💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › iain-macsaorsa-ecology-or-anarcho-capitalism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:55:12. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Ecology or “Anarcho”-capitalism?
Author: Iain MacSaorsa
Date: 1995
Language: en
Topics: ecology, environment, right libertarian
Source: Retrieved on November 29, 2009 from http://www.spunk.org/library/otherpol/critique/sp001279.txt

Iain MacSaorsa

Ecology or “Anarcho”-capitalism?

Can “absolute” private property rights protect the environment?

According to Libertarians, only private property can protect the

environment. Rothbard claims that “if private firms were able to own the

rivers and lakes... anyone dumping garbage... would promptly be sued in

the courts for their aggression against private property... Thus, only

private property rights will insure an end to pollution-invasion of

resources” (Rothbard, For a New Liberty, page 256).

This ignores one major point, why would the private owner be interested

in keeping it clean? Why not just assume that the company makes more

money turing the lakes and rivers into a dumping site, or trees into

junk mail. Its no less plausible, in fact more likely to happen in many

cases. Its just another example of Libertarianism’s attempt to give the

reader what he or she whats to hear.

But, of course, the Libertarian will jump in and say that if dumping was

allowed, this would cause pollution which would affect others, who would

sue the owner in question. Maybe, is the answer to that. What if the

locals are slum dwellers and cannot afford to sue, or if they are afraid

that their land-lords will evict them if they do so (particularly if

they also own the polluting property in question)?

But, beyond these points lies the most important one. Namely, is the

option to sue about pollution really available in the free market?

Rothbard thinks it is. Taking the case of factory smoke in the 19^(th)

Century, he notes that it and “many of its bad effects have been known

since the Industrial Revolution, known to the extent that the American

courts, during the... nineteenth century made the deliberate decision to

allow property rights to be violated by industrial smoke. To do so, the

courts had to — and did — systematically change and weaken the defences

of property rights embedded in Anglo-Saxon common law... the courts

systematically altered the law of negligence and the law of nuisance to

permit any air pollution which was not unusually greater than any

similar manufacturing firm” (Rothbard, op cit, page 257).

In this remarkably self-contradictory passage, we are invited to draw

the conclusion that private property must provide the solution to the

pollution problem from an account of how it clearly did not do so! If

the nineteenth century USA — which for many Libertarian’s is a kind of

“golden era” of free market capitalism — saw a move from an initial

situation of well defended property rights to a later situation were

greater pollution was tolerated, as Rothbard claims, then property

rights cannot provide a solution to the pollution problem.

It is, of course, likely that Rothbard and other “Libertarians” will

claim that the system was not pure enough, that the courts were

motivated to act under pressure from the state (which in turn was

pressured by powerful industrialists). But can it be purified by just

removing the government and placingcourts into a free market? The

pressure from the industrialists remains, if not increases, on the

privately-owned courts trying to make a living on the market.

The characteristically Libertarian argument that if X was privately

owned, Y would almost certainly occur, is just wishful thinking.

Does economic power affect pollution controls?

The last section notes that wealth can affect how environmental and

other externalities are delt with in a capitalist system. This critique,

however, ignores other important factors in society, such as the

mobility of capital and economic power. These are important weapons in

ensuring that the agenda of business is untroubled by social concerns,

such as pollution.

Let us assume that a company is polluting a local area. It is usually

the case that capitalist owners rarely live near to the workplaces they

own, unlike workers and their families. This means that the decision

makers do not have to live with the consequences of their decisions. The

right libertarian argument would be that those affected by the pollution

would sue the company. We will assume that concentrations of wealth have

little or no effect on the social system (which is a highly unlikely

assumption, but nevermind). Surely, if local people did sue, the company

would be harmed economically — directly, in terms of costs, indirectly

in terms of new, eco-friendly processes. Hence the company would be

handicapped in competition and this would have obvious knock-on effects

for the local (and wider) economy.

Also, if the company was sued, it could just up and move to an area

which would tolerate the pollution. Not only would existing capital

move, but fresh capital would not invest in an area where people stand

up for their rights. This, the natural result of economic power, would

be a “big stick” over the heads of the local community and when combined

with the costs and difficulties in taking a large company to court would

make sueing an unlikely option for most people. That this would happen

can be seen from history, where multi-national have moved production to

countries with little or no polluation laws and court cases take years,

if not decades, to process.

Of course, in a “libertarian” society companies which gather lists of

known “trouble-makers” would be given free reign. These “black-lists” of

people who could cause companies “trouble” (ie by union organising or

sueing employers over “property rights” issues) would often ensure

employee “loyality”, particularly if new jobs need references. Under

wage labour, if you cause your employer “problems”, your position can

become difficult — being black-listed will mean no job, no wages, and

little chance of being re-employed. Continually sueing in defense of

your “absolute” property rights would soon fall into this category

(assuming, of course, you could afford the time and money). Hence a

working class person would be a weak position to defend their “absolute”

rights in “libertarian” capitalism due to the power of employers within

and without the workplace.

All these are strong incentives not to rock the boat, particularly if

employees have signed a contract which ensured that they would be fired

if they discussed company business with others (e.g. lawyers, unions).