to drive on the left or right at
will whatever our political or philosophic persuasion the brute facts of
mobile tons of machinery impose their own discipline. I said that
directives must be issued. They must also be enforced. Whatever your
views on the common ownership of land you cannot be permitted to wander
at will on an airfield, if necessary you must be shot dead before you
can endanger an airliner landing with a hundred passengers aboard.
The usual anarchist reply to the above problem is that it would not, of
course, exist in a free society where all men would behave reasonably.
But reason and goodwill are not enough. Knowledge and understanding must
be there also, and if people are free to learn to ignore simple facts of
their daily life then you must guard against the blunders occasioned by
their ignorance.
Of course we can go back to the argument about the abolition of
technology. By all means yearn for your little womb of pristine safety
and simplicity. Do not expect the rest of us to follow you there, or to
honour you for fleeing thither. And if we find that we could put your
corner of paradise to more congenial use we shall probably wrest it from
you without pity or remorse. Violence is the last resort of the
incompetent, and oft we are incompetent. But the fact that we are
incompetent does now make us scurry off to a dark corner to brood in
fear, we shall try to develop competence, it will cost blood, toil tears
and sweat, both ours and yours. We know a little of whence we come, we
know almost nothing of where we are going, but we shall go on, impelled
by the monkey instinct, by the hands of the artificer, by the thoughts
of the scientist, by the dreams of those who sought the summits of
mountains and the deeps of the sea, the poles of the planet and the
reaches of space. Because we are human.
We build and we also destroy. Often we destroy through ignorance. Our
technology is yet poorly used, we damage ourselves with it. It has
always been thus, the Roman farmers impoverished the soil of Italy with
their sheep two thousand years ago, we must always be aware that every
act may be a mistake. But the symbols of our common humanity are our
artefacts, the tools by which we enrich and enlarge our experience and
comprehension of the universe we inhabit. You may seek to change us, but
to reach us you will have to undergo the discipline of language, perhaps
the complex of our artefacts, and the search to convey your meaning to
us will lead you first to examine our meaning and to be tainted by it.