💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › peter-sabatini-libertarianism-bogus-anarchy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:30:01. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy Author: Peter Sabatini Date: 1994–1995 Language: en Topics: individualist, right libertarian Source: Retrieved on December 3, 2009 from http://www.spunk.org/library/otherpol/critique/sp000713.txt Notes: This article appears in issue #41 (Fall/Winter 1994–95) of Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed available for 3.50 postpaid from B.A.L. Press, P.O. Box 2647, New York, NY 10009.
A distinct mainstream movement specific to the United States,
Libertarianism had its inception during the 1960s. In 1971 it formed
into a political party and went on to make a strong showing in several
elections.[1]
Libertarianism is at times referred to as “anarchism,” and certain of
its adherents call themselves “anarchists,” e.g., the economist James
Buchanan.[2] More significant, the work of US individualist anarchists
(Benjamin Tucker et al.) is cited by some Libertarians.[3] Accordingly,
it may rightly be asked whether Libertarianism is in fact anarchism.
Exactly what is the relationship between the two? To properly decide the
question requires a synopsis of anarchist history.
The chronology of anarchism within the United States corresponds to what
transpired in Europe and other locations. An organized anarchist
movement imbued with a revolutionary collectivist, then communist,
orientation came to fruition in the late 1870s. At that time, Chicago
was a primary center of anarchist activity within the USA, due in part
to its large immigrant population.[4] (Chicago was also where the
Haymarket affair occurred in 1886. An unknown assailant threw a bomb as
police broke up a public protest demonstration. Many radicals were
arrested, and several hanged on the flimsiest of evidence.) Despite off
and on political repression, the US anarchist movement continued in an
expansive mode until the mid-1890s, when it then began to flounder. By
1900, anarchy was visibly in decline.[5]
But like its counterpart in Europe, anarchism’s marginalization in the
United States was temporarily slowed by the arrival of syndicalism.
North American syndicalism appeared 1904–1905 in the form of a militant
unionism known as the Industrial Workers of the World (IWW). Anarchists
entered the IWW along with revolutionary socialists. The alliance did
not last long. [6] Internal squabbles soon split the IWW, and for a time
there existed anarchist and socialist versions. Finally, with
involvement of the US in WWI, the anarchist IWW, and anarchism in
general, dropped from the public domain.[7]
Anarchy in the USA consisted not only of the
Bakunin-collectivist/syndicalist and Kropotkin-communist strains, but
also the Proudhon-mutualist/individualist variant associated most
closely with Benjamin Tucker. Individualist anarchy actually had a
longer history of duration within the United States than the other two,
but not only because Proudhon preceded Bakunin and Kropotkin. There were
other individualist anarchists before Tucker who had ties to various
radical movements which predate Proudhon. Within the United States of
early to mid-19^(th) century, there appeared an array of communal and
“utopian” counterculture groups (including the so-called free love
movement). William Godwin’s anarchism exerted an ideological influence
on some of this, but more so the socialism of Robert Owen and Charles
Fourier. [8] After success of his British venture, Owen himself
established a cooperative community within the United States at New
Harmony, Indiana during 1825. One member of this commune was Josiah
Warren (1798–1874), considered to be the first individualist
anarchist.[9] After New Harmony failed Warren shifted his ideological
loyalties from socialism to anarchism (which was no great leap, given
that Owen’s socialism had been predicated on Godwin’s anarchism).[10]
Then he founded his own commune (“Modern Times”) and propounded an
individualist doctrine which nicely dovetailed with Proudhon’s mutualism
arriving from abroad.[11] Warren’s activities attracted a number of
converts, some of whom helped to further develop American mutualism. The
most important of these were Ezra Heywood (1829–1893), William B. Greene
(1819–1878), and Lysander Spooner (1808–1887). The advent of the Civil
War put an end to much of the utopian movement and its communal living
experiments. Individualist anarchism was itself reduced to an agitprop
journalistic enterprise of some measurable popularity.[12]
And in this form it found its most eloquent voice with Benjamin Tucker
and his magazine Liberty. Tucker had been acquainted with Heywood and
other individualist anarchists, and he subsequently converted to
mutualism.[13] Thereafter he served as the movement’s chief polemist and
guiding hand.
The Proudhonist anarchy that Tucker represented was largely superseded
in Europe by revolutionary collectivism and anarcho-communism. The same
changeover occurred in the US, although mainly among subgroups of
working class immigrants who were settling in urban areas. For these
recent immigrants caught up in tenuous circumstances within the vortex
of emerging corporate capitalism, a revolutionary anarchy had greater
relevancy than go slow mutualism. On the other hand, individualist
anarchism also persisted within the United States because it had the
support of a different (more established, middle class, and formally
educated) audience that represented the earlier stream of indigenous
North American radicalism reflecting this region’s unique, and rapidly
fading, decentralized economic development. Although individualist and
communist anarchy are fundamentally one and the same doctrine, their
respective supporters still ended up at loggerheads over tactical
differences.[14] But in any event, the clash between the two variants
was ultimately resolved by factors beyond their control. Just as
anarcho-communism entered a political twilight zone in the 1890s,
American mutualism did likewise. Tucker’s bookstore operation burned
down in 1908, and this not only terminated publication of Liberty, but
also what remained of the individualist anarchism “movement.” The
aggregate of support upon which this thread of thought had depended was
already in dissipation.[15] Individualist anarchy after 1900 receded
rapidly to the radical outback.
What then does any of this have to do with Libertarianism? In effect,
nothing, aside from a few unsupported claims. Libertarianism is not
anarchism, but actually a form of liberalism. It does, however, have a
point of origin that is traceable to the same juncture as anarchism’s
marginalization. So in this limited sense there is a shared commonality.
To be more precise, the rapid industrialization that occurred within the
United States after the Civil War went hand in glove with a sizable
expansion of the American state.[16] At the turn of the century, local
entrepreneurial (proprietorship/partnership) business was overshadowed
in short order by transnational corporate capitalism.[17] The
catastrophic transformation of US society that followed in the wake of
corporate capitalism fueled not only left wing radicalism (anarchism and
socialism), but also some prominent right wing opposition from dissident
elements anchored within liberalism. The various stratum comprising the
capitalist class responded differentially to these transpiring events as
a function of their respective position of benefit. Small business that
remained as such came to greatly resent the economic advantage corporate
capitalism secured to itself, and the sweeping changes the latter
imposed on the presumed ground rules of bourgeois competition.[18]
Nevertheless, because capitalism is liberalism’s raison d’être, small
business operators had little choice but to blame the state for their
financial woes, otherwise they moved themselves to another ideological
camp (anti-capitalism). Hence, the enlarged state was imputed as the
primary cause for capitalism’s “aberration” into its monopoly form, and
thus it became the scapegoat for small business complaint. Such
sentiments are found vented within a small body of literature extending
from this time, e.g., Albert Jay Nock’s Our Enemy, The State (1935);
what may now rightly be called proto-Libertarianism.[19]
As a self-identified ideological movement, however, Libertarianism took
more definite shape from the 1940s onward through the writings of
novelist Ayn Rand. The exaltation of liberal individualism and minimal
state laissez-faire capitalism that permeates Rand’s fictional work as a
chronic theme attracted a cult following within the United States. To
further accommodate supporters, Rand fashioned her own popular
philosophy (“Objectivism”) and a membership organization. Many of those
who would later form the nucleus of Libertarianism came out of
Objectivism, including two of its chief theoreticians, John Hospers and
Murray Rothbard.[20] Another conduit into Libertarianism carried a
breakaway faction from William F. Buckley’s college youth club, the
Edmund Burke-style conservative Young Americans For Freedom.[21] More
academic input arrived from the Austrian school of neoclassical
economics promulgated by F.A. Hayek and Ludwig von Mises (of which the
economist Rothbard subscribes).[22] All these marginal streams
intermingled during the mid to late 1960s, and finally settled out as
Libertarianism in the early 1970s.[23]
It is no coincidence that Libertarianism solidified and conspicuously
appeared on the scene just after the United States entered an economic
downturn (at the same time Keynesian economics was discredited and
neoclassical theory staged a comeback). The world-wide retrenchment of
capitalism that began in the late 1960s broke the ideological strangle
hold of a particular variant of (Locke-Rousseau) liberalism, thereby
allowing the public airing of other (Locke-Burke) strains representing
disaffected elements within the capitalist class, including small
business interests. Libertarianism was one aspect of this New Right
offensive. It appeared to be something sui generis. Libertarianism
provided a simplistic status quo explanation to an anxious middle class
threatened by the unfathomed malaise of capitalism and growing societal
deterioration, i.e., blame the state. And this prevalent grasping at
straws attitude accounts for the success of Robert Nozick’s
popularization of Libertarianism, Anarchy, State, And Utopia (1974). It
rode the crest of this polemic rift within liberalism. The book was
deemed controversial, even extreme, by establishment liberals (and
social democrats long pacified by the welfare state), who, secure in
power for decades, were now under sustained attack by their own right
wing. Yet at bedrock, Nozick’s treatise was nothing more than old wine
in a new bottle, an updating of John Locke.[24]
Libertarianism is not anarchism. Some Libertarians readily admit this.
For example, Ayn Rand, the radical egoist, expressly disavows the
communal individuality of Stirner in favor of liberalism’s stark
individualism.[25] Plus Robert Nozick makes pointed reference to the US
individualist anarchists, and summarily dismisses them.[26] This
explicit rejection of anarchism is evidence of the basic liberalist
ideology that Libertarians hold dear. But more specifically, within the
movement itself there exist factional interests.[27] There are
Libertarians who emphasize lifestyle issues and civil liberties (an
amplification of John Stuart Mill’s On Liberty). They want the state out
of their “private” lives, e.g., in drug use and sexual activity. Others
are chiefly concerned with economics. They champion laissez-faire
“free-market” neoclassical economics, and fault the state for corrupting
“natural” capitalism. Although both groups despise the state intensely,
neither wants to completely do away with it. This minimal state
position, sufficient by itself to debar Libertarianism from
classification as anarchism, is embraced by Rand, Buchanan, Hospers, and
Nozick.[28] More revealing, however, is why Libertarians retain the
state. What they always insist on maintaining are the state’s coercive
apparatuses of law, police, and military.[29] The reason flows directly
from their view of human nature, which is a hallmark of liberalism, not
anarchism. That is, Libertarianism ascribes social problems within
society (crime, poverty, etc.) to an inherent disposition of humans (re:
why Locke argues people leave the “state of nature”), hence the constant
need for “impartial” force supplied by the state. Human corruption and
degeneracy stemming from structural externalities as a function of power
is never admitted because Libertarianism, like liberalism, fully
supports capitalism. It does not object to its power, centralization,
economic inequality, hierarchy, and authority. The “liberty” to exploit
labor and amass property unencumbered by the state is the quintessence
of capitalism, and the credo of Libertarianism née liberalism, all of
which is the utter negation of anarchism.
Lastly to be addressed is the apparent anomaly of Murray Rothbard.
Within Libertarianism, Rothbard represents a minority perspective that
actually argues for the total elimination of the state. However
Rothbard’s claim as an anarchist is quickly voided when it is shown that
he only wants an end to the public state. In its place he allows
countless private states, with each person supplying their own police
force, army, and law, or else purchasing these services from capitalist
venders.[30] Rothbard has no problem whatsoever with the amassing of
wealth, therefore those with more capital will inevitably have greater
coercive force at their disposal, just as they do now. Additionally, in
those rare moments when Rothbard (or any other Libertarian) does draw
upon individualist anarchism, he is always highly selective about what
he pulls out. Most of the doctrine’s core principles, being decidedly
anti-Libertarianism, are conveniently ignored, and so what remains is
shrill anti-statism conjoined to a vacuous freedom in hackneyed defense
of capitalism. In sum, the “anarchy” of Libertarianism reduces to a
liberal fraud. David Wieck’s critique of Rothbard, applicable to
Libertarianism in general, will close this discussion.
“Out of the history of anarchist thought and action Rothbard has pulled
forth a single thread, the thread of individualism, and defines that
individualism in a way alien even to the spirit of a Max Stirner or a
Benjamin Tucker, whose heritage I presume he would claim — to say
nothing of how alien is his way to the spirit of Godwin, Proudhon,
Bakunin, Kropotkin, Malatesta, and the historically anonymous persons
who through their thoughts and action have tried to give anarchism a
living meaning. Out of this thread Rothbard manufactures one more
bourgeois ideology.”[31]
Â
[1] David DeLeon, The American As Anarchist: Reflections On Indigenous
Radicalism (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University, 1978), p. 147; Jay
Kinney;
“What’s Left? Revisiting The Revolution”, in Stewart Brand, ed., The
Next Whole Earth Catalog (Sausalito, CA: Point, 1980), p. 393;
David Miller, Anarchism (London: J.M. Dent & Sons, 1984), p. 4. By
itself, the fact that Libertarianism formed a political party and has
attempted to attain power through the electoral system seriously
undermines its claim to be anarchism.
[2] James M. Buchanan, “A Contractarian Perspective On Anarchy”, in J.
Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds., Anarchism: NOMOS XIX (New
York: New York University, 1978), p. 29. Libertarianism is also referred
to as “anarcho-capitalism” and “philosophical anarchism.” The word
“libertarian” was used by French anarchists in the 1890s as a synonym
for “anarchist.” Consequently, some contemporary anarchists refer to
themselves and/or anarchy as “libertarian.” But here there is no implied
connection to Libertarianism. Michael P. Smith, The Libertarians And
Education (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1983), pp. 2, 3.
[3] David Friedman, The Machinery Of Freedom: Guide To Radical
Capitalism, Second Edition (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1989), pp. 37,
113; Murray Rothbard, For A New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto
(Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1978), pp. 51–52.
[4] Bruce Nelson, Beyond The Martyrs: A Social History of Chicago’s
Anarchists, 1870–1900 (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University, 1988), pp.
4, 15, 25; Laurence Veysey,
The Communal Experience: Anarchist and Mystical Counter-Cultures in
America (New York: Harper & Row, 1973), p. 35.
[5] Ibid., p. 35.
[6] Sima Lieberman, Labor Movements And Labor Thought: Spain, France,
Germany, and the United States (New York: Praeger Publishers, 1986), p.
247.
Dorothy Gallagher, All The Right Enemies: The Life and Murder of Carlo
Tresca (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University, 1988), pp. 60–61.
[7] James Joll, The Anarchists. Second Edition (London: Metheun, 1979),
pp. 201–203; Miller, pp. 134–135;
Terry M. Perlin, Anarchist-Communism In America, 1890–1914 (Ph.D.
dissertation, Brandeis University, 1970), p. 294.
[8] John C. Spurlock, Free Love: Marriage and Middle-Class Radicalism in
America, 1825–1860 (New York: New York University, 1988), pp. 28, 62.
[9] James J. Martin, Men Against The State: The Expositors of
Individualist Anarchism in America 1827–1908 (New York: Libertarian Book
Club, 1957), pp. 14, 17;
William O. Reichert, Partisans Of Freedom: A Study in American Anarchism
(Bowling Green, OH: Bowling Green University, 1976), p. 66.
[10] G.D.H. Cole, Socialist Thought: The Forerunners 1789–1859 (London:
Macmillan, 1953), pp. 87–88.
[11] Martin, p. 97.
[12] Veysey, pp. 35, 36.
[13] Edward K. Spann, Brotherly Tomorrows: Movements for a Cooperative
Society in America 1820–1920 (New York: Columbia University, 1989), p.
146.
[14] For example, see the vitriolic exchange between Kropotkin and
Tucker. Peter Kropotkin, Modern Science And Anarchism, Second Edition
(London: Freedom Press, 1923), pp. 70–71. Benjamin R. Tucker, Instead Of
A Book, By A Man Too Busy To Write One (New York: Haskell House, 1969),
pp. 388–389.
[15] Martin, pp. 258–259.
[16] See, Stephen Skowronek, Building A New American State: The
Expansion of National Administrative Capacities, 1877–1920 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University, 1982).
[17] See, Olivier Zunz, Making America Corporate 1870–1920 (Chicago:
University of Chicago, 1990).
[18] David M. Gordon, Richard Edwards and Michael Reich, Segmented Work,
Divided Workers: The Historical Transformation of Labor in the United
States (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1982), pp. 109, 110.
[19] Albert Jay Nock, Our Enemy, The State (Caldwell, ID: Caxton
Printers, 1935).
Peter Marshall, Demanding The Impossible: A History of Anarchism
(London: HarperCollins, 1992), p. 560.
Veysey, p. 36.
[20] John Hospers, Libertarianism: A Political Philosophy for Tomorrow
(Los Angeles: Nash Publishing, 1971), p. 466.
Ted Goertzel, Turncoats And True Believers: The Dynamics of Political
Belief and Disillusionment (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1992), pp.
141, 263.
[21] DeLeon, pp. 119–123; Micheal G. Newbrough, Individualist Anarchism
In American Political Thought (Ph.D. dissertation, University of
California, Santa Barbara, 1975), p. 216.
[22] Murray Rothbard is the “academic vice president” of the Ludwig von
Mises Institute at Auburn, Alabama, and contributing editor to its
publication, The Free Market. Llewellyn H. Rockwell Jr., ed., The Free
Market 11(7–8), July-August 1993, 1–8.
[23] Newbrough, p. 217.
[24] John Gray, Liberalism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1986),
pp. xi, 41; J.G. Merquior, Liberalism: Old and New (Boston: Twayne
Publishers, 1991), p. 138.
[25] Ayn Rand and Nathaniel Branden, The Virtue of Selfishness: A New
Concept of Egoism (New York: Signet Books, 1964), p. 135.
[26] Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, And Utopia (New York: Basic Books,
1974), p. 276.
Also see, Tibor Machan, “Libertarianism: The Principle of Liberty”, in
George W. Carey, ed., Freedom And Virtue: The Conservative/Libertarian
Debate (Lanham, MD: University Press of America and The Intercollegiate
Studies Institute, 1984), pp. 40–41.
[27] Goertzel, p. 262.
[28] Gray, p. 42; Hospers, p. 417; Nozick, p. 276; Rand and Branden, pp.
112, 113.
[29] Hospers, p. 419; Nozick, p. ix; Rand and Branden, p. 112.
[30] Murray N. Rothbard, “Society Without A State”, in Pennock and
Chapman, eds., p. 192.
[31] David Wieck, “Anarchist Justice”, in Pennock and Chapman, eds., pp.
227–228.