💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › anarcho-propertarianism-and-fascism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:27:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Propertarianism and Fascism
Author: Anarcho
Date: November 6, 2018
Language: en
Topics: property, right libertarianism, fascism
Source: Retrieved on 24th April 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=1083

Anarcho

Propertarianism and Fascism

As discussed previously in ASR (in “160 Years of Libertarian,” ASR

71–2), the good word libertarian was knowingly stolen from the left by

American right-wing (classical) liberals in the 1950s. This

appropriation of libertarian to describe an ideology which happily

supports “voluntary” slavery and dictatorship by property owners, never

mind wage-labour, has resulted in much confusion – as well as ASR

(Anarcho-Syndicalist Review changing its name from Libertarian Labor

Review in the 1990s.

In short, in America the word has reversed its meaning in a few decades.

That the new “libertarians” were not particularly libertarian has been

noted by many perplexed observers for they regularly express

authoritarian ideas while wholeheartedly supporting the authoritarian

social-relationships which genuine libertarians had opposed. This is why

the ideology is better termed propertarianism.

It is also seen by their respective positions on fascism: genuine

libertarians fought fascism tooth-and-nail from its birth in Italy to

now while those proclaimed today as “libertarians” have praised and

supported it with a grim regularity. This can be seen by Ludwig von

Mises, as his biographer Jörg Guido Hülsmann cannot quite bring himself

to admit in spite of the evidence he presents in Mises: The Last Knight

of Liberalism (Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2007).

Ludwig von Mises (1881–1973) was a leading member of what is termed the

Austrian School of economics, which advocates no state intervention

beyond defining and defending capitalist property rights. He was chief

economist for the Austrian Chamber of Commerce, before emigrating to the

United States in 1940, where the American propertarians have been

strongly influenced by his writings (John Kenneth Galbraith once noted

in passing, that the Austrian economy did much better once the

economists of the Austrian school stayed in America after the war.).

As another propertarian recounts, “[d]uring this period [of the Great

Depression] Mises was chief economist for the Austrian Chamber of

Commerce. Before Dollfuss was murdered for his politics [in July 1934,

by Nazis], Mises was one of his closest advisers.” (Hans-Hermann Hoppe,

“The Meaning of the Mises Papers,” Free Market Vol. 14, No. 4 [April

1997]) Hoppe, like Hülsmann, does not mention some important aspects of

this period. Engelbert Dollfuss (1892–1934) was an Austrian Christian

Social and Patriotic Front politician who became Federal Chancellor in

1932. In March 1933, he shut down parliament and governed as dictator by

emergency decree. He fully suppressed the Socialist and trade union

movement in February 1934, when he cemented austrofascism – similar to

Italian fascism – through the authoritarian First of May Constitution.

Our hagiographer, sorry, biographer seeks to downplay von Mises’ support

for fascism and cannot bring himself to admit that Dollfuss was a

fascist, although he has to admit that Dollfuss “abolished the

parliamentary republic” and “ruled dictatorially.” (676) He also notes

“the government of Engelbert Dollfuss, which had reintroduced

authoritarian corporatism into Austrian politics to resist the socialism

of both the Marxist and the Nazi variety” (683) but fails to mention

this is called Austrofascism for a reason.

Not that the Nazis were socialists, in spite of their name. For the

Nazis called themselves “National Socialists” because they wanted to

appeal to a population with a significant number of socialists in it and

where even the conservatives embraced some form of welfare state

(Bismarck famously built elements of the welfare state in the 1880s to

tempt workers away from social democracy). In short, the German fascists

tried to steal “socialist” from the left just as the American

propertarians knowingly stole “libertarian” from the left decades later.

We should remember that regardless of current right-wing revisionism, at

the time the wider right supported fascism – including the Nazis. The

right, along with business, saw its benefits for breaking unions,

removing agitators, and such like – not to mention getting funds from

the new regime. Indeed, the Nazis placed many formally nationalised

enterprises back into private hands and so coined the term

“privatisation.”

While our biographer takes pains to distance von Mises from fascism, his

support for Dolfuss was very much in line with his late 1920s eulogising

of fascism in the book Liberalism. Hülsmann does quote this infamous

passage in a footnote:

“It cannot be denied that fascism and similar movements aiming at the

establishment of dictatorships are full of the best intentions and that

their intervention has, for the moment, saved European civilization. The

merit that fascism has thereby won for itself will live on eternally in

history. But though its policy has brought salvation for the moment, it

is not the kind which could promise continued success.” (560)

Hülsmann’s ex cathedra complaints that von Mises is unfairly painted as

a supporter of fascism is undermined somewhat by later admitting that

for von Mises “Dollfuss’s authoritarian policies were in his view only a

quick fix to safeguard Austria’s independence—unsuitable in the long

run, especially if the general political mentality did not change.”

(684) Which is exactly what he argued in Liberalism, namely that a dose

of fascism in the short-term is fine, but not as a long-term solution.

For some reason from all this Hülsmann concludes von Mises was not a

supporter of fascism.

Why was von Mises so keen on fascism as “a quick fix”? Some of this was

his fear of (state) socialism – whether in the Bolshevik or social

democratic form. Some of it was based on von Mises’ position on the

Great Depression, namely that economic crisis in Austria had as its

“main culprits” the “welfare state and the labor unions” and so the

“main cause of unemployment was clear: government-supported labor

unions.” (619, 615) Let us ignore that mass unemployment in America came

after the collapse of trade unionism in the 1920s – or that unemployment

fell there as the unions grew in influence. The key point is that von

Mises – like all propertarians – was of that school whose perspective

was memorably summarised by Proudhon:

“Political economy – that is, proprietary despotism – can never be in

the wrong: it must be the proletariat.” (Property is Theft! A

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology [AK Press, 2009], 187)

In short, von Mises was of the opinion that soup kitchens caused the

Great Depression (to use Paul Krugman’s phrase) and that against all

logic and all evidence that unions are strongest in periods of mass

unemployment. Before discussing whether the Austrian experience confirms

von Mises’ position, we need to clarify what “government-supported labor

unions” actually meant. Hülsmann provides a useful quote:

“These union tactics naturally presuppose that the government tolerates

this behavior, at the least. Were it to proceed in its usual way and

interfere with the criminals who abuse jobseekers and vandalize the

machines and other of the entrepreneurs’ facilities, then circumstances

would be different. But that it has capitulated to the unions is the

precise feature that characterizes the modern state.” (620)

So the problem is that the government does not smash the unions, outlaw

picketing, etc. In other words, for von Mises the government takes (what

is the expression? ah, right!) a laissez faire approach to labour

organisation. Our biographer then writes the following words with no

apparent sense of irony or awareness:

“Mises argued that ultimately there was no choice but to abolish all

government intervention and to confront union power head on.” (621)

It takes a true ideologue to not notice the contradiction in urging the

abolition of all government intervention while also urging that troops

be sent in against rebel workers. However, this is no isolated case as

Kropotkin noted:

“Furthermore, the state of laissez-faire, which liberal economists like

to talk to us about, and against which social-democrats love to break

their lances, is a product of the imagination that has never existed and

will not exist since it would be a contradiction of principles.

“Fundamentally, liberal economists (including M. Molinari and Adam

Smith) never wanted it – their ideal having not been laissez-faire, not

laissez-passer, but on the contrary, to do a lot on behalf of the

capitalist. Carte Blanche for exploitation guaranteed by the State –

they never had another ideal. What can be said of the facts? […] when

did the State not take the side of the capitalist against the worker?

They have many sabres and bullets for the workers, but have they ever

thrashed the exploiters?” (“Une Conférence sur l’Anarchie”, La Révolte,

5 August 1893)

While slightly unfair on Adam Smith, this is correct. Hülsmann expresses

an ideological blindness which is staggering – government intervention

against labour and for capitalist property rights is not government

intervention in his eyes. In short, the state clubbing workers is good

(and liberty) but it providing medical care for the cracked heads is

wrong (and tyranny).

Now understanding what von Mises viewed as the root causes of the Great

Depression – high wages and state welfare for workers rather than bosses

– we can now ask did it work? Well, Dollfuss – as a good fascist – did

crush the labour movement and cut back on welfare, as von Mises

recommended but things got worse rather than better.

The onslaught on labour started long before Austria officially became a

dictatorship in 1934 as the government sought to balance the budget and

imposed austerity (as von Mises recommended). Yet the “effects of the

government’s policies were to be seen in the continued stagnation of the

Austrian economy right up to the German invasion of 1938. By 1932

industrial production had fallen to 61 per cent of its 1929 output, and

unemployment had reached 21.7 per cent of the workforce. It remained at

this level throughout the mid 1930s, and still stood at 20.4 per cent in

1937.” (Tom Kirk, Nazism and the working class in Austria: industrial

unrest and political dissent in the ‘national community [Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1996], 31)

It must first be noted that the welfare state was rudimentary at best. A

worker “had to provide evidence of twenty weeks work during the previous

year to be eligible” for unemployment benefit, which “ceased altogether

after fifty-two weeks” and after twenty-two weeks if under 25. In 1931,

the average unemployment benefit was 891 shillings a year and so

“approximately one quarter of the average worker’s income,” falling to

769 shillings in 1933. (Jill Lewis, Fascism and the working class in

Austria, 1918–1934: the failure of labour in the First Republic [New

York/Oxford: Berg, 1991], 169–70) That benefits “were meagre for only

one year” meant “that the long term unemployed – perhaps half as many

again as the number of claimants had no means of support.” Ironically,

“benefits for the long-term unemployed, abolished by the ‘Corporate

State,’ were restored” by the Nazis after they annexed Austria. (Kirk,

31, 49)

As for those in work, the situation hardly suggested a rise in union

power. Indeed, “[i]n the vain hope of avoiding more redundancies, many

workers were at first willing to accept a reduction in hourly rates, in

addition to cuts in the working day.” As von Mises had urged, the

government “backed the employers. In fact government action had given

the employers the green light in the first place. Under the terms of the

1930 Anti-Terror Act the legal status of collective contracts had been

altered, invalidating all closed shop agreements and halting the

practice of deducting union dues at source.” The appointment of a known

union buster to the director of the national railways in 1930 and “by

the introduction of the Anti-Terror Act the government had shown that

the attack on the Free Trade Unions, which had hitherto been led by

private employers, was to be extended to the public sector and

intensified.” (Lewis, 173, 175–6) In short:

“Rising unemployment strengthened the hand of the employers in the

labour, and they attempted to dismantle what was left of the Republic’s

labour legislation […] There was a noticeable effect on the incidence of

industrial action. The number of disputes fell from 242 in 1928 to 30 in

1932, and over the same period the total number of strikers declined

from 562,992 to 79,942, reflecting the erosion of economic security.”

(Kirk, 31–2)

Thus the “depression also gave the employers even greater opportunities

to attack the remaining labour legislation.” For example, in 1931 one

pit director successfully fired all 1,300 miners and offered them

re-employment if they accepted individual contracts and rejected

collective bargaining. The “tactic was then repeated in other plants and

other companies” and “without collective contracts the battle for

employment became a free-for-all, in which workers could undercut each

other for work.” Unsurprisingly, there was also “an increase in

industrial accidents.” (Lewis, 173–4)

The “standard of living for those in work declined as wages fell further

and faster than prices” (Kirk, 31) and it is likely that “real wages

fell by between 20 and 30 per cent in the four years from 1929 to 1933.”

This drop in wages did not mean a fall in unemployment but rather a

change in who was employed, with employers initially turning to youth

and women “at rates which were far lower than those of adult males” but

by 1931 “these workers were once again out of work, as wage rates for

men fell to a level which made them once again competitive.” Yet in

spite of falling wages, insured unemployed rose from 110,266 in June

1929 to 307,873 in June 1933. (Lewis, 173–4, 214–5)

As wages fell and unemployment rose during the state and boss onslaught

on labour, the economy worsened with real GDP in falling in 1930 by

2.75%, 8.02% in 1931, 10.32% in 1932 and 3.31% in 1933. (Angus Maddison,

The World Economy: Historical Statistics [OECD Publishing, Paris, 2003],

50) Indeed, unlike other industrial nations, Austria saw no real

reduction in unemployment during the 1930s.

By May 1933, the Dolfuss administration had ended parliamentary rule,

banned “all strikes and demonstrations.” (Lewis, 148) In April 1934 the

government assumed all the powers previously held by parliament and so

became officially a fascist dictatorship rather than a close

approximation. The “new regime brought immediate and tangible gains to

employers at the expense of a further deterioration in working-class

living standards. Firms quickly took advantage of the absence of trade

unions and the weak bargaining position of the workforce to enforce wage

cuts on their workforces.” However, workers “were also often ready to

take collective action against the widespread wage cuts introduced under

the new regime.” Sometimes they were successful, usually – taking one

strike in 1936 which raised the demands for a 15 per cent wage increase

as an example – they were “quickly put down by the authorities” (Kirk,

44, 46 47) Thus the results of these “anti-social economic measures of

the government” were grim:

“A persistent deflationary economic policy combined with an

anti-democratic determination served to demoralise and weaken the

working class […] Dollfuss was determined to use the opportunities

offered by the depression to the full. Once parliament had been closed

down and the government began to rule by emergency degree, a series of

measures were taken to further weaken the organised working class.

‘Economic necessity’ was used as an excuse for such political moves.

Social security payments were reduced. Strikes were forbidden. The

rights of workers to even discuss wages and working conditions were

drastically reduced. […] Thus by February 1934 the condition of the

Austrian working class was miserable […] With massive unemployment, the

erosion of political rights and wretched living conditions the vast

majority of the workers were demoralised, tired, hungry and lacking in a

sense of common purpose and direction.” (Martin Kitchen, The Coming of

Austrian Fascism [Croom Helm, 1980], 94–5)

In short, Dolfuss and his successor followed the advice of von Mises as

regards austerity and confronting the unions: the economy went from bad

to worse (unlike under the New Deal in America). Wages fell and

unemployment rose (so confirming Keynes’ argument in 1936). Unions were

banned and strikes repressed, but unemployment remained at over 20%.

The facts are clear but rest assured for not all is lost for the

propertarian. We must recall that Mises argued that if there is a clash

between your theory and the facts, then the facts are wrong and so

reality must be ignored:

“If a contradiction appears between a theory and experience, we must

always assume that a condition pre-supposed by the theory was not

present, or else there is some error in our observation. The

disagreement between the theory and the facts of experience frequently

forces us to think through the problems of the theory again. But so long

as a rethinking of the theory uncovers no errors in our thinking, we are

not entitled to doubt its truth” (Epistemological Problems of Economics

[New York: Van Nostrand, 1960], 30)

This means that it will be argued that Dollfuss did not follow all the

advice “one of his closest advisors.” Most obviously, the meagre

unemployment benefits for some workers existed for a year rather than

being eliminated. It also could be argued that the state repression did

not go far enough, that some workers still felt able to take collective

action in spite of unions, strikes, protests and assembling being

illegal and subject to attack, that wages were not driven low enough by

employers, and so on. Yet an argument that a fascist regime was not

authoritarian enough would be unconvincing and unappealing to the

unconverted. It could be argued that other Austofascist policies caused

unemployment to stay high, but given that the economy finally stopped

contracting in 1934 and started to grow again (albeit at a low rate)

this is likewise unconvincing given that von Mises left Austria that

year, fearing the rise of the Nazis who would have subjected him – as a

Jew – to similar treatment as he had happily urged against workers.

In short, the period which von Mises provided economic advice to a

fascist leader saw significant drops in real GDP and unemployment rise

to over 20 per cent, in spite of the “main cause” of unemployment having

been eliminated. The same occurred under Thatcher, incidentally, where

unemployment was higher when the Tories left office in 1997 than it was

when they entered it in 1979 (and this in spite of numerous revisions of

the official definition to bring the numbers down).

Still, we must remember when a propertarian publicly supports fascism,

advises fascists, urges state intervention to break the voluntary

associations of working class people, to smash strikes, and so forth

then this is a champion of liberty lecturing us. Or perhaps not. Perhaps

we should remember this grim history and draw obvious conclusions from

it.

Likewise, we should also recall that von Mises was not alone in support

for the “quick-fix” of fascism. Fellow “Austrian” economist von Hayek,

likewise, had long postulated the need for a temporary dictator to

eliminate the excesses of democracy before supporting the dictatorship

of Pinochet in Chile (Andrew Farrant, Edward McPhail and Sebastian

Berger, “Preventing the ‘Abuses’ of Democracy: Hayek, the ‘Military

Usurper’ and Transitional Dictatorship in Chile?” The American Journal

of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 71, No. 3 [July, 2012], pp. 513–538).

Nor should we forget that Milton Friedman praised Pinochet for

introducing a “free market” in Chile: apparently a “free” market in

labour is consistent with workers being terrified of striking – or

merely talking back to their boss – in case their tortured corpse ends

up on the side of the road. Both, needless to say, praised the Chilean

economic “miracle” shortly before it crashed in 1982.

All this does point to the heart of the contradiction in

propertarianism, as Proudhon noted long ago “Individualism, incapable of

resolving a priori its famous problem of the harmony of interests, and

forced to lay down at least provisional laws, abdicates in its turn

before this new power, which was excluded by the pure practice of

liberty.” (De la Justice dans la Revolution et dans l’Eglise [Paris:

Marpon et Flammarion, 1870] vol. I: 123) This is because they are not

interested in liberty but in property. This means that they at best

ignore, at worse defend, the power of the owner over those who use their

property. This leads to obvious – at least obvious to the non-believer –

authoritarian social relations as shown by Murray Rothbard seeming

obliviousness to the grim nature of what he was advocating:

“A particularly thorny question is the whole matter of picketing and

demonstrations. Freedom of speech implies, of course, freedom of

assembly—the freedom to gather together and express oneself in concert

with others. […] But even ‘peaceful picketing’ is not clearly

legitimate, for it is part of a wider problem: Who decides on the use of

the streets? The problem stems from the fact that the streets are almost

universally owned by (local) government. But the government, not being a

private owner, lacks any criterion for allocating the use of its

streets, so that any decision it makes will be arbitrary. […] The police

ban the demonstration, claiming that it will clog the streets and

disrupt traffic. Civil libertarians will automatically protest […] It is

only the universal fact of government ownership and control of the

streets that makes this problem insoluble and cloaks the true solution

to it. The point is that whoever owns a resource will decide on how that

resource is to be used. […] In a purely libertarian world, where all

streets are privately owned, the various street owners will decide, at

any given time, whether to rent out the street for demonstrations, whom

to rent it to, and what price to charge. It would then be clear that

what is involved is not a ‘free speech’ or ‘free assembly’ question at

all, but a question of property rights: of the right of a group to offer

to rent a street, and of the right of the street owner either to accept

or reject the offer.” (Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty: The

Libertarian Manifesto, Macmillan, 1978, 96–7)

Compare this “libertarian world” to the regime Dolfuss created. Thus for

the working class – the non-property owner – there are no freedom of

speech, assembly, organisation, picketing, etc. In short, no liberty at

all. Propertarianism generalises factory fascism and office oligarchy to

all aspects of society, not freedom.

It may help to understand why such blatant contradiction was put into

print by noting that Rothbard was one of von Mises’ pupils, becoming a

leading American “Austrian” economist and playing a key role in the

stealing of the word libertarian as well as inventing the oxymoron

“anarcho-capitalism.” Rothbard is not alone, Robert Nozick – a

well-known propertarian – likewise argued that “if one starts a private

town […] persons who chose to move there or later remain there would

have no right to a say in how the town was run.” Thus dictatorship is

“libertarian” – along with “voluntary” slavery. (Anarchy, State and

Utopia [Oxford: B. Blackwell, 1974], 270, 371) Strangely such positions

did not impact on others accepting his use of the term “libertarian” to

describe such obvious tyranny.

In short, if it reduces the freedom (power) of the property-owner then

they are against it. Which is why almost all propertarians were on the

wrong side of history with regard to every movement for greater freedom

in the 20^(th) century: civil rights, feminism, labour, and so on.

All of which means that so-called “libertarians” supporting fascism is

not that surprising after all. For they are happy to support

authoritarian social relationships (such as wage-labour), particularly

when it is produced by property. Indeed, they get indignant when the

state pays even lip-service to making the property-owner recognise the

rights and liberty of those subject to their authority/property. As

Corey Robin notes, the current association of “libertarians” (i.e.,

propertarians) with conservatives should not come as a surprise for both

share a common perspective in defending subjugation:

“Conservatism, then, is […] the opposition to the liberation of men and

women from the fetters of their superiors, particularly in the private

sphere. Such a view might seem miles away from the libertarian defense

of the free market, with its celebration of the atomistic and autonomous

individual. But it is not. When the libertarian looks out upon society,

he does not see isolated individuals; he sees private, often

hierarchical, groups, where a father governs his family and an owner his

employees.” (Corey Robin, The Reactionary Mind: Conservatism from Edmund

Burke to Sarah Palin, [Oxford University Press, 2011], 15–6)

The difference is the propertarian tries to present such subjugation as

“liberty” while the conservative is more honest:

“Despite the very real differences between them, workers in a factory

are like secretaries in an office, peasants on a manor, slaves on a

plantation—even wives in a marriage—in that they live and labor in

conditions of unequal power. They submit and obey, heeding the demands

of their managers and masters, husbands and lords. They are disciplined

and punished. They do much and receive little. Sometimes their lot is

freely chosen—workers contract with their employers, wives with their

husbands—but its entailments seldom are. What contract, after all, could

ever itemize the ins and outs, the daily pains and ongoing sufferance,

of a job or a marriage? Throughout American history, in fact, the

contract often has served as a conduit to unforeseen coercion and

constraint, particularly in institutions like the workplace and the

family where men and women spend so much of their lives. Employment and

marriage contracts have been interpreted by judges, themselves friendly

to the interests of employers and husbands, to contain all sorts of

unwritten and unwanted provisions of servitude to which wives and

workers tacitly consent, even when they have no knowledge of such

provisions or wish to stipulate otherwise.[…] Every once in a while,

however, the subordinates of this world contest their fates. They

protest their conditions, write letters and petitions, join movements,

and make demands. Their goals may be minimal and discrete—better safety

guards on factory machines, an end to marital rape—but in voicing them,

they raise the specter of a more fundamental change in power. They cease

to be servants or supplicants and become agents, speaking and acting on

their own behalf. More than the reforms themselves, it is this assertion

of agency by the subject class—the appearance of an insistent and

independent voice of demand—that vexes their superiors.” (Robin, 4–6)

As is clear from his writings and activities, von Mises was very vexed

by that spectre – so much as to embrace fascism, at least for a while.

Once the masses were sufficiently terrorised and internalised their

inferior position then a “liberal” regime could and should return. For

as he wrote in a fan letter to Ayn Rand: “You have the courage to tell

the masses what no politician told them: you are inferior and all the

improvements in your conditions which you simply take for granted you

owe to the effort of men who are better than you.” (Hülsmann, 996) It is

no coincidence that he echoed Hitler:

“What right have these people [workers] to demand a share in property or

even in the administration? […] would you permit your typist to have any

voice in your affairs? The employer who accepts the responsibility for

production also gives the workpeople their livelihood. Our greatest

industrialists are not concerned with the acquisition of wealth or with

good living, but, above all else, with responsibility and power. They

have worked their way to the top by their own abilities, and this proof

of their capacity – a capacity only displayed by a higher race – gives

them the right to lead.” (quoted, Konrad Heiden, A History of National

Socialism [Routledge, 2010] 2: 126–7)

Hence the soft-place propertarians have for fascism – for they defend

the dictatorship of the property owner (considered inherently superior)

over those who use their property, a despotism which anarchists and

genuine libertarians have long recognised and opposed in the name of

freedom. That von Mises supported fascism as a mere temporary expedient

is meaningless – after all, he was happy to use the state against uppity

workers rebelling against their betters in “normal” times.

We will end by ignoring Hülsmann’s gibberish when repeating – when not

adding to – von Mises’ clearly ignorant commentary of syndicalism and

“socialism,” in favour of noting his summation of von Mises’

post-fascist vision:

“Mises championed a program of thorough political centralization […] the

state alone should direct the whole administration of the county […] The

communal authorities would have to execute the tasks set for them by the

general legislation. Their only revenue would come from the state and

from public firms and property.” (743–4)

It should be noted that von Mises urged this centralised, top-down state

because he had seen municipal socialism in Austria before Dollfuss. It

was driven by the urge to stop experiments like “Red Vienna” which saw

the local municipality provide housing, swimming baths, parks, health

care, school meals alongside a fall in child morality from 158 deaths

per thousand live births in 1918 to 60 per thousand in 1933. (Lewis,

77–8) Better for children to die at birth than a millionaire be taxed to

prevent it – if children did not want to die then they should have

chosen parents who earned enough for private health care.

As Thatcherism showed, neo-liberalism is marked by an increase in the

authoritarian tendencies of the state – at least for the many. As well

as using the state to break the unions, she also embraced von Mises’s

post-fascist political vision when faced with the problem that people

would vote locally for parties which would protect them from the market

fundamentalism of the government (this had also happened in the late

19^(th) and early 20^(th) centuries with municipal socialism developing

across Britain to counter-act the evils of freer-market capitalism –

Kropotkin mentions these experiments in Modern Science and Anarchy [AK

Press, 2018]). This annoyed her and so people had to be forced to be

free: Britain was turned from a relatively decentralised system into the

most centralised in Europe. This did not stop Tories prattling on about

“localism” – as shown most recently when such talk was quickly forgotten

to allow fracking to take place against overwhelming local opposition.

While Thatcher did not completely destroy trade unionism, she did

regulate it (while denouncing the dead-hand of regulations on “the

market”). She made it illegal for unionists to strike spontaneously and

to show solidarity with others. Her party has followed her, imposing a

50% turn-out requirement for strike action which became law in 2016.

Inequality has soared, low wages abound, and productivity gains flow

upwards… what a surprise. Indeed, social problems have got so bad that

the Tory party today pays lip-service about addressing the evils its own

policies have caused.

Which raises the issue of elections, particularly given the hideous

current governments in America and Britain. The experience of the right

always makes “the left” look better (as if the best of the Democrats

were anything other than slightly to the left!). The anarchist argument

against electoral reformism is not that it cannot lead to improvements

in working-class life (it has) but these benefits will not be as great,

as long lasting or as empowering as those won by working class people by

their own direct action and solidarity. More, by giving such functions

to the capitalist state it allows future governments – conservative or

social democratic – to undermine such reforms as well as determine how

they are run (that is, run not be in the interests of our class but

rather to bolster the system). Also, such intervention can become – as

in “Red Vienna” – paternalistic as well as inevitably changing the

party, which goes from seeking to transform the system to – at best –

tinkering with it. Most fatally, it accustoms labour to rely on others

to act on its behalf and so hinders its ability to resist when it counts

– as shown by the success of the CNT in 1936 and the failure of Marxism

in 1933 and 1934 in Germany and Austria, respectively.

Which means that whether you vote or not is ultimately irrelevant – is

it what you do before and after that 5 minutes in the voting booth which

counts. Our masters know this, as shown by von Mises’ hatred of trade

unionism and the neo-liberal onslaught against labour since Reagan and

Thatcher. Time we recognised this and organised where it counts – in our

workplaces and communities. This is a much harder task than voting once

in a while but it is the only means by which freedom can be defended and

conditions improved in the here and now, never mind create the

possibility of a free and just society.