💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-ecology-and-revolutionary-thought.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:30:01. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Ecology and Revolutionary Thought
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: February 1965
Language: en
Topics: ecology, human ecology, social ecology, revolution
Source: Chapter from *Post-Scarcity Anarchism*.

Murray Bookchin

Ecology and Revolutionary Thought

In almost every period since the Renaissance the development of

revolutionary thought has been heavily influenced by a branch of

science, often in conjunction with a school of philosophy.

Astronomy in the time of Copernicus and Galileo helped to change a

sweeping movement of ideas from the medieval world, riddled by

superstition, into one pervaded by a critical rationalism and openly

naturalistic and humanistic in outlook. During the Enlightenment—the era

that culminated in the French Revolution—this liberatory movement of

ideas was reinforced by advances in mechanics and mathematics. The

Victorian era was shaken to its very foundations by evolutionary

theories in biology and anthropology, by Marx’s contributions to

political economy, and by Freudian psychology.

In our own time, we have seen the assimilation of these once-liberatory

sciences by the established social order. Indeed, we have begun to

regard science itself as an instrument of control over the thought

processes and physical being of man. This distrust of science and of the

scientific method is not without justification. “Many sensitive people,

especially artists,” observes Abraham Maslow, “are afraid that science

besmirches and depresses, that it tears things apart rather than

integrating them, thereby killing rather than creating.”[1] What is

perhaps equally important, modern science has lost its critical edge.

Largely functional or instrumental in intent, the branches of science

that once tore at the chains of man are now used to perpetuate and gild

them. Even philosophy has yielded to instrumentalism and tends to be

little more than a body of logical contrivances; it is the handmaiden of

the computer rather than of the revolutionary.

There is one science, however, that may yet restore and even transcend

the liberatory estate of the traditional sciences and philosophies. It

passes rather loosely under the name “ecology”—a term coined by Haeckel

a century ago to denote “the investigation of the total relations of the

animal both to its inorganic and to its organic environment.”[2] At

first glance, Haeckel’s definition is innocuous enough; and ecology

narrowly conceived of as one of the biological sciences, is often

reduced to a variety of biometrics in which field workers focus on food

chains and statistical studies of animal populations. There is an

ecology of health that would hardly offend the sensibilities of the

American Medical Association and a concept of social ecology that would

conform to the most well-engineered notions of the New York City

Planning Commission.

Broadly conceived of, however, ecology deals with the balance of nature.

Inasmuch as nature includes man, the science basically deals with the

harmonization of nature and man. The explosive implications of an

ecological approach arise not only because ecology is intrinsically a

critical science—critical on a scale that the most radical systems of

political economy have failed to attain—but also because it is an

integrative and reconstructive science. This integrative, reconstructive

aspect of ecology, carried through to all its implications, leads

directly into anarchic areas of social thought. For, in the final

analysis, it is impossible to achieve a harmonization of man and nature

without creating a human community that lives in a lasting balance with

its natural environment.

The Critical Nature of Ecology

The critical edge of ecology, a unique feature of the science in a

period of general scientific docility, derives from its subject

matter—from its very domain. The issues with which ecology deals are

imperishable in the sense that they cannot be ignored without bringing

into question the survival of man and the survival of the planet itself.

The critical edge of ecology is due not so much to the power of human

reason—a power which science hallowed during its most revolutionary

periods—but to a still higher power, the sovereignty of nature. It may

be that man is manipulable, as the owners of the mass media argue, or

that elements of nature are manipulable, as the engineers demonstrate,

but ecology clearly shows that the totality of the natural world—nature

viewed in all its aspects, cycles and interrelationships—cancels out all

human pretensions to mastery over the planet. The great wastelands of

the Mediterranean basin, once areas of a thriving agriculture or a rich

natural flora, are historic evidence of nature’s revenge against human

parasitism.

No historic examples compare in weight and scope with the effects of

man’s despoliation—and nature’s revenge—since the days of the Industrial

Revolution, and especially since the end of the Second World War.

Ancient examples of human parasitism were essentially local in scope;

they were precisely examples of man’s potential for destruction, and

nothing more. Often, they were compensated by remarkable improvements in

the natural ecology of a region, such as the European peasantry’s superb

reworking of the soil during centuries of cultivation and the

achievements of Inca agriculturists in terracing the Andes Mountains

during the pre-Columbian times.

Modern man’s despoliation of the environment is global in scope, like

his imperialisms. It is even extraterrestrial, as witness the

disturbances of the Van Alien Belt a few years ago. Today human

parasitism disrupts more than the atmosphere, climate, water resources,

soil, flora and fauna of a region: it upsets virtually all the basic

cycles of nature and threatens to undermine the stability of the

environment on a worldwide scale.

As an example of the scope of modern man’s disruptive role, it has been

estimated that the burning of fossil fuels (coal and oil) adds 600

million tons of carbon dioxide to the air annually, about .03 percent of

the total atmospheric mass-this, I may add, aside from an incalculable

quantity of toxicants. Since the Industrial Revolution, the overall

atmospheric mass of carbon dioxide has increased by 25 percent over

earlier, more stable, levels. It can be argued on very sound theoretical

grounds that this growing blanket of carbon dioxide, by intercepting

heat radiated from the earth, will lead to more destructive storm

patterns and eventually to melting of the polar ice caps, rising sea

levels, and the inundation of vast land areas. Far removed as such a

deluge may be, the changing proportion of carbon dioxide to other

atmospheric gases is a warning about the impact man is having on the

balance of nature.

A more immediate ecological issue is man’s extensive pollution of the

earth’s waterways. What counts here is not the fact that man befouls a

given stream, river or lake—a thing he has done for ages—but rather the

magnitude water pollution has reached in the past two generations.

Nearly all the surface waters of the United States are now polluted.

Many American waterways are open cesspools that properly qualify as

extensions of urban sewage systems. It is a euphemism to describe them

as rivers or lakes. More significantly, large amounts of ground water

are sufficiently polluted to be undrinkable, and a number of local

hepatitis epidemics have been traced to polluted wells in suburban

areas. In contrast to surface-water pollution, the pollution of ground

or subsurface water is immensely difficult to eliminate and tends to

linger on for decades after the sources of pollution have been removed.

An article in a mass-circulation magazine appropriately describes the

polluted waterways of the United States as “Our Dying Waters.” This

despairing, apocalyptic description of the water pollution problem in

the United States really applies to the world at large. The waters of

the earth are literally dying. Massive pollution is destroying the

rivers and lakes of Africa, Asia and Latin America, as well as the

long-abused waterways of highly industrialized continents, as media of

life. (I speak here not only of radioactive pollutants from nuclear bomb

tests and power reactors, which apparently reach all the flora and fauna

of the sea; the oil spills and the discharge of diesel oil have also

become massive pollution problems, claiming marine life in enormous

quantities every year.)

Accounts of this kind can be repeated for virtually every part of the

biosphere. Pages could be written on the immense losses of productive

soil that occur annually in almost every continent of the earth; on

lethal air pollution episodes in major urban areas; on the worldwide

distribution of toxic agents, such as radioactive isotopes and lead; on

the chemicalization of man’s immediate environment—one might say his

very dinner table—with pesticide residues and food additives. Pieced

together like bits of a jigsaw puzzle, these affronts to the environment

form a pattern of destruction that has no precedent in man’s long

history on earth.

Obviously, man could be described as a highly destructive parasite who

threatens to destroy his host—the natural world—and eventually himself.

In ecology, however, the word “parasite” is not an answer to a question,

but raises a question itself. Ecologists know that a destructive

parasitism of this kind usually reflects the disruption of an ecological

situation; indeed, many species that seem highly destructive under one

set of conditions are eminently useful under another set of conditions.

What imparts a profoundly critical function to ecology is the question

raised by man’s destructive abilities: What is the disruption that has

turned man into a destructive parasite? What produces a form of

parasitism that results not only in vast natural imbalances but also

threatens the existence of humanity itself?

Man has produced imbalances not only in nature, but, more fundamentally,

in his relations with his fellow man and in the very structure of his

society. The imbalances man has produced in the natural world are caused

by the imbalances he has produced in the social world. A century ago it

would have been possible to regard air pollution and water contamination

as the result of the self-seeking activities of industrial barons and

bureaucrats. Today, this moral explanation would be a gross

oversimplification. It is doubtless true that most bourgeois enterprises

are still guided by a public-be-damned attitude, as witness the

reactions of power utilities, automobile concerns and steel corporations

to pollution problems. But a more serious problem than the attitude of

the owners is the size of the firms themselves—their enormous

proportions, their location in a particular region, their density with

respect to a community or waterway, their requirements for raw materials

and water, and their role in the national division of labor.

What we are seeing today is a crisis in social ecology. Modern society,

especially as we know it in the United States and Europe, is being

organized around immense urban belts, a highly industrialized

agriculture and, capping both, a swollen, bureaucratized, anonymous

state apparatus. If we put all moral considerations aside for the moment

and examine the physical structure of this society, what must

necessarily impress us is the incredible logistical problems it is

obliged to solve—problems of transportation, of density, of supply (of

raw materials, manufactured commodities and foodstuffs), of economic and

political organization, of industrial location, and so forth. The burden

this type of urbanized and centralized society places on any continental

area is enormous.

Diversity and Simplicity

The problem runs even deeper. The notion that man must dominate nature

emerges directly from the domination of man by man. The patriarchal

family planted the seed of domination in the nuclear relations of

humanity; the classical split in the ancient world between spirit and

reality—indeed, between mind and labor—nourished it; the antinaturalist

bias of Christianity tended to its growth. But it was not until organic

community relations, feudal or peasant in form, dissolved into market

relationships that the planet itself was reduced to a resource for

exploitation. This centuries-long tendency finds its most exacerbating

development in modern capitalism. Owing to its inherently competitive

nature, bourgeois society not only pits humans against each other, it

also pits the mass of humanity against the natural world. Just as men

are converted into commodities, so every aspect of nature is converted

into a commodity, a resource to be manufactured and merchandised

wantonly. The liberal euphemisms for the processes involved are

“growth,” “industrial society” and “urban blight.” By whatever language

they are described, the phenomena have their roots in the domination of

man by man.

The phrase “consumer society” complements the description of the present

social order as an “industrial society.” Needs are tailored by the mass

media to create a public demand for utterly useless commodities, each

carefully engineered to deteriorate after a predetermined period of

time. The plundering of the human spirit by the marketplace is

paralleled by the plundering of the earth by capital. (The liberal

identification is a metaphor that neutralizes the social thrust of the

ecological crisis.)

Despite the current clamor about population growth, the strategic ratios

in the ecological crisis are not the population growth rates of India

but the production rates of the United States, a country that produces

more than half of the world’s goods. Here, too, liberal euphemisms like

“affluence” conceal the critical thrust of a blunt word like “waste.”

With a ninth of its industrial capacity committed to war production, the

U.S. is literally trampling upon the earth and shredding ecological

links that are vital to human survival. If current industrial

projections prove to be accurate, the remaining thirty years of the

century will witness a fivefold increase in electric power production,

based mostly on nuclear fuels and coal. The colossal burden in

radioactive wastes and other effluents that this increase will place on

the natural ecology of the earth hardly needs description.

In shorter perspective, the problem is no less disquieting. Within the

next five years, lumber production may increase an overall twenty

percent; the output of paper, five percent annually; folding boxes,

three percent annually; plastics (which currently form one to two

percent of municipal wastes), seven percent annually. Collectively,

these industries account for the most serious pollutants in the

environment. The utterly senseless nature of modern industrial activity

is perhaps best illustrated by the decline in returnable (and reusable)

beer bottles from 54 billion bottles in 1960 to 26 billion today. Their

place has been taken over by “one-way” bottles (a rise from 8 to 21

billion in the same period) and cans (an increase from 38 to 53

billion). The “one-way” bottles and the cans, of course, pose tremendous

problems in solid waste disposal.

The planet, conceived of as a lump of minerals, can support these

mindless increases in the output of trash. The earth, conceived of as a

complex web of life, certainly cannot. The only question is whether the

earth can survive its looting long enough for man to replace the current

destructive social system with a humanistic, ecologically oriented

society.

Ecologists are often asked, rather tauntingly, to locate with scientific

exactness the ecological breaking point of nature—the point at which the

natural world will cave in on man. This is equivalent to asking a

psychiatrist for the precise moment when a neurotic will become a

nonfunctional psychotic. No such answer is ever likely to be available.

But the ecologist can supply a strategic insight into the directions man

seems to be following as a result of his split with the natural world.

From the standpoint of ecology, man is dangerously oversimplifying his

environment. The modern city represents a regressive encroachment of the

synthetic on the natural, of the inorganic (concrete, metals, and glass)

on the organic, of crude, elemental stimuli on variegated, wide-ranging

ones. The vast urban belts now developing in industrialized areas of the

world are not only grossly offensive to the eye and the ear, they are

chronically smog-ridden, noisy, and virtually immobilized by congestion.

The process of simplifying man’s environment and rendering it

increasingly elemental and crude has a cultural as well as a physical

dimension. The need to manipulate immense urban populations—to

transport, feed, employ, educate and somehow entertain millions of

densely concentrated people—leads to a crucial decline in civic and

social standards. A mass concept of human relations—totalitarian,

centralistic and regimented in orientation—tends to dominate the more

individuated concepts of the past. Bureaucratic techniques of social

management tend to replace humanistic approaches. All that is

spontaneous, creative and individuated is circumscribed by the

standardized, the regulated and the massified. The space of the

individual is steadily narrowed by restrictions imposed upon him by a

faceless, impersonal social apparatus. Any recognition of unique

personal qualities is increasingly surrendered to the manipulation of

the lowest common denominator of the mass. A quantitative, statistical

approach, a beehive manner of dealing with man, tends to triumph over

the precious individualized and qualitative approach which places the

strongest emphasis on personal uniqueness, free expression and cultural

complexity.

The same regressive simplification of the environment occurs in modern

agriculture.[3] The manipulated people in modern cities must be fed, and

to feed them involves an extension of industrial farming. Food plants

must be cultivated in a manner that allows for a high degree of

mechanization—not to reduce human toil but to increase productivity and

efficiency, to maximize investments, and to exploit the biosphere.

Accordingly, the terrain must be reduced to a flat plain-to a factory

floor, if you will—and natural variations in topography must be

diminished as much as possible. Plant growth must be closely regulated

to meet the tight schedules of food-processing factories. Plowing, soil

fertilization, sowing and harvesting must be handled on a mass scale,

often in total disregard of the natural ecology of an area. Large areas

of the land must be used to cultivate a single crop—a form of plantation

agriculture that not only lends itself to mechanization but also to pest

infestation. A single crop is the ideal environment for the

proliferation of pest species. Finally, chemical agents must be used

lavishly to deal with the problems created by insects, weeds, and plant

diseases, to regulate crop production, and to maximize soil

exploitation. The real symbol of modern agriculture is not the sickle

(or, for that matter, the tractor), but the airplane. The modern food

cultivator is represented not by the peasant, the yeoman, or even the

agronomist—men who could be expected to have an intimate relationship

with the unique qualities of the land on which they grow crops—but the

pilot or chemist, for whom soil is a mere resource, an inorganic raw

material.

The simplification process is carried still further by an exaggerated

regional (indeed, national) division of labor. Immense areas of the

planet are increasingly reserved for specific industrial tasks or

reduced to depots for raw materials. Others are turned into centers of

urban population, largely occupied with commerce and trade. Cities and

regions (in fact, countries and continents) are specifically identified

with special products—Pittsburgh, Cleveland and Youngstown with steel,

New York with finance, Bolivia with tin, Arabia with oil, Europe and the

U.S. with industrial goods, and the rest of the world with raw materials

of one kind or another. The complex ecosystems which make up the regions

of a continent are submerged by an organization of entire nations into

economically rationalized entities, each a way station in avast

industrial belt-system, global in its dimensions. It is only a matter of

time before the most attractive areas of the countryside succumb to the

concrete mixer, just as most of the Eastern seashore areas of the United

States have already succumbed to subdivisions and bungalows. What will

remain in the way of natural beauty will be debased by trailer lots,

canvas slums, “scenic” highways, motels, food stalls and the oil slicks

of motor boats.

The point is that man is undoing the work of organic evolution. By

creating vast urban agglomerations of concrete, metal and glass, by

overriding and undermining the complex, subtly organized ecosystems that

constitute local differences in the natural world—in short, by replacing

a highly complex, organic environment with a simplified, inorganic

one-man is disassembling the biotic pyramid that supported humanity for

countless millennia. In the course of replacing the complex ecological

relationships, on which all advanced living things depend, for more

elementary relationships, man is steadily restoring the biosphere to a

stage which will be able to support only simpler forms of life. If this

great reversal of the evolutionary process continues, it is by no means

fanciful to suppose that the preconditions for higher forms of life will

be irreparably destroyed and the earth will become incapable of

supporting man himself.

Ecology derives its critical edge not only from the fact that it alone,

among all the sciences, presents this awesome message to humanity, but

also because it presents this message in a new social dimension. From an

ecological viewpoint, the reversal of organic evolution is the result of

appalling contradictions between town and country, state and community,

industry and husbandry, mass manufacture and craftsmanship, centralism

and regionalism, the bureaucratic scale and the human scale.

The Reconstructive Nature of Ecology

Until recently, attempts to resolve the contradictions created by

urbanization, centralization, bureaucratic growth and statification were

viewed as a vain counterdrift to “progress”—a counterdrift that could be

dismissed as chimerical and reactionary. The anarchist was regarded as a

forlorn visionary, a social outcast, filled with nostalgia for the

peasant village or the medieval commune. His yearnings for a

decentralized society and for a humanistic community at one with nature

and the needs of the individual—the spontaneous individual, unfettered

by authority—were viewed as the reactions of a romantic, of a declassed

craftsman or an intellectual “misfit.” His protest against

centralization and statification seemed all the less persuasive because

it was supported primarily by ethical considerations-by Utopian,

ostensibly “unrealistic,” notions of what man could be, not by what he

was. In response to this protest, opponents of anarchist

thought—liberals, rightists and authoritarian “leftists”—argued that

they were the voices of historic reality, that their statist and

centralist notions were rooted in the objective, practical world.

Time is not very kind to the conflict of ideas. Whatever may have been

the validity of libertarian and non-libertarian views a few years ago,

historical development has rendered virtually all objections to

anarchist thought meaningless today. The modern city and state, the

massive coal-steel technology of the Industrial Revolution, the later,

more rationalized, systems of mass production and assembly-line systems

of labor organization, the centralized nation, the state and its

bureaucratic apparatus—all have reached their limits. Whatever

progressive or liberatory role they may have possessed, they have now

become entirely regressive and oppressive. They are regressive not only

because they erode the human spirit and drain the community of all its

cohesiveness, solidarity and ethico-cultural standards; they are

regressive from an objective standpoint, from an ecological standpoint.

For they undermine not only the human spirit and the human community but

also the viability of the planet and all living things on it.

It cannot be emphasized too strongly that the anarchist concepts of a

balanced community, a face-to-face democracy, a humanistic technology

and a decentralized society—these rich libertarian concepts—are not only

desirable, they are also necessary. They belong not only to the great

visions of man’s future, they now constitute the preconditions for human

survival. The process of social development has carried them out of the

ethical, subjective dimension into a practical, objective dimension.

What was once regarded as impractical and visionary has become eminently

practical. And what was once regarded as practical and objective has

become eminently impractical and irrelevant in terms of man’s

development towards a fuller, unfettered existence. If we conceive of

demands for community, face-to-face democracy, a humanistic liberatory

technology and decentralization merely as reactions to the prevailing

state of affairs-a vigorous “nay” to the “yea” of what exists today—a

compelling, objective case can now be made for the practicality of an

anarchist society.

A rejection of the prevailing state of affairs accounts, I think, for

the explosive growth of intuitive anarchism among young people today.

Their love of nature is a reaction against the highly synthetic

qualities of our urban environment and its shabby products. Their

informality of dress and manners is a reaction against the formalized,

standardized nature of modern institutionalized living. Their

predisposition for direct action is a reaction against the

bureaucratization and centralization of society. Their tendency to drop

out, to avoid toil and the rat race, reflects a growing anger towards

the mindless industrial routine bred by modern mass manufacture in the

factory, the office or the university. Their intense individualism is,

in its own elemental way, a de facto decentralization of social life—a

personal withdrawal from mass society.

What is most significant about ecology is its ability to convert this

often nihilistic rejection of the status quo into an emphatic

affirmation of life—indeed, into a reconstructive credo for a humanistic

society. The essence of ecology’s reconstructive message can be summed

up in the word “diversity.” From an ecological viewpoint, balance and

harmony in nature, in society and, by inference, in behavior, are

achieved not by mechanical standardization but by its opposite, organic

differentiation. This message can be understood clearly only by

examining its practical meaning.

Let us consider the ecological principle of diversity—what Charles Elton

calls the “conservation of variety”—as it applies to biology,

specifically to agriculture. A number of studies—Lotka’s and Volterra’s

mathematical models, Bause’s experiments with protozoa and mites in

controlled environments, and extensive field research-clearly

demonstrate that fluctuations in animal and plant populations, ranging

from mild to pestlike proportions, depend heavily upon the number of

species in an ecosystem and on the degree of variety in the environment.

The greater the variety of prey and predators, the more stable the

population; the more diversified the environment in terms of flora and

fauna, the less likely there is to be ecological instability. Stability

is a function of variety and diversity: if the environment is simplified

and the variety of animal and plant species is reduced, fluctuations in

population become marked and tend to get out of control. They tend to

reach pest proportions.

In the case of pest control, many ecologists now conclude that we can

avoid the repetitive use of toxic chemicals such as insecticides and

herbicides by allowing for a greater interplay between living things. We

must leave more room for natural spontaneity, for the diverse biological

forces that make up an ecological situation. “European entomologists now

speak of managing the entire plant-insect community,” observes Robert L.

Rudd. “It is called manipulation of the biocenose[4] The biocenetic

environment is varied, complex and dynamic. Although numbers of

individuals will constantly change, no one species will normally reach

pest proportions. The special conditions which allow high populations of

a single species in a complex ecosystem are rare events. Management of

the biocenose or ecosystem should become our goal, challenging as it

is.”[5]

The “manipulation” of the biocenose in a meaningful way, however,

presupposes a far-reaching decentralization of agriculture. Wherever

feasible, industrial agriculture must give way to soil and agricultural

husbandry; the factory floor must yield to gardening and horticulture. I

do not wish to imply that we must surrender the gains acquired by

large-scale agriculture and mechanization. What I do contend, however,

is that the land must be cultivated as though it were a garden; its

flora must be diversified and carefully tended, balanced by fauna and

tree shelter appropriate to the region. Decentralization is important,

moreover, for the development of the agriculturist as well as for the

development of agriculture. Food cultivation, practiced in a truly

ecological sense, presupposes that the agriculturist is familiar with

all the features and subtleties of the terrain on which the crops are

grown. He must have a thorough knowledge of the physiography of the

land, its variegated soils—crop land, forest land, pasture land—its

mineral and organic content and its micro-climate, and he must be

engaged in a continuing study of the effects produced by new flora and

fauna. He must develop his sensitivity to the land’s possibilities and

needs while he becomes an organic part of the agricultural situation. We

can hardly hope to achieve this high degree of sensitivity and

integration in the food cultivator without reducing agriculture to a

human scale, without bringing agriculture within the scope of the

individual. To meet the demands of an ecological approach to food

cultivation, agriculture must be re-scaled from huge industrial farms to

moderate-sized units.

The same reasoning applies to a rational development of energy

resources. The Industrial Revolution increased the quantity of energy

used by man. Although it is certainly true that pre-industrial societies

relied primarily on animal power and human muscles, complex energy

patterns developed in many regions of Europe, involving a subtle

integration of resources such as wind and water power, and a variety of

fuels (wood, peat, coal, vegetable starches and animal fats).

The Industrial Revolution overwhelmed and largely destroyed these

regional energy patterns, replacing them first by a single energy system

(coal) and later by a dual system (coal and petroleum). Regions

disappeared as models of integrated energy patterns—indeed, the very

concept of integration through diversity was obliterated. As I indicated

earlier, many regions became predominantly mining areas, devoted to the

extraction of a single resource, while others were turned into immense

industrial areas, often devoted to the production of a few commodities.

We need not review the role this breakdown in true regionalism has

played in producing air and water pollution, the damage it has inflicted

on large areas of the countryside, and the prospect we face in the

depletion of our precious hydrocarbon fuels.

We can, of course, turn to nuclear fuels, but it is chilling to think of

the lethal radioactive wastes that would require disposal if power

reactors were our sole energy source. Eventually, an energy system based

on radioactive materials would lead to the widespread contamination of

the environment—at first in a subtle form, but later on a massive and

palpably destructive scale. Or we could apply ecological principles to

the solution of our energy problems. We could try to re-establish

earlier regional energy patterns, using a combined system of energy

provided by wind, water and solar power. We would be aided by devices

more sophisticated than any known in the past.

Solar devices, wind turbines and hydro-electric resources, taken singly,

do not provide a solution for our energy problems and the ecological

disruption created by conventional fuels. Pieced together as a mosaic,

as an organic energy pattern developed from the potentialities of a

region, they could amply meet the needs of a decentralized society. In

sunny latitudes, we could rely more heavily on solar energy than on

combustible fuels. In areas marked by atmospheric turbulence, we could

rely more heavily on wind devices; and in suitable coastal areas or

inland regions with a good network of rivers, the greater part of our

energy would come from hydro-electric installations. In all cases, we

would use a mosaic of non-combustible, combustible, and nuclear fuels.

The point I wish to make is that by diversifying our use of energy

resources, by organizing them into an ecologically balanced pattern, we

could combine wind, solar and water power in a given region to meet the

industrial and domestic needs of a given community with only a minimal

use of harmful fuels. And, eventually, we might sophisticate our

non-combustion energy devices to a point where all harmful sources of

energy could be eliminated.

As in the case of agriculture, however, the application of ecological

principles to energy resources presupposes a far-reaching

decentralization of society and a truly regional concept of social

organization. To maintain a large city requires immense quantities of

coal and petroleum. By contrast, solar, wind and tidal energy reach us

mainly in small packets; except for spectacular tidal dams, the new

devices seldom provide more than a few thousand kilowatt-hours of

electricity. It is difficult to believe that we will ever be able to

design solar collectors that can furnish us with the immense blocks of

electric power produced by a giant steam plant; it is equally difficult

to conceive of a battery of wind turbines that will provide us with

enough electricity to illuminate Manhattan Island. If homes and

factories are heavily concentrated, devices for using clean sources of

energy will probably remain mere playthings; but if urban communities

are reduced in size and widely dispersed over the land, there is no

reason why these devices cannot be combined to provide us with all the

amenities of an industrialized civilization. To use solar, wind and

tidal power effectively, the megalopolis must be decentralized. A new

type of community, carefully tailored to the characteristics and

resources of a region, must replace the sprawling urban belts that are

emerging today.

To be sure, an objective case for decentralization does not end with a

discussion of agriculture and the problems created by combustible energy

resources. The validity of the decentralist case can be demonstrated for

nearly all the “logistical” problems of our time. Let me cite an example

from the problematical area of transportation. A great deal has been

written about the harmful effects of gasoline-driven motor

vehicles—their wastefulness, their role in urban air pollution, the

noise they contribute to the city environment, the enormous death toll

they claim annually in the large cities of the world and on highways. In

a highly urbanized civilization it would be useless to replace these

noxious vehicles by clean, efficient, virtually noiseless, and certainly

safer, battery-powered vehicles. The best of our electric cars must be

recharged about every hundred miles—a feature which limits their

usefulness for transportation in large cities. In a small, decentralized

community, however, it would be feasible to use these electric vehicles

for urban or regional transportation and establish monorail networks for

long-distance transportation.

It is fairly well known that gasoline-powered vehicles contribute

enormously to urban air pollution, and there is a strong sentiment to

“engineer” the more noxious features of the automobile into oblivion.

Our age characteristically tries to solve all its irrationalities with a

gimmick—afterburners for toxic gasoline fumes, antibiotics for ill

health, tranquilizers for psychic disturbances. But the problem of urban

air pollution is too intractable for gimmicks; perhaps it is more

intractable than we care to believe. Basically, air pollution is caused

by high population densities—by an excessive concentration of people in

a small area. Millions of people, densely concentrated in a large city,

necessarily produce serious local air pollution merely by their

day-to-day activities. They must burn fuels for domestic and industrial

reasons; they must construct or tear down buildings (the aerial debris

produced by these activities is a major source of urban air pollution);

they must dispose of immense quantities of rubbish; they must travel on

roads with rubber tires (the particles produced by the erosion of tires

and roadway materials add significantly to air pollution). Whatever

pollution-control devices we add to automobiles and power plants, the

improvements these devices will produce in the quality of urban air will

be more than canceled out by future megalopolitan growth.

There is more to anarchism than decentralized communities. If I have

examined this possibility in some detail, it has been to demonstrate

that an anarchist society, far from being a remote ideal, has become a

precondition for the practice of ecological principles. To sum up the

critical message of ecology: if we diminish variety in the natural

world, we debase its unity and wholeness; we destroy the forces making

for natural harmony and for a lasting equilibrium; and, what is even

more significant, we introduce an absolute retrogression in the

development of the natural world which may eventually render the

environment unfit for advanced forms of life. To sum up the

reconstructive message of ecology: if we wish to advance the unity and

stability of the natural world, if we wish to harmonize it, we must

conserve and promote variety. To be sure, mere variety for its own sake

is a vacuous goal. In nature, variety emerges spontaneously. The

capacities of a new species are tested by the rigors of climate, by its

ability to deal with predators and by its capacity to establish and

enlarge its niche. Yet the species that succeeds in enlarging its niche

in the environment also enlarges the ecological situation as a whole. To

borrow E. A. Gutkind’s phrase, it “expands the environment,”[6] both for

itself and for the species with which it enters into a balanced

relationship.

How do these concepts apply to social theory? To many readers, I

suppose, it should suffice to say that, inasmuch as man is part of

nature, an expanding natural environment enlarges the basis for social

development. But the answer to the question goes much deeper than many

ecologists and libertarians suspect. Again, allow me to return to the

ecological principle of wholeness and balance as a product of diversity.

Keeping this principle in mind, the first step towards an answer is

provided by a passage in Herbert Read’s “The Philosophy of Anarchism.”

In presenting his “measure of progress,” Read observes: “Progress is

measured by the degree of differentiation within a society. If the

individual is a unit in a corporate mass, his life will be limited,

dull, and mechanical. If the individual is a unit on his own, with space

and potentiality for separate action, then he may be more subject to

accident or chance, but at least he can expand and express himself. He

can develop—develop in the only real meaning of the word—develop in

consciousness of strength, vitality, and joy.”

Read’s thought, unfortunately, is not fully developed, but it provides

an interesting point of departure. What first strikes us is that both

the ecologist and the anarchist place a strong emphasis on spontaneity.

The ecologist, insofar as he is more than a technician, tends to reject

the notion of “power over nature.” He speaks, instead, of “steering” his

way through an ecological situation, of managing rather than recreating

an ecosystem. The anarchist, in turn, speaks in terms of social

spontaneity, of releasing the potentialities of society and humanity, of

giving free and unfettered rein to the creativity of people. Both, in

their own way, regard authority as inhibitory, as a weight limiting the

creative potential of a natural and social situation. Their object is

not to rule a domain, but to release it. They regard insight, reason and

knowledge as means for fulfilling the potentialities of a situation, as

facilitating the working out of the logic of a situation, not as

replacing its potentialities with preconceived notions or distorting

their development with dogmas.

Turning to Read’s words, what strikes us is that both the ecologist and

the anarchist view differentiation as a measure of progress. The

ecologist uses the term “biotic pyramid” in speaking of biological

advances; the anarchist, the word “individuation” to denote social

advances. If we go beyond Read we will observe that, to both the

ecologist and the anarchist, an ever-increasing unity is achieved by

growing differentiation. An expanding whole is created by the

diversification and enrichment of its parts.

Just as the ecologist seeks to expand the range of an ecosystem and

promote a free interplay between species, so the anarchist seeks to

expand the range of social experience and remove all fetters to its

development. Anarchism is not only a stateless society but also a

harmonized society which exposes man to the stimuli provided by both

agrarian and urban life, to physical activity and mental activity, to

unrepressed sensuality and self-directed spirituality, to communal

solidarity and individual development, to regional uniqueness and

worldwide brotherhood, to spontaneity and self-discipline, to the

elimination of toil and the promotion of craftsmanship. In our schizoid

society, these goals are regarded as mutually exclusive, indeed as

sharply opposed. They appear as dualities because of the very logistics

of present-day society—the separation of town and country, the

specialization of labor, the atomization of man—and it would be

preposterous to believe that these dualities could be resolved without a

general idea of the physical structure of an anarchist society. We can

gain some idea of what such a society would be like by reading William

Morris’s News From Nowhere and the writings of Peter Kropotkin. But

these works provide us with mere glimpses. They do not take into account

the post-World War II developments of technology and the contributions

made by the development of ecology. This is not the place to embark on

“utopian writing,” but certain guidelines can be presented even in a

general discussion. And in presenting these guidelines, I am eager to

emphasize not only the more obvious ecological premises that support

them, but also the humanistic ones.

An anarchist society should be a decentralized society, not only to

establish a lasting basis for the harmonization of man and nature, but

also to add new dimensions to the harmonization of man and man. The

Greeks, we are often reminded, would have been horrified by a city whose

size and population precluded a face-to-face, often familiar,

relationship between citizens. There is plainly a need to reduce the

dimensions of the human community—partly to solve our pollution and

transportation problems, partly also to create real communities. In a

sense, we must humanize humanity. Electronic devices such as telephones,

telegraphs, radios and television receivers should be used as little as

possible to mediate the relations between people. In making collective

decisions—the ancient Athenian ecclesia was, in some ways, a model for

making social decisions—all members of the community should have an

opportunity to acquire in full the measure of anyone who addresses the

assembly. They should be in a position to absorb his attitudes, study

his expressions, and weigh his motives as well as his ideas in a direct

personal encounter and through face-to-face discussion.

Our small communities should be economically balanced and well rounded,

partly so that they can make full use of local raw materials and energy

resources, partly also to enlarge the agricultural and industrial

stimuli to which individuals are exposed. The member of a community who

has a predilection for engineering, for instance, should be encouraged

to steep his hands in humus; the man of ideas should be encouraged to

employ his musculature; the “inborn” farmer should gain a familiarity

with the workings of a rolling mill. To separate the engineer from the

soil, the thinker from the spade, and the farmer from the industrial

plant promotes a degree of vocational overspecialization that leads to a

dangerous measure of social control by specialists. What is equally

important, professional and vocational specialization prevents society

from achieving a vital goal: the humanization of nature by the

technician and the naturalization of society by the biologist.

I submit that an anarchist community would approximate a clearly

definable ecosystem; it would be diversified, balanced and harmonious.

It is arguable whether such an ecosystem would acquire the configuration

of an urban entity with a distinct center, such as we find in the Greek

polis or the medieval commune, or whether, as Gutkind proposes, society

would consist of widely dispersed communities without a distinct center.

I n any case, the ecological scale for any of these communities would be

determined by the smallest ecosystem capable of supporting a population

of moderate size.

A relatively self-sufficient community, visibly dependent on its

environment for the means of life, would gain a new respect for the

organic interrelationships that sustain it. In the long run, the attempt

to approximate self-sufficiency would, I think, prove more efficient

than the exaggerated national division of labor that prevails today.

Although there would doubtless be many duplications of small industrial

facilities from community to community, the familiarity of each group

with its local environment and its ecological roots would make for a

more intelligent and more loving use of its environment. I submit that,

far from producing provincialism, relative self-sufficiency would create

a new matrix for individual and communal development—a oneness with the

surroundings that would vitalize the community.

The rotation of civic, vocational and professional responsibilities

would stimulate the senses in the being of the individual, creating and

rounding out new dimensions in self-development. In a complete society

we could hope to create complete men; in a rounded society, rounded men.

In the Western world, the Athenians, for all their shortcomings and

limitations, were the first to give us a notion of this completeness.

“The polis was made for the amateur,” H. D. F. Kitto tells us. “Its

ideal was that every citizen (more or less, according as the polis was

democratic or oligarchic) should play his part in all of its many

activities-an ideal that is recognizably descended from the generous

Homeric conception of arete as an all-round excellence and an all-round

activity. It implies a respect for the wholeness or the oneness of life,

and a consequent dislike of specialization. It implies a contempt for

efficiency-or rather a much higher ideal of efficiency; and efficiency

which exists not in one department of life, but in life itself.”[7] An

anarchist society, although it would surely aspire to more, could hardly

hope to achieve less than this state of mind.

If the ecological community is ever achieved in practice, social life

will yield a sensitive development of human and natural diversity,

falling together into a well balanced, harmonious whole. Ranging from

community through region to entire continents, we will see a colorful

differentiation of human groups and ecosystems, each developing its

unique potentialities and exposing members of the community to a wide

spectrum of economic, cultural and behavioral stimuli. Falling within

our purview will be an exciting, often dramatic, variety of communal

forms—here marked by architectural and industrial adaptations to

semi-arid ecosystems, there to grasslands, elsewhere by adaptation to

forested areas. We will witness a creative interplay between individual

and group, community and environment, humanity and nature. The cast of

mind that today organizes differences among humans and other life-forms

along hierarchical lines, defining the external in terms of its

“superiority” or “inferiority,” will give way to an outlook that deals

with diversity in an ecological manner. Differences among people will be

respected, indeed fostered, as elements that enrich the unity of

experience and phenomena. The traditional relationship which pits

subject against object will be altered qualitatively; the “external,”

the “different,” the “other” will be conceived of as individual parts of

a whole all the richer because of its complexity. This sense of unity

will reflect the harmonization of interests between individuals and

between society and nature. Freed from an oppressive routine, from

paralyzing repressions and insecurities, from the burdens of toil and

false needs, from the trammels of authority and irrational compulsion,

individuals will finally, for the first time in history, be in a

position to realize their potentialities as members of the human

community and the natural world.

New York

February 1965

[1] Abraham H. Maslow, Toward a Psychology of Being (Van Nostrand; New

York, 1962), p. viii.

[2] Quoted in Angus M. Woodbury, Principles of General Ecology

(Blakiston; New York, 1954), p. 4.

[3] For insight into this problem the reader may consult The Ecology of

Invasions by Charles S. Elton (Wiley; New York, 1958), Soil and

Civilisation by Edward Hyams (Thames and Hudson; London, 1952), Our

Synthetic Environment by Murray Bookchin [pseud. Lewis Herber] (Knopf;

New York, 1962), and Silent Spring by Rachel Carson (Houghton Mifflin;

Boston, 1962). The last should be read not as a diatribe against

pesticides but as a plea for ecological diversification.

[4] Rudd’s use of the word “manipulation” is likely to create the

erroneous impression that an ecological situation can be described by

simple mechanical terms. Lest this impression arise, I would like to

emphasize that our knowledge of an ecological situation and the

practical use of this knowledge are matters of insight rather than

power. Charles Elton states the case for the management of an ecological

situation when he writes: “The world’s future has to be managed, but

this management would not be like a game of chess ... [but] more like

steering a boat.”

[5] Robert L. Rudd, “Pesticides: The Real Peril,” The Nation, vol. 189

(1959), p. 401.

[6]

E. A. Gutkind, The Twilight of the Cities (Free Press; Glencoe, N.Y.,

1962), pp. 55–144.

[7]

H. D. F. Kitto, The Greeks (Aldine; Chicago, 1951), p. 16.