💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › errico-malatesta-science-and-social-reform.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:43:14. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Science and Social Reform
Author: Errico Malatesta
Date: 1913
Language: en
Topics: science, scientific socialism, Marxism
Source: The Method of Freedom: An Errico Malatesta Reader, edited by Davide Turcato, translated by Paul Sharkey.
Notes: Man! (San Francisco) 3, no. 2 [recte 3] (March 1935), translated by Eli J. Boche. Originally published as “Scienza e riforma sociale,” Volontà (Ancona) 1, no. 29 (27 December 1913).

Errico Malatesta

Science and Social Reform

The great scientific discoveries of the nineteenth century and the

victorious criticism which science made against the lies and the errors

of religions, had the effect upon progressive spirits, of making them

enthusiastic admirers if not intelligent and patient cultivators, of

science. These progressives exaggerated the importance of science by

attributing to it the power to solve and understand everything; they

made of science a new religion.

Social reformers of every kind that is, of every kind which, by whatever

means and ends, wished to modify the existing social order believed

themselves obliged to found their aspirations upon Science. Similarly,

the conservatives also, when they saw that religious faith was

vacillating and that it was no longer sufficient to keep the people in

subjection, sought to justify the existing regime by means of science.

It was verily a state of intellectual intoxication (not yet vanished)

which caused the loss of a clear concept of nature and of the methods

and scope of science, and it was to the utter detriment of scientific

truth and social action.

Hardly anyone was saved; and if we anarchists were saved from the

ridiculousness of calling ourselves scientific anarchists, it was

perhaps only because the adjective “scientific” had already been taken

and rendered antipathetic by Marxian socialism. In fact, many of our

Comrades (and among them some of the most deserving and illustrious)

actually maintained that Anarchism is a deduction consolidated with

scientific truths, and, furthermore, that it is nothing but the

application of the mechanical conception of the universe to human

interests.[1]

Meanwhile, the fact that they remain anarchists even while science

progresses and changes, demonstrates the fallacy of their scientific-ism

and demonstrates likewise, that their anarchism is derived from their

sentiments and not from their scientific convictions. But, in spite of

their professed objectivism, in practice they will not admit facts or

accept theories which seem to contradict their anarchical aspirations.

And, if they had not had the opportunity to pursue scientific studies,

or science did not exist and human knowledge had remained in the state

in which it was centuries ago,[2] they would probably be anarchists just

the same because, being good and sensible men, they would suffer because

of human sorrows and would want to find a remedy and because, being

proud and just men, they would rebel against oppression and would want

complete liberty for themselves and for all. In addition they recognize

the quality of conscious anarchism in that immense majority of Comrades

who do not know science, and, when they do propaganda work, they do just

as we do, that is, they seek to awaken in men the sentiments of personal

dignity and love of others; they strive to excite the passion for

liberty and justice; they speak of general well-being and of human

brotherhood; they bring to light the social ills and they arouse the

desire to destroy them; and they do not wait until the people have

studied mathematics, astronomy, and chemistry.

The study of the sciences is an excellent thing and we will speak later

of those things which they serve. But to pretend that anarchism (and the

same holds true for socialism or any other human aspiration) is a

scientific deduction and especially, therefore, a consequence of one of

those vast cosmogonical hypotheses in which philosophy takes such great

delight, is a thing which is false per se and is pernicious because of

the consequent effect it can have upon the intellectual development of

individuals and upon their capacity as combatants.

The idea of a personal god, creator of all things, which is the oldest,

the most ingenuous, and the most grossly absurd of these hypotheses, has

done immense harm because it has accustomed people to believing without

understanding and, by suffocating the spirit of examination, it has made

intellectual slaves, well prepared to support political and economic

slavery.

But do not scientific hypotheses do the same when they are presented as

firm facts and as motives for actions, to those who know little or

nothing of science and who are therefore in no position to judge? Some

vague notions of scientific facts, more or less true, and the knowledge

of a few strange words, are not enough to make of a man a scientist or

even one who knows what he is talking about or who can choose from among

the things that he is told.

For the public in general Moses and Haeckel are equally mythical figures

and the belief in the monism of the one rather than in the genesis of

the other just because it happens to be in style in the present

environment, does not make one any the less ignorant, any the less

superstitious, or any the less religious.[3] And to speak to the

unbelievers of atoms, ions, and electrons (which are only hypotheses for

explaining and binding certain categories of fact—convenient hypotheses

useful to the ends of scientific research, but, nevertheless, only

hypotheses, simple mental concepts, and not at all positive discoveries,

pace friend Cassisa)[4]—to speak, I say, without adequate preparation,

of mysterious and incomprehensible things to one who does not

understand, is the same as to speak of god and of angels. It means the

teaching of words as things and the accustoming of the mind to

contenting itself with affirmations which it can neither understand, nor

prove, nor define.

This would be only a change in religion because it would still be a

religion in the sense of blind submission to a revealed truth, which can

be neither controlled nor comprehended. If it were true that anarchy is

a scientific truth, then there would be no real anarchists except the

very few scientists who would call themselves such; all we others would

constitute a non-conscious herd which would blindly follow a few holy

men who had been initiated into the reasons for faith!

Nor is there any difference in the moral deductions or in the social

applications which can be obtained out of the various cosmogonical

theories. The priests had God say the things which were convenient to

them and they used him as a medium for justifying and strengthening the

dominion of the victors.

However, in the course of history there was no lack of rebels who, in

the name of God, preached justice and equality. It is said that

everything occurs by the will of God and that, therefore, we must accept

with resignation our own position. But it can also be said that

rebellion is holy since it does occur and hence must be willed by God.

It can also be said that, if God is the common father, we are all

brothers and ought, therefore, to be equal. In sum, this idea may be

turned in any manner, to suit any taste—for example, we know that

Mazzini invented God of goodness, of love, and of progress, who was

entirely different from the ferocious God of Pius IX.

Bakunin used to say that, if God exists, men can have neither liberty

nor dignity. Another might say—and many, in fact, have said it—that if

all is matter, if everything is subject to natural laws, the will is an

illusion, liberty a chimera and man nothing but an automaton.

So it is that, if the convictions and the moral aspirations are based

upon the mobile foundations of philosophic hypotheses, they are always

uncertain and mutable. Like the catholic who, basing his conduct upon

belief in God, is left without any moral criterion as soon as his faith

is shaken, so the anarchist, if he were really an anarchist because of

scientific convictions, would have to continually consult the latest

bulletins of the Academy of Science in order to determine whether he can

continue to be an anarchist.

Cassisa furnishes an example of how, by means of philosophy, the

simplest and most evident things can be confounded. According to him,

“the principle of property is based upon the false belief in creation

from nothing.” I, truly, do not understand what he wants to say: but it

seems to me that if, before having a revolution and expropriating the

holders of social wealth, we must first attend to nothing but the

question of the origin of the world, then the capitalists may sleep in

tranquility! Oh, isn’t it much more simple, much more comprehensible, to

say that, however the world may have been formed, it is here and ought

to serve the needs of all, and to incite the workers to take it and to

work it on their own account, and to no longer permit themselves to be

despoiled by those who, by violence or fraud, have made themselves the

owners?

---

If then, from the clouds of philosophy, we descend to the more solid

domain of the positive sciences and of the so-called social sciences, we

find here, too, that they can serve to defend the most diverse political

regimes, the most contradictory social aspirations. From the immense

heap of more of less established facts, each one chooses those which

support his own position, and each one formulates theories which in

reality, become programs, desires, and objectives which he proposes and

which he, deluding himself as well as others, calls scientific truths.

In the interpretation of the facts of natural history, in anthropology,

in the philosophy of history, in political economy, and in every phase

of sociology, at every turning of a page we come upon dubious

affirmations which say “it is” when they should say “it ought to be” or,

better, “I wish it were.” The result is that scientific, objective, and

impartial investigation suffers; the social struggle passes from the

ardent field of passion and interest which are its very own, to

degenerate itself in the chattering of the academicians and the pedants.

Science gathers facts, classifies them, and, when it finds that these

facts are necessary and that they necessarily reproduce themselves every

time the same conditions are set up, formulates natural laws. The latter

are, for this reason, nothing but affirmations that under given

conditions certain definite phenomena occur. But this does not tell man

what to desire, whether he should love or hate, be good or bad, just or

unjust. Goodness, justice, and right are concepts which science ignores

completely.

Science tends to delimit the field between fatalism and free will. The

more science advances the more powerful does man become because he

learns what are the the necessary conditions which he must fulfill in

order to be able to execute his will. But this will, executed or not,

remains an extra scientific force with its own origins and its own

tendencies.

Toxology teaches us the physiology of poisons, but it does not tell us

whether we should use the acquired knowledge to poison or to cure

people. Mechanics discovers the laws of equilibrium and of the

resistance of materials, it teaches us to build bridges, steamships, and

aeroplanes, but it does not tell us whether it is better to build the

bridge where it may serve the greed of a proprietor, or where it may

serve the interests of all; it does not tell us whether ships and planes

should be used to carry soldiers and to hurl bombs upon the people or to

spread throughout the world, civility, well-being, and brotherhood.

Science is a weapon that can serve for good or for evil; but it ignores

completely the idea of good or evil.

So then, we are not anarchists, because sciences tell us to be: we are,

instead, anarchists because, among other reasons, we want everyone to be

able to enjoy the advantages and the joys that science can procure for

us.

[1] The implicit but obvious reference is to the theories of Peter

Kropotkin.

[2] The words from “science did” to “knowledge had” were missing from

the English version. They have been added on the basis of the Italian

original.

[3] Ernst Haeckel (1834–1919) was a German scientist who promoted and

popularized Darwin’s theories. His philosophical monism proposed the

unity of organic and physical nature, including social phenomena and

mental processes.

[4] In the article “L’Anarchia è atea” (Anarchy is atheistic), which

appeared in the previous issue of VolontĂ , the anarchist Gian Salvatore

Cassisa had taken issue with Malatesta on religion and science. Taking a

strongly positivistic stance, he had maintained that Anarchy was the

synthesis of a new “scientific civilization.”