💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › gaston-leval-kropotkin-and-malatesta.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:35:05. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Kropotkin and Malatesta Author: Gaston Leval Date: n.d. Language: en Topics: PĂ«tr Kropotkin, Errico Malatesta, science, scientific method Notes: Translated from the French by the uploader. From Les Cahiers de Contre-courant (Paris: Sofrim, n.d.); scan of French original here: https://archive.org/details/GastonLeval-KropotkineEtMalatesta
Counter-current recently reproduced an article in which Malatesta
attacked Kropotkin's intellectual ouevre. This article wasn't the only
one on the same subject published by the same author. I have read others
which, in their time, had exercised in South America (where I then was)
a real but passing influence in certain anarchist-communist milieux. I
was myself, at first brush, impressed by his apparent logic, and at the
death of Malatesta I affirmed in the Buenos Aires journal Nervio that
the Malatestan principle was superior to that of Kropotkin.
But, as an autodidact in constant training, always searching, always
studying, and taking up Kropotkin as well as Malatesta, it was not long
before I convinced myself that the position of the latter led to an
impasse, to a kind of medieval scholasticism in which study would be
banned, and in which the dialectics of the most skillful literati would
outweigh a thorough knowledge of the facts. That is, in rebuffing
science we in reality rebuff all systematic and serious study of the
different problems that occupy us—because such is what science is— and
we condemn anarchist thought to be nothing more than prattle, more or
less skilled, more or less eloquent, but without consistency and without
the possibility of having a real scope in the social thought of the
present and the future. That, in practical terms, was leading us to
nothingness. Only the vain, in this century in which coordinated studies
provide and continue to provide so many relevant factors which limit our
pretensions to know everything and to wish to decide everything, can be
satisfied with it.
Malatesta's critiques were formulated after the death of Kropotkin,
which is and has been deeply regrettable. Taken on the whole, I daresay
that only a few valid points stand. This is not apparent for those who
have not read sufficiently either the attacker, or his target.
Malatesta is off-base when he presents Kropotkin as a simple "poet of
science." It would first be necessary to know in what way he is
qualified to say so. For all his keen intelligence does not change the
fact that he was never anything but a student who frequented
revolutionary circles more than the university, and that subsequently
nothing in all of his writings permits us to attribute him a sufficient
erudition to judge Kropotkin this way.
Kropotkin was, at 30 years of age, named the president of the Russian
Geographical Society, for the brilliant discoveries he had made
concerning the general orography of Asia. He was, replacing Huxley, the
great continuator of Darwin, and a collaborator-editor of the British
Encyclopedia. His value as a naturalist was apparent in books such as
Mutual Aid, where for the first time he presented a whole social
philosophy founded on the solidarity within animal species and in the
prehistory and history of humanity. Elisée Reclus got Kropotkin to
collaborate in the editing of the Universal Geography, on what concerned
Russia and Asia. Whoever has read Fields, Factories, and Workshops has
seen his vast knowledge in material economy, a knowledge which, along
with that of the history of civilization, bursts from the page in the
first chapters of The Conquest of Bread, which we find in the powerful
pamphlet The State, Its Historic Role, and in Modern Science and
Anarchy. Ethics shows an immense erudition, and even this or that
chapter in Words of a Rebel prove a knowledge which exceeded that of an
amateur. If, at the moment of Kropotkin's imprisonment in France, men
such as Herbert Spencer signed the petition in protest on behalf of the
English scientific world, this was not only because he was a political
criminal.
A "poet of science" he may have been, but he was much more than this.
There have been greater men of science, but Kropotkin was one of them.
And we can regret not having had many others of the same caliber—the one
I cannot forget being Elisée Reclus.
Thus launched, Malatesta made some fundamental reproaches of Kropotkin.
First, that of having based anarchy on science alone, and on nothing but
science. For this he reproduced many times a phrase pulled from Modern
Science and Anarchy. This sentence, thus: "Anarchy is a conception of
the universe, based on a mechanical interpretation of phenomena, which
embraces all of nature, including the life of societies." What does that
have to do with anarchy? asked Malatesta, several times. Whether or not
the universe is or is not explicable according to the latest discoveries
of physics does not at all preclude that the oppression and exploitation
of man by man are an injustice, and that we must fight them.
In this, he was right, and this first reaction is so obvious that he has
all of his readers with him. But his first fault was to present this
sentence, extracted from a paragraph which appeared in a chapter of a
book which contains many others, as the only base which Kropotkin gave
to anarchy.
I am obliged to say that in proceeding this way Malatesta absolutely
deforms Kropotkin's thought. Anyone who reads Modern Science and Anarchy
will see, on page 46 of the French edition, that the reproduced sentence
belongs to the chapter entitled "The Place of Anarchy in Modern
Science". There Kropotkin responds to the question: "What place does
anarchy occupy in the great intellectual movement of the nineteenth
century?" Situating himself on this ground where philosophy cannot
ignore new discoveries, he explains that science, that is to say the
knowledge acquired on the nature and constitution of matter, the
mechanism of the universe and the evolution of living forms and social
organisms, constitutes a whole which gives a sure basis to materialist
philosophy; that this materialist philosophy, by eliminating the
authoritarian conception that supposes a God as creator and director of
the world, allows the development of a philosophy where progress is the
work of a perfectly natural evolution, without the interposition of an
exterior source or intelligence. That consequently natural laws—or
rather natural "facts"—are essentially non-authoritarian, and that this
vast synthesis of the world permits the elaboration of a new social
philosophy. Thus, says Kropotkin, the place of anarchy is "ahead of the
intellectual movement of the nineteenth century."
That this exceeds the intellectual preoccupations of Malatesta is his
own affair. Bakunin, before Kropotkin, had elaborated a similar
philosophy. For him, socialism was the direct and logical consequence of
the materialist conception of the universe. But we well know that he had
other reasons to fight. Kropotkin also had his own. Reading him is
enough to know this.
Because, as Malatesta seems to ignore, from the first chapter of Modern
Science and Anarchy, everyone can read: "Like socialism in general, and
like every other social movement, anarchy is born among the people, and
it will only maintain its vitality and its creative force as long as it
remains popular." On page 3 he insists at length on this claim. Then he
shows the popular elements fighting against oppression, creating customs
such as judicial norms, but preceded most often by "more or less
isolated individuals who rebelled."
"All reformers, politicians, religious leaders, economists," he writes,
"belonged to the first category. And, among them, one always finds
individuals who, without waiting for all of their fellow citizens, or
even for a minority of them, to be imbued with the same intentions, rose
up against oppression—whether in more or less numerous groups, or all
alone, as individuals if they were not followed. We encounter these
revolutionaries in all epochs of history."
The basis of anarchy is therefore not limited to the latest discoveries
of physics, and it's a complete distortion of Kropotkin's thought to say
so.
It's another unfounded reproach of Malatesta's that depicts Kropotkin as
advocating the submission of man to universal determinism, in the sacred
name of science. If some "scientists" have written similar things,
Kropotkin is not responsible, anymore than Malatesta is responsible that
in the name of his "voluntarism" some individuals chuck bombs to
demonstrate their revolutionary will [volonté - trans.]. Kropotkin—and
here again Bakunin who had preceded him, with an unsurpassable depth—was
too intelligent not to know that the human will, however determined it
may be, is also, on its own scale, a factor on the cosmic and above all
planetary determinism, and never, in any writing, did he recommend the
submission of man to physical laws, or laws of biology. The citations I
have given are sufficient proof.
We can prove it again by reading all of Kropotkin's books. Whether it be
in The Great French Revolution, in his Memoirs [of a Revolutionist], in
Words of a Rebel, in Modern Science and Anarchy, in various pamphlets,
for instance "Anarchist Morality," in which he exhorts the youth to
struggle for justice, in the name of fullness of life; in the pamphlet
"To The Young," etc., Kropotkin always considered the factor of human
will (which is the principle Malatestan discovery) as one of the
necessary elements of history. To take one aspect of his thought—which
in every way exceeds philosophic mediocrity—and making it all of his
thought, is not a fair treatment, and not ethically defensible.
I am familiar with nearly everthing which has been published of
Malatesta's writings, in Italian and in Spanish, and I am familiar with
Kropotkin, as with other theorists of anarchism. I can say that as
concerns science, Malatesta is the only one who took this negative and
contemptuous view of science. It's a position which coincides with the
dangerous antiscientific reaction of a certain spiritualist philosophy
of which Benedetto Croce is the most notable theorist in Italy. That we
would react against the excesses of the materialist conceptions of the
nineteenth century, which ignore too much, in the slow discovery of
truth, of that which psychology and the study of the physical world
would reveal to us, is good and necessary. That we would repudiate
science itself: no. That is why, in certain anarchist milieux where we
study, the influence exercised by Malatesta and his voluntarist
philosophy—it is already nonsense to oppose the will to science—has been
ephemeral. This is why, in occupying myself with with economy,
sociology, and the reorganization of society (other than in the
imagination), not contenting myself with the discursive method to
understand the origin of the state and the evolution of human societies,
I have taken an entirely different path than that given by Malatesta.
Not having been born infused with science, nor with a genius sufficient
in itself, I modestly believed I had to study.
In my intellectual formation, it is the method recommended by Kropotkin
which has proved for me to be the most useful. But, let us repeat it,
was this method solely Kropotkinian? Not at all. All the
non-individualist anarchist social thinkers: Proudhon, Bakounine, Elisée
Reclus, Ricardo Mella, Pietro Gori, Anselmo Lorenzo, Jean Grave, Tarrida
del Marmol, etc., have seen in science, that is, it must be repeated
again, in knowledge as broad, serious and profound as possible, one of
the bases or one of the weapons of anarchism. In this sense, Malatesta
is the only one of his opinion, and in attacking Kropotkin, he attacks
all the others.
He has the right to take the position that pleases him, but if I already
responded to his anti-Kropotkin articles, if I answer them tirelessly,
it is because they demolish, for those who are not warned, Kropotkin as
a sociologist and as a thinker. Reading this articles, we might believe
that it is useless to read Kropotkin, and useless to study. Sociology
becomes the domain of those who know how to rattle off an article
according to their momentary inspiration, and to defend (because they
have an excellent literary don, in Malatesta) the most contradictory
things under an apparent logic of reasoning. It is a dialectical
question, a question of dialectical games.
This happens frequently with Malatesta. I had, around 1934, with his
disciple Luigi Fabbri, who then published Studi Sociali in Montevideo, a
correspondence in which this comrade and friend wrote me that it would
be necessary to pass through authoritarian stages before the triumph of
our ideas in a revolution. I responded to him that he had the duty to
write what he thought, and proposed to him a debate in his journal in
which I collaborated. He accepted. Fabbri defended ideas which were
those of Malatesta, as he emphasized in his letter. They seemed to me so
different from what I knew of the latter that I began to read
methodically the articles, pamphlets, and collections of articles of
Malatesta and I noticed that he advocated the same issues, always with
the same dialectical ease, the same gift of reasoning which in turn
makes the uninformed reader accept the most contradictory theses. With
the same convincing logic he declared that if anarchists did not know
how to orient the revolution by putting themselves at its head, it would
be the authoritiarians who would do it, "and then, goodbye to anarchy!";
or that the anarchists being a minority, could not think of making an
anarchist revolution without exercising a dictatorship, which would be
the negation of anarchy; or that, as we could not cope with all the
tasks that a revolution would impose, we should be content with other
parties taking charge of them (and we still wonder what would happen to
anarchy); then, and this was his last position, that in a revolution we
had to limit ourselves to "free experimentalism." In what did that
consist? To demand from the Bolshevik Communists, arms in hand if
necessary, our right to practice our ideas, to experiment them freely in
the anarchist islands formed in the midst of the dictatorial revolution.
The slightest logic, and historical experience, proved to us that this
would never be possible. It was enough to remember what had happened in
Russia. Even if they did not resort to violent dissolution and massacre
against us, as Trotsky had done in Russia, it would be enough to deprive
us of raw materials to stifle such attempts dangerous for the
dictatorship. Malatesta did not seem to perceive this. And all these
contradictory dispositions were defended almost simultaneously. It was
the same with other problems of decisive importance, such as that of
unions before a revolution. Six months apart, Malatesta advocated their
disappearance because, being born out of the struggle against
capitalism, they would have no reason to exist after capitalism, or else
the activity of anarchists in the unions, the use of which he advocated
as the basis of the new society. Also, contradictions as to the most
recommendable economic legal principle. Malatesta defended anarchist
communism quite well, and also certain formes of collectivism. And when
Fabbri wrote a book on the thought of his master-- which thought had, in
part, paralyzed his own—he could only conclude that in economy,
Malatesta wanted "freedom."
The absence of method, of coordinated thought has caused a brilliant
intelligence, a sharp mind to be somehow wasted for lack of coherence,
of continuity, of will in intellectual effort.
Moreover, Malatesta, more briefly, impugned Bakunin, reproaching him, as
if this had been the essential and the only aspect of the thought of
this formidable man as a thinker and organizer, of having defied nature.
It is truly disconcerting.
Of course, one finds some errors in Kropotkin's writings. I have already
formulated my reservations on various points. Malatesta was right when
he wrote—though others have said it as well—that Kropotkin elaborated
certain ideas, then strove to justify them through science. But does
this go against the use of science in sociology, of the scientific
method, applied according to the aptitudes and the culture of each, of
the systematic and serious study, coordinated, controlled and
recontrolled which, even if it does not claim to be scientific, is so
without knowing it? Not at all. When Kropotkin sees only mutual aid
associations in the corporations of the Middle Ages, he can be
criticized for not having sufficiently emphasized the struggles and
inter-corporative inequalities and the formation of a bourgeoisie of
masters against the companions who were to compose the proletariat. When
he opposes the customary rights to the state, we can respond that if it
is the case that human societies have been known, in certain periods, to
live on the basis of these rights, that customs have been often worse
than the law, and that all things considered, the latter is still
preferable. When he attributes to the masses a too-spontaneous creative
gift, we can respond that is wrong to do so because he also recommends
what the Kropotkinist "mass" has not wanted to see, the responsible and
relentless activity of revolutionary minorities, and that of the
anarchist minority for the present and the immediate future.
We can still make other reproaches, justified and founded otherwise than
those of Malatesta. But I ask if, in the elaboration of all sciences, in
the research and discovery of all the great truths which involve
prolonged studies, has it not always been so? Must science be abandoned
if it has made more than one mistake? To demolish everything because
contradictions are revealed in the successive contributions of
researchers? And to fall back on an empiricism dominated by ignorance or
irresponsibility?
Whatever may be the errors for which we may reproach Kropotkin, at the
very least the method he recommended offers, as is proper with all
scientific method, the possibility of correction, rectification, and
successive complement. Those who apply it will have a much greater
chance to find the truth than those who will write a bit haphazardly, as
has Malatesta. A social movement, a social philosophy, a current of
thought cannot work usefully, according to the goals they pursue, unless
they act in an organic way, in a continuity of coherent efforts where
the critical spirit, which oversees all research, is a guide for a
better construction.
Malatesta has not been an example of this, and he himself, the
anti-Kropotkinian, was Kropotkinian in the best of his pamphlets, the
small masterpiece, "Anarchy." The theses he developed there are borrowed
from Mutual Aid, which I name again, because this book, with all we
learn therein, poses the foundation of a biological and social
philosophy, theoretical and practical, of immense scope. If we are
capable of developing the fundamental theses and intrinsic
possibilities, even as we prune what may appear to us to be
questionable, our ideas will exert an enormous positive influence on the
future of humanity. They will not exert any with the "thought," or the
Malatestan method of thought-absent-method, in spite of the sometimes
interesting insights which one finds there.