💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › john-hewetson-dormant-seeds-of-1848.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:18:59. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Dormant Seeds of 1848
Author: John Hewetson
Date: 1948
Language: en
Topics: revolution 1848, anarchist analysis, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Michael Bakunin
Source: A Hundred Years of Revolution: 1848 And After, edited by George Woodcock (Porcupine Press, London, 1948)
Notes: Scanned from original.

John Hewetson

Dormant Seeds of 1848

"As for the greater number of revolutionists, they unhappily know only

of the theatrical side of former revolutions as related with forced

effect by historians, and they scarcely suspected the immense work

accomplished in France during the years 1789 through 1793 by millions of

obscure persons--work which caused France to be in 1793 quite a

different nation from what she was four years previously." (Peter

Kropotkin, Revolutionary Studies)

Revolutions in the past have resulted from the accumulation of

tendencies in social evolution. It has not been difficult for historians

to disentangle the various factors and analyse them--to show where they

reinforce one another, and where their clashes brought suddenly into the

open long dormant antagonisms. At such moments the old structures of

society fall away and the new society thus born seems to take steps

forward more rapidly in a few years--or even months--than the whole

preceding century had achieved.

Revolutions are thus occasions of progress, and its opportunity. It is

therefore natural that the revolutions of the past should be anatomised

more and more closely today when dissatisfaction with existing social

forms is almost universal. It is for their lessons that we chiefly study

such movements of the past, and 1848 provides a focus for many trends

which have by no means exhausted their interest or relevance for the

present age.

We live in a pre-eminently political epoch. For years now we have grown

accustomed to the spectacle of masses of humanity groaning under

conditions of misery, and often enough of horror, resulting from no

action of their own, but from some political decision taken by people

they have never seen, in Capitals they have never visited. They are

completely divorced from responsibility for their own lives. The Treaty

of Versailles produced a mass of miserable and dissatisfied minority

populations; the "settlements" of today are repeating the process on an

even grander scale. While between the two trudge the columns of

refugees, of displaced persons, fleeing from France, from Spain, from

Chiang Kai-shek, from Japanese or German or Russian invaders, from

hostile Sikh or Moslem majorities, always from some manoeuvres which may

have reality in the dim world of politics, but which are hideously alien

from the warm world of human contact and human kinship.

These helpless and hopeless columns of dehumanised humanity are almost

the distinguishing feature of recent history. The callousness, the

inhuman indifference which sets these weary symptoms afoot is scarcely

unexpected however. They spring from political actions, from the domain

of leaders, of men in morning suits or other uniform signing documents

in the dreary splendour of state apartments. The pre-eminent engines of

such contemporary misery are the determined and disciplined groups who

constitute the political parties, more especially the totalitarian,

monolithic political parties which have been increasingly dominant since

1918.

The manifest misery of the refugees is only the open symptom of our age

and our politics-ridden lives. Where human relations should be warm and

touched with sympathy, they are in fact sterilised by the distrust and

stiffness which is implied in the word "bureaucracy". Its increasing

pervasion of human life and its effects on human character are

responsible for the almost universal dissatisfaction with existing

social forms; but the massive misery which forms the background to the

weary journeyings, and the frustration and defeat of human hopes and

aspirations has at the same time removed the optimism which used to

inform the conception of Progress.

Hence social change is not now greeted as an opportunity for a new life,

but rather feared as the probable precursor of yet more misery. Horrible

as these are, men today prefer the ills they know to flying to others

that they know not of. Disillusionment, and disillusionment that extends

to the revolutionary periods of our own day, has made cowards of us all.

A hundred years ago men of vision awaited the Revolution expectantly,

with determination and hopes high. It is quite otherwise today.

Yet the revolutions of the future must still provide the opportunities

for renewed life. They will offer the disintegration of social forms;

and hopes can be reposed still less in conservatism, in maintaining the

existing social structures than was ever the case in the nineteenth or

even the early twentieth centuries. More than ever therefore are we

thrown back on the study of the revolutions of the past, in the search

for solutions to problems of the present and future. Nevertheless, the

accent has shifted: instead of deriving hope and consolation from

revolutionary successes, we have to consider chiefly the failures and

omissions which opened the door to defeat.

The history of 1848 is appropriate for us to study, since it was chiefly

a political revolution. Yet, although the influence of mass movements

was less evident than in the Great Revolution or the Commune of 1871, it

was nevertheless present, and the most important factor. No attempt will

be made here, however, to study political issues in detail; instead,

certain broader issues--one might almost call them philosophical

questions--will be emphasised.

In its general outlines, 1848 followed the historical lines of all

revolutions. As early as 1842, Heine had reported the conscious misery

of the workers: "Everything is as quiet as a winter's night after a new

fall of snow. But in the silence you hear continually dripping,

dripping, the profits of the capitalist, as they steadily increase. You

can actually hear them piling up--the riches of the rich. Sometimes

there is the smothered cry of poverty, and often, too, a scraping sound,

like a knife being sharpened." And, as always, it was the sudden action

of the anonymous mass which toppled over the bourgeois monarchy of

Louis-Philippe. In January 1848, a spokesman of the Government had

declared in the Chamber that "the Ministry will not yield one step", and

it only needed the trivial occasion of the forbidding of the reform

banquet arranged in Paris for February 22nd to start the demonstrations

which led to the barricades going up in the Paris working-class

districts.

The fallen ministry and Monarchy were succeeded by the Republic and a

government composed of Republican leaders like Ledru-Rollin, and

Socialists like Louis Blanc. Such political figures were provided with

their opportunity by the mass uprising; but they were not the cause of

it. Kropotkin has described the process which leads up to revolutionary

situations. Revolutionists of vision, who have a clear view of what

human life could be like, are always in a minority. But events gather to

their ranks many more who are merely dissatisfied with the existing

regime.

"This affluence to the ranks of the revolutionaries of a mass of

malcontents of all shades creates the force of revolutions and renders

them inevitable. A simple conspiracy in the palace, or of Parliament,

more or less supported by what is called public opinion, suffices to

change the men in power, and sometimes the form of government. But a

Revolution, to effect any change whatever in the economic order,

requires the agreement of an immense number of wills. Without the

agreement, more or less active, of millions, no revolution is possible.

It is necessary that everywhere, in each hamlet even, there should be

men to act in the destruction of the past; also that other millions

remain inactive in the hope of seeing something arise to improve their

future conditions. And it is just this vague, undecided discontent--very

often unconscious--surging in the minds of men at the eve of great

events, and that loss of confidence in the existing order, which permits

true revolutionists to accomplish their immense task--the Titanic task

of reconstructing in a few years institutions venerated for centuries."

(Kropotkin: Revolutionary Studies.)

The revolutionists of 1848, however, were not equal to the task, for in

general they had neither the vision to provide the ideas necessary for a

new society, nor the courage to break with and destroy the past. One of

them, at least, recognised this from the outset, for on the day after

the events of February 24th, Proudhon wrote that the revolution had no

plan: "It must be given direction, and already I see it perishing in a

flood of speeches." As D.W. Brogan says, "to have written this diagnosis

of the Revolution of February 24th, on February 25th, was an astonishing

feat of penetration for it was Proudhon who was right--and the naïve

enthusiasts who were wrong". [1]

Proudhon was an intensely practical thinker, despite his many paradoxes,

and it is worth following some of his ideas further. In this country he

suffers under the rival reputation of Marx, whose answer, entitled The

Poverty of Philosophy, to Proudhon's The Philosophy of Poverty is

uncritically accepted by thousands of socialists who have read neither

the original nor the reply. In France, Proudhon's influence powerfully

affected the uprising of 1871 and the development of the French Labour

Movement. His outlook and his attitude affect the social activity of the

French workers even today.

Proudhon was elected to the Assembly by a substantial majority at a

by-election in Paris in June, but by that time the initiative had

already passed from the hands of the workers into those of timid

political leaders. Hence Proudhon's contribution to the ideas of the

Revolution was received with hostility. Alone among the revolutionists

of the time, he saw the necessity to destroy the social basis of the

past by expropriating the bourgeois class and by the equalisation of

incomes. This was no mere socialistic flourish. Proudhon knew from

practical experience of life that the obedience of the ruled is chiefly

exacted by economic pressures and he saw that the power of the reaction

and the social order over which it ruled could only be broken by radical

economic adjustments. Expropriation was not merely an act of social

justice, it was a severely practical safeguard for the revolution.

Of course, such economic measures against the possessing class had been

recognised as necessary by the socialist schools of Saint Simon and

Fourier long before Proudhon. Such ideas were part of the accepted ideas

of socialism. Yet the Ledru-Rollins and Louis Blancs, far from

acclaiming Proudhon's proposition, voted with the majority that "the

proposition of Citizen Proudhon is an odious attack on the principles of

public morals". Proudhon's resolution, which he put before the Assembly

on July 31st, 1848, received only two votes in favour--his own and that

of a Socialist named Greppo.

The interesting point is not that such a resolution should have been put

forward, but that none of the prominent Socialists except Proudhon

should have supported it. The process is one which has been repeated in

succeeding revolutions: in Kropotkin's words about the day after

revolutionary uprisings, "when the immense majority of those who

yesterday gloried in the name of revolutionaries hasten to pass into the

ranks of the defenders of order". It was in defence of order that the

military laid siege to the working-class districts and overcame the

working-men's army in June, 1848. It was in the name of order that

Thiers massacred in 1871 the Communards, whose very appellation of

"Federals" was a tribute to Proudhon's federalist conceptions.

This matter of the economic timidity of revolutionary leaders is of

immense practical importance, for it has contributed to the failure of

the great revolutions of our own time, in 1917 and 1936.

At the fourth Congress of the First International at Basle in September,

1869, the followers of Bakunin advanced a resolution condemning the

principle of hereditary succession to property, and then went on to

demand the abolition of private property altogether. Although such a

step would seem to be an essential prerequisite for the social ownership

of production by the community at large (I do not say by the State), it

was fiercely contested by the Marxist section of the International. The

resolution was nevertheless accepted by a majority vote, and it was this

victory for the ideas of Bakunin that determined Marx on the

manoeuvrings which ended with the removal of the General Council to New

York and the virtual destruction of the International. That Marx's

hostility to the complete abolition of private property on this occasion

was not merely a tactical question is shown by his assertion that in the

Communist Manifesto of 1847 he only sought the expropriation of

capitalists' property. [2]

Despite the success of Bakunin's resolution in the Fourth Congress of

the International, the Paris Commune of 1871 merely advocated a limited

collectivism making only large-scale industry socially owned. Where

Proudhon had put expropriation of the Banks as the first act which the

revolution must accomplish and the only one which could in no

circumstances be allowed to wait, the Communards failed to see the need

to cut away the economic basis of the bourgeois power by expropriating

the Bank of France and all economic undertakings. Hence with his

economic powers virtually unimpaired, Thiers was able to exact his

brutal revenge.

And the revolutions in Russia and Spain also left intact a money and

wages system which permitted the new rulers to impose the same economic

fetters on the workers which they imagined they had destroyed in the

uprisings that brought down the old regime. Proudhon's lesson has yet to

be learned.

So mar the events of 1848 have been treated only as they relate to

France. But the significant thing about the revolutions of that year was

just the fact that they were not confined to one country; the whole of

Europe was affected by the revolutionary unrest. Beginning in Italy, the

revolution spread to France and then to Germany, Austria and the Slav

countries, while in England the Chartist movement flickered before going

out altogether. It is not, however, true that the movement "spread" from

one country to another, certainly not in the sense that it was

consciously carried by revolutionists across national frontiers. For, as

other writers have pointed out, 1848 was notable for the nationalist

character of its uprisings. For the most part, the active revolutionists

had no internationalist conceptions, and the armies of one republic were

used to crush the republican aspirations of another revolution.

Subsequent revolutions have made fully clear the lesson that radical

social changes cannot be made and maintained by a revolutionary people

in isolation. But in 1848 this lesson appears to have been grasped by

one man only. In other directions Bakunin's social ideas were to mature

considerably in the years that followed. But he was already an

internationalist when he wrote in 1848:

"Two great questions were posed from the first days of the spring: the

social question and that of the independence of all nations, the

emancipation at once of people at home and abroad. It was not a few

individuals, nor was it a party; it was the admirable instinct of the

masses which had raised these two questions above all others and which

demanded a prompt solution to them. Everybody had understood that

liberty is only a lie where the great majority of the population is

reduced to leading a poverty-stricken existence, where, deprived of

education, leisure, and bread, they find themselves more or less

destined to serve as stepping-stones for the powerful and the rich. The

social revolution then appears as a natural and necessary consequence of

the political revolution. In the same way it was felt that while there

was in Europe a single nation persecuted, the decisive and complete

triumph of democracy would not be possible anywhere. The oppression of a

people, even of a single individual, is the oppression of all, and it is

impossible to violate the liberty of one without violating the liberty

of all....The social question, a very difficult question, bristling with

dangers and big with tempests, cannot be resolved either by a

pre-conceived theory or by any isolated system. To solve it, there must

be the faith of all in the right of everybody to an equal liberty. It is

necessary to overthrow the material and moral conditions of our present

existence, break into ruins from below this decaying social world, which

has become impotent and sterile and which will be unable to contain or

allow such a great mass of liberty. It will be necessary beforehand to

purify our atmosphere and transform completely the surroundings in which

we live, which corrupt our instincts and our wills, in limiting our

hearts and our intelligences. The social question thus appeared from the

first as the overthrowing of society."

I have quoted this passage at length because it contains so many points

of interest--to some of which I shall return later. But for the moment

what concerns us is the breadth of Bakunin's revolutionary conceptions

which extend far beyond the boundaries of mere political frontiers. The

factors which made 1848 the year of European revolutions were doubtless

mainly the economic ones which underlay them all. But the nationalist

revolutionists did not recognise this fundamental community of

interests. Marx had addressed his peroration in the Communist Manifesto

to the workers of the world, but twenty odd years later in 1870 he still

thought in nationalist terms, for he looked for the victory of Prussia

over France as a step forward for Socialism. For the internationalists

of that time he had nothing but scorn. French workers in a manifesto to

the German workers had declared in 1870: "Brothers, we protest against

the war, we who wish for peace, labour, and liberty. Brothers, do not

listen to the hirelings who seek to deceive you as to the real wishes of

France." And German internationalists replied: "We too wish for peace,

labour and liberty. We know that on both sides of the Rhine there are

brothers with whom we are ready to die for the Universal Republic."

These men--anonymous workers--had a vision of the human race undivided

by war-making frontiers. But Marx and Engels wrote to one another of the

"imbeciles of Paris and their ridiculous manifesto".

Nor were internationalist conceptions fully grasped by the Russian and

Spanish revolutionaries. It is only too clear that even advanced

theoreticians in these countries thought primarily of their national

problems and considered revolutionary trends in other countries only as

possible adjuncts to their own struggle. Absorbed in the local upheaval,

they could not see it as a symptom of world unrest which must either

spread universally or be engulfed by the reaction. It is a sobering

reflection that Bakunin had grasped the universal position as long as a

hundred years ago, for internationalism can hardly ever have been at

such a low ebb as now.

A radical view of the economic problem of the social revolution, and

internationalism: Proudhon and Bakunin had understood these questions in

1848 and revolutionary theorists have conceded the correctness of their

views. But more important still, because almost unrecognised even today,

were certain views about the motive force and the directing power behind

revolutionary events. Once again the anarchists Proudhon and Bakunin had

reached conclusions far in advance of contemporary social thinkers, in

the course of those all-night sessions in which they argued about Hegel

and listened to the symphonies of Beethoven.

Even today it is regarded almost as axiomatic that revolutions are led.

Led by intellectuals, men who have pondered the social questions and in

their wisdom instruct the "blind masses" as to what is best for them.

Intellectual leaders or military adventurers: these are still the

revolutionists of romantic history and propaganda build-ups. And

inevitably the ambitious men who seek such roles make use of an

instrument suitable for imposing their views on the "blind mass". That

instrument is the political party, and its power, its malign power over

the lives of millions has already been referred to. Can the ideas of

1848 shed any light for us on these dark places?

The most outstanding characteristic of revolutions is their tremendous

energy. As Kropotkin pointed out, this overbounding energy sweeps away

old institutions and in a few years transforms the social structure in

directions which cannot be reversed.

Such changes cannot be the work solely of parties, for no such changes

occur at non-revolutionary moments when initiative rests much more

securely in the hands of the political grouping which forms the

government. Revolutions emerge from the initiative of masses of

anonymous people, from "the agreement", in Kropotkin's words, of immense

numbers of wills". The dominance of the party requires the exact

opposite; initiative must rest in the hands of a comparatively small

number of party functionaries and their will must prevail over a more or

less docile population. It is to be noted that such docile submission,

if not vouchsafed voluntarily, is secured by practical politicians by

means of police, secret or otherwise, wielding an immense system of

punitive laws and penal institutions. Such structures most certainly do

not exist to give free play to the revolutionary energy and aspirations

of masses of a population.

It is not perhaps surprising that the power for social change possessed

by a mere party is trivial compared to that which a revolutionary

population achieves in a few months. Such a conception of the motive

force of revolutionary events is not widely current today. Yet Proudhon

had grasped it well enough when he wrote: "Philosophic reason...does not

admit, with the Jacobins and the doctrinaires, that one can proceed

to...reform by legislative authority. It only gives its confidence to

reforms which come out of the free will of societies; the only

revolutions which it acknowledges are those which proceed from the

initiative of the masses; it denies, in the most absolute manner, the

revolutionary competence of governments." [3]

In the passage quoted already Bakunin is seen to have reached the same

conception. Regarding the social question and internationalism, he

declared: "It was not a few individuals, nor was it a party; it was the

admirable instinct of the masses which raised these two questions above

all others, and which demanded a prompt solution of them."

With such a conception, it is clear that any move which tends to remove

initiative from the revolutionary mass by placing it in the hands of a

few individuals or a party will undermine the source of energy for

revolutionary change. Such a transference of initiative will bring the

revolution to a standstill.

And so it proves in history. In 1848, as in 1789, the revolution came to

a standstill when the period of revolutionary motivation gave place to

the formation of a strong government. In Russia, the revolution of

workers and peasants was overwhelmed by the emergence of a strongly

centralised political party with its discipline and its secret police.

And the outstanding achievements of the Spanish revolution were the work

of the anonymous peasants and workers in the collective farms and

factories which they organised and controlled independent of the shadow

government of Largo Caballero. The function of the party government of

Negrin was to dismantle these achievements and inevitably (though

apparently incidentally) the anti-Fascist struggle as well.

The reliance on political parties and political leaders is in no small

part due to the influence of Marx. He and Engels were capable of

regarding even international wars from the point of view of whether or

not they advanced their particular theories within the Socialist

movement. The following letter from Marx to his collaborator shows this

with brutal clarity, and at the same time exhibits the contempt which

these leaders evinced for the revolutionary workers, and also their

underlying nationalism:

The French need a thrashing. If the Prussians are victorious the

centralisation of state power will be helpful for the centralisation of

the German working class; furthermore, German predominance will shift

the centre of gravity of West European labour movements from France to

Germany. And one had but to compare the movement from 1866 till today to

see that the German working class is in theory and organisation superior

to the French. Its dominance over the French on the world stage would

mean likewise the dominance of our theory over that of Proudhon...."

The leadership conception is clearly expressed in this passage. It leads

directly on not only to Lenin's outspoken opinion that the workers could

only achieve a trade-union mentality and therefore require intellectuals

to do their thinking for them, but also to the more polite dictatorship

of the intellectuals expressed by the Labour Party.

With such a conception it is not surprising that Marx and Engels

deplored the initiative of the French workers in 1870. "If one could

have any influence at Paris," wrote Engels to his friend, "it would be

necessary to prevent the working folk from budging until the peace." [4]

No doubt it was the same fear of the energy of revolutionary masses

which made Marx continually exclaim:" Tell the working men of Marseilles

to put their heads in a bucket!"

There is no need to idealise or to idolise the "masses": it is enough to

regard the political fiascoes of 1848 with a clear eye and to reflect

that in this, as in preceding and succeeding revolutions, the

revolutionary achievements derived from the spontaneous uprisings of the

mass. The leadership conception is the antithesis of this, and its

corollary, the emergence of the political party as the would-be

controlling force, signifies the end of the revolution, the beginning of

the counter-revolution. With all its imperfections, futilities and

failures, 1848 contains the seeds whose germination could fructify the

social revolutions of the future.

[1] Proudhon, p. 48.

[2]

F. R. Salter, Karl Marx and Modern Socialism, p. 52.

[3] P.J. Proudhon: Confessions of a Revolutionary (1849).

[4] F.R. Salter: Karl Marx and Modern Socialism, p. 61.