đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș javier-sethness-castro-imperiled-life.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:33:33. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Imperiled life Author: Javier Sethness-Castro Date: 2012 Language: en Topics: revolution, green anarchism, climate change
The basic structure of capitalism is at the heart of the climate crisis.
Carbon emissions, the primary source of our changing climate, are the
by-product of industrial production. Capitalism is literally changing
the weather. Often, industry is blamed for climate change. People
frequently talk about burning oil and coal, or fault cars and factories,
but this misses the underlying dynamic that ties all these things
together: industry is an expression of a system. Ascending over the last
four hundred years, capitalism continues to be the dominant organizing
force in the world, shaping life as we know it. All attempts at
slowingâmuch less stoppingâits growth have failed. The emission of
climate-changing gases is intrinsic to the capitalist logic. Every day
that this continues, the climate will continue to change. The year 2010
saw the highest emission of greenhouse gases in history.
Capitalism is based on a philosophy of âgrow or dieâ and ruthless
competition; companies need to continually expand and grow, or they will
not survive. It is a system that seeks to maximize profit by exploiting
labor as well as treating nature as both a âresourceâ and garbage dump.
Despite all the warning signsâsuch as news of drought, heat waves, and
new species being threatened by changing habitatâand what scientists
say, the system marches on, with absolutely no sign of letting up. That
is because it cannot change its fundamental nature. It is a form of
economic and social organization at odds with nature and human community
that has come to shape nearly everything in life, such that we can
hardly imagine the possibility of life outside capitalism. It promotes
qualities like greed and selfishness, and creates us in its image.
Capitalism is more than an economic system; it is a way of life.
Maximizing profit at the expense of all else is its very metabolism. To
stop catastrophic climate change, we must stop capitalism.
So what is capitalism? At its core, it is based on only paying a worker
the worth of a portion of their work. The owner keeps the remaining
worth, or value. This âsurplus valueâ is one of the sources of profit.
Thus capitalism is an organized system of theft, wherein those who
actually do the work are not paid the full value of their effort. The
owners keep as profit the difference between the value that is created
by the worker and that which the worker is paid as a wage. Because it is
a system designed by and for capitalists, workers are necessarily
exploited and mistreated. It is this same focus on profit that sees
nature as a place where materials are found and then converted into
commodities, with an emphasis on doing this as cheaply as possible. The
way in which materials are obtained from nature is guided not by any
thought about the integrity of nature itself, or the delicate balance of
natural processes. It is guided by making money, pure and simple. The
same is true at the other end of the productive process, when toxic
chemicals and by-products are dumped as cheaply as possible. Hence
owners fight attempts to regulate their ability to pollute. Not
polluting costs money. It costs money to buy filters and scrubbers to
limit toxic emissions, or to research and develop alternative sources of
energy, and all this cuts into profits. Generally the fines for
polluting are so insignificant that owners calculate that it is more
worthwhile to pollute and pay the fines rather than, for example,
upgrading their machinery to satisfy clean air or water regulations.
This is a system ruled by the bottom line.
To stop capitalism, we need a social and political movement. This past
year, 2011, marked the emergence of just such a movement. The Arab
Spring saw millions of people rise up in opposition to long-standing
tyrannical regimes. Some of these governments fell. Millions of people
occupied prominent squares and did not back down against the power of
states. This inspired people in the United States to launch their own
movementâan occupation movement at Wall Street, the symbolic heart of
global capitalism. Occupy Wall Street (OWS), which spread around the
United States, Canada, and the world, is a populist movement that
challenges the economic control of what they call the 1 percent. OWS
champions the 99 percent, or those without great sources of wealth. This
is significant because it points to the machinations of the 1 percent,
or ruling class, and suggests the possibility of creating what Antonio
Gramsci calls a âcounterhegemonicâ movement. For Gramsci, ruling-class
ideas are the dominant ones. They are so widely propagated that they
become âcommon sense.â An example is the belief that the sign of a
healthy economy is vigorous growth. Or that to be a productive member of
society, you have to have a job, which basically discounts stay-at-home
parents, many artists, self-sufficient farmers, and others, while
valuing only those who are enmeshed in the dominant economy. It is this
common sense that serves the interests of the capitalist class. The OWS
protests represent the development of an ideological alternative that
puts the interests of everyday, working people ahead of those of the
rulers. OWS has successfully changed the nature of discussion in the
United States, forcing issues of economic equality and social justice
onto the agenda. It signals a good beginning.
In addition to challenging ruling-class economic ideas, or those held by
the 1 percent, OWS has put ideals of direct democracy, long championed
by anarchists and other antiauthoritarians, into practice. The use of
general assemblies as policymaking bodies and the reliance on modified
forms of consensus decision making, however problematic consensus may be
in certain situations, both have long histories within antiauthoritarian
leftist movements. This new movement hopes to unite the majority against
the minority currently running the show.
The historic development of capitalism is intertwined with colonialism,
and later, neocolonialism. The economy, in its never-ending need to
expand and accumulate, resolved early crises by going to the so-called
third world to seek resources for production and sources of cheapâor in
the case of slavery, freeâlabor. By waging war and asserting its
military dominance, Europe was able to control vast territory from which
raw materials could be obtained. European colonialism, the North
American slave trade, and later neocolonial domination such as the
Algerian and Vietnam wars all represent the attempted dominance of what
was once called the first world over the peoples of the so-called third
world. This is a racist dynamic in which the largely white, European
people of the North dominate and exploit the people of the South. And it
is exactly these people, the poor of the Southern Hemisphere, who will
suffer the most from the changing climate. They already are suffering,
as attested to by the recent floods that devastated Pakistan and
Thailand along with the droughts that ravaged Mexico and Africa.
It will take a sustained movement to fundamentally transform society and
stop climate change. Such revolutionary change will require a
democratically controlled economy that puts human needs and ecological
integrity ahead of short-term profit. It will require instituting
directly democratic ways of making political decisions, so that the
people affected by the outcomes are the ones with the power to determine
solutions.
OWS began at Zuccotti Park, once called Liberty Plaza. It was at this
same Liberty Plaza twenty years earlier that an organization called the
Youth Greens met in the chilly, predawn hours the day after the
twentieth Earth Day anniversary to challenge what it saw as the primary
cause of the ecological crisis: capitalism, as symbolized by the
institution of Wall Street. In solidarity with the Wall Street
Actionâwhich was endorsed by over fifty social and political groups, and
turned out two thousand people organized into affinity groups, with
close to three hundred arrestedâactions were held in San Francisco,
Eugene (Oregon), Minneapolis, and St. Louis. In San Francisco, six
hundred people marched on the Pacific Stock Exchange at 6:00 a.m., with
fifty of those later arrested.
The Youth Greens was largely an ecological anarchist organization,
working with the Green movement of the 1980s and 1990s. It had active
chapters in five U.S. cities, with annual decision-making conferences,
and infused antiauthoritarian ideas and practices into the emerging
Green movement, arguing against reformists. The Youth Greens asserted
that the ecological crisis was a result of social forms of domination,
and that humans dominating and exploiting other humans extended into the
natural world in the attempt to dominate nature. Thus, for the Youth
Greens and its allies in the Left Green Network, resolving the social
crisis, by addressing and overturning all forms of social hierarchy and
domination, was the only way to solve the ecological crisis.
We can learn from the ideas and practices of the Youth Greens. At the
Earth Day Wall Street Action, Youth Greens assembled the first black
bloc in the United Statesâinspired by the German autonomen, or âthose
who are autonomous.â Dozens of young people dressed in all black and
covered their faces with black bandanas as a way to avoid being
identified and surveilled by police. Nine years later, this tactic would
gain worldwide visibility at the World Trade Organization protests in
Seattle. The Youth Greens also developed political principles covering
almost every aspect of contemporary life, from gay and lesbian
liberation to antiracism to the practice of direct democracy, viewing
all this as interrelated and part of a larger global movement.
As new movements continue, we need to incorporate an ecological
sensibility and understanding of how capitalismâwhich is responsible for
most of the social ills being protestedâis also responsible for changing
the climate. We will need to fundamentally reorganize society to not
only ensure social and economic justice but also preserve humanity. For
humanity to thrive, capitalism must die. Climate change is racist.
Whether dubbed the 1 percent or the ruling class, the people who control
the countries of the Northern Hemisphere are sacrificing the lives of
largely poor people of color to maintain their rule and accumulate
wealth. The most privileged people on the planet are letting millions of
the less fortunate suffer and die. Three hundred thousand people a year
are dying, mostly the poor of the Southern Hemisphere, due to the
climate catastrophe. This number will only increase every year that
things do not change.
Instead of acting to stop the emission of greenhouse gases, the
so-called 1 percent is reorienting its military to adapt to changing
climate conditions. The military is the part of the U.S. government that
actually takes climate change seriously. The Pentagon, taking climate
change as a given, is planning on fighting all the wars that will be
necessitated by imperialism within the emerging context of drought,
famine, mass death, and millions of refugees. Whereas recent U.S. wars
have been in part over the control of oil, future wars will be in
response to the destabilizing effects of climate change. It is a vicious
dialectic in which oil and coal continue to propel the economy, then
wars are fought to maintain control over those resources, and further
wars are fought to respond to the results of climate change that stem
from relying on those forms of energy.
To be most profitable, capitalism seeks the cheapest sources of energy.
These happen to be oil and coal. Control of these âresourcesâ is also
highly profitable. The entire capitalist apparatus is built on the
exploitation of oil and coal. Despite all the warning signs and reports
from scientists, the dominant economic system is pushing irrationally to
exploit the remaining reserves of oil and coal through the ecologically
disastrous tar sands mining operations in Canada, fracking and mountain
top removal in Appalachia, and oil drilling in pristine areas of Alaska
and along the ocean shores. Capitalism has become an obsessive, hungry
ghost, wanting more and more, despite its inevitable doom.
My child will be born this year. If our society does not change
fundamentally in his lifetime, the world will be a very different place
by the time he reaches old age. In 2112, life on Earth may be
unrecognizable. He and his generation will likely ask us what we did to
stop this madness when we still had time. Some scientists say we need to
reduce carbon output by 90 percent by 2020, and others assert we need to
drastically cut emissions by 2015. What is inarguable is that the time
to act is now. We know what is happening and what we must do. What stops
us? If our children and our childrenâs children are to have a life worth
living, we must act.
This book is an impassioned plea for sanity, reason, and justice. It
breaks through the collective denial we indulge in to call attention to
the perilous nature of life. The weather is changingâthat is clear.
Crucially, though, the climate is changing. This is the long-term,
underlying reality behind the changes in the weather. Severe weather
events are becoming common, such as floods, storms, and extremes of hot
and cold. We all know something is not right. Matters will only get
worse unless we act. But to act, we need to know what to do. We need to
understand what is happening. Imperiled Life is a critical reflection on
what is going on, and why. It contains diagnosis, prognosis, and
remedies. The diagnosis is clear, the prognosis is not good, and the
remedies are extreme and radical. These are the times in which we live.
Javier Sethness-Castro, like the critical theorists of the Frankfurt
school in whose tradition he writes, invites the reader to come and
think with him. This book is an invitation to an honest reflection on
our changing climate. It is thoughtful, angry, pessimistic, but
ultimately hopeful. It asks us to be bold, remake the world, overthrow
capitalism, and create a directly democratic, ecological society, in
which we live in harmony with nature and each other. We need a society
that does not change the weather or exploit humans, and one that leaves
the world a better place for future generations. Enjoy reading and, as
importantly, act to change the world.
âPaul Messersmith-Glavin
I would like to thank my primary editor Paul Messersmith-Glavin for his
solidarity, patience, and kindness over the course of this work. I also
am indebted to Cindy Milstein for the copyediting, Josh MacPhee for his
book design, Zach Blue for the layout and proofreading, and Santiago
Armengod for sharing his wondrous art. Moreover, I would like to
recognize and thank everyone with the Institute for Anarchist Studies
and AK Press for agreeing to include Imperiled Life in the Anarchist
Interventions series in the first place.
In addition, I am grateful to my mother and father for their support
over the years. I would also like to acknowledge my past formal
instructors Peter Wright, Michael Mason, David Goldfrank, Robert Bruce
Douglass, and Raymundo SĂĄnchez for their enlightenment and aid, along
with Binu Mathew and Ian Angus, who kindly served as editors for some of
the writings that predate and foreshadow this work. Beyond these
individuals, I would like particularly to thank Clark Donley, Brian
Lynch, and Daniela McBane, who served as informal editors and advisers
on the developing manuscript. I greatly appreciate all those who agreed
to provide review blurbs for the book as well. Lastly, I would like to
thank the following comrades and colleagues for their love and
friendship: Liz LĂłpez, Jakob Rieken, Aris Chatzinikoloau, Costas
Stratilatis, Nancy Moreno, Allen Kim, Marcus Benigno, Sierra Lapoint,
Andrew Stefan, Philippe Goute, Cristian Guerrero, Max Hoiland, Jonathan
Carl Vogel, Andrew Enciso, Nate Pitts, and Alexei Hong.
As regards this workâs title, I am indebted to feminist queer theorist
Judith Butlerâs 2004 work Precarious Life, and the call posited by
antinuclear thinker and activist GĂŒnther Anders in his 1955 work
Hiroshima ist Ăberall (Hiroshima Is Everywhere): âImperiled of all
lands, unite!â
I dedicate this work to Bety Cariño, Jyri Jaakkola, the children of
Nablus, Betsy Boyd, Vittorio Arrigoni, Javier Torres Cruz, and many
others.
âJavier Sethness-Castro
We turn a blind eye to what surrounds us and a deaf ear to humanityâs
never-ending cry.
âAlain Resnais, Nuit et Broillard
The survival of humanity is imperiled. Whereas the prospect of
humanityâs collective suicide through nuclear war seemed a plausible
threat during much of the twentieth century, today the specter of
catastrophic climate change has eclipsed nuclear annihilation in this
horrifying role. The dangerous human interference with Earthâs climate
systems that has been driven by the historical rise of capitalism stands
within the near future to destroy the very material conditions on which
much of lifeâhumanity as well as other beingsâdepends for its
reproduction and sustenance. Basic reflection bears this out.
Average global temperatures in 2010 were tied with those of 2005, when
Earth experienced the hottest temperatures observed since people started
keeping records in 1880.[1] The average global temperature of the planet
has risen 0.8°C (1.4°F) since the beginning of industrialization.
Atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide have risen from an
estimated preindustrial level of 280 parts per million (ppm) to 394
ppmâthe level found in May 2011.[2] The rate of annual percentage
increase in carbon emissions has in fact accelerated in recent years,
exceeding the worst-case scenarios considered by the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in its 2007 Fourth Annual Report, the
most recent of its periodic assessments of the state of the planetâs
climate.[3] Carbon emissions in 2010 were the highest ever recorded,
despite the ongoing recession.[4] As the International Energy Agency
notes, the continued reproduction of such trends in the foreseeable
future would entirely jeopardize hopes for limiting climate change to a
2°C (3.6°F) rise in average global temperatures, the warming threshold
considered âsafe.â Worse, a climatological study released just before
the 2010 Copenhagen climate negotiations found the world to be on course
for a 6°C (10.5°F) rise in average global temperatures by the end of the
present century.[5] Change on such a destructive scale would undoubtedly
result in mass death among humans as agriculture generally fails, water
supplies significantly diminish, and diseases spread. Billions of people
would be expected to die under such conditions, as British Earth
scientist James Lovelock has warned.[6] British climatologist Kevin
Anderson estimates that a mere 10 percent of the present human
populationâaround a half-billion peopleâwould survive a 4°Câ6°C (7°F
â10.5°F) increase.[7]
Plainly stated, much of humanity, together with future generations, is
being sacrificed in the interest of what Marxist U.S. geographer David
Harvey terms âthe two primary systemic agents in our timeâ: capital and
the state.[8] This consideration is readily observed in the behavior
engaged in by the worldâs states at the NovemberâDecember 2010
Conference of Parties (COP16) to the United Nations Framework Convention
on Climate Change held in CancĂșn, Mexico, as in other exercises in
absurdist theater that pass for climate negotiations. That CancĂșnâs Moon
Palace, the forum for the talks, is located less than two hundred miles
from the Chicxulub siteâthe location of the impact crater of the
infamous asteroid that, striking Earth 65 million years ago, is believed
to have induced the mass-extinction event that destroyed the dinosaurs
and approximately half of all other existing speciesâseems fitting, for
a similar mass-extinction event is currently being enacted by global
capitalism, with present extinction rates having been estimated in 2004
to be a hundred to a thousand times the âbackgroundâ or average
extinction rate observed in Earthâs fossil record.[9] Indeed, of the 8.7
million species estimated in August 2011 to exist on Earth, many are
expected to go extinct well before being discovered by science.[10]
Whether the present extinction crisis will be as near terminal as that
experienced during the Great Dying visited on Earth 251 million years
ago in the Permian Age, when over 90 percent of all existing species
perished, remains to be seen. It bears noting that the Permian Age,
unlike the end-Cretaceous extinction event that began at Chicxulub, is
thought to have been caused not by asteroid impact but rather by
catastrophic climate change induced by intense volcanic activity that
was accelerated through positive-feedback mechanisms that ultimately
synergized in dismantling the planetâs protective ozone layer. Unless
radically interrupted, the life destruction currently being prosecuted
by global capitalism will be similarly catastrophic.
Such reflections militate sharply against German idealist George Wilhelm
Friedrich Hegelâs interpretation of human historyâthe dubious notion
that âthe Real is the rational, and the rational is the Realââas well as
other manners of understanding and relating to the world denounced by
antiauthoritarian French psychoanalyst FĂ©lix Guattari as being
âsedativeââthat is, ones that render invisible the acute suffering
perpetrated by the profoundly wrong nature of existing society.[11] In
place of this, reflection on the present climate predicament, taken
alongside consideration of the threat of imperial war and other
potential relapses, could come close to German Marxists Max Horkheimer
and Theodor W. Adornoâs assertion in the mid-1940s that the âdialectic
of Enlightenmentâ as well as the chance for human progress generally
have failed to bring about an emancipated humanity that does not
dominate nature, and have instead ushered in a âworld radiant with
calamity.â[12] Guattari was in this sense far too optimistic in his 1989
warning that âthere is at least a risk that there will be no more human
history unless humanity undertakes a radical reconsideration of
itself.â[13] It instead now seems to be the case that the chance for
âcontinued progressâ necessitates the âradical subversion of the
prevailing direction and organization of progress,â as German critical
theorist Herbert Marcuse recommends, together with the institution of
the categorical imperative identified by Karl Marx in his early
reflections on religion: that humanity âoverthrow all relations in which
man [sic] is a debased, enslaved, abandoned, contemptible being.â[14]
The world has long been calamitous, of course. Before the threat posed
by climate change came to be understood, the destructions of Vietnam and
Iraq were prosecuted, just decades after the attempted extermination of
European Jewry along with the nuclear bombings of Hiroshima and
Nagasaki. Before these world-historical regressions occurred were the
myriad horrors of the First World War. Preceding this mindless conflict
were European colonialism and genocides as practiced against southern
peoples. The year 1492 CE, when the European powers began destroying the
peoples indigenous to what would later be referred to as North and South
America, was the same year in which chauvinist Spaniards defeated the
Moors, and expelled large swathes of Jews and Muslims from the lands
subsequently claimed by the Catholic monarchy. The Crusades as well as
the Roman Empire mimicked the ethnocide and slavery engaged in by
centralized power since the historical rise of empires in Mesopotamia
and later Egypt. The reign of czars, kings, and emperors mirrors the
regression that overthrew original nonhierarchical societies. Hannah
Arendt, a compelling twentieth-century critic of authority and
totalitarianism, rightly notes that âany long-range view of historyââor
at least recorded human historyââis not very encouraging.â[15] Hegelâs
âhistory as slaughter-benchâ is too accurate a characterization of a
great deal of human history to justify faith in the present and the
likely future, as demonstrated most fundamentally in the prospect of
catastrophic climate change.[16]
Reflection on this question, however, can also bring one to advocate and
promote the cause of revolutionârevolution, as French syndicalist and
playwright Albert Camus has it, âfor the sake of life,â to âgive life a
chance.â[17] A resolution of the climate crisis might be possible
through popular disruption of the operations of presently concentrated
power.
The COP16 negotiations held in the Moon Palace continued the same
disastrous pattern of the nearly twenty years of UN-sponsored talks
dedicated to addressing the problem of climate change. In an astounding
dismissal of recommendations made by the IPCC for avoiding a 2°C (3.6°F)
increase in average global temperatures beyond those that prevailed in
preindustrial timesâthe end toward which the CancĂșn Accord itself
ineffectually claims to striveâno binding world carbon-reduction
trajectory was agreed to at the CancĂșn COP, nor was any date set for a
global peak in carbon emissions. Instead, representatives of powerful
states defended existing power and privilege, following the established
pattern.
The site of CancĂșn provided an appropriate backdrop for COPâs
absurdities. The city, the product of the imagination of Mexican
planners some forty years ago, is notable relative to other Mexican
cities for the degree to which its lifeworld has been colonized by
capital, both national and transnational: installations belonging to
Walmart, OXXO, Chedraui, Soriana, and Office Depot blight the built
environment in the city center, while a seemingly endless number of
hotel monstrosities line the beach of CancĂșnâs zona hotelera. Most of
these sites have been granted either four- or five-star awards, and
hence are completely unaffordable to everyone other than the very
privileged. The scale of these installations is gigantic; one hotel in
particular models itself after the pyramids of Giza. Located on the
supposedly public beaches to which their administrators consciously
block off access, these stunning testaments to the social inequality
created and overseen by global capitalism stand to be destroyed, like
Jimi Hendrixâs castles made of sand, by the sea-level rise induced by
the melting of the polar ice caps. This sea-level rise is naturally one
of the most serious future risks entailed by climate catastrophe. While
the destruction of these temples might represent a justified response to
the concentration of power and dismissal of human concerns that is
practiced by the wealthy and powerful, this sort of resolution could not
be had without devastation for large swathes of humanity, two-thirds of
which resides in coastal settlements threatened by rising sea
levels.[18]
The maintenance and operation of CancĂșnâs luxury hotels and massive
corporations is the work of Mexican proletarians. The living conditions
of many of these workersâlike their counterparts the world overâare
lamentable, especially given the contrast of the concentration of wealth
exhibited in their places of work. The lot of hotel workers in CancĂșn
calls to mind Marxâs comments on capital accumulation: âAccumulation of
wealth at one pole is therefore at the same time the accumulation of
misery, agony of toil, slavery, ignorance, brutality, [and] mental
degradation at the other pole.â[19] Whether or not CancĂșnâs proletarians
will rise up in defiance, as famously predicted by Marx, is an open
question. The seeming lack of participation on the part of locals in
mobilizations, discussions, and other events against COP16 proved to be
disconcerting, notwithstanding the organizational efforts taken up by
various climate activists against this trend.
The master of ceremonies at COP16 was Mexican president Felipe CalderĂłn
Hinojosa, from the far-right National Action Party. At one point during
COPâs two weeks, CalderĂłn was seen literally dressed in green; his major
proposal as presented in CancĂșn was to mandate that the Mexican federal
government phase out incandescent bulbs within the country over the next
three years.[20] This decidedly minimalist moveâone, it should be said,
in keeping with the more general trend among the worldâs states in light
of the climate crisisâalso was reflected in CalderĂłnâs inauguration of a
lone wind-energy plant near CancĂșn on the eve of the summit; the Villa
ClimĂĄtica, a space located next to a McDonaldâs south of the city in
which the federal government held exhibits sponsored by Coca-Cola that
purportedly examined climate change and hosted a âcultural exhibitionâ
where Nextel, Symantec, Oracle, and other telecommunications
corporations were afforded space. The Villa ClimĂĄtica was catered by,
among others, Dominoâs and Señor Frogâs; it also featured a section
dedicated to the commemoration of Mexicoâs bicentennial of formal
independence, bearing the title â200 Years of Being Proudly Mexican.â No
similar space could be found in memory of the Mexican Revolution, the
centennial of which was also celebrated in 2010.
COP16 featured a heavy Mexican military and police presence too. One
estimate claims there were six thousand units in total at the beginning
of the talks.[21] Military patrols in Hummers with machine guns trained
on crowds of Cancunenses and outsiders alike were regular events, as was
movement by police trucks carrying masked officers with assault rifles.
Local news reports in CancĂșn suggest that the Mexican government
acquired a crowd-monitoring drone from the Israeli military.[22] Police
and military helicopters originating from the United States could be
seen surveilling mobilizations.
In spite of the repressive powers projected in CancĂșn, though,
resistance was also practiced. The international organization Via
Campesina put together the Global Forum for Environmental and Social
Justice in CancĂșnâs San Jacinto Canek Park to coincide with the second
week of COP16. The forum brought six caravans of Mexicans from several
regions of the country to report on the socioenvironmental situations
experienced around the republic, at the end of a year that saw
unprecedented rains and attendant flooding in much of southeastern
Mexicoâa reality for which climate change likely bears responsibility.
Via Campesina also invited a number of journalists and other public
intellectuals to speak on the climate and socioenvironmental crises, and
helped organize a march of approximately three thousand people from
central CancĂșn toward the site of the Moon Palace during COPâs second
week. The forum was even addressed by Bolivian president Evo Morales,
who spoke of the need for a âneosocialismâ that incorporates a defense
of ecology with class struggle and called for the third millennium to be
a âpeopleâs millennium,â one in which âoligarchy, hierarchy, and
monarchyâ are overcome as historical residuesâhowever lacking his own
leadership has been in these terms for Bolivia itself, particularly in
light of the violence exercised by his police in September 2011 against
indigenous protesters opposed to the construction of a highway through
the highly biodiverse Isiboro Secure National Park.[23]
Apart from Via Campesinaâs event, Klimaforum10, the successor to
Klimaforum09, which at COP15 in Copenhagen released a rather sensible
antisystemic analysis of the climate predicament, held an alternative
summit on the site of a polo club near Puerto Morelos, a town south of
CancĂșn. Polo players on horseback could be seen some distance from the
Klimaforum campus. The summitâs site was mirrored in its mainstream
politics, which in contrast to those of Klimaforum09, seemed to revolve
around inadequate reforms and approaches stressing lifestyle changes to
address the environmental crisis. This current was perhaps best
symbolized by the talk given at Klimaforum10 by Polly Higgins, a former
corporate lawyer from the United Kingdom who argued that what must be
done in light of the climate and environmental crises is to codify the
crime of ecocide into international lawâas though capital respected such
law in any sense.[24]
Against approaches that defend existing society through reforms were the
perspectives and actions of the revolutionary association known as
Anti-C@p in CancĂșn. An explicitly anticapitalist grouping, Anti-C@p was
comprised of autonomous youths hailing largely from Mexico City and
connected to Marea Creciente MĂ©xico (Rising Tide Mexico). Anti-C@pâs
vegetable-oil-powered bus, which also had appeared at the Encounter for
Autonomous Life in Oaxaca de JuĂĄrez eight months previously, was
decorated with murals commemorating the life of Lee Kyung Hae, a Korean
agriculturalist who committed suicide in protest of neoliberal
capitalism during the World Trade Organization meetings in CancĂșn in
2003. While tied in ways to Via Campesinaâs forum against COP, Anti-C@p
carried out autonomous actions separate from it. One march organized
without a permit by Anti-C@p in the streets of downtown CancĂșn saw
scores of Mexican youths donning Zapatista-style masks and mobilizing
with the goal of reaching the local branch of PROFEPA, the Mexican
federal governmentâs environmental prosecution agency. Anti-C@p had also
planned to disrupt a conference at which CalderĂłn, World Bank president
Robert Zoellick, and Walmart CEO Robson Walton were to speakâbut it was
prevented from doing so due to the police checkpoints erected between
the city center and the zona hotelera. Indeed, in a spirit of
internationalism, during the mobilization called for by Via Campesina
during COPâs second week, the Anti-C@p bus carried a banner
commemorating the two-year anniversary of the murder in Athens of
fifteen-year-old Alexandros Grigoropoulos by police. At these and other
demonstrations, Anti-C@p presented a spirit of passionate rage against
the cruelties of constituted power and the system it upholdsââoutbursts
of anger in memory of the suffering of [humanity],â as Christos
Filippidis characterizes the December 2008 riots in Greece.[25] Similar
in this sense to their Greek comrades, and in marked contrast to the
other critical currents to be found in CancĂșn, those associated with
Anti-C@p also expressed a degree of sadness with regard to the state of
the world. It is unclear whether this intermixing of passions can be
considered an expression of the âhopeless sorrowâ of which Hegel warns,
but it was undoubtedly informed by what Arendt finds to be âthe most
powerful and perhaps the most devastating passion motivating
revolutionariesâ: âthe passion of compassion.â[26]
Above all else, human-induced climate change constitutes a brutal
assault on humanity and life itselfâbut with regard to the former, its
effects are to be borne overwhelmingly by peoples of the Global South.
The drought, famine, flooding, extreme weather events, increased
susceptibility to disease, and sea-level rise that follow from climate
change will affect human populations residing in southern societies far
more severely than those who find themselves in the northern latitudes.
While crop yields may well decline some 50 percent over the next ten
years on much of the African continent and about 25 percent in Pakistan
and Mexico by 2080, parts of Europe and North America stand to enjoy
more favorable conditions for agriculture on average under moderate
warming scenarios.[27] In the dry language of McGill doctoral candidate
Jason Samson and company, global warming can be expected soon to cause
âclimate conditions currently associated with high population densitiesâ
to âshift towards climate conditions associated with low population
densities,â in regions determined by Samson and his colleaguesâ findings
to suffer from high vulnerability to projected climate change: central
South America, eastern and southern Africa, the Middle East, and
Southeast Asia.[28] In their study of possible future drought scenarios,
geographers Justin Sheffield and Eric Wood similarly find that southern
Africa, West Africa, Central America, and the Tibetan plateau would be
the regions worst affected by unchecked climate change.[29] Of the three
hundred thousand annual deaths that have been attributed to human
interference with Earthâs climate systems to date, all take place within
the âdeveloping worldâ; 98 percent of those âseriously affectedâ by
climate change live in such regions, and an estimated 90 percent of the
total economic losses resulting from climate change are borne by
southern societies.[30] Over 99 percent of the five million who may well
be killed by climate catastrophe in the next decade reside within
societies called âthird world.â[31]
What is currently occurring, then, is the mass murder of the Global
South by much of the Global North. This trend in world affairs is sadly
not without precedent, given neoliberalism, formal colonization, the
Atlantic slave trade, and the process known as the Columbian Exchange.
Under prevailing assumptions, humanity is little more than an instrument
or object by which to advance capital accumulation, or else âunpeopleâ
whose interests are to be dismissed entirely.[32] Individuals in general
are afforded the same regard as that shown to K. by his murderers at the
close of Franz Kafkaâs The Trial, when the protagonist is simply
murdered âlike a dog.â
Prevailing societyâs relationship to the climate predicament can be
described as upholding a sort of climate barbarism reminiscent of
fascism. Fascismâthe violent defense of authoritarian social structures,
maintained by the silencing of sufferingâis hardly the exclusive mantle
of the Nazis, Benito Mussolini, Francisco Franco, or imperial Japan. In
the view of Tunisian anticolonial theorist Alberto Memmi, fascism refers
to âa regime of oppression for the benefit of a few.â[33] On Arendtâs
account, totalitarianism originated precisely from imperialist
liberalism; for Marcuse, the âtotal-authoritarian stateâ is the form
that corresponds to the monopoly stage of capitalism, to which liberal
capitalism inevitably gives rise.[34] As Horkheimer argues, âThey have
nothing to say about fascism who do not want to mention capitalism.â[35]
The stubborn refusal by those in power to commit to mitigating future
climate change and making resources available for humanityâs materially
impoverished societies to attempt to adapt to the destruction wrought by
climate change amounts to collaboration with the future death of a
decidedly overwhelming number of human beings on a scale far greater
than any other in human history. In this is seen the irrationality and
barbarism of capitalismâits total authoritarianism. Given that present
climate change has been observed to be contingent on the rise and
perpetuation of the capitalist system, deaths due to climate
destabilization would result not from ânaturalâ causes but rather
human-induced ones, and should be considered homicides. Humanity thus
âwaits to be woken one day by the memory of what has been
lostââprincipally, the three hundred thousand individuals currently
killed each year by capital-induced climate change, and a sum that could
well rise to a million annual deaths within the near future if matters
are not radically changed.[36]
As Marx insists, shame can be a revolutionary virtue.[37] Shame
regarding humanityâs marked failures to protect itself along with the
other forms of life with which it shares Earth could help contribute to
the radical reconstruction of global societyâfor this society, though
ruled over by the repressive order of statist militarism, is âafter all
constituted out of us,â Adorno observes, âmade up of us ourselves.â[38]
The response of the worldâs peoples to the massive suffering brought
about by climate changeâdramatically illustrated, for example, in the
extreme devastation seen in the 2011 âchildrenâs famineâ in the Horn of
Africa, which has caused tens of thousands of deaths and imperiled the
lives of millions, mainly in Somaliaâmust not ape that of the old
manservant at the close of the The Misunderstanding by Camus. In Camusâs
work, the character Maria, having just learned of her husbandâs murder
at the hands of the servantâs managers, desperately asks him to aid her,
to âbe kind and say that you will help meâ: his response is a rather
pointed âNo.â[39]
Among many other considerations, the problem of climate change raises
serious questions about the place of progress in history. âHowever
passionately we may desire the elimination of fascism,â asserts German
Marxist Franz Neumann, âwe cannot close our eyes to the possibility that
it may not be wiped out.â[40] The many horrors promised by climate
change, with their potentially fascist implications, may well not be
prevented and averted. It is hardly inconceivable that the present
course toward a climate-devastated Earth will not be arrested and
radically redirected. While human history would have likely fared far
better were it not subjected to events such as European colonialism,
World War I, or the invention and proliferation of nuclear weapons, the
fact of the matter is that such horrors did in fact come about. The
âastonishmentâ Walter Benjamin notes in the realization that âthe things
we are experiencing in the 20^(th) [or 21^(st)] century are still
possibleâ is tenable only if one subscribes to philosophical
orientations that see, like Hegel, the steady march of progress in the
passage of historical time.[41] In words written by journalist Ulrike
Meinhof before her questionable collaboration with the Red Army Faction,
âRecognizing that something is unreasonable does not necessarily mean it
will not happen. There has already been a time in Germany when people
thought âThis canât be true,â and it was true, and cost millions of them
their lives.â[42]
Adorno writes that âthere is horror because there is no freedom
yet.â[43] The Chinese Marxist economist Minqi Li is correct to note that
âthere is no hope whatsoever to achieve climate stabilization so long as
the world is organized as a system that is based on production for
profit and structured to pursue endless capital accumulation.â[44]
Against this radical lack that characterizes the forms in which humanity
is at present entrapped nonetheless stands the chance for what French
aesthetician Maurice Merleau-Ponty calls the âadvent of humanity,â or
what Adorno terms âa rational establishment of overall society as
humankindââa possibility that in the latterâs view âopens in the face of
extinction.â[45] Global human society must come to âabandon blood and
horror,â both as an intrinsic and instrumental end, for the
âdebarbarization of humanity is the immediate prerequisite for
survival.â[46]
Fortunately for our prospects, humanity has long resisted. The revolt of
the Helots against Sparta as well as the slave rebellions led by
Spartacus and Toussaint LâOuverture are in ways continued in modern
times by the efforts of the Spanish anarchists, the anti-Nazi
resistance, the Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacional (EZLN), the
Naxalites of eastern and central India, and the Movement for the
Emancipation of the Niger Delta, among other groups and collectives.
This tradition, advanced in CancĂșn by Anti-C@p, involves âresistance of
the eye that does not want the colors of the world to fade.â[47] It has
been continued by activists in recent years through, for example, the
attempted shutdown of the city of San Francisco the day after the
commencement of the March 2003 invasion of Iraq, the blockading of an
Israeli air base during the July 2006 war on southern Lebanon, the
âdecommissioningâ of an EDO MBM weapons production plant in the United
Kingdom in January 2009, the direct actions to defend and liberate
oppressed nonhuman animals, the antagonistic fury expressed in Greece
against the state and capital in December 2008, the destruction of
police stations in Egypt and popular storming of the Israeli embassy in
Cairo, and the peoplesâ rebellions that have gripped much of the Arab
world since December 2010, in addition to the popular occupations of
public space that have followed in many Western societies.
As can readily be seen through reflection on the fate to date of these
revolts, thoughâand generally on the âfailed cultureâ that has allowed
for genocide, the possibility of nuclear warfare, and potentially
catastrophic climate changeâthe specter of despair is far from illusory.
While it is to be hoped, as Egyptian Marxist Samir Amin suggests, that
the recent waves of popular revolt against oligarchy and tyranny will
amount to the âautumn for capitalism and the springtime for the peoples
of the Southââor that, as world-systems theorist Immanuel Wallerstein
writes, the global protest movement of 2011 will carry the revolutionary
â1968 currentâ into the futureâthe outcome remains uncertain.[48] An
orthodox Marxist faith that the subordinated necessarily will be
victorious in historyâthat the abolition of capitalism follows from âthe
premises now in existenceââcannot itself be justified.[49] On the
contrary, the fear Adorno observes in Marx regarding a ârelapse into
barbarismâ is a rational one, considering that âthe relapse has already
occurred.â[50]
In light of the problems posed by the threat of capital-induced climate
destabilization, it remains clear that if humanity does not âdetermine
itself,â it will âbring about terrestrial catastrophe.â[51] The dark
choice presently faced by humankind, in the prognosis of Belgian
Situationist Raoul Vaneigem, is that of suicide or revolution.[52]
Contemplation of this choice is the task of the remainder of this work,
which investigates past catastrophes, synthesizes current climatological
findings, and considers the question of hope for a âprogress that leads
out and awayâ from total negation.[53]
Against the dominion of death, it is to be the position expressed in
this book, as Arendt declares beautifully in a repudiation of the
philosophy advanced by her mentor Martin Heidegger, that humans, âthough
they must die, are not born in order to die but in order to begin.â[54]
One wants to break free from the past: rightly, because nothing at all
can live in its shadow ... ; wrongly, because the past that one would
like to evade is still very much alive.
âTheodor W. Adorno, âThe Meaning of Working through the Pastâ
Reflecting in Remnants of Auschwitz, Italian political theorist Giorgio
Agamben notes that âhuman beings are human insofar as they bear witness
to the inhuman.â[55] Besides the value of such a perspective as regards
the particularity of the Nazi genocide of European Jews as well as other
serious historical crimes, such a consideration could be helpful in
terms of the current predicament, for an examination of the degree of
inhumanity threatened by prevailing society could perhaps aid humanity
in protecting itself against a general lapse into barbarism.
In what follows, climate catastrophe is compared with the horror posed
by nuclear conflagrationâa horror that is hardly a mere historical one.
U.S. antinuclear writer Jonathan Schellâs The Fate of the Earth (1982)
and The Abolition (1984) are used to navigate this exploration. While
world-renowned anarchist philosopher Noam Chomsky is right to state that
it is ânot pleasant to speculate about the likely consequences if
concentrated power continues on its present course,â it is also true
that the chance for overcoming brutality and unreason can be helped
along by critical inquiry, as Chomsky often stresses.[56]
The central question examined in Schellâs The Fate of the Earth and The
Abolition is the implications raised by the existence of nuclear weapons
in relation to Earthâs very habitability. The mere existence of such
weapons threatens the âmurder of the future,â in Schellâs words.[57] In
a world imperiled by the factual existence of nuclear arms, the primary
responsibility is to reverse the conditions that threaten human
survival, because there can self-evidently be no value without human
existence, as Schell rightly argues. Just as the right to food is âthe
first right,â as utopian socialist Charles Fourier assertsâone that
underpins all othersâhuman survival is a precondition for all aspects of
human social life, not least of these the very âself reflectionâ Adorno
finds to be necessary for the protection of survival itself.[58]
Schellâs harrowing account of nuclear annihilation places future
generations, whose potential existence would quite simply be canceled by
the death of humanity resulting from nuclear holocaust, at the center of
concern. Voiceless and disregarded, future generations thus share much
with the nonhuman world and ecosphere, generally understood. Schell
movingly expresses the gravity of the situation faced by a nuclear-armed
humanity in his reflections on Arendtâs notion of natalityâthe various
beginnings made possible by life. He writes that the annihilation risked
by nuclear weapons threatens the âroot of life, the spring from which
life arisesâ: birth, or the âpower of communities composed of mortal
beings to regenerate and preserve themselves in history.â Clearly, such
a predicament is far more serious than that posed by individual death,
for extinction, in threatening natality, jeopardizes âthe continuation
of the world in which all our common enterprises occur and have their
meaning.â[59]
The threat of extinction for Schell is a systemic evil. It follows the
legacy of terror and genocide as practiced by the Nazis and other
fascist forcesâincluding as a matter of course the U.S. government, the
first and only force to have directly employed nuclear weapons against
human populations. The existence of these weapons jeopardizes, in the
first place, the lives of billions of human beings and the very
underpinnings of global human society, but their being also threatens a
total assault on Earthâs systems taken as a whole. Nuclear arms in this
sense amount to the single most advanced weapon in humanityâs general
assault on nature. Given that the support systems allowing for the
biological existence of the millions of species on Earth would
essentially be dismantled by a war involving nuclear armsâthat is, a
possibility that follows from the very existence of such armsâa
nuclear-devastated planet Earth would be capable of supporting only
radically simplified life-forms, if any life at all is to survive such
an event. Indeed, the extent of human knowledge regarding the effects
that can be expected from the hypothetical future event of nuclear war
is both vast and alarming, says Schell.[60]
In light of the knowledge available to humans regarding the risks
implied by the development and possession of nuclear weapons, the lack
of conscious action on humanityâs part designed to resolve the problem
of nuclear weaponsâabolitionâis to Schell a manifestation of social
insanity. At times mirroring the critiques of social democracy and other
reformist political philosophies raised by Benjamin and others, Schell
writes with concern on the tendency to repress reflection on the
existence of nuclear weapons. The ânormalityâ sought by ideologies and
practices that distract from as well as actively subvert the project of
resolving the nuclear threat is in this sense âmass insanity,â since it
defends the iron cage that has âquietly grown up around the earth,
imprisoning every person on it.â Statist nuclear policy, which seeks to
prevent the employment of nuclear weapons by threatening total
destruction of a would-be nuclear aggressor by means of nuclear weapons,
is drastically bereft of reason, as its effectiveness results precisely
from its stated commitment to bringing about nuclear hostilitiesâan
eventuality that could well end in nuclear annihilation. Such a
development would be self-evidently absurd and totally unjust. As the
destruction of humanity can never be an ethical actâfor the drowning of
âall human purposesâ for âall timeâ would be the supreme negation of
ethical actionâit follows that no justification can be had for postures
and acts that threaten humanityâs collective suicide by means of nuclear
annihilationâconditions that rationally can be expected to âtransform
the world into a desert,â as Arendt fears, and thus deliver what German
philosopher GĂŒnther Anders terms âsheer nothingnessâ: a ârotating globe
without any life on it.â[61] That humanity in fact came to endanger
itself through the invention, development, and maintenance of nuclear
arms constitutes, in Schellâs view, the âgreatest collective failure of
responsibility by any generation in history.â Under such conditions,
âself-congratulation is certainly out of order,â however much people in
general may seem to have adjusted to and accepted the monstrousness
implied in the threat nuclear weapons hold for life.[62]
The political arrangements Schell analyzes, then, threaten the
institution of what he terms the âabsolute and eternal darknessâ of
human extinction.[63] Were there to be a nuclear war, no escape would be
possible; that a given society were consciously to have elected to ban
nuclear weapons within its territory, for example, would matter little
for its fate in light of the possibility of nuclear annihilation
originating elsewhere. Under such conditions, writes Schell, there is
within the corridors of power âno one to speak for man [sic] and for the
earth,â even if both are threatened with destruction.[64] As P. D. James
has her character Theo in The Children of Men lament, it would seem that
there exists âno security or home for [our] endangered species anywhere
under the uncaring sky.â[65]
For Schell, the prospect of resolving the terminal threat posed by
nuclear destruction can begin only through reflection on this very
questionâa process likely serving as the basis for his The Fate of the
Earth and The Abolition. A means to âsalvationâ could be made possible
if humanity were to âpermit [itself] to recognize clearly the breadth
and depth of the perilâto assure [itself] once and for all of its
boundlessness and durability,â for if the profundity of the threat were
to be generally acknowledged, consideration of the âperil of
self-extinctionâ could take the place Schell claims it deserves within
our conceptions of beingâthat is to say, central. Humans may of course
choose to âignore the peril,â though such a position would be patently
absurd and grossly irresponsible, writes Schell, given the âdanger of
imminent self-destruction.â Echoing Marcuse, Schell notes that it is
necessary for the possibility of nuclear annihilation to repress any
contemplation of the âmagnitude and significance of the peril,â since
the means that threaten this end can persist only if humanity in general
fails to understand the nuclear predicament and act accordingly. The
possibility of extinction, then, arises through the dominance of modes
of thinking about the problem that âat least partly deflec[t] our
attention from what it is.â[66]
Far from subscribing to philosophical idealism, Schell hardly considers
the threat of humanityâs collective suicide at the hands of nuclear
weapons just âsomething to contemplate.â He emphasizes that it is
instead âsomething to rebel againstâ and ultimately defeat. On his
account, recognition of the peril posed by nuclear weapons could in
concrete terms lead first to the development of a subject that could
carry out the abolition of nuclear weapons and second to the
reorganization of global human society along lines that would minimize
the chance that they be constructed again. Humanity in this sense is
called to break with the âresignation and acceptanceâ with which many
persons approach individual death, and come to engage in âarousal,
rejection, indignation, and actionâ aimed at overthrowing the threat of
the death of the species by means of nuclear self-destruction.[67]
Despite the enormity of the problem, overthrowing existing social
relations is in fact a possibility, claims Schell. It is still possible
for humanity to prevail in this sense, on Schellâs account, though the
abolition of the threat of nuclear annihilation would demand
thoroughgoing sociopolitical change of an unprecedented scale. The
chance for such change could begin only through recognizing that the
worldâs prevailing modes of political organization, in failing to
resolve the very real threat posed to life by nuclear weapons, are in
âdrastic need of replacement.â[68] In place of the exercise of
statecraft, people would âreinventâ politics and âreinventâ the
world.[69] The action of a self-conscious humanity would institute the
principle whereby humans have no right to destroy the âearthly creation
on which everyone depends for survivalâ and would overturn the despair
that prevails under conditions in which hope for survival is itself
jeopardized. Against the remarkable lack of action on the part of
constituted power to ensure survival, then, humanity in general could
counterpose a âworldwide program of action for preserving the species.â
Such an end demands that the âpolitics of the earthâ be
ârevolutionize[d],â for only a ârevolution in thought and in actionâ
will allow for survival. The choice for Schell is quite simply
âextinctionâ or âglobal political revolutionâ: âOur present system and
the institutions that make it up are the debris of history. They have
become inimical to life, and must be swept away. They constitute a noose
around the neck of mankind [sic], threatening to choke off the human
future, but we can cut the noose and break free.â Humans in this sense
are called to become âpartners in the protection of life itselfâ rather
than the âallies of death.â Schell envisions âall human beingsâ coming
together to âjoin in a defensive alliance, with nuclear weapons as their
common enemy.â[70]
Schellâs concern in The Fate of the Earth and The Abolition is not
exactly to explore the possible nature of such a conscious political
movement, but he does at times make fragmentary comments regarding it.
For him, the imperative of survival demands that each person take on a
âshare of the responsibility for guaranteeing the existence of all
future generations.â The institution of action motivated by such maxims
would establish a ânew relationship among human beingsââone basing
itself in a sociable responsibility for others. Indeed, Schell writes
that the âfirst principleâ of the movement on the part of a conscious
humanity in defense of life would be ârespect for human beings, born and
unborn, based on our common love of life and our common jeopardy in the
face of our own destructive powers and inclinations.â[71]
In Kantian terms, no human being, whether currently existing or
rationally expected to come into life in the future, would be âregarded
as an auxiliaryâ within the new political world to be fashioned by
conscious opponents of extinction. Radical exclusion, that is, would be
a reality to overcome in the bringing about of an Earth liberated from
nuclear weapons. This point is particularly relevant to a consideration
of the fate of potential future generations, whose very future birth is
imperiled by nuclear weapons. âLove,â in Schellâs view, âcan enable them
to be,â by resolving the arrangements that threaten to âshut [them] up
in nothingnessâ forever.[72]
According to Schell, the abolition of the state form is central to the
task of resisting the total darkness of nuclear annihilation. Those
societies that possess nuclear weapons have placed a âhigher value on
national sovereigntyâ than on human survival, writes Schell, as they are
âultimately prepared to bring an end to [humanity] in their attempt to
protect their own countries.â In a real way, the threat of extinction
follows from the division of the worldâs peoples and territories into
sovereign states, for the state and its war-making capacities have been
preserved even following the advent of nuclear arms, at the cost of all
human life. The alternative to such death as proposed by Schell is that
the worldâs states relinquish their sovereignty, destroy nuclear
weapons, dismantle offensive military capabilities, and establish a
global political system in which violence has ceased to be the final
arbiter.[73]
Prior to a look at current climatological findings, some commentary on
Schellâs views as presented here is in order. The similarities between
Schellâs account of the threat of nuclear annihilation and the present
climate predicament should be fairly clear, since they are âtwo of a
kind,â as Schell himself recognizes in a January 2010 interview.[74] The
perpetuation of dangerous human interference with Earthâs climate
systems, like the prospect of nuclear war, would be âirredeemably
senseless,â and may even threaten oblivion for humanity.[75] If we are
to attempt to even begin resolving the threats posed by climate change
and nuclear armsâif we are to avoid becoming âthe allies of deathâ and
âunderwriters of the slaughter of billions of innocent peopleââwe must
rebel with the aim of overthrowing that which exists, as Schell and
other commentators rightly noteâand as our own reason and conscience
would demand.[76]
Besides the justified urgency that motivates Schellâs works, much of the
commentary he makes on the sociopolitical implications of the nuclear
arms problem bears consideration. It is the historical division of the
world into sovereign states that raises the threat of nuclear
annihilation in the first place, and it is the perpetuation of this
state system that defends the capitalist mode of production threatening
climate catastrophe. âThe state of death is identical to that of
sovereignty,â Benjamin writesâor at least it threatens to be so.[77] The
nuclear danger continues to exist as long as nuclear weapons and the
states that protect them exist too; as Chomsky observes, it has
effectively been a âmiracleâ that nuclear arms have not again been
directly employed against persons since their first use in August
1945.[78] Similarly, the threat of irradiation of the biosphere that
would follow from the related problem of a full-blown meltdown at any
one of the hundreds of the worldâs nuclear energy plants lives on, as
the 2011 disaster at the Fukushima-Daichi site reminds us. This risk
persists insofar as such technologies are generally found to be
acceptable.
Considerations regarding human vulnerability to these various threats
have guided popular mobilizations in opposition to technological madness
in antinuclear movements past and present. This movement from
belowâdesde abajo y a la izquierda (âfrom below and to the leftâ), as
the neo-Zapatistas put itâwould do well to heed Schellâs call for an
association to overthrow social exclusion, both for the presently
suffering social majorities and the expected future generations, and in
so doing, institute a political act of love and respect. Particularly
important for this end, as Schell contends, is the task of examining the
depth of the peril and the darkness it promises. To contemplate recent
climatological findings on the current and possible future state of
Earthâs climate systems is to confirm Benjaminâs diagnosis of the
prevailing state of affairs as amounting to an emergency that demands
revolutionary resolution.
The need to lend suffering a voice is a condition for all truth.
âTheodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics
In the estimation of world-renowned NASA climatologist James Hansen,
âPlanet Earth ... is in imminent peril,â is âin imminent danger of
crashing,â precisely because of the dangerous interference since the
rise of industrial capitalism by the West and its followers with Earthâs
climate systems.[79] This interferenceâdriven primarily by the use of
fossil fuels, which in turn have driven economic expansion and attendant
explosions of social inequality since the origins of modernityâhas
caused the atmospheric carbon dioxide (CO2) concentration to rise from a
preindustrial level of 280 ppm to the present 394 ppm. Due to the
heat-trapping characteristics of atmospheric CO2, average global
temperatures have risen an estimated 0.8°C (1.4°F) since preindustrial
times. Because a time lapse of some decades exists between the point at
which hydrocarbons are released into the environment and the point at
which they in fact contribute to global warming, a great deal more
warming can be expected based solely on the emissions that have been
caused to dateâat least 1.4°C (2.45°F) over preindustrial average global
temperature levels, according to one estimate.[80] The Nobel
Prizeâwinning IPCC estimates in its 2007 Fourth Annual Report that
global average temperatures could rise by a total of between 1.1°C and
6.4°C (1.93°Fâ11.2°F) by the end of this centuryâthough as some
commentators disconcertingly note, such predictions may constitute
significant underestimates, considering that the various feedback
mechanisms that might turn climate change into a self-perpetuating
phenomenonâdiscussed belowâare still unquantified and hence excluded
from the data on which the IPCC bases its conclusions.[81] Hansen, for
one, insists that the global atmospheric carbon concentration must be
reduced to no more than 350 ppm, âif humanity wishes to preserve a
planet similar to that on which civilization is based.â[82] Australian
environmentalists David Spratt and Philip Sutton recommend an even more
radical target of 315 ppm, which they associate with an average increase
of only 0.5°C (0.88°F) over the temperature that prevailed in
preindustrial human historyâa goal similar to that endorsed at the April
2010 World Peopleâs Conference on Climate Change and the Rights of
Mother Earth held by the Morales government in Cochabamba.[83]
The average global temperature increase of 0.8°C (1.4°F) observed to
date has already profoundly affected many of Earthâs peoples and much of
the planet itself. While mainstream U.S. media has frantically sought to
cast doubt on the responsibility that the warming experienced until now
has had for the marked increase in the frequency and destructiveness of
recent extreme weather events, a number of climatologists are alleging
that such skepticism is unwarranted, in a marked reversal of the
reluctance with which many climate researchers have so far approached
this question.[84]
Turning to the devastation for which capital-induced climate catastrophe
is responsible, some 20 million residents of Pakistan, for instance,
were displaced by the unprecedented flooding in summer 2010 that
destroyed some 1.2 million homes, killed 1,600 people, and injured over
2,300 others, leaving between one-fifth and one-third of the stateâs
cultivated farmland temporarily submerged.[85] When the floodwaters
receded from Pakistanâs central province of Punjab, silt deposits were
left behind, covering large swathes of land previously dedicated to
agricultural production.[86] A United Nations Childrenâs Fund report
from September 2010 warned that more than 100,000 Pakistani children
were at risk of dying of malnutrition over the subsequent six months
because of the floods.[87] A follow-up report in early 2011 found that
about one-quarter of the children in the Sindh Province were
malnourished, with 6 percent âseverely underfedâârates analogous to
those observed in African famines.[88] Flooding in Pakistan in summer
2011, while less apocalyptically disastrous than the preceding year,
nonetheless destroyed 100,000 homes, inundated 900 villages, and
displaced an estimated 5 million people.[89]
Climate change has been deemed directly responsible, because local
scientists have found that warming has steadily shifted monsoon rains to
the northwestern regions of Pakistan over the past four decades, away
from the larger rivers more capable of absorbing significant rains.[90]
Everything else being equal, moreover, a warmer atmosphere can also be
expected to produce more violent precipitation events such as these, as
warmer air holds more water vapor than does colder air.[91] That
constituted power has failed to provide the resources needed for some
sort of adequate reconstruction of Pakistan after the floodsâthat some 8
million affected people lacked basic health care, food, shelter, and
schooling a year after the disasterâis entirely unsurprising, however
grave the implications for human welfare.[92]
Shifting to the continent of Africa, 2010 also saw the emergence of
famine conditions that jeopardized the lives of approximately 10 million
residents of Africaâs Sahel regionâprincipally the countries of Niger,
Chad, Mali, and Mauritaniaâas rains failed for a second consecutive
year, causing the annual âlean seasonâ between the running down of food
stocks and harvest season to come three months earlier than usual.[93]
Oxfam representative Caroline Gluck compared the social devastation
induced by the famine conditions in Niger to suffering caused by the
1984â85 famine in Ethiopia, which killed 1 million people.[94] As was
the case with a similarly severe food crisis that gripped the Sahel in
2005, it is unknown precisely how many actually lost their lives, but an
estimated 400,000 children were expected to die from starvation in the
months following June 2010 without an appropriate relief response.[95]
Fire conflagrations experienced in much of central Russia in 2010 led to
the death of an estimated 56,000 people and destroyed an estimated
one-fourth of the countryâs arable land, leading Prime Minister Vladimir
Putin to declare an indefinite moratorium on grain exportation from
Russia, the worldâs fourth-largest grain exporter, with serious
consequences for food pricesâand hence, peopleâs ability to feed
themselvesâin importer countries.[96] Those worst affected in this sense
reside in Afghanistan, Burundi, the Democratic Republic of Congo, Sudan,
Eritrea, and Ethiopia, among other impoverished states.[97] Heat waves
were to blame for unprecedented temperatures in South Asia in May and
June 2010â53.7°C (128.6°F) at the ruins of Mohenjo-Daro in Pakistan in
early Juneâthat killed thousands, though it is unclear if the death toll
from these events approached that of Europe in summer 2003, when some
35,000 people succumbed to heat-induced death.[98] The UN Global
Disaster Alert and Coordination System dubbed the flooding caused by
torrential rains in Sri Lanka in late 2010 and early 2011 a
once-in-a-century event; the rains washed away 80 percent of the rice
crop on the island countryâs eastern Batticaloa district.[99]
Additionally, 2010 saw a drought in Amazonia the likes of which had not
been experienced for some forty years, with the Rio Negro, one of the
Amazonâs largest tributaries, reduced to its lowest levels since records
began in 1902 and an estimated eight gigatons of CO2 emitted by dying
treesâa greater total amount, it should be added, than the estimated
present annual carbon emissions of China, the greatest current emitter
of all.[100] In the Arctic, an ice island four times the size of
Manhattan broke off Greenlandâs Petermann glacier in August of the same
year; indeed, the 2010 Arctic summer ice extent was the third-lowest
ever recorded, and the same data for 2011 may well match the all-time
low observed in 2007âreflections of the âdeath spiralâ into which the
Arctic ice has been forced.[101]
Climate change likely also bears responsibility for the disastrous
flooding experienced in the U.S. South in mid-2011 and Hurricane Irene
that same summer as well as the dry spring in northern Europe and the
southwestern United Statesâthe former having brought about the driest
April observed since people started keeping records in England in the
seventeenth century, and the latter the driest spring in more than a
century.[102] Climate overheating is also the likely culprit for the
spectacular drought suffered in China in 2011, which drove Chinese
authorities to release some five billion cubic meters of water from
behind the infamous Three Gorges Dam for irrigation and personal
use.[103] Anthropogenic interference with Earthâs climate systems is
clearly seen as well in the catastrophic failure of rains in the Horn of
Africa in 2011 and the attendant drought, found by the United Nations to
be the worst in six decades.[104] This devastating event left some 13
million individuals at risk of dying from starvationâa number that
included millions of children, thousands of whom have perished to
date.[105] It is this event, together with the ongoing torturous civil
conflict in the region, that has seen thousands of desperate Somalis
arriving daily at the Dadaab refugee camp in Kenya, a settlement
originally established two decades ago to house 90,000 persons, but now
populated by some 500,000; it is this event that has brought about the
conditions for the emergence of malnutrition rates of 58 percent among
children in Somaliaâs Bay region, and thus the potential death of
three-quarters of a million people, as the United Nations warns.[106]
These disconcerting events have taken place in just the past two years.
In addition to the 2003 heat waves in Europe, episodes of drought in
western North America (1994â2004) and Central and Southwest Asia
(1998â2003) along with flooding in Europe (2002) are âconsistent,â in
the IPCCâs words, with âphysically based expectations arising from
climate change.â[107] It is estimated that China loses 965 square miles
to desertification annually; increased sea levels have already begun to
sterilize the soils of Tuvalu and the Solomon Islands, hampering the
cultivation of taro in both island groups.[108] In Kiribati, rising sea
levels are salinizing the water supplies; on Vietnamâs Mekong Delta
rivers, they are forcing agriculturists to abandon rice cultivation en
masse.[109] Lake Chad in the Sahel has been reduced to 10 percent of its
size only forty years ago, and Lake Tanganyika was observed in mid-2010
to have higher temperatures than at any other time in the past fifteen
hundred years and is warming at an unprecedented rate.[110] The worldâs
oceans are 30 percent more acidic now than a century ago.[111] Glaciers
across the globe are in steady retreat, with 75 percent of the Himalayan
glaciers now classified this way according to a March 2011 study.[112]
Temperatures observed in Tibet in 2010 reached highs not previously seen
in the past five decades of record keeping.[113] Peruâs glaciers have
lost 22 percent of their surface area over the past few decades.[114]
Oxfam reports that flooding and extreme storm disaster events have
tripled in impoverished southern societies since the 1980s.[115] As
Edward S. Herman and David Peterson note, the genocidal conflict in
Darfur may have found some of its basis in the climate change that has
already occurred.[116] A recent Columbia University study found that
historical conflict in southern societies were twice as likely in years
with an active El Niño Southern Oscillation, which in drastically
decreasing rainfall patterns over much of the tropicsâAfrica, the Middle
East, India, and Southeast Asiaâsimulate the conditions that further
climate destabilization can be expected to bring about.[117] Mike
Davisâs findings that the historical synergy between late
nineteenth-century El Niño events and the onset of capitalist
colonialism in India, China, and much of Africa produced the worst
famines recorded in human historyâones that killed between 30 and 60
million peopleâtake on new meaning in light of todayâs climate
change.[118]
To date, then, climate change has proven disastrous, yet the threats
posed by climate destabilization will likely be far more severe in the
near future. The following examines some of the climatological findings
regarding our downward spiral toward climate catastropheâan eventuality
that is promised without a rational and revolutionary intervention to
check it.
In its 2007 Fourth Annual Report, the IPCC offers its worst-case
scenario of a 6.4ÂșC (11.2°F) increase in average temperatures by the end
of the twenty-first century as being based on the lack of any sort of
sensible mitigating policies and the reproduction of
fossil-fuel-intensive capitalist growth. The report states that a 2ÂșC
(3.6ÂșF) increase in average temperatures is associated with an
atmospheric carbon concentration of about 500 ppm, a 3ÂșC (5.25ÂșF) rise
with 600 ppm, and a 5ÂșCâ6ÂșC (8.75â11.2ÂșF) increase with 900â1,000
ppm.[119] As has already been noted, humanity presently finds itself
tied to a trajectory that would see the realization of this 6ÂșC increase
by the centuryâs end. The UK Met Office maintains that a 4ÂșC (7ÂșF)
increase by the year 2060 is entirely possible. Andersonâs predictions
for life in a world warmer by 4ÂșC, mentioned above, is relevant here, as
is Hansen and his colleaguesâ determination that the current warming
rate is progressing between ten and a thousand times more rapidly than
the nearly terminal extinction rate at the end of the end of the Permian
era.[120]
At lower levels of climate change (1ÂșCâ2ÂșC), say climatological reports,
much of the worldâs oceans will be rendered dangerously acidic due to
the mass dissolving of CO2 in water, the subtropical arid belt that
currently rests where the Sahara lies will likely move into southern
Europe, Indiaâs wheat-producing northern states will be devastated, the
Andesâ glacial ice could well disappear altogether, and the critical
melt threshold for the Greenland ice sheet will have been
surpassed.[121] Regions of China face significantly higher vulnerability
to parasitic disease given a 2ÂșC (3.6ÂșF) global temperature increase,
and the general incidence of diarrheal diseases will likely increase
significantly under such conditions.[122] Drought and desertification
from such warming levels will increase the probability that little food
will be available on the international markets; mass starvation is thus
to be expected.[123] With a 3ÂșC (5.25ÂșF) increase, the sand seas of the
Kalahari Desert are expected to begin expanding, thereby rendering
Botswana and much of the rest of southern Africa uninhabitable by
humans; much of Central America and Australia will no longer be able to
support agricultural production; Amazonia will likely collapse into a
desert of Saharan proportions; and a permanent El Niño would be
instituted.[124] Citing his colleague David Archer, German climatologist
Hans Joachim Schellnhuber asserts that a 2ÂșCâ3ÂșC increase in average
global temperatures could provoke a sea-level rise of 164 feet (50
meters).[125] With a 4ÂșCâ5ÂșC temperature increase, agriculture would be
abandoned throughout much of the world, with devastating increases in
mortality. This destruction of agriculture would result not just from
overheating, increased evaporation rates, and decreased rainfall rates,
but also by the intrusion of saltwater into aquifers used for
agricultural purposes, as follows from rising sea levels.[126] The
terrestrial conflagration seen even in a world 2ÂșC warmer than
preindustrial levels would itself be accelerated and exacerbated by the
release of the estimated 1.5 trillion tons of carbon presently trapped
in the Arctic permafrost. A mid-2011 study found that the catastrophic,
entirely irreversible potential mass release of permafrost could well
transpire within two decades.[127] Russian authorities have recently
announced that their countryâs permafrost regions could well shrink by
30 percent before midcentury.[128]
Of perhaps all climatological findings, research on the positive
feedback loops that are being induced by warming is the most
frightening: the increased absorption of solar radiation that results
from reduced deflection by disappearing glacial white surfaces, higher
frequency and intensity of forest fires, worsening oceanic
acidification, and permafrost and methane release unleashed by
overheating would cause warming trends to generate their own momentum
toward even hotter states. A 2009 study on climate change performed at
the Massachusetts Institute of Technologyâless optimistic and thus
perhaps more realistic, for example, than the IPCCâs reports to date
regarding the prospect of achieving significant carbon emission
reductions in the near futureâfinds there indeed to be a chance that
temperatures will increase 7.4°C (13°F) over preindustrial temperatures
by the centuryâs end, with a 90 percent chance that the temperature
increase would range between 3.5°C and 7.4°C (4.8°Fâ13°F).[129] The
studyâs authors are quick to clarify that even their decidedly bleak
conclusions might be underestimates, as they, like the IPCC, do not
fully account for the various feedback mechanisms that could arise given
catastrophic climate change. NASAâs Dennis Bushnell, for his part,
estimates that the average global temperature increase expected during
this century once these feedbacks have been accounted for would amount
to between 6°C and 12°C (10.5°Fâ21°F).[130] Warming of such apocalyptic
proportions would be entirely horrific: it should be remembered that it
was a 6ÂșC (10.5°F) increase that triggered the end-Permian mass
extinction.[131]
Though a matter of controversy among climatologists, there is reason to
fear that overheating beyond these levels could induce a runaway
greenhouse effect that would give rise to what Hansen terms âthe Venus
syndrome,â whereby climatic change abruptly delivers Earth to a state
resembling that of Venus, where life simply cannot exist.[132]
The beauty that is to be found throughout much of the lifeworld points
to a âbeyond,â a radically other lived experience. The experience of
beauty thus displaces the everyday world, similar in this sense to the
experience of interpersonal love. Nature can also be seen as âa subject
with which to live.â[133] As Adorno writes, natural beauty ârecollects a
world without domination.â[134] It militates radically against the world
that has been reduced to âa gigantic gasoline stationâ in favor of a
totality that overthrows âthe evil senselessly visitedâ on âall the
persecuted, whether animals or human beings.â[135]
Reflecting on nature can help people remember their origins, for
humanity itself arose from nature. Humans are not aliens that chanced on
Earth; they came about through coevolution with other beings, however
destructive their present relationships. Anyone familiar with the
genetic similarity between humans and particular apes, or who has ever
observed a chimpanzee infant, is familiar with the continuum of
evolution of which humans are a partâa point rightly stressed by animal
rights theorist Steven Best.[136] These commonalities might be a
potential basis for solidarity among species, and particularly for the
human abolition of the practice of speciesism.
Ethology, the study of different ape species, has been seminal to the
human understanding of self and other. While its demonstration of the
similarities among the different species of the primate order should
lend itself to concern for and sensitivity among humans toward other
animals, it does not follow that primate ethology necessarily advances
liberatory perspectivesâjust as considerations of the even higher rates
of genetic similarity among humans themselves has hardly put an end to
interhuman oppression. Through highlighting the violent, hierarchical
behavior engaged in by given chimpanzee groupings, anthropologist
Christopher Boehm, for one, attempts to show that the human race is
doomed to a similar fate precisely due to the biological similarities
between the two species.[137] For commentator Elise Boulding, though,
humans have the capacity to behave less like chimpanzees and baboons,
and more like the âunaggressive, vegetarian, food-sharingâ gibbon, who
also has fathers âas much involved in child-rearing as mother[s].â[138]
It is perhaps heartening that Friedrich Engels claims that the first
humansâthose at the âlower stageâ of âsavagery,â or the first of three
historical-developmental stages identified by Engels and Lewis Henry
Morgan before himâconsumed nothing more than âfruits, nuts, and
roots.â[139] Such considerations, taken together with many others, may
give credence to Marcuseâs claim that only at a later, contingent point
of humanityâs historical development does âan essentially aggressive,
offensive subject, whose thoughts and actions [are] designed for
mastering objects,â emerge.[140] And in this we may perhaps discover a
sense of the importance of Adorno and Horkheimerâs injunction to
remember nature, the very origin of humankind.[141]
Adorno is somewhat mistaken in his assertion that human history
âcontinues the unconscious history of nature, of devouring and being
devoured.â[142] While human society surely apes the thoughtless violence
experienced throughout much of the nonhuman world, it cannot so quickly
be said that all of nature itself perpetuates this dynamic. Adornoâs
claim overlooks the numerous herbivore species that have arisen through
the processes of evolution. In addition, it ignores the very real
cooperation engaged in by members of species with species members, as
well as members of other species. This factor has shaped evolution at
least as much as Darwinian struggle, as anarchist biologist Peter
Kropotkinâs work Mutual Aid shows.[143]
The French Collectif Argosâs 2007 volume RĂ©fugiĂ©s climatiques (Climate
Refugees) is a series of essays and sets of photographs that examine the
lives of a number of social groups of people from around the globe who
have been or likely soon will be victimized by climate change. The work
itself is proof of massive human rights violations, whether past or
possible future, as well as the stunning destruction of ethnodiversity
that climate catastrophe threatens to bring about. Though much of its
textual argumentation is allied to reformism, its coverage of a number
of regions in which individuals are menaced by climate changeâthe
Arctic, Bangladesh, Chad, the Maldives Islands, the U.S. Gulf Coast,
northern Germany, Tuvalu, northern China, and Nepalâis crucial;
moreover, many of its photos are certainly worthy of reflection.
Yet RĂ©fugiĂ©s climatiquesâs written reflections on the prospect of
climate catastrophe are disappointingly tameâperhaps the product of a
reliance on the now-outdated climatological reports available when the
work was written. One of the bookâs introductory essays, by Jean Jouzel,
a high-ranking IPCC official, alleges that while âstabilizing our
climate is a huge challenge,â the worldâs âpolitical leaders deserve
credit for making this issue a centrepiece of their discussions at the
international level.â In Collectif Argosâs account, global warming
constitutes the âlast strawâ for the impoverished of the world, and not,
as seems to be the case, their death sentence. The work, in addition,
rather dramatically underestimates the possible number of climate
refugeesâthat is, those who have survived and been displaced by the
effects of climate changeâas two hundred million by centuryâs end,
despite the fact that some twenty million were displaced by
unprecedented flooding in Pakistan within a matter of weeks in recent
memory. Sadly, the already-horrifying numbers pointed to by the authors
regarding the recession of the Himalayan glaciersâthat two billion
people could be affected by water shortages within fifty to a hundred
yearsâalso seem unjustifiably optimistic.[144]
Despite such drawbacks, however, much of the material in Réfugiés
climatiques is quite good as well as critically important. An Inupiaq
woman residing on an island threatened by warming seas in northern
Alaska is quoted as saying that she has âtrouble imagining a future for
[herself].â In Bangladesh, Collectif Argos demonstrates the undeniable
dangers posed by rising sea levels, including the penetration of
saltwater into bodies of groundwaterâa development that quite simply
renders agricultural production impossible. Writing honestly, Donatien
Garnier, the author of the Bangladesh section, states that the
âprospects for survival seem grim.â RĂ©fugiĂ©s climatiques examines the
life of Chadians who reside by the ever-retreating shores of Lake Chad
and depend on it. As has been mentioned, Lake Chad has undergone a 90
percent reduction in size in the last four decades; Aude Raux, the
author of the article on Chad, quotes the United Nations Educational,
Scientific, and Cultural Organization as asserting that Lake Chadâs fate
constitutes âthe most spectacular example of the effects of climate
change in tropical Africa.â[145]
Réfugiés climatiques also explores the phenomenon of the outburst floods
of Nepali glacial lakes, formed through the marked retreat in recent
years of the Himalayan glaciers; these outburst floods undoubtedly
jeopardize the existence of underlying human populations. Rauxâs article
on China at points constitutes a particularly compelling look at migrant
labor refugees who, abandoned by capitalists and government, remind one
of the masses of humanity dispossessed and proletarianized around the
world with the introduction of capitalist social relations. The workâs
treatment of the expanding Gobi Desert also illustrates the general trap
that capitalism has imposed on Chinese society, as on global society as
a whole: destroying itself environmentally, in addition to practically
enslaving its working class, so as to promote âdevelopment.â This
dynamic, naturally, has surely been advanced historically by northern
industrial societies before China, as is certainly reflected in the
workâs sections on New Orleans, devastated in 2005 by extreme weather,
and on islands threatened by rising sea levels in Germanyâs north. But
the juxtaposition of the example of northern China with the threats that
warmer oceans pose to the coral that currently protects the Maldives
Islands, or the disrupted climatic patterns that promote greater rates
of dengue fever on these same islands, serves as commentary on the
pronounced lack of solidarity among southern societies on climate
changeâa dynamic already experienced at the 2009 talks in Copenhagen.
In essence, Réfugiés climatiques constitutes a stark warning regarding
the âendangered paradise[s]â it studiesâall of them metaphors for the
totality of Earth, itself a potential paradise imperiled by climate
catastrophe. In its focus on southern peoples and marginalized
northerners, the work certainly functions as a reminder of the
unmitigated brutality currently being enacted by the contributions of
industrial-capitalist societies to climate change as well. Of course,
many of the worldâs regions not discussed in RĂ©fugiĂ©s climatiques could
today be examined similarly, and hopefully in a fruitful fashion; the
Sahel, Bolivia and Peru, Mozambique, Russia, and the South Asian
subcontinent all come to mind.
The bookâs value is perhaps best encapsulated in its closing image:
Rames Rai, a Nepalese yak-herding boy, is shown running in the mountains
with a large grin on his face. It is precisely toward this endâsecuring
the happiness of the worldâs children, and its peoples as a wholeâthat
radical action must soon be taken to avert the disaster promised by
climate change.
The intentional refusal of food products that demand massacre is
naturally to be applauded and carried forward, as is the rejection of
commodities produced by those who have been effectively enslaved. The
mere adoption of individual lifestyle choices, though, clearly fails to
prevent the totality of animal slaughter for consumption by humans and
nonhuman animals. While it is undeniable that nonhuman animals resist
their subjugation by humanityâas is seen in the attacks performed by
circus elephants and captive orcas against their trainersâit is obvious
that they cannot defend themselves effectively against human violence.
Hence, the need for solidarity from among humans themselves.
Turtle beaches and whale migrations are manifestations of life that
should be cherished rather than destroyed.
Contemplation of the acute failures of human historyâthe defense of
nonhuman life being one central failureâgrants ever more reason to the
project of âreactivat[ing] the revolutionary fight,â as James D.
Cockcroft notes on the present-day relevance of the Mexican
Revolution.[146] As Adorno writes metaphorically, the mind could not
despair over the color gray were it not for its cognizance of different
colors altogether.[147]
Approaches that attempt to glean ecological insights from Marx are
questionable. As leftist sociologist John Bellamy Foster often stresses,
even though Marx expresses concern about the effects of capitalist
agriculture on soil nutrient quality and argues that Earth should be
handed down to successive generations in a better state than before,
there is little sense in Marx that the nonhuman, considered of no
instrumental use to humanity, should be valued.[148] Such failures
likely follow from Marxâs assertion that humanity represents the
âsovereign of natureâ as well as his call for the âhumanization of
nature.â[149]
These perspectives on nature are not as developed or sympathetic as
those of Rosa Luxemburg, who writes of the suffering of a buffalo she
encountered as a political prisoner during the First World War: the
animal, having been violently exploited for conscription, was then
subjected to merciless flogging by its handler. Regarding the animal,
Luxemburg observes the âexpression on its black face and in its soft
black eyes [to be] like that of a weeping childâone that has been
severely thrashed and does not know why, nor how to escape from the
torment of ill-treatment.â When the beast looked at her observing the
scene, she writes, âThe tears welled from my eyes.â She is also pained
by the âsilent, irresistible extinctionâ of the âdefenselessâ warblers
whose habitats are decimated by German capitalism. For Luxemburg,
concern for the nonhuman should not be separated from a regard for
humanity. As she remarks, âI am at home wherever in the world there are
clouds, birds and human tears.â[150]
Fellow German Marxist Ernst Blochâs vision is similarly compelling: a
âsocialized humanityâ that is âalliedâ with nature, or âthe
reconstruction of the world into homeland.â[151]
The radical displacement induced by the experience of nature can
likewise be communicated in the experience of the negation of beauty.
The destruction of rainforests to make way for the raising of cattle,
later to be slaughtered, joins the observation of mass collections of
refuse in rivers, canyons, and entire oceans as well as the presence in
azure shallows of patrol boats, cruise liners, and Jet Skis. This is
also found in urban areas, where automobiles, airplanes, police
helicopters, and gas-powered lawn mowers, among other things, come into
conflict with nature and humanity.
The reduction of the world to private property and advertising space
represses orientations sensitive to the vulnerability and fragility of
terrestrial life. The system that exterminated many of the indigenous
peoples of what is now known as North and South America and relegated
many of the descendants of the survivors to reservations has also
radically imperiled the biological diversity of life on Earth, beyond
having destroyed millions of lives and entire societies outside the
Western hemisphere. When people reflect on nature, historical crimes,
and possible alternatives, then âconsciousness of freedom and anxiety
fuse.â[152]
According to North American environmental activist Bill McKibben, planet
Earth has died. Earthâs replacement, however, does not constitute
progress toward a higher or better state. The newborn planet, named
Eaarth by McKibben in his book of the same title, instead develops from
the brutality and thoughtlessness engaged in by much of humanity. In
McKibbenâs estimation, the Holocene geological epochâone that,
characterized by a narrow range of fluctuation in average global
temperatures, has allowed for humanityâs rise and development on Earth
over the past twelve thousand yearsâcan no longer be said to exist, due
to interference with planetary climate systems as well as human-induced
environmental destruction overall.
As an academic concerned with environmental studies, McKibben is aware
of the dire nature of the present state of affairs. On the new Eaarth,
he mentions that the flow of the Euphrates and Nile rivers could well
decline significantly in the near future, and that glacier retreat in
the Himalayas and Andes could cause the water supplies of billions of
people to dwindle within decades. In light of the various horrors that
climate catastrophe could visit on history, McKibben suggests that
humanity recognize biophysical limits and jettison âthe consumer
lifestyleâ altogether, instead adopting a âPlan Bâ characterized by the
sharing of resources between northern and southern societies within the
context of a joint effort to thoroughly rearrange global society on
rational, ecological grounds. Toward the end of attaining an atmospheric
carbon concentration of 350 ppm, McKibben endorses what he labels a
âclean-tech Apollo missionâ and âecological New Deal,â arguing that such
thoroughgoing changes be accompanied by a return to small-scale organic
agriculture on humanityâs part.[153]
Despite the critical perspectives advanced in McKibbenâs contributions
in Eaarth, much of the bookâs argument unfortunately serves present
power arrangements, in keeping with McKibbenâs reformist project. For
one, the author blames âmodernity,â which he defines as âthe sudden
availabilityâ of âcheap fossil fuelâ in the eighteenth century, for the
regression to Eaarth and the various possible future scenarios, given
climate catastrophe.[154] There is no recognition here, or at any point
in the work, of the processes sparked by the onset of the capitalist
mode of production during this period of human history; similarly, there
is no explicit critique of the highly destructive nature of capitalism
in general. It should not be surprising, then, that McKibbenâs
recommendations do not include a call for the abolition of capitalism.
McKibben presents these inadequate reflections while engaging in a
tendency to attribute responsibility for the current socioenvironmental
predicament to an amorphous âweââas though the impoverished, the young,
and other excluded groups have had any sort of choice on climate policy,
let alone the course of history. This line of thought contrasts
significantly with views advanced by Chomsky, who in June 2009 suggested
the following thought experiment: that North Americans fifty years ago
had been given the choice of directing resources toward either the
development of âiPods and the internetâ or the creation of âa livable
and sustainable socioeconomic orderââa false choice, as Chomsky points
out, for no such option has ever been on offer.[155] That McKibben
claims at one point in Eaarth that âwe donât pay much attention to poor
peopleâ should need little comment, however much this side note says
about U.S. liberalism.[156]
Given his recognition of the dire situation today, it is perhaps strange
that he does not come to conclusions more substantive than his call for
a return to small-scale agriculture coupled with an ominous âgreen
Manhattan project.â[157] Eaarth, for example, includes little reflection
on the terrifyingly repressive actions that capitalists and their
defenders may well take to attempt to maintain their privileges within
the context of a climate-destabilized world, as examined in Gwynne
Dyerâs Climate Wars (2008). Remarkably, McKibben fails to systematically
explore the alarming possible impacts that climate change could have on
future agricultural productionâconsiderations that may well prove
important for the viability of his âback to the landâ project.
McKibbenâs perspectives are surely far from those advanced by Benjamin.
Yet hope for the present predicament may lie in the possibility that
contemplation of the profundity of the climate crisis can help move
humanity toward adopting Benjaminâs concept of revolutionâthe âattempt
by the passengersâ on a metaphoric train âto activate the emergency
brakeâ rather than being propelled into the abyss.[158]
For his part, Marcuse sketches a clearer vision of the radically
different relationship between humanity and external nature he favors
than what can be deduced from Adorno and Horkheimerâs Dialectic of
Enlightenment. Marcuse sees the institution of what he calls a socialist
rationalityâthat is, one âfree from [the rationality] of
exploitationââas putting an end to the former experience of self and
other as mediated by âaggressive acquisition, competition, and defensive
possession.â[159] Under these new conditions, external nature would lose
âits mere utility,â judged not âin terms of its usefulnessâ or
âaccording to any purpose it may possibly serve,â but instead seen as a
âlife force in its own right.â[160] This new, ânonviolent,
nondestructiveâ human-nature relationship, which Marcuse views as a
precondition for the self-realization of humanity, is to be
characterized by a âletting beâ and âacceptanceâ of the nonhuman
other.[161] Where external nature was formerly âmastered and
controlled,â Marcuse believes it can come to be âliberatedâ and hence
âfreely [be] itself.â[162]
Politically speaking, James Lovelockâs contributions are highly
problematic. He states that he believes humanity has not yet evolved to
the point at which it could âhandleâ climate change.[163] Following from
this, he urges people to suspend democratic governance, at least
temporarilyâthereby joining environmental journalist Mark Lynas in
calling for a green movement that is âhappy with capitalismâ and openly
promotes the use of nuclear energy.[164] Lovelockâs famous Gaia
hypothesis may have some explanatory power, and his ongoing advocacy for
biodiversity and terrestrial life generally is decidedly important, but
his political prescriptions are unpalatable, in addition to being
unfounded. Humanity can consciously and anarchically choose to put an
end to the social structures as well as ideologies that perpetuate
social and environmental devastation. In place of continuing the
prevailing catastrophe, it can act differently.
What is not can still become.
âErnst Bloch, The Principle of Hope
If the climatological reports synthesized here are remotely accurateâand
there seems to be little reason to doubt their integrity, considering
the degree to which climatologistsâ predictions regarding the effects of
climate change have been borne out by a number of disastrous occurrences
in recent memoryâit would seem that humanityâs future existence is
indeed imperiled. This problematic raises the question of hope today:
whether, in Yale anthropologist James C. Scottâs words, âthe world is
heading [our] way.â[165]
Initial reflections on this question should emphasize the rather obvious
point that the mere existence of hope for social progressâthe
overthrowing of humanityâs oppressors, in Bertolt Brechtâs
formulationâreflects what Bloch calls the âenduring problemâ of the
nonrealization of the very conditions sought by hope.[166] Simply put,
such conditions are possibilities. As Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri
put it, â[If] evil were primary, we would be helpless against it.â[167]
Furthermore, Arendt seems entirely correct to claim that the prevention
of âevilââat its most extreme, the âtotal destructionâ that Adorno sees
as being the âobjective potentialâ of âbourgeois societyâârequires the
âexercise of reason as the faculty of thought.â[168] Against the twin
catastrophes of war and climate destabilization, reason would minimally
demand the âpreservation of humanityâ as a species, in Adornoâs words,
so as to allow for the possibility of that âself-reflectionâ that could
âtranscendâ egotistical drives and thus allow humanity to realize
revolution.[169] In light of such potentialities, Arendt writes,
âthinking itself is dangerous,â for it can be employed toward the
withdrawal of consent and obedience âto laws, to rulers, to
institutions,â and a generalized movement to delegitimize a given social
regimeâone that could under ideal conditions overturn the superior means
of violence employed by capital and the state. âThis superiority lasts
only as long as the power structure of the government is intactâthat is,
as long as commands are obeyed,â observes Arendt. âWhen this is no
longer the case, the situation changes abruptly.â[170]
Toward the promotion of abrupt changes in the prevailing state of
affairs, this section explores the question of hope and human progress
as examined by a selection of thoughtful public intellectuals whose work
has contemplated the profound crises of modernity: anarcho-syndicalist
Chomsky, critical theorist Adorno, democratic socialist Robert L.
Heilbroner, and antiauthoritarian leftist Ronald Aronson. Chomskyâs work
is the most contemporary account of the present predicament among the
four, although the perspectives advanced by the others are hardly
invalidated by their ageâa comment on the fact that the âoft-invoked
working through of the past has to this day been unsuccessful,â that the
âcauses of what happenedâ in past catastrophes have failed to date to be
âeliminated.â[171]
For Chomsky, the âprimary challengeâ faced by the worldâs peoples today
is âdecent survival.â[172] Human survival, in Chomskyâs view, is
presently being jeopardized by the specters of war, nuclear
annihilation, and environmental collapse. His reflections on these
questions dovetail with his concerns regarding evolutionary biologist
Ernst Mayrâs assertion that the emergence in evolution of the âhigher
intelligenceâ afforded humans is little more than a âbiological errorâ
that could soon cease to exist, with humans thus joining the billions of
other species that have been relegated to extinction since the origins
of life.[173] Chomsky shares Mayrâs sentiments on the human prospect,
for he has variously referred to the present situation as being âthe
possibly terminal phase of human existenceâ and, borrowing from Indian
journalist Arundhati Roy, the potential âendgame for the human
race.â[174]
Some of the most serious threats to decent survival are, for Chomsky,
those posed by a militarized humanity, especially the increasingly
advanced death technologies maintained and developed by dominant power
groups. Critical for Chomsky in this sense is consideration of U.S.
nuclear weapons policy, which asserts the right to strike first even
against nonnuclear states, and recent U.S. efforts to develop tactical
nuclear weapons for offensive rather than deterrence use.[175] In
addition, U.S. plans to develop ballistic-missile defense programsâbegun
under George W. Bush and advanced by Barack Obamaâare highly
disconcerting to Chomsky, for such putatively defensive capabilities
could well be used offensively, since they provide their possessors with
total defense from retaliatory missile strikes.[176] Because a ballistic
missile defense program would be directed from satellite installations
in space, such systems are in fact vulnerable to antisatellite attack by
means of technologies âreadily availableâ even to those societies
Chomsky terms âlesser powers.â[177] The furtherance of ballistic missile
defense may, then, demand the implementation of a military doctrine of
âtotal spectrum dominance,â implying the subjection of terrestrial
matters to âoverwhelming controlâ and the advancement of the
militarization of spaceâitself a âmajor threat to survival.â[178] Among
other considerations, such policies would likely demand the institution
of a âprompt global strikeâ capability, which would allow its handler
(the United States) to attack any target on Earth within a matter of
hours or even minutes; it bears mentioning that development of the
prompt global strike system has been promoted by the Obama
administration, particularly with the August 2011 attempted flight of
the Falcon HV-2, a remotely controlled military aircraft that could have
traveled at speeds of thirteen thousand miles per hour.[179] Though the
test flight of the Falcon HV-2 thankfully failed, Chomsky is right to
note that the advent of such projects has âno remote historical
parallel.â[180] They follow from the present organization of the world,
threatened with calamity as it is by the policy orientations of the
United Statesâa state with historically unprecedented repressive
capacities.
Beyond potentially terminal imperial war, Chomsky has also identified
the severity of the climate predicament as a threat to survival. Noting
the question to be of âtranscendent importance,â he writes that the
environmental crisis âthreatens real catastrophe for everyone.â[181]
âMaybe some humans will surviveâ unchecked climate catastrophe, he
remarks, âbut it will be scattered and nothing like a decent
existence.â[182] Significant changes to avoid such an eventuality are
missing in existing society, and Chomsky sees them as even being
inherently at odds with the ruling maxims of the given order. In
capitalism, he asserts, short-term profits outweigh long-term
considerations, and externalitiesâthe âside effectsâ or âcollateral
damageâ of profit-seeking behaviorâmust be ignored for normal production
to exist, even if, as in the case of climate change, âthe externalities
happen to be the fate of the species.â[183] Chomsky also believes that
responsibility for the climate crisis lies in the tendency to dismiss
the interests of those who, possessing little to no economic resources,
are considered in the ill-named democracy of the market to have no
interests at all, particularly the materially impoverished as well as
future generations. It follows, he writes, that those who accept this
institutional assemblage will work to âdestroy the possibility for
decent survival for our grandchildren, if by so doing [they] can
maximize [their] own âwealth.ââ[184] Within existing arrangements, then,
âprofits for the next quarter (leading to huge bonuses for the CEOs)â
are valued more than continued human existence.[185] The âdedicated
effortsâ that have been taken to dismantle institutions designed to
âmitigate the harsh consequences of market fundamentalismâ are
principally to blame in this sense, along with those efforts launched
against the âculture of sympathy and solidarity.â[186]
The threats that Chomsky identifies to the prospect of decent human
survival are formidable. Despite the grave implications of having
existing technologies be largely controlled by capitalists and state
managersâagents who respond to little other than profit and
powerâChomsky nonetheless stresses that the present predicament should
not be considered a historical aberration. The unprecedented present
ânear-monopoly of the means of large-scale violence in the hands of one
stateââthe United Statesâcan be said to follow from the conquest of
âmost of the worldâ by Europe and its settler societiesâa process
greatly accelerated by the events of 1492, and subsequently carried
forward by the âdevelopmentâ trajectory implied by colonial-capitalist
control of vast foreign territories and labor forces.[187] The Allied
victory in World War II left the United States as the reigning
superpower, and the collapse of the Soviet Union only strengthened the
U.S. position as world ruler. Though it should be uncontroversial to
observe that those with power and privilege act to protect and defend
such power and privilege, an understanding of this dynamic can greatly
help to explain the prevailing situation. In this sense, Chomskyâs
drawing of parallels between the actions of the United States since its
rise to superpower status in the mid-twentieth century and the efforts
of the reactionary Austrian Count Metternich and Russian czars to hold
then-prevailing power relations is instructive.[188] It helps account
for a particularly salient characteristic of global political experience
as subordinated to U.S. power: the fierce repression by the United
States and its various allies of what Oxfam has termed the âthreat of a
good example,â or âsuccessful independent development,â as in Cuba,
Guatemala, Nicaragua, and Vietnam, to name only a handful of rebellious
societies that have met with the U.S. âMafiaâ doctrine: that
disobedience, a âvirusâ that âspread[s] contagion,â cannot be
toleratedâthat âthe idea of taking matters into [oneâs] own handsâ must
be repressed.[189] âThe threat,â as Caribbean scholar Nick Nesbitt
notes, âis one of ideological contamination.â[190] It is reproduced, for
one, in the alternative that highland stateless societies represent to
the captive subjects of Southeast Asian padi states, and in those
alternatives posed to centralized power by the Parisian sections of the
French Revolution of 1789 and the soviets after 1917.[191]
The United States can hardly be said to have a monopoly on the practice
of Chomskyâs Mafia doctrine, in light of similar actions taken by
powerful states from Israel to the Russian Federation. The doctrine is a
practice following from the existence of hierarchical power structures
in the first place and the violent efforts taken by those privileged by
such arrangements to maintain such power relations. Perhaps most
important, though, an understanding of this dynamic may go some way in
explaining the marked absence today of substantive spaces dedicated to
the advancement of social revolution.
Though the correlation of present-day forces is undoubtedly dire,
Chomsky, as an Enlightenment rationalist, holds this reality to be
socially contingent. The policy choices that enhance the threats to
survival posed by militarism and environmental catastrophe are
formulated by elite classes the world overâindividuals whom Chomsky
refers to as the âprincipal architects of policyââthemselves constrained
by their embeddedness within prevailing institutional frameworks
championing capitalist profit along with the maintenance and furtherance
of domination as fundamental ends to be advanced.[192] If these two
aspects of global society can somehow be overcome, Chomsky argues,
rationality and humanity may in fact be allowed to prevail, and the
various threats to human survival be resolved.
Critical for the project of avoiding âsevere consequences for the
speciesâ is in Chomskyâs view a radical reconsideration of the âsectors
that are in a position to determine policy.â[193] In the U.S. context,
Chomsky identifies this agent as being the presently dormant âsecond
superpower,â or the general public, which under normal conditions is
relegated to being little more than a spectator observing the work of
âresponsibleâ functionaries of capital and the state.[194] Mirroring
recommendations made by Jacques RanciĂšre for the âpart that has no partâ
to intervene in the political world, Chomsky calls for an âaroused
publicâ to engage in popular mobilizations that seek to disrupt
hegemonic politics and remake society along lines radically different
than those propagated by dominant interests to date.[195] In concrete
terms, he writes of the âauthentic hopeâ to be gleaned from the
grassroots campaigning efforts that propelled Obama to the
presidencyâthat is, that those who have been âorganized to take
instructions from the leader might âbreak free,ââ and come to
participate directly in the deliberation on and formulation of
policymaking, which is usually considered to be the reserve of the
political class.[196] The various atrocities engaged in by the United
States and its alliesâas well as those advanced by power structures
independent of U.S. influence and power projectionâcan in Chomskyâs view
only be halted if âinhibited from within,â for only the subjects of
rights-violating states can enforce the demands stipulated by
international law, to say nothing of reason.[197] The employment of
âscrutinyâ against âconcentrated powerâ is instrumental toward this
endâa responsibility that in Chomskyâs mind goes together with the
obligation to âenter the moral arena in a serious wayâ by means of
âhelp[ing] suffering people as best we can.â[198]
Though Chomsky repeatedly stresses that progress toward such realities
demands radical action above all in the United States, the core of the
global systemâand in this sense echoes the conclusions of German
psychologist Wilhelm Reich, who stresses that âmasses of working men
[sic] will not be relieved of their social responsibilityâ but rather
âburdened with it,â along with those of many autonomous Marxist
theorists, who find the problem of capitalism to be not the imposition
of capital on to workers but instead the complicity of workers
themselves in perpetuating capitalismâthe contributions of an âinformed
and engaged public, worldwideâ are hardly unimportant in Chomskyâs
calculus.[199] In particular, Chomskyâs continued endorsement of
anarchismâwhat he calls the institution of âtruly democratic societiesâ
that âovertur[n] structures of hierarchy and domination,â and are âbased
on popular control of social, economic, political, and cultural
institutionsââshould be read as advocacy of a political project for the
world instead of only isolated communities.[200] All âstudentsâ should
become anarchists, declares Chomsky, just as there should be âdemocratic
control of every institution.â[201]
Were the normally excluded masses to come to replace the existing
overseers as policymakers, rational alternatives to the threats of war
and climate change could indeed be considered viable options. One means
to this end emphasized by Chomsky is the establishment of a nuclear
weapons free zone or even a weapons of mass destruction free zone in
southwestern Asia, given that such a move could significantly ease
tensions between the United States/Israel and Iran regarding the
question of the latterâs nuclear weapons capabilities.[202] As the
possibility of armed conflict passing beyond the nuclear threshold is
perhaps highest at present in the Middle East, it follows that priority
should be placed on establishing such zones there first, although this
should not be taken to mean that other regions of the world could not be
similarly explosive: one thinks of India and Pakistan, for example.
Given that even a nuclear conflict constrained to a relatively small
region of the globe could well provoke a nuclear winter that would prove
catastrophic to peoples unaffected by the direct impact of a nuclear
weapons exchange and its fallout, as reviewed in recent memory by Fidel
Castro, it follows that the world as a whole should itself become a
nuclear weapon or weapons of mass destruction free zone.[203] As with
wildlife reserves, whether marine or land based, merely declaring
certain regions of Earth free from such weapons would however do little
to protect the world from noncooperating states and regions. Thankfully,
support for disarmament policies has apparently been reported among
large majorities of the U.S. and Iranian publicsâhence Chomskyâs
conclusion that âfunctioning democracy might alleviate severe dangersâ
to decent human survival.[204] Were such publics to come to power, the
massive resources dedicated to the military could be redirected to more
productive ends.
Beyond providing alternatives to militarization and war, Chomskyâs
conception of democratic societies could also offer much-needed policy
regarding climate change. Liberated from the strictures of capitalism,
global society could âmove with dispatch toward conservation and
renewable energy,â and in particular dedicate âsubstantial resourcesâ
toward âharnessing solar energy,â though in Chomskyâs view human society
would necessarily have to overturn the âhuge state-corporate social
engineering projects of the postâWorld War II periodâ based on âwasteful
reliance on fossil fuelsâ while also âdismantl[ing]â the âentire
sociological, cultural, economic, and ideological structure which is
just driving [humankind] to disaster.â[205] In particular, Chomsky sees
great promise in the prospect of redesigning the U.S. manufacturing base
so as to advance the project of mitigating climate change, as is
commensurate with his anarcho-syndicalism: âOne of the things that could
happen is that the workers in [General Motors] plants could simply take
over the factories and say, Okay, weâre going to construct and develop,
weâre going to reconvert, weâre going to develop high-speed rail, which
they have the capacity to do.â[206]
The contemplation of catastrophe and historical regression were primary
questions for Adorno. He asked âwhether culture, and whatever culture
has become, permits something like the good life,â whether the âgood
lifeâ is possible âwithin the bad one,â whether the âright form of
politicsâ lies âwithin the realm of what can be achieved today,â and
âwhether humankind is able to prevent catastrophe.â[207]
For Adorno, speaking after the military defeat of Nazism, âany appeal to
the idea of progress would seem absurd given the scale of the
catastrophe [of the industrial genocide perpetrated by the Nazi
regime].â[208] The âtotalityâ in which Adorno finds himself is for him
âodious and abhorrent,â as it reduces people to the âlevel of objects,â
thus âradically erod[ing]â the âpossibility of the good life.â[209] The
prevailing Weltlauf, or course of the world, âcontinues to hold a pistol
to the heads of human beings,â and the âdream that humanity would
organize the world humanelyâ is one that âthe actual world of humanity
is resolutely eradicating.â[210] In messianic terms, Adorno claims that
the âname of history may not be spoken,â as âwhat would truly be
history, the other, has not yet begun.â[211] In his view, the very
chance for freedom has âsunk to such a minimal levelâ that it calls into
question the possibility of moral action in the world. At the very
least, he says, the nature of existing society would ânecessarily lead
almost everyone to protest.â[212] Though it is unclear whether this call
in particular should be taken as equivalent to the Russian âĐŃĐ” ĐœĐ°
баŃŃĐžĐșĐ°ĐŽŃ!â (âEveryone to the barricades!â), at other points Adorno
finds space for antisystemic violence.[213]
The present, Adorno argues, could give birth to âboth utopian and
absolutely destructive possibilities.â[214] In conversation with his
colleague Horkheimer, he claims that âwe should talk to mankind [sic]
once again as in the eighteenth century: you are upholding a system that
threatens to destroy you.â[215] In light of such considerations, nothing
less than the âprevention and avoidance of total catastropheâ
constitutes for Adorno âthe possibility of progress,â for only if
catastrophe were averted could progress be said to exist.[216] In
Adornoâs view, progress is indelibly linked to âthe survival of the
species.â There can be no progress without the realization of the
âhappiness of unborn generationsââan idea Adorno takes from the work of
his comrade Benjamin as constituting the very ânotion of
redemption.â[217] Progress, moreover, can exist only if humanity âas a
whole can be said to progress,â for progress only in some areas is for
Adorno no progress at all.[218] This positionâitself close to Bakuninâs
claim that freedom exists only under conditions in which âall human
beings, men and women, are equally freeââis reiterated elsewhere when
Adorno asserts that there is âno emancipation without that of
society.â[219] Adornoâs account of progress here can also be compared
fruitfully with that of French socialist and feminist Simone de
Beauvoir, who holds that âthe existence of othersâ in âfreedomâ is the
very âcondition of [oneâs] own freedom.â[220] For Adorno, indeed, the
prospect of progress presupposes the as yet unfulfilled historical
possibility for the âestablishment of humankind,â since insofar as
âhumankind remains entrapped by the totality which it itself fashions,â
he writes, âprogress has not yet taken place at all.â[221]
Prevailing reality thus allows for the possibility of total regression,
but the chance to both avoid and abolish such a threat is in Adornoâs
view âstill not without all hope,â as he âbelieve[s] that things can
come right in the end.â[222] Adorno contends in Hegelian terms that
âpart of the dialectic of progress is that historical setbacks ...
provide the condition needed for humanity to find the means to avert
them in the future.â[223] Like Benjamin, who sees in âevery secondâ of
the future âthe door through which the Messiah could enter,â Adorno
suggests that progress can begin âat any instant.â[224] Adorno contrasts
his own position in this sense from that of Hegel and Marx, with the
former finding the realization of reason in the historical emergence of
the state, and the latter maintaining that communism is born out of
capitalism, instead stating that freedom âhas been possible at every
moment.â[225]
Expressing claims similar to those made by Chomsky and anarchist social
theorist Murray Bookchin, among others, Adorno argues that the
already-existing âmaterial baseâ provided by the historical trajectory
taken by the capitalist mode of productionâand specifically, its
technologiesâcould be redirected and reorganized to supply a reasonable
life for all humans.[226] Asserting in rationalist terms that âthe
responsibility for the threats that the advancing sciences unleash on
[humanity]â is to be found ânot with reason or scienceâ but rather in
the manner in which âreason is entwined with very real social
relations,â Adorno claims that âno one on earth needs to suffer
poverty,â because the state of productive forces could in theory âfree
the world from want.â[227] âFor the first time,â even âviolence might
vanish altogether.â[228] The promising potentialities Adorno sees in
technology, for instance, are expressed in a rare deviation from his
notorious reluctance to positively sketch out social redemption when he
mentions that societies could be organized âfar more rationallyâ in
small, decentralized units from which âall those aggressive and
destructive tendencies would have been banished,â and that could thus
âcollaborate peaceably with one another.â[229]
The âphilosophy of reflectionâ is central to the prospect of realizing
the âutopian possibilitiesâ that Adorno envisages.[230] Such a
philosophy would develop out of the promise of a âcritical confrontation
with society as it actually existsââone that would result in the
overhaul of existing reality toward ends other than prevailing
ones.[231]
Adorno sees such critical thought by itself, though, as insufficient,
for âreasonâs helpful self-reflection ... would be its transition to
praxis.â He agrees here with his comrade Horkheimer, who claims theory
to be âauthenticâ only âwhere it serves practice.â[232] Adorno and
Horkheimerâs emphasis on the need for such action aimed at rearranging
social relations should not be underestimated: human survival itself is
in jeopardy, Adorno states, if a âself-conscious global subject does not
develop and intervene.â The very âpossibility of progress,â then, âhas
devolved to this subject alone.â[233] In this sense, the âawakeningâ of
humanity is âthe sole potential for a coming of age,â and progress is to
be attained through a âcoming out of the spell.â It is only when
âhumanity becomes aware of its own indigenousness to nature and brings
to a halt the domination it exacts over nature through which domination
by nature continuesâ that progress can exist, according to Adorno. The
domination of humanity and of nature must be halted, writes Adorno;
paradoxically, âprogress occurs only where it ends.â[234]
As exhilarating as Adornoâs account of the prospect of humanityâs
awakening may be, Adorno himself seems to have long been pessimistic
about the possibility of its actual realization. In âProgress,â he quite
plainly observes that âthe idea of a progress which leads out and away
is presently blocked ... because the subjective moments of spontaneity
are beginning to wither in the historical process.â[235] Adornoâs view
here is doubtlessly informed by what he and Horkheimer refer to as the
âculture industryâ in Dialectic of Enlightenment: the socialization
processes of existing society that work to âensure that the simple
reproduction of mind does not lead on to the expansion of mindâ through
formal education, the mass media, television, and the dominant culture.
In these theoristsâ disturbing account, such processes reign within the
existing society, creating a âtotally administered worldâ and hence
fettering humanity in large part to the âgigantic apparatus.â[236]
As serious as Adorno and Horkheimer considered the threat of the culture
industry to freedom and historical progress, the former seems not
necessarily to have believed that the colonization of mind propagated by
existing social relations implies the absolute victory of capitalism and
other authoritarian social relations. âNo light falls on [humans] and
things without reflecting transcendence,â Adorno writes toward the end
of Negative Dialectics. âAll happiness is but a fragment of the entire
happiness men [sic] are denied.â[237] Though the mindlessness promoted
by the culture industry is to a degree generally accepted by people, it
is at times done so with âa kind of reservation,â Adorno contends, and
it is perhaps even ânot quite believed in.â[238] This principle is well
reflected in a 1955 study Adorno authored examining group attitudes
among Germans about the Second World War and the experience of National
Socialism; the close of the study considers those individuals who
expressed reasonable and humane perspectives opposed to war, militarism,
and racism.[239] Adornoâs fundamental position is best described in his
following comments to Horkheimer: âOn the one hand, the world contains
opportunities enough for success. On the other hand, everything is
bewitched, as if under a spell. If the spell could be broken, success
would be a possibility.â[240]
Even Horkheimer, perhaps the more resigned of these two theorists,
expresses similar faith in humanityâs potential: âMutilated as men [sic]
are, in the duration of a brief moment they can become aware that in the
world which has been thoroughly rationalized they can dispense with the
interests of self-preservation which still set them one against the
other.â[241]
Once the uninhibited interest of self-preservation itself is
transcended, humans then can transcend âdestruction,â violence, and the
âmegaton bomb.â[242] Reason then can be employed, as Horkheimer writes,
to ârecognize and denounce the forms of injustice and thus emancipate
itself from them.â[243] Hence the importance Adorno reserves for the
practice of reason, since in his view only reason alone is capable of
abolishing dominationâhence and also his hypothetical assertion that
âfinally progress can begin, at any instant.â[244]
Also worthy of consideration for the present crisis are Heilbronerâs
reflections in An Inquiry into the Human Prospectâa work that attempts
to answer the question of whether there is hope for humanity.[245]
Heilbroner begins by asking whether the likely future of humanity can be
imagined as something other than a perpetuation of the âdarkness,
cruelty, and disorder of the past,â and especially whether a
âcatastrophe of fearful proportionsâ is looming. His answerâafter
considering the problems of human population, warfare, ecological
devastation, and technological developmentâis quite simply that there is
no reason for hope. Against the resignation that could follow from such
a conclusion, though, he comes to moderate this claim by clarifying that
he does not hold the human prospect to be âan irrevocable death
sentenceâ or that humanity is headed toward an âinevitable doomsdayâ but
rather that âthe risk of enormous catastrophe exist[s],â and that these
serious obstacles must be overcome before human survival can be assured.
These challenges can be resolved by the intervention of human
mindfulness, says Heilbroner, though he stresses that nature, too, could
similarly resolve such problems by means of the collapse of the
ecological conditions that underpin human society.
For Heilbroner, contemplation on the human prospect necessitates an
examination of the âdangers of the knowable external challenges of the
futureâ as well as an evaluation of humanityâs ability to meet such
challenges. He imagines that the future will bring with it resource
wars, whereby impoverished southern societies develop nuclear weapons so
as to force northern societies into engaging in mass-redistribution
schemes. Heilbroner does not expect future violence to consist
exclusively of such South-on-North conflict, for continued aggression by
rich nations against poor will surely complement it.[246] He mentions
the possibility that industrialized societies will embark on âwars of
âpreemptive seizureââ to secure access to critical natural resources,
even and especially those located in the Global South. Rather strangely,
however, and in sharp contrast to many contemporary commentators,
Heilbroner exerts little energy pondering the threat of nuclear war and
concomitant human annihilation. Yet he does suggest that a voluntary
redistribution of wealth from North to South could help avoid the
large-scale human suffering he sees as likely, in light of population
growth patterns and impending ecological declineâalthough only if such
redistribution schemes are promoted on a large enough scale. Reviewing
the number of interstate conflicts in the decades since the 1940s,
Heilbroner somewhat helpfully concludes that such wars can be expected
to continue as long as states exist, though he foresees no exit from
this situation.[247]
Another critical challenge Heilbroner sees for the human prospect is the
environmental consequences following from the adoption of industrial
technology. Even if nuclear attacks are somehow avoided, Heilbroner
asserts that human society is rapidly approaching the end point of
Earthâs systems to support âindustrial activity,â thus allying himself
with the Club of Rome and other contemporary socioenvironmental
observers. Anticipating that which eco-Marxist James OâConnor terms the
second contradiction of capitalism, Heilbroner maintains that a grave
decline in material living conditions might result from modernityâs
âmassive assault against the biosphere.â In particular, he identifies
the threat of âserious climatic problemsâ due to the ever-increasing
surplus heat emission produced by industrial processes and argues that
this may be the most formidable challenge faced by humanity. He asserts,
rather optimistically, that the climate threat is a distant oneâhence
his claim that the climatic limits to industrial activity will become
evident within three or four generations, after which âindustrial
growthâ will have to be completely halted, for its continuation beyond
this point in time would, on Heilbronerâs account, ensure extinction. He
nonetheless prefers that growth be put to an end some time before this
point is reached, advocating the widespread adoption of solar energy and
other renewable energy sources. For Heilbroner, the environmental crisis
as a wholeâthe prospect of climate catastrophe, but also the various
other ecological problems induced by modernityâdemands that industrial
activity be âdrastically curtailedâ or even dismantled.[248]
The problem of science and technology is, in Heilbronerâs view,
connected to the environmental crisis. The development of science has
overemphasized âdisequilibrating or perilous aspects without giving rise
to enough benign technologies or compensating control measures.â
Claiming that science and technology are the principal forces of the
age, Heilbroner bases the contemporary predicament in âthe advent of a
command over natural processes and forces that far exceeds the reach of
our present mechanisms of social controlââreification, in the
terminology of Western Marxists. It follows from this that the horrors
toward which modernity is propelling humanity do not come out of
nowhere, for they are caused by humans, and thus can be changed by
humans. In this sense, Heilbroner argues that the prevailing frameworks
in which much of this human behavior takes placeâindustrial
civilization, as he calls itâare the main problem. The âsocialismâ
practiced in the Soviet Union is insufficiently different from
capitalism to merit endorsement from Heilbroner as an alternative, in
light of its endorsement of efficiency, productivism, increased material
consumption, and the domination of nature.[249]
Heilbroner does hold out the possibility that under different
conditions, matters could be made radically different too. He offers the
example of a polity characterized by âextensive decentralization,â
âworkersâ control,â and âan atmosphere of political and social freedom,â
but does not dwell on this alternativeâinstead embarking on a discussion
of whether capitalism could bring about a stationary state, as advocated
by John Stuart Mill and Herman Daly, among others. Heilbroner naturally
observes that no capitalist society has yet to seriously consider the
scale of change needed to achieve something approximating a viable
steady state. Nonetheless, he acknowledges that many of the
thoroughgoing changes in social relations that would need to be realized
if global society were to stave off catastropheâthe âcontrol over the
direction of science, over its rate of incorporation in technology, and
over the pace of industrial production as a wholeââwould more easily be
effected under conditions from which considerations of capitalist profit
have been eradicated.[250]
Though Heilbroner devotes relatively little of his Inquiry to
reconstructive political projects, he lays out some of the basic
features of the path he feels would lead away from the prevailing state
of affairs. For one, impoverished southern societies could come to
redefine the term development through stressing the âeducation and
vitality of their citizensâ over the quest for capital accumulation.
Major efforts in northern societies to minimize the âenormous
wastefulness of industrial production as it is used todayâ could
contribute to the success of this project. Heilbroner also holds out the
prospect of a reduction in scale from âimmense nation-statesâ to human
communities emulating the polis of the ancient Greeks, and suggests that
simplicity and frugality must come to replace prevailing consumerism.
For Heilbroner, the chance that these alternative institutions could
emerge and sustain themselves remains possible, though rather
improbable, as he sees an undeniable need for a centralization of
political power to carry through the myriad social transformations that
are in his view required to uphold the human prospect, especially given
his pessimism regarding the question of whether people will consent to
proposed socioeconomic overhauls. Heilbroner emphatically proclaims that
âno substantial voluntary diminution of growth, much less a planned
reorganization of society, is today even remotely imaginable.â Beyond
structural considerations, Heilbroner claims that this is largely the
case because of the radically limited capacity he sees for humans to
empathize and identify with peoples of other societies as well as future
generationsâsuch empathy and identification being, in Heilbronerâs
account, a necessary prerequisite of popular advocacy of the social
changes he endorses.[251]
On the specific question of whether existing generations can be said to
possess a âcollective bond of identityâ to future generations,
Heilbroner desperately extrapolates from what he defines as prevailing
attitudes:
When men [sic] can generally acquiesce in, even relish, the destruction
of their living contemporaries, when they can regard with indifference
or irritation the fate of those who live in slums, rot in prison, or
starve in lands that have meaning only insofar as they are vacation
resorts, why should they be expected to take the painful actions needed
to prevent the destruction of future generations whose faces they will
never see?[252]
Such an indictment, perhaps Heilbronerâs most fundamentally challenging
observation, is reminiscent of similar comments made by Horkheimer: âThe
human species which devours other animal species, the nations with
bursting granaries that allow others to starve, the decent folk who live
next door to the prisons where the poor vegetate in stench and misery
because they wanted a better life or could not stand it any longerâthey
are all criminal if crime means an objective abomination.â[253]
In the end, suggests Heilbroner, little more is left than disjointed
attempts to âpreserve the very will to live.â Heilbroner allows for the
possibility that a âsurvivalist ethicâ may somehow emerge among specific
groups of human communities; the stark alternative is for global human
polities to be reduced to âthe executioners of [humanity].â[254]
Writing over twenty-five years ago, Aronson considers much the same
question in his Dialectics of Disaster: A Preface to Hope as that
driving Heilbronerâs Inquiry: is there reason for hope? Aronson begins
his exploration by citing Gil Elliot in his claim that the âscale of
man-made death is the central moral as well as material fact of our
timeââthis, in the closing years of the twentieth century, a time period
that has constituted a âcharnel houseâ in which ârevolutionary
expectations have been so thwarted.â[255]
Examining some of the various lapses of that centuryâthe Nazi genocide
of European Jewry, the âSoviet Holocaustâ prosecuted by Leninism and
Stalinism after 1917, the âbourgeois-democratic holocaustâ of the
Vietnam War, the dispossession and oppression visited on the Palestinian
people by Zionism, and the possibility of a âuniversal holocaustâ by
means of nuclear annihilationâAronson reaches several conclusions about
the reasons for the emergence of such social disasters. One fundamental
commonality is the complicity of social majorities with prevailing
realityâthe often-remarkable lack of popular resistance to inhuman
sociopolitical projects. Echoing some of Arendtâs commentary on the
experience of Nazi and Soviet totalitarianisms at points, Aronson
stresses the importance that repressive ideologiesânationalism, racism,
and corrupted senses of Hegelianismâhave had in legitimizing decidedly
illegitimate practices. Distancing himself from accounts of genocide
that find static national cultures responsible for such crimes, Aronson
argues that âno form of society is exempt from becoming genocidal,â
noting that âany contemporary ruling class or national group is capable
of using the modern stateâs weapons for catastrophic purposes.â Citing
U.S. psychologist Stanley Milgramâs investigations into authority,
Aronson contends that the tendency to obey within hierarchical apparatus
helps explain the Nazi experience, but he also stresses the active
complicity of many and the âsilent acquiescenceâ of others as important
considerations. Stalinism, Aronson finds, developed directly out of the
October 1917 Bolshevik takeover, and the genocide perpetrated during the
Vietnam War was prosecuted by a âsmoothly functioning society at the
peak of its wealth and power.â[256]
Writing of the contemporary world, Aronson notes the limited resistance
to âincreasingly mad mainstreams,â lamenting madness as being âascendant
over the oppositional forces of sanity and humanity it continues to
generate.â With nuclear weapons in mind, Aronson writes that âhuman life
itself has been put in question by the people and technology who
ostensibly serve it,â making the following crucial point: âTo jeopardize
life on any scale without compelling reason, and to do this while
denying that one is doing it, is mad.â Against this, Aronson holds out
the promise of an antiauthoritarian classless society in which âordinary
people really do exercise collective control over their lives.â He
claims humanityâs inability to institute such a set of social relations
as being at the very root of the threat of nuclear annihilation.[257]
Similar to Arendt and Adorno, Aronson concludes that the social
catastrophes he explores need not occur again, if enough people
thoughtfully reflect on historical terror and engage in action that
seeks to prevent its reoccurrence. Claiming âevilâ to âalways [be] a
human project,â he declares that its practice therefore is not
necessarily a given. He believes that people will struggle for reason
and justice as long as the human species exists. Aronson thus finds hope
in the prospect of collective human action aimed at âbring[ing] about
survival, peace, and well-being,â at instituting a better world that
will ârespect both its source and its ultimate term (people), and will
abolish the conditions that led to Auschwitz, the Gulag, Vietnam.â
Political action is for Aronson the only possible means of resolving
societal madness, since âthe commitment to sanity, to truth, to
humanity, to survival, means doing battle.â Considering in particular
the universal holocaust threatened by nuclear weapons, Aronson hopes
that humanity will âawaken from [its] delusions, as the Nazis never did,
to attack the social structures responsible for the impending
disaster.â[258]
What, then, can be made of this? A fair bit, in fact. Much in the
perspectives advanced by these four authors, as that of other serious
theorists, is critical in light of the present predicament.
The desperate urgency of the accounts presented should not be taken as
exaggerated or unfounded, for the fact of the matter is that the very
survival of humanity is imperiled, as these authors claim. It is rather
unclear how one should act in the face of what Castro terms this
âterribly sad realityâ (tristĂsima realidad).[259] For the victims of
climate change, past and present, there is no hopeâonly despair. Any
account of the issue of global warming that does not make this concern
central is radically false.
The disorientation accompanying the recognition that the current
situation jeopardizes the future reproduction of human society is
certainly alarming. Reflection on the problem could promote wild
confusion, as Heilbroner notes, for it challenges the very standing of
legitimate action in the world. Certainly one concern is the possibility
that people in general, once having come to reflect on the radically
absurd nature of the prevailing state of affairs, will conclude that the
situation is hopeless, and subsequently further retreat from engaging
with the public sphere and political matters, thereby perpetuating
existing arrangements.[260] Heilbroner raises this worry, which in turn
McKibben has also recently done.[261] Yet Heilbroner himself has little
patience for such a position. Echoing Camus, he writes that âavoidable
evil remains, as it always will, an enemy that can be defeated; and the
fact that the collective destiny of man [sic] portends unavoidable
travail is no reason, and cannot be tolerated as an excuse, for doing
nothing.â[262]
One of the most important contributions made by these authors is the
stress they place on the fact that however catastrophic the designs of
constituted power, humanityâs âglobal societal constitutionâ is
contingent; it can be changed, as it is the result of given political
and cultural institutions, social and economic structures, and
ideologies. Such a critical position is the very foundation for hope
today.[263] Revolutionary humanist commitment and action are not traits
that are foreign to humanity, as Chomsky rightly notes; where they are
present, they can be carried forward, and where they are missing, they
can be revitalized.[264] All the authors examined in this section,
except for the ambiguous Heilbroner, hold such faith in humanityâs
potentialities. The confidence that Chomsky, Adorno, and Aronson hold
for the chance to overcome catastrophe and establish something
approximating reason seems far more convincing than Heilbronerâs
pessimism.
Another significant aspect of these authorsâ accountsâitself inseparable
from claims about the contingency of prevailing societyâis their
anticapitalist perspective. Heilbroner, for one, is certainly justified
in questioning economic growth on environmental grounds, as such
environmental commentators as George Monbiot, James Gustav Speth, and
John Bellamy Foster, among others, have also done. For his part, Chomsky
holds the capitalist mode of production directly responsible for looming
environmental catastrophe, while Aronson sees it as a key component of
the general societal madness that threatens the human prospect.
Capitalism, in Adornoâs view, is part and parcel of the monstrous
apparatus that perpetuates radical human alienation. In his call for
humanityâs âdebarbarization,â Adorno would likely agree with Cornelius
Castoriadisâs claim that âthe present cris[e]s of humanity will be able
to be resolved only through a socialist revolution.â[265]
Nonetheless, Heilbronerâs critique of âindustrial activityââa position
that seems not terribly far from that of primitivismâseems fairly
mistaken. His concerns regarding the environmental destructiveness of
economic expansion as practiced under both Western capitalism and
Soviet-style state capitalism are justified, for both systems have been
thoroughly discredited on these grounds, as on many others. His mistake
nonetheless begins in seeing these two regimes as the only alternatives
open to humanity. If a society used industrial production to produce
essential medicines or energy from solar or wind power, for example, it
would not necessarily be unsustainable. The more relevant consideration
here regards the nature of social relations, particularly economic ones.
As the three other theorists argue, a reorganization of existing
technologies on a basis different than that dictated by growth
economies, whether capitalist or Soviet, together with efforts dedicated
to further technological innovation aimed at drastically reducing human
suffering as well as minimizing or even reversing human destruction of
the nonhuman world, would be instrumental in improving humanityâs
prospects. Rationality and humanity demand that humans dedicate
themselves, as Horkheimer asserts, to assisting people, caring for the
sick, and aiding the poor, in place of valorizing capital and
perpetuating the prevailing modes of domination, including especially
those that maintain alienated labor and warfare.[266] In light of the
climate predicament, moreover, these demands should definitively include
calling for a radical reduction in greenhouse gas emissions within the
near future. This, in turn, necessitates what Adorno calls a âglobal
self-conscious subjectâ or Chomsky dubs a âsecond superpower,â armed
with a recognition of Neumannâs claim that âthe primary fact of modern
civilization is this very antagonism between an economy that can produce
in abundance for welfare but that does so only for destruction.â[267]
Autonomous action exercised by the subordinated could model itself after
the historical experience of the 1871 Paris Commune, the workersâ
councils that arose in the general strike wave that gripped Russia in
1905, the soviet-based democracy that briefly flourished in Russia in
the wake of czardomâs collapse, anarchist upheaval in Catalunya in the
1930s, worker and student mobilizations in May 1968, and indeed the
various oppositional developments that emerged in 2011âin addition to
the speculative reflections of Ursula K. Le Guinâs The Dispossessed,
Ernest Callenbachâs Ecotopia, and Kim Stanley Robinsonâs Mars trilogy
(Red Mars, Green Mars, and Blue Mars).
To assess the chance of a revolutionary interruption of societyâs
prevailing direction, it is crucial to first take account of the various
threats to decent survival. The gravity of the climate crisis has
already been discussed here, but itâs worth restating the urgency of the
situationâto declare, with Horkheimer, that humanity is destroying
itself.[268] Beyond the barbarism promised by climate destabilization,
militarism and the specter of military conflict in the foreseeable
future threaten humanity. The much-celebrated election of Obama as U.S.
president has seen the marked continuation of previously existing
barbarism. His administration has requested âdefenseâ budgets larger
than those overseen by Bush at the end of his time in power and has
advanced the development of a number of alarming weapons-system
programsâthe principal ones in this sense being thirteen-ton âmassive
ordnance penetratorsâ designed to be dropped on deeply buried bunkers
from B-52 bombers, arms found by Chomsky to be âthe most lethal weapons
in the [U.S] arsenal short of nuclear weaponsâ; the prompt global strike
system and Falcon HV-2; and the X-37B and X-47B, unstaffed machines to
be launched into space for surveillance purposes and, it is to be
imagined, possible space-to-Earth strikes.[269] Current near-term plans
to utilize agrofuel sources as part of U.S. military operations are
similarly worrying, given the well-known conflict between agrofuel and
food cultivationâand this under conditions in which some one billion
individuals are undernourished, with billions more expected to starve
because of climate change.[270] The sixty billion dollar sale of U.S.
arms to Saudi Arabia in 2010, war preparations against Iran, and Obamaâs
drone war over Pakistan, which has killed hundreds of Pakistani
noncombatants, all offer glimpses of what can be expected from
continuing to employ such disconcerting technologiesâillustrations of
the wrongly developed nature of a false society, on Horkheimerâs
account.[271] For their part, the millions murdered and displaced in the
aftermath of the U.S. invasion of Iraq would demand that nothing similar
recur in the future.
Such a brief account of some of the more frightening implications of
militarism today necessarily stresses the central role of the United
States in the perpetuation of contemporary problems, but this should in
no way be taken to mean that other existing regimes have overturned the
maxims that govern dominant groups in the United Statesâfor one would be
hard-pressed to find other states that are significantly opposed to
these approaches. This fact has much to do with the realities of U.S.
hegemony, yet this critique should not overlook hegemony exercised
elsewhereâsuch as Han Chinese over Tibetans, Brahmins over Dalits, men
of all places over women and children, and heterosexuals over
nonheterosexuals. The presupposition of universal human equality should
manifest itself as a universal opposition to oppression.
The central question is whether humanity, or at least a significant part
of it, is preparing for a critical confrontation with prevailing power
structures. Given the gravity of the present crisis, everything depends
on this. Social resistance can be found among several existing political
movements, and opposition to the prevailing state of affairs can be
observed in much of everyday life, as explored by Bloch and John
Holloway, among others.[272] The far more obvious reality, however, is
that the world is radically wrong, and that no existing force seems
capable of overturning the present state of affairs. âToo little that is
good has power in the world for the world to be said to have achieved
progress,â in Adornoâs words, just as âthere is [presently] no resolute
and sufficiently unified anti-capitalist movement that can adequately
challenge the reproduction of the capitalist class and the perpetuation
of its power on the world stage,â as Harvey concludes.[273]
While Adornoâs diagnosis of political apathy as âthe universal rule in
all countries nowâ was surely mistaken in 1964, just as it is in 2012,
popular alienation is still strong in the present global system.[274]
Indeed, this remarkable lack of democracy (power of the people, as in
the Greek demos + kratia) seems to be a trend far more present than any
opposing countercurrent, notwithstanding the dramatic impulses expressed
in the recent popular Arab rebellions and occupy/decolonize movements.
Even though Castoriadisâs assertion that âthe peoples of the world are
complicit with the world-courseâ is an unfair exaggeration, it is true
that many individuals and groups of peopleâsay, particularly the middle
classes of industrialized northern societiesâidentify with as well as
actively support the monstrousness of the present. Heilbronerâs
reservations about the egotistical, aggressive character structure
encouraged by the reign of capital, themselves reflections of concerns
expressed by critical psychoanalyst Erich Fromm throughout his life,
seem well founded. Arendt, for one, is right to stress that one reason
why âtotalitarian regimes can get so farâ is that people generally
indulge in âwishful thinkingâ and âshir[k] reality in the face of real
insanityâ rather than rebelling.[275] The phenomenon of societal
mimesisâthe chameleonlike tendency to adjust to and accept given
realityâis tied into this dynamic, because generalized conformity tends
to induce what U.S. antimilitarist philosopher Henry Giroux terms a
âmoral coma.â[276] That everyone en masse should be manifesting a clear
opposition to the status quo is a demand more pressing now than in any
previous era. The lack of conscious opposition among those relatively
privileged in material and political terms speaks to the degree that
many northern residents have been colonized and integrated into the
prevailing realityâa tendency that must be overcome.
The tolerance on the part of Westerners to the inhumanity and barbarism
practiced by and within their societiesâas well as the active support of
some for such realitiesâcalls into question the more optimistic
assertions of the commentators examined here. Adorno may well have been
betraying Hegelian-Marxian optimism in his assertion that he âcannot
imagine a world intensified to the point of insanity without objective
oppositional forces being unleashedââfor the world has already descended
into insanity, and resistance can hardly be said to have been entirely
unleashed. âHell is not something that lies ahead of us, but this very
life, here and now,â observes Benjamin.[277] Sociopathic oligarchs
âruthlessly creating a system of neo-feudalism and killing the ecosystem
that sustains the human species,â as antiauthoritarian journalist Chris
Hedges puts it, are the current managers of society.[278] Progress under
such conditions can only amount to the âfirst revolutionary measures
taken,â in Benjaminâs terms, or action that works to bring about the
abolition of presently constituted power.[279]
The task of bringing about a state that allows for freedom is radically
removed from the conformist orientations that allow for the election of
reactionaries like members of the U.S. Republican Partyâor for that
matter, the U.S. Democratic Party. That openly barbarous forces are
gaining increased control of government in many locations beyond the
United Statesâsuch as Hungary, the Czech Republic, the Netherlands, the
United Kingdom, and Russiaâreflects a rapidly deteriorating world,
although drawing conclusions about given societies from election results
is not a straightforward task, given considerations, for instance,
regarding participation rates or limitations on electoral choices.
If, then, as Adorno says, âanything that we can call morality today
merges into the question of the organization of the world,â serious
questions arise about the possibility of morality under present
conditions.[280] Acceptance of the cultural hegemony promoted by
dominant groups, as in Adornoâs and Antonio Gramsciâs accounts, goes a
long way toward explaining the absence of self-determined societies, as
does the mélange of self-interest, fear, and mindlessness that
perpetuates the status quo.[281] The lack of alternative
societiesâdisenfranchisement, in Chomskyâs conceptionâas well as
generalized antisystemic movements aimed at instituting social
alternatives is consistent with the continuation of radical exclusion
and alienation: it condemns humanity to oblivion. In Horkheimerïżœïżœïżœs words:
âAs long as world history follows its logical course, it fails to
fulfill its human destiny.â[282] Or as Holloway remarks: âPut simply,
the tendency of current development is that humanity is
annihilated.â[283]
The task of overthrowing the present material reality and its
ideological supportâfor humanity to debarbarize itselfâis as immense as
it is necessary. Unlike the end sought by Marxian science, humanityâs
chances are hardly ensured. âWe can no longer proclaim with confidence
that our victory is inevitable,â writes Holloway; in Marcuseâs words,
âThe critical theory of society possesses no concepts which could bridge
the gap between the present and its future.â[284] The hope, thenâif
there can be hopeâis that social passivity and conformism will be
shattered so as to allow for the âgenerally social democratic
attitudes,â which Chomsky claims are widespread among the U.S. populace,
to be made more profound by means of a transition to more radically
participatory political spaces.
The grounds for the hope that a reasonable and just future can be born
from the present are not entirely baseless, as alarming as the threats
posed to humanity by environmental catastrophe are. It is now imaginable
that inclusive, egalitarian antisystemic movements will develop in core
societies, hand in hand with resistance movements the world over, from
striking Chinese industrial workers to Arab antistatist protesters,
revolutionary Kurds, Indian Marxists, indigenous peoples, and the
victims of global militarism and capitalism everywhere. To continue with
this image, this multitudinous international movement could be of and
for the subordinated peoples of the worldâan egalitarian association
that advances solidarity and revolutionary love. This movement would
have to be wide-ranging and diverse, taking account of human plurality
along with the various and multiple factors that perpetuate exclusion,
oppression, and unreasonâsuch as climate catastrophe and war, in
addition to neoliberal global capitalism, patriarchy, and racism.
The point is that the means of production and social relations must be
socializedâdecolonizedâif barbarism is to be averted. In this way, only
through what Arendt terms a âfull experienceâ of the human capacity for
a ânew beginningââthe faculty of interrupting what exists and in its
place âbeginning something anew,â like de Beauvoirâs âsurpass[ing]â of
âthe given toward an open futureââcan hope be bestowed on the human
condition.[285]
If justice perishes, the life of [humans] on Earth has no value.
âImmanuel Kant, âJustice and Punishmentâ
Writing in Negative Dialectics, his last major work, Adorno claims to
have identified a ânew categorical imperativeâ beyond that established
by Kant over two centuries agoâone âimposed by [Adolf] Hitler upon
unfree [humanity]â: humans must âarrange their thoughts and actions so
that Auschwitz will not repeat itself, so that nothing similar will
happen.â[286]
Auschwitz, of course, was one of the major sites erected by Nazi
occupation forces in Poland that, following the institution of the
Endlösung (âFinal Solutionâ) in 1941, served as an extermination camp
for European Jews. It is estimated that approximately a million people
were murdered there by means of mass industrial killing: the infamous
gas chambers and crematoriums.[287] Its genesis apparently found its
basis in the relative âinefficiencyâ of massacres carried out by the
Einsatzgruppen (âmobile killing unitsâ) and related groups within the
Eastern European territories taken over by the Nazi war machine. This
purported inefficacy arguably had to do in large part with the toll
exacted on the executioners who murdered individual Jewsâincluding women
and childrenâas openly recognized by SS chief Heinrich Himmler.[288]
Adornoâs stress in his new categorical imperative on Auschwitz, then,
should be taken as a stand-in for the Nazisâ attempted extermination of
European Jewry as a whole: the Holocaust, or HaShoah (âcatastropheâ).
In Adornoâs own words, his postulated new imperative has âpriority
before any other requirement.â[289] Being categorical, such an
imperative âlay[s] claim to universal validity,â as Kantâs interlocutor
Karl Jaspers explains.[290] It applies to us unconditionally; it is the
âpremier demand upon all education.â[291] As a response to the breadth
of the event of Auschwitz, Adornoâs categorical imperative is a
commentary on the centrality of the Shoah as a historical event, an
expression of the âpractical abhorrence of the unbearable physical agony
to which individuals are exposed.â[292] J. M. Bernstein notes in a study
of Adornoâs ethics that such abhorrence is, for Adorno, the âdetermining
ground for all future action,â a âreorientationâ of being aimed at
shaping human behavior in such a way that no one will come to experience
bodily suffering of the type brought about by the Shoahâone comparable
to Horkheimerâs assertion that âsuffering is the fact from which all
considerations about human life must set out.â[293] Such a reorientation
would in negative terms demand the abolition of the âaggressive
nationalismâ that Adorno sees as birthing Nazism and other genocidal
regimesâfor example, that imposed on Armenians during the First World
Warâas well as the positive institution of the generalized social
recognition that âthe Jew is a human beingâ: that the oppressed,
excluded other is an end whose interests are to be defended and
promoted. It is a call for a new humanityâone that no longer âinflict[s]
[death] administratively on innumerable people.â[294]
Adornoâs new categorical imperative should be taken as a profound
critique of radical exclusion and dehumanization along with the very
real violence that follows. It is a continuation or even a restatement
of Kantâs original imperative, which calls for humanity to be treated as
an end in itself. As such, Adornoâs demand should not be read as
asserting the singularity of the Shoah, as many apologists for Israelâs
dispossession of the Palestinians hold, for instance, given that his
critique of Auschwitz is related to the task of preventing the future
recurrence of something âsimilar.â His perspective in this sense is
close to that of Emmanuel Levinas, who dedicates his Otherwise Than
Being, or Beyond Essence to âthe memory of those who were closest among
the six million assassinated by the National Socialistsâ as well as âthe
millions on millions of all confessions and all nations, victims of the
same hatred of the other man [sic], the same anti-semitism.â[295]
As Levinasâs dedication here intimates, readers of Adorno may be
skeptical about the stress in his imperative on Auschwitz, however
radical an atrocity it was. The millions of Jews killed by the National
Socialist regime were surely âdenied the moral regard they deserved,â in
Bernsteinâs words, but âsuch a lack of regard is massively routine in
human history.â[296] The destruction of the European Jews at the Nazisâ
hands is for Bernstein ânothing historically or sociologically unique,â
but instead represents the âdirection of modern societies as a
consequence of rationalization,â the âhorrific instantiation and
intensification of the dominant sociological and reflective trends of
modernity.â[297] It follows from the fact of state sovereignty, under
which states claim the right to commit genocide against those subject to
their dominion; the Shoah cannot be easily dismissed as a âcasual
aberration of a Western world essentially sane,â as historians Edmund
Stillman and William Pfaff argue.[298] For Polish sociologist Zygmunt
Bauman, the Shoah âwas not an irrational outflow of the
non-yet-fully-eradicated residues of pre-modern barbarityâ but rather âa
legitimate resident in the house of modernity,â which brought about the
unchecked rule of statist bureaucracy, efficiency considerations, and
scientific positivism that Bauman finds principally responsible for the
Nazi genocide.[299]
Adorno follows Max Weberâs observation that the ââobjectiveâ discharge
of businessâ performed by modern administration is carried out âwithout
regard for persons.â[300] Such objectivization is evidenced in the
subsumption of Jewish lives to the demands of National Socialism, as in
laborâs subsumption to capital, as Adorno points out. Even in the formal
freedom afforded the individual in liberal capitalist society, persons
are as âreplaceable as [they] will be under the liquidatorsâ boots,â
claims Adorno.[301] Such assertionsâglaring, perhaps, to those attracted
to liberal politicsâare related to his interpretation of fascismâs
causes, which in his view were born out of âthe concentration of
economic and administrative powerâ by capitalism, on the one hand, and
âcomplete [societal] impotence on the other.â[302] Bauman also takes
this position, placing the Shoahâs locus in âthe emancipation of the
political state ... from social controlâfollowing the step-by-step
dismantling of all non-political power resources and institutions of
social self-management.â[303]
With such considerations in mind, one can then ask why Adorno stresses
Auschwitz as that which must not be allowed to recur, and why, for
example, he does not identify the barbaric genocides visited by European
powers on colonized bodies decades and even centuries before the
emergence of National Socialism as focal points of critique, as was done
before Adornoâs time by Luxemburg and contemporarily by Arendtâwith the
latter, incidentally, arguing that European colonialism served as an
important model for Hitler and his associates.[304] The world-historical
near extermination of the indigenous peoples of the Americas, or Abya
Yalaâthe result of the European conquest, estimated by French historian
Pierre Chaunu as resulting in the death of between forty and a hundred
million peopleâfinds little mention in Adornoâs oeuvre.[305] He pays
little heed to European societyâs application of fascism to non-European
peoples through imperialism, as Caribbean theorist Aimé Césaire
formulates it.[306] Nowhere does Adorno write or speak of the âbones of
defenseless Herero women ... bleaching in the sun,â as Luxemburg does in
commemoration of the peoples of Namibia victimized by German
imperialism, or âthe death cries of martyred [indigenous] women ...
[which] fade away in the rubber plantations of the international
capitalists,â in Colombia as elsewhere.[307]
As is noted by U.S. Marxist literary critic Fredric Jameson, Adorno
showed little enthusiasm for contemporary decolonization and
anti-imperialist efforts in southern societies, in contrast, say, to his
colleague Marcuse.[308] While this omission could have to do with a lack
of faith on Adornoâs part as regards the expected progress for southern
peoples by means of formal decolonization, it is true, as Lebanese
Marxist Gilbert Achcar notes, that the history of imperialism is
multiple, such that âcolonialist usurpation of a [given] territoryâ need
not ipso facto entail âthe racist extermination of whole
populations.â[309] Foreign domination as practiced by the Ottomans, for
example, was rather different than occupation overseen by the Nazis.
Still, recognition of this distinction should hardly be an excuse for
Adornoâs failure to concern himself centrally with the lived experiences
of those subjected to European imperialism, for the inhumanity of this
project should clearly have been self-evident to any observer. This
tendency to overlook Frantz Fanonâs âwretched of the earthâ can indeed
be observed as having been shared by many other contemporary Western
intellectuals, even radical onesâBookchin and Arendt not the least of
these.
While it may be that Adornoâs rendering invisible of the colonialism
problem amounts to an omission indicative of racism, Adorno generally
does not seem to have been a racist, in keeping with his concerns
regarding social exclusion and authoritarianism. In his view, the atomic
bombing of Hiroshima was an act reminiscent of Auschwitz and the
invention of nuclear weapons âbelongs in the same historical context as
genocide.â[310] His further opposition to racist imperial politics is
seen in his denunciation of the âhorror of the napalm bombsâ used by the
U.S. military in Vietnam and the sympathy that biographer Stefan
MĂŒller-Doohm sees him as having for those protesting the war.[311]
Indeed, in his 1965 lectures on metaphysics, Adorno states that his use
of the term Auschwitz should be taken to mean ânot only Auschwitz but
the world of torture which has continued to exist after Auschwitz,â
particularly as reflected in the âmost horrifying reports [coming] from
Vietnam.â[312] While Adornoâs concrete efforts to resist the Vietnam War
were rather minimal in comparison with those of his more activist
colleague Marcuse, and though his new categorical imperative is not, as
in Andersâs demand, that there be âno more Hiroshima[s],â the
formulation of his imperative should be read as one demanding the total
rejection of social systems responsible for the perpetuation of human
suffering, as follows from Kantâs original imperative.[313]
Serious efforts directed toward preventing the recurrence of Auschwitz
or anything similar should likely take account of the barbarism that did
in fact allow for Auschwitz and the Shoah. Explanations for the rise of
Nazism and institution of the Endlösung are varied, as well as highly
contentious. Neumann, for one, finds Nazism to have been the product of
collaboration among Germanyâs industrial capitalists, governmental
bureaucracy, military leadership, and the National Socialist Party. The
Nazi regime in this sense was in Neumannâs view a reality imposed by
dominant power groups as opposed to any expression of the will of
Germanyâs subordinated classes, which âmerely follow[ed] that leadership
or even resist[ed] it.â[314]
In stark contrast to Neumannâs conclusion here is the questionable
depiction by Harvard professor Daniel Jonah Goldhagen in his Hitlerâs
Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust. Goldhagen
contends that National Socialism and the Shoah reflected widespread,
almost primordial anti-Jewish sentiments on the part of the German
people as a wholeâan âeliminationist anti-Semitismâ found among
amorphous groups of Christian Europeans in general and particularly
Germans, who are described by Goldhagen as being fundamentally
anti-Semitic.[315] Goldhagen claims that such sentiments took hold of
German society before Nazism, and even and especially gripped the German
industrial proletariatâa rather unconvincing theory on all counts.
Reviewing relevant scholarship on these questions, dissident
ex-professor and activist Norman Finkelstein notes that economic
considerations among Germans served as grounds for support for the
National Socialist Party, and that âmost Germansâ did not support Nazi
atrocities against Jews before the war years and even expressed outrage
at such.[316] Bauman similarly finds that Germans in general did not
accept the Nazisâ racist propaganda, observing rightly that the
historical legacy of anti-Jewish sentiments was much less extreme in
Germany as compared with other European societies. Even toward the end
of the war, following the hardening of many Germans to the suffering of
others, it was German commoners who provided aid to Jews forced by the
Nazis to engage in death marches, as Goldhagen himself recognizes.
Continuing this line of thought, antifascist researcher Ruth Birn sees
Goldhagenâs voluntarist interpretations of the perpetration of the Shoah
at the hands of âordinary Germansâ as highly problematic, agreeing
instead with historical scholarship that stresses the âmixture of peer
pressure, careerism, and obedienceâ that Goldhagen dismisses
entirely.[317]
Another way to understand the rise of Nazism is Nicolas Hollimanâs claim
in Principia Dialectica that the emergence of racist Nazi sociological
theories, brutal imperialist expansionism, and the Endlösung would
likely have not entered history had the popular revolution attempted in
Germany at the close of World War I been successful rather than
suppressed as it was by the Social Democrats.[318] Indeed, Germanyâs
Social Democratic Party and the attendant lack of an autonomous labor
movement must assume a great deal of the responsibility for the Nazi
catastrophe. The partyâs hierarchical form of organizing, together with
a generalized internalization of the Hegelian sense of progress
propagated by the Social Democrats, may well have alienated the general
populace from considering a direct confrontation with the emerging Nazi
movement, as was, for instance, practiced contemporarily in Spain among
radical workers. The social programs and economic stimulation provided
by the National Socialist Party in response to the crippling depression
also helps explain popular consent to the regime.
More fundamentally, Richard Koenigsbergâs critique of the state and its
ideology of nationalism is another aid in understanding complicity with
fascism and mass industrial murder. In a discursive move reminiscent of
Adorno and Horkheimerâs assertion that the domination of nature
reproduces itself through domination among humans, Koenigsberg claims
that the sacrifice of millions of people in World War I served as an
example reproduced by Hitler in the case of his own soldiers, on the one
hand, and Jews, on the other.[319] Adorno himself similarly argues that
âhorror is potentially already positedâ wherever the stateâs right is
enshrined over the rights of its membersâor whenever perpetrators of
barbarism pass off their crimes as mere âacts of state.â[320] Wilhelm
Reich is similarly correct to find a social institution in the bourgeois
nuclear family that generally prepares new generations for adjustment to
reactionary social relations and hence perpetuates their dominance.[321]
The fascist stress on traditional gender, sexual, and familial roles is
well known.
Another important factor in attempting to make sense of the Nazi
experience is Adornoâs critique of what he terms âbourgeois coldness,â
or a âdeficient libidinal relationship to other personsâ that can be
observed among âpeople who cannot love.â He claims that, if âcoldness
were not a fundamental trait of anthropology, that is, the constitution
of people as they in fact exist,â if people in general were something
other than âprofoundly indifferent toward whatever happens to everyone
else except for a few to whom they are closely bound,â the Shoah âwould
not have been possible,â as âpeople would not have accepted it.â This
coldness, this âindifference to the fate of others,â in turn finds its
basis in antagonistic, egotistical forms of social organization. Adorno
views the âinability to identify with othersââthis capitalist,
antihumanist traitâto be âunquestionably the most important
psychological condition for the fact that something like Auschwitz could
have occurred in the midst of more or less civilized and innocent
people.â[322] The grip that such coldness seems to have held on the
German social imaginary helps explain, according to Arendt, the
remarkable absence of resistance on Germansâ part to the Nazi
regimeâthis in marked contradistinction to the responses of several
peoples residing in spaces occupied by the Nazis, from Yugoslav and
Greek guerrillas to Jewish Communist female partisans.[323] One must not
forget, though, the courageous and desperate efforts of the youthful
members of the White Rose to denounce fascism as well as those Germans
who gave Jews refuge in their homes, however much bourgeois coldness
likely synergized with popular anti-Jewish sentiments among the general
German population to allow for the Shoah.
This brief review of analyses of the Nazi catastrophe, while partial and
incomplete, leads to the following conclusions regarding Nazi
totalitarianism: it was imposed by dominant groups and met with moderate
opposition, which proved inadequate; its dominance was supported by
preexisting reactionary social institutions; and its world-historical
crimes were allowed to continue in part because of a marked absence of
solidarity with those victimized.
While history cannot simply be said to repeat itself, social structures
of domination, subjugation, and exclusion surely do reproduce
themselves, as attested to by a basic understanding of recorded human
historyâHegelâs slaughter-bench. Many observers have criticized attempts
to draw parallels between happenings since the defeat of National
Socialism in 1945 and what occurred during Nazismâs twelve-year reign
over Germany and much of Europeâfor example, the Bush presidency and
particularly his 2003 invasion of Iraq, or Israelâs treatment of the
Palestinians and other Arabs. Many of these same commentators would
likely find Bernsteinâs and Baumanâs explorations of the positional
similarity between the Shoah and other dominative practices highly
problematic.
It nonetheless must be âcried outââĂĄ la Jacques Derrida in his
observation that ânever have violence, inequality, exclusion, famine,
and thus economic oppression affected as many human beings in the
history of the earth and of humanityâ as in the late twentieth
centuryâthat the climate catastrophe currently under way is causing
social exclusion, human suffering, and senseless death on a scale for
which the historical examples of Auschwitz and the Shoah are a useful
analogue.[324] Horkheimerâs assertion in 1956 that humanity is âheading
for a situation compared to which Nazism was a relatively moderate
affairâ surely merits consideration, especially in light of Adornoâs
injunction that nothing similar to Auschwitz should be allowed to occur
again.[325] The case of industrial genocide is not dissimilar to that of
nuclear annihilation, as analyzed by Schell and others, including Adorno
himself, for the latter would amount to a âuniversal holocaust,â to
recall Aronson.[326] It follows that there seems to be no reason not to
likewise consider the various threats posed by climate catastrophe;
there is, in fact, much reason to do so.
Climate change threatens to induce severe, widespread human suffering
the world over, and greatly increase the suffering imposed and overseen
by capitalism. Does the desertification of formerly populated
agricultural lands around the globeâeventualities entirely dependent on
the use of hydrocarbons by industrial societies through their employment
of capitalism and growth economiesânot constitute a monstrous crime? Can
the eradication of numerous Pacific island societies due to increased
sea levels ever be justified, or the destruction of coastal human
settlements housing the vast majority of humanity? What can be said
regarding the prospect that some five million people, many of them
children, are expected to die over the coming decade because of climate
change, or the specter of âbillion-person faminesââor indeed, the
likelihood that the Andes and Himalayan glaciers, on which billions of
lives depend for water, will be radically diminished by the global
heating induced by capitalismâother than that everything should be done
to attempt to prevent such possibilities from coming to pass?[327] An
Earth that experiences climatic changes that make large
areasâparticularly the tropicsâuninhabitable would clearly violate
Adornoâs new categorical imperative, as would truly apocalyptic degrees
of warming (6°Câ12°C, or 10.5°Fâ21°F) that would likely amount to what
antiauthoritarian scholar Maia Ramnath terms a âfinal solution for
humanity as a whole.â[328]
Faced with such horrific possibilities, humanity can turn to the Shoah
experience as a way of illuminating the current climate predicament. As
has been noted, climate catastrophe could well disrupt agricultural
production in much of the world, thus provoking devastating increases in
malnutrition, hunger, and starvation rates, with enormous increases in
human deaths. Such a possible future eventuality can be likened to the
phenomenon of der MusselmÀnner in the Nazi camps, or inmates who had
reached such a state of acute malnutrition due to their exclusion that
they became little more than âstaggering corpse[s],â largely incapable
of expressing emotion or thoughtâMuslims, in the Orientalist imaginary
of the imprisoned.[329] Though âstill nominally alive,â der MusselmĂ€nner
attested to the âtotal triumph of power over the human being,â similar
to those potentially facing starvation induced by climate change.[330]
The total disregard suffered by those who became MusselmÀnner, alongside
that shown to those who were outright murdered, speaks to the nature of
the concentration camp administration. Similar observations could be
made about currently prevailing administrative processes and
administrators. Indeed, in light of the clearly horrendous toll that
climate change stands to take on human life across the globe, the ease
with which premier U.S. climate envoy Todd Stern dismisses the
historical responsibility of industrial capitalist societies for the
climate crisis, let alone moves toward making resources available to aid
southern societies in adapting to the climate catastrophe, is in ways
reminiscent of Adolf Eichmannâs claim, when facing prosecution by the
Israeli state for his crimes against European Jewry, that ârepentance is
for little children.â[331] In similar terms, at the conclusion of the
Copenhagen climate negotiations, Sudanese negotiator Lumumba Stanislaus
Di-Aping observed that the dominant approaches endorsed by the global
powers at COPâapproaches radically at odds with recommendations based on
established scienceâare based on maxims like those that âfunneled six
million people in Europe into furnaces.â[332] In naming the accord for
what it isâan agreement âdevoid of any sense of responsibility or
moralityââDi-Aping points to the âantireason of totalitarian
capitalism,â which as Horkheimer and Adorno melancholically state,
âmakes the satisfaction of needs impossible and tends toward the
extermination of humanity.â[333] Clearly, such trends have been affirmed
rather than overthrown by the subsequent negotiations since Copenhagen,
from Tianjin to Bonn and CancĂșn to Durban, and can be expected to be
reproduced by policymakers at the COP18 talks to be hosted by the Qatari
dictatorship in 2012 and beyond. The most recent agreement drawn up at
Durban, for example, which envisions a postponement until 2020 of the
institution of a new global accord to regulate carbon emissions, is
nothing if not entirely authoritarian in its implications.
The radical evil represented by climate changeâprincipally, the three
hundred thousand people who die each year due to the dangerous human
interference with the worldâs atmosphere that has already taken place as
well as the various horrifying realities that global warming stands to
visit on the peoples of Earth in the futureâhas it seems become banal,
in the sense that constituted power finds little reason in the prospect
of the mass suffering and death that results from climate change to
recognize the present as an emergency necessitating radical action. This
follows, of course, from the dominant imperatives to maintain and expand
existing power structures and privileges. It represents perhaps the most
extreme expression of the dominant trend within capitalist societies
that valorizes capitalist profit over the interests of peopleâa
continuation, again, of the decidedly extreme oppression historically
visited on southern peoples by imperialist powers.[334]
Within the framework of a system such as this, it is largely assumed
that the ânormalâ operation of capitalist society need not be
interrupted by concerns about the continued existence of much of
humanityâit is expected, indeed, that humankind and even life itself
should be subordinated to the demands of capital. Such an arrangement is
undoubtedly totalitarian, for it sacrifices âhuman freedomâ to
âhistorical development.â[335] While the nameless, foreign others
sacrificed by climate change are not usually referred to as a âplague
bacillusâ or an âepidemicâ against which one must defend the interests
of the fatherland or stateâindeed, the victims of global warming are
conspicuous for their absence in the northern imaginationâthe end
result, which amounts to massive disregard for the welfare of the other
and mass death, is not terribly different.
Dominant relations can hence be characterized as governed by what
Chomsky calls a âdepraved indifferenceâ to human life.[336] Australian
scientist Gideon Polya has termed the current situation âclimate
genocide,â while Bangladeshi climatologist Atiq Rahman similarly labels
it âclimatic genocide.â[337] These phrases are accurate if the word
genocide is to be understood as murder of persons belonging to
particular classes and social groups, as originally formulated by
Raphael Lemkin, the conceptâs inventor.[338] If the definition is
extended to membership or residence in particular geographic regionsâa
collective belonging of sortsâthe term fits better, even if the question
of intent for such eventualities is left unresolved: under the
internationally accepted definition, acts of genocide occur only if
governed by conscious intent. Against this view, Chomsky is right to
suggest that those concerned with such problems focus âon predictable
outcome as evidence for intent.â[339] Not to work to undermine global
capitalism is effectively to be complicit with the genocide of southern
peoples. Jean-Paul Sartre put it well in a statement that he issued as
president of the International War Crimes Tribunal on Vietnam: âThe
genocidal intent is implicit in the facts. It is not necessarily
premeditated.â[340]
The enormity of suffering threatened by climate catastrophe returns us
to the most important remaining question. It is certainly the case that
climate policy to date has been shaped almost entirely by power
interests acting in defense of capitalism and sovereign states. It
therefore could not immediately be claimed that the policies that have
been practiced necessarily reflect the popular will on such mattersâor
to paraphrase Spanish philosopher Miguel de Unamuno, it may be that the
dominant have so far been victorious, but that this victory has failed
to convince those subjected to this domination. The undemocratic
implications of such policyâself-evidently rather clearâlead us to the
question of whether we can envision alternative policies being
instituted within the near term by agents other than those who have thus
far been considered responsible for such matters: Can the nonstate,
which is humanity, take the place of the state in these terms?[341]
Unfortunately, the U.S. public in particular is decidedly unconvinced
that climate change poses serious threats to peoplesâ well-being now and
in the foreseeable future.[342] While the attitudes of residents of
other publics on this question is undoubtedly important, those of
residents of the society most responsible for the climate predicament
are of particular significance, for they surely influence the degree
that people would be willing to undertake steps toward the radical
reconstruction of society along humane ecological groundsâa crucial
project that must be realized if humanity is to survive.
A great deal rests on the thought and activity of the subordinated
classes of societies that can be described, like Immanuel Wallerstein
does, as residing within the core of the present world system. It
remains to be seen whether industrial workers who find themselves in the
core will break radically with prevailing ideology and contribute to the
remaking of society, as foreseen by Marx, although considerations of the
observed behavior of large sections of the proletariat leave
considerable room for doubt. The lack of concern and indifference often
expressed for the fate of geographically distant othersâsuch as Iraqis,
Haitians, Mexicans, Bangladeshis, Palestinians, Pakistanis, and Sahelian
residentsâis particularly alarming, given the implications this has for
international solidarity as well as the prospect of cooperative global
relations and global climate rationality. The making invisible of others
that is propagated by the dominant forces and accepted by the
nondominant is a worrisome situationâone that must be broken radically.
While Hedges may be exaggerating when he claims U.S. society to have
âlost the capacity for empathy,â it hardly seems to be the case that
Western publics will quite literally take up arms to defend those
imperiled elsewhere, as Catalunyan anarchists and others did when faced
with the prospect of a fascist takeover of Spain in July 1936.[343] âThe
disregard for the subject makes things easy for the administration,â as
Adorno and Horkheimer write.[344]
Progress toward the realization of autonomous social relations
presupposes the existence of autonomous individuals âcapable of putting
existing laws into question,â as Castoriadis claims, or ones who
practice what Marcuse terms an âautonomous reason.â[345] Movements for
autonomy and reason are alarmingly lacking across much of the globe, but
particularly so in the North. It is at times as though the dominant U.S.
imaginary considered other regions of the world to be a vast East that
merits little investigation. It would indeed be difficult to maintain
that the Western industrial proletariat has distinguished itself in its
historical defense of humanityâhence the present predicament. The
complicity of core publics with the destruction visited on Iraq in
particular during the past quarter century has been monstrous, as has
their resignation in the face of an economic system responsible for the
death of millions of children annually through starvation and material
deprivation. A recognition of and struggle over the âmoral character of
actionâ is missing among many who have the privilege of not personally
confronting todayâs acute horrors, many of which are impelled by the
socioeconomic system to which these people have seemingly adjusted;
presumably, such individuals would act differently than they do, were
they concerned about such questions.[346]
Still, such a âtrend is not destiny,â as environmental commentator David
Orr puts it.[347] The fate of the future, though potentially
catastrophic, is not yet a fait accompli; âthe worldâs course is not
absolutely conclusive,â as Adorno claims, and âthe horizon of history is
still open,â in Marcuseâs words.[348] As Hardt and Negri observe, and as
has been dramatically demonstrated in, say, the recent wave of popular
revolts in Arab-majority societies, a âmetropolis can ignite
overnightââas can a countryside or an entire region.[349]
There may be value in recalling Horkheimerâs explosive assessment of
Kantâs original imperative as regards the relevance of Adornoâs new
categorical imperative to the present: âIn this society of isolated
individuals, the categorical imperative ... runs up against the
impossibility of its own meaningful realization. Consequently, it
necessarily implies the transformation of this society.â[350]
Similar conclusions follow from reflecting on Adornoâs posited
imperative on Auschwitz. Just as the reign of capital and the state
renders impossible the generalized treatment of humans as ends, the
forms of prevailing society threaten fundamentally to violate Adornoâs
formulated imperative. That which exists must be negated and overcome to
give way to a liberated societyâone that would neither engage in
genocide, whether climatic or otherwise, nor take actions that would
effectively destroy Earthâs ability to support life. This new society
would reverse the traditional reality that affords capital and the state
unchecked power; instead of merely being spectators subjected to the
prevailing power, participants in the construction of this new world
would seek to abolish these authoritarian forms.[351] To paraphrase
Camus, we must rebel so that we will continue to exist.[352] All rests
on the development of an exit from the monstrous present. As Neumann
declares, the system âcan only be overthrown by the conscious political
action of the oppressed masses.â[353]
This conscious political action is seen, among other
geographic-historical spaces, in the efforts of slaves in the French
colony of Saint-Domingueâthereafter Haitiâto liberate themselves from
domination. In Hardt and Negriâs view, âNeither moral arguments at home
nor calculations of profitability abroad could move European capital to
dismantle the slave regimes [in Saint-Domingue and elsewhere]. Only the
revolt and revolution of slaves themselves could provide an adequate
lever.â[354]
âThe rights of human beings must be held sacred, however great a
sacrifice this may cost the ruling power,â writes Kant.[355] The
existing system âcannot be adjusted to; like an iron collar, it can only
be broken.â[356]
It is to be hoped that once people reflect on and discuss climate
destabilization, they will respond with sympathy, turning radically
against the institutions and realities that perpetuate suffering. Such
resistance is perhaps prefigured in the often-generous reactions of
ordinary people to the misfortunes experienced by strangers following
storms, earthquakes, landslides, and mine disasters. It is nonetheless
imperative that the opposition to the causes of climate change pass from
being a matter of individual charity to one of systematic resistance.
Without this, the prospect for what Arendt calls a âworld fit for human
habitationâ is difficult to conceive.[357]
Compassionâconsideration of the other as a subject with interests worth
valuing, defending, and promotingâthen can be seen as constituting a
potential exit point from the present. As Bernstein notes, compassion is
a prefiguring of political justice and âanticipates the generality that
justice would be.â[358]
Another important consideration regarding Adornoâs new categorical
imperative in relation to the climate predicament is the question of
responsibilityâand precisely who bears it. Dyerâs assertion that ânobody
is to blameâ is absurd; such apologism has no place here.[359]
Perhaps one of the most radical takes on responsibility for the Nazi
catastrophe is the one advanced by Reich in his The Mass Psychology of
Fascism, in which he quite bluntly states that âthe working masses of
men and women, they and they alone, are responsible for everything that
takes place, the good things and the bad things.â âUnder the influence
of politicians,â Reich maintains, people in general are led to blame
particular interests for the outbreak of given wars. World War I, for
example, is generally held to be the result of the actions of âmunitions
industrialists,â while âpsychopathic generalsâ are in this sense blamed
for World War II within much of popular consciousness. Reich dismisses
such explanations, equating them to a âpassing [of] the buck.â He
instead finds the âresponsibility for warsâ to fall âsolelyâ on the
masses of people, precisely because âthey have all the necessary means
to avert war in their own hands.â His analysis is similar for the
problem of imperialism, which he finds to be both tolerated and actively
supported by the masses. Due to this dynamic, however, these same forces
can overthrow such phenomena dialectically. In sum, âat the bottom of
the failure to achieve a genuine social revolution,â asserts Reich,
âlies the failure of the masses of people.â The crucial point is to
âactivate the passive majority of the population, which always helps
political reaction to achieve victoryâ and âeliminate those inhibitions
that run counter to the development of the will to freedom.â[360]
Arendt, in contrast to Reich, claims that the cry âWe are all guiltyâ in
fact serves to âexculpate to a considerable degree those who actually
were guilty,â given, in her view, that âwhere all are guilty, nobody
is.â As she writes, there clearly were âwrongdoersâ within the context
of the experience of Nazism, but these people should not be seen as
equivalent with the German masses as a whole. In her 1963 book Eichmann
in Jerusalem, in particularâa work dedicated to examining Israelâs
prosecution of the mass-murdering Nazi bureaucratâArendt emphasizes
thoughtlessness and conformity to hierarchy as conditions that enabled
as well as facilitated the prosecution of the Nazi genocide of European
Jewry. In her words, âgreat evilâ is not necessarily brought about by
the machinations of a âwicked heart,â which she contends is a
ârelatively rare phenomenonâ; instead âmost evil is done by people who
never made up their mind to be either bad or good.â[361] The point for
Arendt is to stress the importance of obedience in any social regime. As
she remarks near the close of her volume on Eichmann, âPolitics is not
like the nursery; in politics obedience and support are the same.â[362]
The Shoah, like any other collective political effort, was a project
that arose and was sustained âonly out of the cooperative action of many
people,â together with the failures of other people consciously and
practically to put an end to such barbarous forms of cooperation.
Instead of colluding with negating ends, humans can in Arendtâs view
impede totalitarian processes by âact[ing] and interact[ing] in
freedomââby creating new and different realities that âput an end to
what was there before.â[363] Arendt thus calls for the prospect of the
âwind of thoughtâ to be manifest and mindlessness overthrown, for as she
says only this can âprevent catastrophes.â[364]
According to Adorno, the sole force capable of resisting the âprinciple
of Auschwitzâ is âautonomy,â in Kantian terms: âthe power of reflection,
of self-determination, of not cooperating.â The âvery willingness to
connive with power and to submit outwardly to what is stronger ...
should not arise again,â he writes.[365] The grounds that allow the mind
the chance to âoppose the superior strength of the course of the worldâ
are similarly found in the simple fact âthat in every situation there is
a concrete possibility of doing things differently,â that ârebellion,â
in Hollowayâs words, âis always an option, in any situation.â[366]
Naturally, the mere adoption of postures that oppose the course of the
existentâidealism, in philosophical termsâwill hardly suffice in light
of the profundity of the current predicament, for that which exists
necessarily must be displaced in actuality. As Horkheimer puts it, âThe
revolution is no goodâ insofar as âit is not victorious.â[367] In
Merleau-Pontyâs words, âvictory is defeat wherever it is not the success
of a new humanity.[368]
The bourgeoisie may blast and ruin the world they live in before exiting
the stage of history, but we carry another world here in our hearts.
âBuenaventura Durruti
From the arguments presented up to this point, it should be clear that
the demands of decency and reason require a radically different world
organization than presently exists. The alternative political project
offered here is an ecological anarcho-communism. While the case for such
a project is compelling, it does not approximate the status of a
Hegelian end state or Platonic Ideal; Marcuse is right to insist that
those fashioning themselves as critical theorists need to be critical of
their projects and selves.[369] In the words of dissident Russian
novelist Yevgeny Zamyatinâs character I-330, there can be no âfinalâ
revolution, for âthe number of revolutions is infinite.â[370]
The social transformations that will be necessary to avert total climate
catastrophe cannot emerge from conventional approaches to political
questions. This should be evident to the peoples of the world after
having suffered four years of the Obama administrationâs management of
imperialist policies in the United States, for this charlatanâbrought to
power by means of a disconcerting degree of popular delusion about
prospects for âhopeâ and âchangeââhas more than anything else simply
continued the villainy of his predecessor. His numerous other crimes
aside, that Obama could have nearly single-handedly dashed the hopes
raised by the Copenhagen climate summit in December 2009âCopenhagen
being, next to CancĂșn and Durban thereafter, one of official societyâs
final attempts at pretending to address climate changeâjust days after
defending the doctrine of imperial aggression in his acceptance speech
for the 2009 Nobel Peace Prize is a reflection of the utter insanity of
dominant politics. Such political forms must be radically displaced, and
desperately soon, if human life is to be afforded a chance.
The problem today is that of realizing revolutionâone made, as Brecht
characterizes the Paris Commune, âfor the sake of humanityâ and in
defense of life.[371] Revolution should not be taken to mean âtorrents
of blood, the storming of the Winter Palace, and so onâ; rather, it
should constitute âa radical transformation of societyâs institutions,â
as Castoriadis argues.[372] Important as such an end is in light of the
climate crisis, revolution should also be understood as a means to that
end.
As Arendt, Adorno, and many contemporary analysts rightly acknowledge, a
great deal of confusion exists over what constitutes progress toward
revolutionary ends today. In spite of such confusion, though, and in
accordance with Chomsky, humanity is entirely capable of âimagin[ing]
and mov[ing] towards the creation of a better society.â[373] With
Adorno, everyone should outwardly manifest their opposition to the world
as it exists, or as Castoriadis states, âThe immense majority of people
who live in present-day society ought to be opposed to the established
form of the institution of society.â[374] While David Harvey claims in
his Enigma of Capital that there is no âobvious way to attack the
bastions of privilege for capitalist Ă©lites or to curb their inordinate
money power and military might,â his speculations in Spaces of Hope
regarding the future possibility of a largely female-led âmassive
movement of non-violent resistanceâ that âneutralize[s] and eliminate[s]
all weapons of violence and mass destructionâ with the aim of toppling
clerical-military regimes the world over may well represent the very
means he seeks.[375]
In terms of the ends served by revolution, one of the more rational ones
would be an ecological anarcho-communist society. The type of social
relations sought by ecological anarcho-communism would in the first
place be communistâthat is, a society in which Marxâs principle of âfrom
each according to ability, to each according to needâ would govern
economic questions, with classes and the division of labor abolishedâas
well as anarchist, or bereft of authoritarian social practices. Decision
making could be carried out via a series of federated councils affording
residents direct control of their social and economic affairs. As in
Bookchinâs model of libertarian municipalism, communities rather than
orthodox Marxismâs industrial proletarians would control production and
distribution schemesâsince to limit decision-making power merely to
workers would be unnecessarily exclusive, marginalizing youths, older
people, nonindustrial workers (such as agriculturalists), and
nonworkers. Decision-making processes under such conditions would allow
for the flowering of humanityâs reason and compassion as well as fairly
represent the interests of voiceless others, such as future generations
and nonhuman animals.
Nothing in the mere existence of participatory democratic social
relations, of course, would ensure such outcomes. Nevertheless, such a
framework could provide the conditions under which reason and sanity
would be afforded the best chance of prevailing. Takis Fotopoulosâs
claim that the development of a culture critical of patriarchal
relations and hierarchy in general would likely âcreate a new ethos of
non-dominationâ extending to the human and nonhuman world is both
compelling and encouraging in this regard.[376]
An ecological anarcho-communist politics would be directed toward
realizing Adornoâs demand that âno one shall starve any longerââthat no
one shall be denied the material conditions necessary for a dignified
life. In addition, this anarcho-communism should seek to ensure social
conditions under which âno one [will] fear to be differentâ and all will
be able to engage in the âfree development of each as such.â[377]
Radical exclusion would be overthrown, with human multiplicity and
plurality seen as traits to be cherished and celebrated rather than
suppressed. Patriarchy would be largely eradicated under these
conditions, if not fully abolished, as would racism, ageism, homophobia,
ableism, and all other conditions of unfreedom.
Anarcho-communist social relations should strive to maximize the space
available for the practice of what Marx terms free conscious activity,
or autonomyâa practice that can only be had in the realm of freedom,
away from alienated labor. The generalized exercise of self-defined
conscious inquiry would follow from the dramatic reduction of work,
together with the emancipation of social relations from domination.
Solidarity would serve as the basis for interrelating. Friendliness and
respect would be shown to individuals. Peopleâs capacities for autonomy
and creativity along with their vulnerabilities would be acknowledged.
Social life would recognize the place for what Arthur Schopenhauer calls
âthe most necessary thing in lifeâthe tolerance, patience, regard, and
love of neighbor, of which everyone stands in need, and which,
therefore, every [human] owes to [oneâs] fellow.â[378] Individuals
participating in the construction of anarcho-communism hopefully would
institute the âinnate repugnanceâ that Jean-Jacques Rousseau postulates
humans experience in âseeing [their] fellow men [sic] suffer.â[379]
Chomskyâs call to âdeepen the emerging global bonds of sympathy and
solidarityâ would be similarly welcomed; such bonds, like Rousseauâs
pity, might help facilitate the chance for total liberation.[380]
Given that such means and ends are arguably far removed from much of
what currently prevails, how might progress be made toward revolution?
Barring the rapid development of a revolutionary movement, a series of
thoroughgoing transitional social reforms may be needed. Three primary
revolutionary reforms involve a guaranteed minimum income for all, full
universal access to health care, and the decommodification of basic
goods, such as food and water. Guaranteed income levels would allow
working people to break from their dependence on earning a wage, and
hence have greater opportunities to associate autonomously and help
build social alternatives, as recognized by left-wing French philosopher
André Gorz, while the second two demands would have immediate and
significant impacts on health and happiness the world over.
Such changes would demand that a massive redistribution of resources
from the transnational capitalist class in large part be directed at
reconstructing societies devastated by disasters as well as neoliberal
capitalism and militarization processes. Here one thinks of Iraq,
Pakistan, Haiti, and the Democratic Republic of Congo, among other
societies. One potentially transitional means toward the specific end of
redistribution would be the institution of high taxes on luxury
consumption, the expropriation of capitalist wealth, and redirecting the
funds that presently underpin global military spending, or simply the
socialization of property and the means of production.[381] Global
nuclear disarmamentâthe making of the world into a nuclear weapons and
nuclear energy-free zoneâcould be similarly helpful.
A future anarcho-communist society would abolish the presently
widespread practice of humans consumption of nonhuman animals; the
enslavement of these animals for human purposes should be abandoned as a
social practice as much as possible. Beyond the rather inescapable
cruelty and suffering implied by the raising of animals for slaughter,
the mass consumption of animals must be halted or at least radically
reduced in the near term on environmental grounds. Studies estimate that
the industrial processes facilitating meat consumption account for
between 18 and 51 percent of the total greenhouse gas emissions produced
by humanity.[382] Due to the dramatic wastefulness in the production of
animal meats in terms of both the water and grain usedâsurely the grain
fields currently dedicated to the feeding of cattle and other
domesticated animals, which in the United States reaches three-quarters
of the total, could more sensibly be used to feed the billions of humans
who go without foodâit becomes clear that humanity should exercise
conscious reason together with compassion and abolish meat consumption
to the greatest extent possible. Adopting vegetarian or vegan diets can
in part prefigure a liberated future, as could a broader overhaul of the
industrial capitalist food system, which sees southern societies
exporting food for sale to northern consumers while large swathes of the
residents of such societies suffer from food scarcity as their lands are
bought up by transnational firms that seek to cultivate agrofuels crops
there.
These measures are a few examples of action situated within current
realities that would move toward ending the domination of natureâa
demand as thoroughgoing as any other raised by radical, reconstructive
political projects in human history. Like the abolition of patriarchy
sought by feminists, the ecological society or ecological civilization
presupposed here militates radically against the forces that have
controlled much of human history. Without a total revolution, it is to
be expected that the domination of nature would continue in an
otherwise-liberated set of social relations. An anarchist society, for
instance, would likely still engage in deforestation until substitutes
for wood were made available. For solar energy to exist, moreover, there
must also be mining, fossil fuels, and toxic waste, at least as has been
practiced up to this point. Though the domination of nature can be
greatly minimized through the exercise of reason along with the
overturning of dominant social relations, it could live on for some time
regardless of the abolition of capital and the state.
These considerations aside, much is to be gained by insisting on the
critique of the domination of nature. There would be real improvements
for nonhuman nature following the practices that flow from this
critique. This struggle is encapsulated well in the slogan âanimal
liberation/human liberationâ advanced by animal rights proponents. As it
suggests, the project of human liberation should not exclude that of
animal liberation; humans should not forget that they are animals, and
that other animals have interests to be respected. As Marcuse declares,
âNature, too, awaits the revolution!â[383]
The call for an end to the domination of nature need not presuppose a
lurking primitivism, whether anarcho or otherwise. That the
anarcho-communism advanced here is called ecological is a reference to
the sociotechnological basis for the social relations to which such a
project could give birth. It would be a type of
civilizationâânon-repressive,â in Marcuseâs formulationârun on
renewable, âsoftâ forms of energy, such as direct solar, wind,
geothermal, wave, and others, that neither produce carbon dioxide, as
with fossil fuels, nor threaten current and future generations with
potentially terminal exposure to radioactivity, as with nuclear
energy.[384] The potential for participatory, nonhierarchical societies
powered along such lines that, for example, practice socialized medicine
demonstrates the thoughtlessness of primitivist critics who denounce
âcivilizationâ and âtechnology,â instead of critiquing domination and
irrationality. Social ecologist Brian Tokar, for one, offers a
compelling vision of âdecentralized, solar-powered communities empowered
to decide both their energy future and their political future.â[385]
In environmental terms, the successful institution of an ecological
anarcho-communism would seem to be imperative. As Hansen argues, coal
emissions must be ended by 2030 if catastrophe is to be averted, with
2020 being the absolute deadline for northern societies to stop using
coal altogether.[386] Li calculates that global economic growthâthat is,
the totality of production of capitalist valueâwould have to be
suppressed indefinitely in the year 2015 to avoid a 2°C (3.6°F) increase
in average global temperatures.[387] Such calculations accord with
German climatologist Hans Joachim Schellnhuberâs call for the present
United States per capita release of twenty tons of carbon to be reduced
to zero tons within a decade, and with Ted Trainerâs advocacy of a 95
percent reduction in consumption rates in the industrialized North.[388]
In practical terms, Hansen advises that hydrocarbons be used consciously
in the near term for the construction of an alternative
energy-production system. Hansenâs suggestion is in accordance with
academics Peter Schwartzman and David Schwartzmanâs March 2011 findings,
which suggest that the employment of a mere 1 to 5 percent of the global
total of petroleum consumed annually toward the construction of a wind-
and solar-based alternative renewable energy capacity could entirely
replace existing hydrocarbon-based capacity within a matter of a couple
decades, or even more rapidly with the redirection of greater
proportions of existing capacity toward this end as well as the
institution of significant energy conservation measures, particularly in
overdeveloped northern societies.[389] Traditional U.S. environmentalist
Lester Brownâs plan to reduce carbon emissions by 80 percent by 2020
bases itself principally on wind energy production as well as rooftop
photovoltaic energy, solar plants, geothermal stations, and
hydroelectric dams to a lesser degree.[390] His plan excludes nuclear
energy altogether. Writing in the mainstream magazine Scientific
American in 2009, Mark Jacobson and Mark Delucchi present similar
recommendations, as did the IPCC in a special 2011 report.[391] It is in
these senses that Hansenâs highly questionable calls for the mass
employment of third- and fourth-generation nuclear reactors to serve as
base load energy to replace coal are seen as irrelevant, their
irrationality having been readily confirmed once again by the 2011
disaster at the Fukushima plant, which has according to the Japanese
government emitted a full one-fifth of the total radioactive material
released during the 1986 nuclear disaster at Chernobyl.[392] Other
estimates claim that the Fukushima plant has released even more
radioactivity into the environment than Chernobyl did.[393]
Against the absurdities of nuclear energy and hydrocarbon combustion,
the technological basis for averting climate catastrophe is readily at
hand, and it is one that should be taken up by an ecological
anarcho-communist project that would work toward the âsolarizationâ of
global societyâthat is, the replacement of energy resources originating
in geologic solar power, or fossil fuels, with energy presently provided
by the sun, whether directly or indirectly, in mimicry of the light
reactions performed in photosynthesis. This movement toward solarization
would be situated within the context of a more general advocacy of
transition toward a steady state characterized by a closed
production-consumption cycle that centrally features recycling and
waste-free technologies, in accordance with David Schwartzmanâs vision
of âsolar communism.â[394] A solarized global society, helped along by
the institution of anarcho-communism, would then be able to observe the
heretofore-violated precautionary principle, which advises against
action that would harm future generations.
Assuming humanityâs billions live in materially simple fashion rather
than capitalistically, concentrated solar thermal plants erected in the
worldâs deserts could readily provide for a large proportion of energy
needs, as Trainer notes.[395] Alternatively, the potential in launching
photovoltaic-array-laden satellites into outer space that would then
transmit collected energy to Earth could be exploredâa possibility
raised in Elizabeth Kolbertâs writings on climate change as well as
Robinsonâs novels.[396] Space-based solar power is an intriguing option
due to considerations of efficiency, given that solar collectors placed
above the atmosphere receive many times the solar energy available to
terrestrial solar plants, and the launching of âsolar satellitesâ would
avoid the mass erection of solar plants in Earthâs deserts and thus
avert the further degradation of the worldâs ecosystems. Whatever the
potential rationality of this scheme, this project could however
justifiably be met with accusations of gigantism and hence rejected.
Perhaps a combination of terrestrial concentrated and photovoltaic
solar, wind, geothermal, and maybe wave energy sources could instead be
chosen. The newly developing self-legislating global subject will be
tasked with pondering these and other alternatives.
This new constituent power should also be advised that the prospect of
attaining ecologically sound ends within the near term could fruitfully
be linked to the project of a postscarcity anarchism, as identified by
Bookchin in the late 1960s. In postulating the possibility of a
postscarcity anarchism, Bookchin claimsâwith Horkheimer, Adorno, and
Marcuse, following Marxâthat the material basis developed by the
capitalist mode of production by the mid-twentieth century could, if
consciously reappropriated to ends radically different than those
demanded by capital, satisfy the needs of all people and drastically
reduce the amount of time normally dedicated to labor under
capitalism.[397] According to Bookchin, human society has for some time
now been faced with the revolutionary prospect of transcending material
scarcity and thus overcoming what he sees as the rationale for
patriarchy, private property, class society, the state, and even
hierarchy itself.[398]
Radically reorienting the productive forces and existing technologies
has increased in importance since Bookchin and the Frankfurt School
theorists advocated it, as the absurdities toward which production is
directed live on without redress. In a very real sense, the choice
humanity faces is between continuing to dedicate untold billionsâeven
trillionsâto capitalismâs and militarismâs most absurd and life-negating
projects, or carrying out a revolutionary socialization of global
society that eradicates hunger, disease, and material poverty, while
also instituting a radically different energy basis for social life that
does not threaten humanity with destruction. The choice is between
âbarbarism or freedom,â observes Horkheimer, similar to the
juxtaposition between socialism and barbarism that Luxemburg pointed to
amid the First World War. It should be uncontroversial to state that the
technological assemblage that can launch and maintain the Hubble
telescope, or invent, produce, and maintain cluster bombs, stealth jet
fighters, nuclear weapons, and predator drones, can also be directed at
the institution of reason.
An ecological anarcho-communist political project, then, is faced with
reorganizing the worldâthe very reconstruction of society. Though
ecological anarcho-communism would demand the abolition of a great deal
of prevailing practices and the transformation of dominant modes of
being, it probably would not altogether abandon some of the less
irrational technologies developed by capitalism. Secure interregional
travel, for one, likely would not be jettisoned, though it should become
more broadly accessible to the peoples of the world; communization of
resources can promote this end. In place of jet airplanesâwhich in terms
of contributions to climate change, have proven to be among the most
disastrous inventions to dateâa more rational society could perhaps
employ air transport systems using blimps, zeppelins, and other
dirigibles powered by solar energy.[399]
Another crucial infrastructural change would be a general shift toward
electrically powered transportation systemsâsuch as streetcars,
railways, and electric busesâconsidering that the energy needed for
their operation could be provided by solar or other renewable sources.
Generalized short-distance transportation by bicycle could be advanced
by the conscious redesign of cities. In theory, electric batteries could
power cars and trucks, for if power were provided by renewable sources,
the carbon-emissions problem associated with motorized transport could
theoretically be solved easily. Such a resolution of course would not by
itself do away with the considerable dangers posed by private
automobiles to human life, as attested to by the multitudes killed
annually in traffic accidents. Serious reflection on this problem may
indeed demand the outright abolition of the car.
As regards water-based transportation, a prototype solar-powered vessel
analogous to solar zeppelins and planes is presently under
development.[400] Beyond this, water transport in a potentially
liberated future could see a partial return to the employment of wind
and muscle powerâdecolonial caravels, for exampleâin accordance with a
reappropriation of the less destructive practices and sensibilities
instituted by many humans as both individuals and groups before the
historical onset of industrial capitalismâand since then. A compelling
image in this sense is Japanese director Akira Kurosawaâs depiction in
his Dreams of life in a riverine village marked by social cooperation
and vast diversity that is run simply on water mills.
An important means of helping along the social transformation delineated
above would be through the dedicated efforts of an anarcho-communist
international. Such an internationalâwhich would obviously be open to
all, unlike the Marxist First International, which was largely made up
of male members of the proletariatâcould take as a model similar
institutions, such as those established by European anarchists during
the first half of the twentieth centuryâin particular, the Iberian
Anarchist Federation (FAI) or National Confederation of Labor of Spain
and Catalonia (CNT)âKoreans residing in Manchuria via the Korean
Anarchist Communist Federation in the late 1920s, and Uruguayans
struggling against the capitalist military dictatorship in the latter
half of the past century through the Uruguayan Anarchist
Federation.[401] This critical political force could become what Chomsky
calls the âfirst authentic International,â realizing an âera of true
globalizationâ that serves peopleâs interests rather than those of
âinvestors and other concentrations of power.â[402] It could take the
form of Hardt and Negriâs multitude, consisting of an association of the
various multiplicities of subordinated humans united against capital and
domination, or in Negriâs romantic image, âall of being and nature, the
animals, sister moon, brother sun, the birds of the field, the poor and
exploited humans, together against the will of power and
corruption.â[403]
The beginnings of such a movement can be seen, for example, in
contemporary Palestine solidarity effortsâwhether expressed through
public protests, direct participation with the International Solidarity
Movement brigades and other organizations in Palestine, or support for
boycott, divestment, and sanctions campaigns against the Israeli state.
It also can be found in the alter-globalization movement along with
struggles against sweatshop regimes, white supremacy, sexism, police
brutality, whale hunting, the prison-industrial complex, the
criminalization of migration, and imperial wars. It can be discovered
furthermore in campaigns in support of organic and fair trade
production, among many other manifestations of ordinary peopleâs
anarchistic impulses, which are reflected âas soon as one identifies,
challenges and overcomes illegitimate power,â as Chomsky notes.[404]
Being anarchist, this international would have little to do with the
practices of the official Internationals observed to date. The fate of
the First International, which might have proven politically
consequential had the rift between Marxists and anarchists not been so
disastrous, arguably has much to do with Engelsâs redirection of its
course following Marxâs death. That development, in turn, was itself
highly influential for the Second International, which was largely
overtaken by reformist interpretations of Marx, notwithstanding the
efforts of revolutionaries like Luxemburg and Karl Liebknecht, along
with other members of the Spartakusbund. The Second International
logically collapsed when its various national parliamentary
representatives betrayed internationalism and voted in favor of the
prosecution of the First World War, a social catastrophe that gave rise
to fascism, both of the brown and red varieties. The repetition of all
such experiences is naturally to be avoided, as are the practices of the
International overseen by Vladimir Lenin and then Joseph Stalin as well
as in the Trotskyist Fourth International. Doubtless, Leninism has
little place as a political project both today and in the future. It
cannot be said that the Bolsheviksâ historical institution of the Cheka
secret police, imposition of famine-inducing grain requisition regimes,
repression of anarchists, destruction of the popular soviet-based
government, and suppression of the Kronstadt Commune and the libertarian
Makhnovshchina were defensible practices that should be
resurrected.[405]
This international would oppose âthe international of deathâ and eternal
war of neoliberal capitalism, as the EZLN formulates it.[406] It would
serve as the inverse to the transnational alliances made among
tyrannical orders, opposing the relationship seen in the U.S. support
and financing of the âthird world fascismâ explored by Chomsky and
Herman, as evidenced in, say, Ngo Dinh Diemâs Vietnam, Augusto Pinochet
in Chile, Mobutu Sese Seko in Zaire, Pakistanâs Muhammad Zia ul-Haq, or
the Duvalier family in Haiti. The new internationalâs practices would be
far removed from the collaboration observed between Pakistani and
Bahraini regimes to suppress protests in the latter country, and that
practiced between the Turkish and Iranian states against Kurdish rebels;
it would likely have little to do with the âmutual aidâ generally
expressed among highly authoritarian rulers taken in some circles to
serve anti-imperialist endsâRobert Mugabe, Muâammar al-Gadhafi, Mahmoud
Ahmadinejad, and the Chinese Communist Party, to name just a few
examples. Contra Leon Trotsky, this international would never conclude
that humanity is only âright with and by the [Communist] Party,â as
followed from his fanatic (and fantastic) belief that âhistory has
provided no other way of being in the rightââan authoritarian
self-assuredness that Arendt rightly asserts to have contributed to the
totalitarian development of Bolshevik rule.[407] Instituting Royâs
suggestion for a âglobalization of dissent,â this international would
refuse the installation of rulers and sovereignty, demanding that
presently constituted power fall and thereafter no person again unjustly
exercise power over another.[408]
In Derridaâs words, this new international could resemble
a link of affinity, suffering, and hope, a still discreet, almost secret
link, as it was around 1848, but more and more visible.... It is an
untimely link, without status, without title, and without name, barely
public even if it is not clandestine, without contract, âout of joint,â
without coordination, without party, without country, without national
community (International before, across, and beyond any national
determination), without co-citizenship, without common belonging to a
class.[409]
Such an institution probably could not function effectively without some
sort of coordination, and this association surely should not be
dominated by persons hailing from privileged backgrounds, as has been
the case in many past oppositional movements, but it should certainly
not be subordinated to a central party or particular national
leadership, as is revealed through the troubling history of
authoritarian socialism. Yet Derridaâs vision here is helpful in many
ways, particularly in terms of basing a movement on âaffinity,
suffering, and hopeââa âlinkâ that is becoming âmore visible.â In place
of nationalist identities propagated by the statist world system, the
international could base its association on a universal solidarity among
humans. Beyond a concern for human freedom, this international likely
also should extend its solidarity to nonhuman life. In bringing together
currents opposing domination exerted among humans as well as humanityâs
domination of nature, it could take after Schellâs vision of a general
âdefensive allianceâ working to protect life from the threats to
survival impelled by capitalist barbarism. It could continue the work of
the âmass rising on behalf of reasonâ that György LukĂĄcs sees in the
historical social movements opposed to nuclear weapons, and especially
in the five hundred million signatures to the 1950 Stockholm Appeal for
unconditional nuclear disarmamentâthe very âprotection of reason as
taking the form of a mass movement,â which LukĂĄcs views as taking on a
âpreventive, averting character.â[410] The 2011 popular uprisings, both
preventive and reactive at once, aimed at reason and sanity must be
carried forward. Inspiration comes from the millions of Egyptians who
mobilized in Cairoâs Tahrir Square and elsewhere in the country to
overthrow the Mubarak regime in early 2011, as from the hundreds of
thousands of Spaniards who assembled publicly to denounce the prevailing
systemâincluding, for instance, playing the Ode to Joy at the close of
Ludwig van Beethovenâs Ninth Symphony during one such gatheringâand the
many people who mobilized in a coordinated action worldwide on October
15, 2011, to express their support for the presently developing global
antisystemic political movement.
While this oppositional mass movement may not need to turn to fiction to
explore resistance efforts, the new international could consider the
shadowy Human Project from Alfonso CuarĂłnâs Children of Men, itself
nowhere to be found in the eponymous novel by P. D. James on which the
film bases itself: a group of dissident scientists purportedly based out
of the Azores Islands who metaphorically labor to find a cure to the
universal infertility gripping the future dystopian world depicted in
the film. As in this speculative example, territorial autonomy should be
an important goal for an actual movement to attainâthat is, independence
from the global capitalist market and state control as well as from
subjection to militarism. Such an end could greatly help efforts to
develop alternative rebel technologies, remake society, and launch
actions against constituted power along with demonstrating the value of
such an alternative. Cubaâs defiance of the United States and its
promotion of a more humane sort of international relationsâabove all in
its international brigades of medical workers, but also in its material
assistance for movements fighting the South African apartheid regimeâhas
relevance in this sense, however problematic Castroâs specific support
for Haile Mengistu Mariamâs Leninist regime in Ethiopia, not to mention
the dictatorial nature of his own rule, as manifested, say, in Cubaâs
practice of imprisoning political dissidents as well as its historical
persecution of nonheterosexuals.
The historical fact of Haitiâs independence is also germane to the task
of imagining this new international, given that this event was the first
rebellion by slaves to successfully overthrow the forces enslaving them,
however much a number of European powers (including NapolĂ©onâs France)
attempted to reverse these gains by means of invasions seeking to
reinstate the institution. That the uprising gave rise, as C.L.R. James
reviews, to humanist notions of launching military campaigns against the
slave-processing infrastructure then found in West Africa carries
meaning for the present, constituting as it does a manifestation of the
normally repressed revolutionary dreams of the subordinated.[411] It is
also worth noting the particularly radical decolonization of South Yemen
(later the Peopleâs Democratic Republic of Yemen), which brought a
nominally Marxist regime to power that in contradistinction to many
other putatively âsocialistâ polities in the Middle East and beyond,
engaged in significant redistribution schemes and public health
improvements domestically even as it actively aided groups working to
overthrow reactionary bourgeois Arab governments in the Gulf
regionâdespite its problematic professed democratic centralism.[412]
In recent years, Wikileaks has done significant work to expose the
madness and brutality of dominant power, and thus is justifiably a
beacon for the disenfranchised everywhere. Its release of documents on
the U.S. ambassador to Tunisia arguably contributed to the outbreak of
popular revolt in that country following Mohammed Bouaziziâs
self-immolation in December 2010, and its publication of a cable
detailing a U.S. military massacre of Iraqi civilians was instrumental
in the Iraqi stateâs refusal to allow occupying U.S. troops immunity
from prosecutionâa development that catalyzed the general withdrawal of
troops from that country.[413] Through its checks on constituted power,
this regulative anarchic body has contributed immensely to the struggle
against hegemony, generally informing global publics of the myriad
crimes of global capitalism, from the details regarding U.S. military
death squads to intimidation and coercion as practiced by stronger
states against less powerful ones in climate negotiations and the United
Statesâ opposition to international treaties banning the use of cluster
munitions.[414] It is unfortunate, though unsurprising, that the
authorities have hampered Wikileaksâ work, but it would seem that this
fate follows from the organizationâs dependence on its founder and
editor Julian Assange, who for all his importance is readily suppressed
by the state and capitalâas his alleged assistant, Private First Class
Bradley Manning, infamously has been. Perhaps more promising in this
sense is the more decentralized model exercised by anarchic hacking
groups such as Anonymous and Anti-Sec, which, like Wikileaks,
collaborate to disrupt the functioning of existing power.
With regard specifically to climate catastrophe, the efforts of this new
international probably should intertwine with those promoted by such
international radical ecological associations as Climate Justice Action,
Rising Tide, the Mobilization for Climate JusticeâWest, and Climate
S.O.S. Some of the key tasks of this international would overlap with
Climate Justice Actionâs primary demands, which include working to
prevent the future exploitation of fossil fuels, massively reducing
northern consumption patterns, recognizing the Global Northâs ecological
debt, and concurrently making reparations available to southern
societies for the crimes of colonialism, neoliberal capitalism, and
climate destabilization. Against the seemingly âboundless imperialismâ
driven by mindless capitalist modes of being, participants in the
international could advance Warner Sachsâs model for a âpolitics of
sufficiencyâ by promoting the generalized adoption of simpler, less
materially intensive lifestyles among northern residents.[415] Beyond
this, and more concretely, it could work toward the appropriation of a
federated series of territorial commons in which social and physical
autonomy is to be developed, renewable energy infrastructures
constructed, and mass reforestation and afforestation campaigns
advanced, with this last perhaps following Wangari Maathaiâs model. In
its rejection of dominant policy, the new international could reflect
and amplify the radicality of the movements contesting dams that have
organized politically from South Asia to Latin America.
In philosophical terms at least, this new association should avoid the
racist assumptions that have informed a great deal of Western
environmentalism to date. This includes, especially, the Malthusianism
that faults southern high population growth rates rather than capitalism
for human suffering and environmental destruction, as well as the
continued advocacy of nuclear energy, which unavoidably disregards the
oppressed peoples who disproportionately suffer the effects of nuclear
waste, whether Native Americans or Somalis, to say nothing of those
directly exposed to radioactivity emitted by malfunctioning reactors.
Exercising reason and compassion, the builders of this international
would promote the dissemination of antisystemic perspectives on
prevailing society, and generally work to implement the vision of a
global society freed from the reproduction of capitalist value and
social domination.
The new international also would strive to (re)activate the
potenzaâpotentialâof the constituent power represented by the
subordinated human multitudes of the world, working for the counterpower
or dual-power model of humanity against the concentrated power of
capital and the state (potere). This social antagonist model, advocated
by a number of anarchist thinkers, has been observed historically in
forms of directly democratic government as temporarily and partially
realized, for instance, in the events of 1871, 1905, 1936, 1956, and
1968; as prefigured in the U.S.-based Movement for a New Society during
the last quarter of the twentieth century; and arguably as practiced in
the Russian agrarian mir system and perhaps the village councils of
traditional India.[416]
Continuing the examples set in recent memory by the popular rebellions
that have erupted across the world, the internationalâs constituent
parts would work to simultaneously construct popular participation in
sociopolitical matters and seek to interfere with the institutions and
processes that imperil life. The former end is seen in the task of
devolving power to the global demos, as Arendt, Chomsky, and Bookchin
advocate, and in the project of constructing and appropriating the
commons as well as through broadly communal and sympathetic ways of
interrelating. The work of disrupting prevailing power relations can be
envisioned in direct action against spaces that are especially
destructive in environmental terms, the efforts of international brigade
groupsâmedical and otherwiseâthat seek to provide solidarity with and
care for those abandoned as well as destroyed by capitalism, and a
generalized advocacy of and political organizing toward the realization
of a general strike along with popular social revolution to overthrow
capitalism and the state.
The direct action that members of the international could both promote
and engage in would continue the work of Plane Stupid, the Kingsnorth
Six, and other UK-based radical environmental groupings that have
consciously intervened against air travel and coal-based energy
production in recent years as well as the sustained mass protests seen
in 2011 in Indiaâs West Bengal, Maharashtra, and Tamil Nadu states
against the planned construction of nuclear plants.[417] To turn to
fiction again, the international could look toward the example of the
Central American rebels found in John Brunnerâs The Sheep Look Up who
actively disable the operations of polluting factories. It could gain
insight from the factual shuttering of the Dalian petrochemical complex
in northeastern China, propelled as it was by popular mobilizations on
the part of hundreds of thousands opposed to its continued operation,
and the concessions made by the German state in its recent pledge to
close all nuclear plants within a decade following mass street protests
in that country in the wake of the Fukushima disaster.[418]
Toward the end of presenting a serious challenge to prevailing power
relations, this new international critically should seek to avoid the
depressingly unproductive squabbling that has long plagued many
interactions among libertarian socialist theorists and actors.
Bookchinâs rather baseless invective directed at the Frankfurt School
theorists comes to mind hereâhe bizarrely claims these thinkers âin no
senseâ to be âresolutely critical of hierarchy and dominationââas does
his irrational denunciations of Takis Fotopoulos and the inclusive
democracy project for their âsubjectivism.â[419] Hardly innocent
themselves, proponents of the inclusive democracy project have in fact
perpetuated such infighting, as is seen in the hostility at times
evinced by these to the thought of Castoriadis and Chomskyâdirected
toward the latter for the purported statism seen in his open support for
Medicare, Medicaid, and other basic social welfare programs provided by
the U.S. government. This problem, indeed, seems to extend from
anarchist theorists to anarchist actors. One observer of the present
Greek anarchist movement notes that the various differences among
distinctly self-identified Greek libertarians has to an extent
discouraged common revolutionary efforts.[420]
Naturally, dissent is important, and it is arguably more crucial now
than at any other point in human history: human survival is intimately
linked with the prospect of rebellion, as Camus notes. This should not
mean, though, that thinkers and other agents associated with radical
political projects should themselves reproduce much of the fragmentation
that permeates mainstream institutions by either refusing respectfully
to consider the work of theorists and action of activists with whom they
justifiably share a great deal of concern or dismissing them altogether
for not sharing their precise views on every given question. This is not
to say that social anarchists should suspend their opposition to
Leninist politics or desist from critiquing primitivist and
individualist currents that refuse to engage with collective efforts in
search of liberation.[421]
Revolutionary transformation has a tradition that must continue.
âMax Horkheimer, âThe End of Reasonâ
The miracle that save the world ... from its normal, ânaturalâ ruin is
ultimately the fact of natality.
âHannah Arendt, The Human Condition
In general terms, reflection on human history and global society
necessarily reveals a seemingly limitless diversity of sociopolitical
practices among different groups and individuals across both space and
time. This understanding, one of the central points advanced by Karl
Polanyi in his The Great Transformation, is a significant one, echoed by
Arendtâs emphasis on human plurality, âembodiedâ as it is âin the
absolute difference of all [humans] from one another.â[422]
Contemplation of such plurality, as of art or natural beauty, can serve
as a source of inspiration for revolutionary action in the world,
especially when one considers that this pluralityâlike art, beauty, or
the world entireâis imperiled as it is by the specter of the
perpetuation of capitalism and domination.
Briefly, then, this final section takes account of a few noteworthy
antisystemic projects and developments, both contemporary and
historical. This examination is necessarily partial and limited.
Following the collapse of the Soviet Union along with the attendant
marginalization of leftist thought and action in official circles, the
Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacional (EZLN) represented one of the
most inspiring political developments at the time. Based in the highly
impoverished state of Chiapas, Mexico, the EZLN began as a guerrilla
group among excluded, largely landless indigenous peoples residing in
the jungles of the eastern part of the state. Its insurrection on
January 1, 1994âthe outcome of the democratic exercise of the voice of
EZLN base communities, and a reflection of recognition among the
guerrillas that resorting to conventional political methods could offer
them no solutionâwas met with fierce repression by the Mexican
authorities, although this was tempered by rapid protest mobilizations
undertaken through much of Mexico and internationally. Since it emerged
on the world stage in 1994, the movement has been targeted by the
Mexican military, state-supported paramilitary groups, and
developmentalist counterinsurgency strategies, as taken up in much of
Chiapas by Mexicoâs various governments.
Despite these challenges, the neo-Zapatista movementââneoâ because it
extends the tradition of the largely indigenous Ejército Libertador del
Sur led by Emiliano Zapata during the Mexican Revolutionâhas doubtlessly
distinguished itself in its defense of humanity. This is evident in its
efforts since 1994 and before to create spaces promoting autonomy and
dignity, by means of the establishment of educational systems and health
clinics, the stress on womenâs liberation campaigns under traditional
indigenous patriarchal settings, physical resistance to global
capitalism in affirmation of humanity and its will to live, advocacy of
a communal effort by all those âfrom below and to the Leftâ to remake
Mexican and global society outside electoral politics (La Otra Campaña,
or the Other Campaign), thoughtful intervention and critique regarding
political matters in Mexico, and opposition to Israelâs murderous
assaults on Gazans, among many other advances. The international
meetings held in neo-Zapatista communities in the 1990s are considered
legendary, given such titles as the Intercontinental Meeting for
Humanity and against Neo-Liberalism, considering the righteous
declarations and communiqués that resulted from them. That few such
meetings have been held in recent years is unfortunate, itself perhaps
an expression of the movementâs decline, as arguably was reflected in
the EZLNâs two-year period of silence from 2009 to 2011, as well as the
reported abandonment of the movement by many former members faced with
impoverishment, on the one hand, and statist repression, on the other.
If it is true that the neo-Zapatista movement is in decline, this would
amount to a significant loss for humanity, for the Zapatista emphasis on
direct confrontation with power, opposition to inhumanity, participatory
democracy, social inclusion, and international solidarity certainly all
remain highly relevant for the present and likely future. Dissident
writer Ramor Ryan, echoing his comrade Niels Barmeyerâs criticism of the
movement, is correct to note that many Zapatista adherents are
disappointingly âauthoritarian, patriarchal, and conservativeâ in the
flesh.[423] Whatever the fate of the EZLN and its supporters, its
politics clearly have roused the revolutionary passions of countless
persons, from autonomous youths and proletarians in Mexico, to
privileged Europeans who accompany the movement as international
observers. As with other revolutionary insurgencies, the neo-Zapatista
demand for dignity will not soon be forgotten. Perhaps it can be
synthesized to a more generalized movement, in accordance with the
EZLNâs call to âbe a Zapatista wherever you are.â
On Mexicoâs national stage, there have been mass protests in opposition
to the violence of CalderĂłnâs drug war, including an April 2011
mobilization in Mexico City titled âEstamos hasta la madre!â (âWe are
fucking fed up!â). The Movement for Peace with Justice and Dignity, born
within this moment of upheaval, has rather significantly given a voice
to the countless thousands whose lives have been shattered by the
conflict, via its series of caravans to different regions of the country
affected by the violence. The movementâs proposal for a âcitizenâs pactâ
among subordinated Mexicans is an encouraging development,
notwithstanding the reformist vision of the movementâs official
leadership and the highly questionable decision to open negotiations
with CalderĂłn in an effort to raise his awareness of the human
implications of his war strategy. This sort of tactic has shown itself
to be absurd on countless occasions, whether during the petitioning by
Saint Petersburgâs urban poor of Czar Nicholas II in January 1905 or in
McKibbenâs 2010 âSolar Road Tripâ to present Carter-era solar panels to
the Obama White House.
The Kurdish Workersâ Party (PKK), which arose in the last quarter of the
twentieth century among the Kurds of the Near Eastâthe largest grouping
of stateless people in the worldâembodies a quite different approach
from the Gandhian attempts to humanize oppressive power structures. This
Leninist organization, founded by Abdullah Ocalan, emerged in response
to the plight of dispossessed Kurds and the widespread recognition that
even nominally leftist currents in Turkeyâthe state of residence for the
majority of the Kurdsâwould not prioritize a just solution to their
exclusionâa position confirmed by the worldwide silence about the
genocidal al-Anfal campaign prosecuted by Saddam Hussein against Kurdish
populations at the end of his war with Iran in 1988. Abandoned, the PKK
initiated armed struggle against the Turkish state and, in turn, met
with fierce repression by the Turkish government, which in the 1990s
destroyed countless villages and forcibly displaced some million Kurds
as part of its counterinsurgency strategy.[424] The struggle continues,
thirteen years after Ocalanâs capture and imprisonment, with little
progress toward the independent state sought by the PKK. Turkey, which
presents itself as a progressive alternative to collaborationist Arab
regimes as regards Israel and the Palestinians, and donates generously
to victims of famine in Somalia, still bombards Kurdish positions
indiscriminately to this day.
Despite the Kurdish peopleâs suffering, an uncritical celebration of the
PKK would be out of order, given its quasi-Stalinist nature, forced
conscription, and exclusion and even murder of those who disapprove of
its methods. Yet it is undeniable, even in light of the unpalatable
aspects of its praxis, that the PKKâs genesis has to a degree aided in
the struggle against patriarchy in Kurdish society, considering the
honored participation of women in PKK ranks, in addition to the partyâs
importance as a source of dignity and self-respect for oppressed
Kurds.[425] As with the Zapatistas of Mexico and the Naxalites of India,
it is in the strength of the PKKâs âNo sayingâ to domination and
abandonment that its significance is apparent.[426] The PKKâs example
hopefully will be developed in the future into a more legitimate model
for the Kurds themselves, not to mention other peoples. Perhaps Ocalanâs
recently expressed interest in Bookchinâs work is indicative of a new
direction for the Kurdish struggle.
In contrast to all Leninist models, the civil unrest in 2011 throughout
much of the Middle East and North Africa seems to hold more promise,
despite the brutal responses of the existing regimes as well as the
discouraging lack of material progress beyond symbolic change. Zine
el-Abidine Ben Ali, Hosni Mubarak, and al-Gadhafi have been deposed.
Radical interventions by masses of people have proven central in the
cases of Tunisia and Egypt; similar interventions aimed at overturning
the status quo have followed in Bahrain, Yemen, Syria, Sudan, Palestine,
Ethiopia, Swaziland, Angola, and many other societies. The millions who
participated in what has been termed the Tahrir Commune in Cairo, in
addition to those other millions who mobilized elsewhere in Egypt
against Mubarakâs rule after the beginning of the revolutionary movement
on January 25, 2011, attest to the collective strength of the human
multitudeâits capacity for resisting brutality and instituting different
relations. The recent uprisings draw from the 2007 industrial strikes in
Mahalla and the 2003 mass mobilizations in Tahrir against the impending
U.S. invasion of Iraq, themselves echoes of the Palestiniansâ resistance
in general, and the First Intifada in particular. Practices like those
observed in the self-management of Tahrir Square, popular and
neighborhood committees in Tunisia and Egypt, and autonomous
mobilizations in Cairo to protect museums from looting are undoubtedly
anarchistic in nature, whatever the expressed political preferences of
the participants.
The efforts taken by the post-Mubarak Supreme Council of the Armed
Forces in Egypt, themselves backed by imperialism, are aimed at
suppressing dissent and containing the prospects for social change.
Hence the Egyptian militaryâs ban on strikes, its multiple violent
attacks on protesters assembled in Tahrir Square, its imprisonment of
thousands of dissidents, and its October 2011 massacre in Cairo of
Christian Copts protesting their marginalization. The movementâs
reactivation after January 25 is seen in the ongoing mobilizations
calling for a âsecond revolutionâ (thawra al-thania) against the Supreme
Council of the Armed Forces and Field Marshall Mohammed
al-Tantawiâreminiscent in a way of the third revolution sought by
proletarians and peasants in the early years of the Bolshevik
dictatorship. It bears reflection that Mubarak fell just as Egyptâs
industrial workers initiated a general strike; the generals, like the
transnational capitalist class, similarly fear these potentialities.
They do not want to see the Egyptian peopleâs resolutely
anti-imperialist views manifested in reality through any sort of
autonomous policy determination, and they do not favor the prospect of a
democratic opening that would most likely develop in anticapitalist
directions, given neoliberal capitalismâs responsibility for the mass
privation generally suffered by the Egyptian people and the substantial
increases in food prices that have only added to the grievances.[427]
Such considerations help explain the juntaâs effective alliance with the
Wahhabite Muslim Brotherhood, before and after the 2011 elections:
better close ties with known reactionary forces than the promises of
critical democratic praxis realized by the radical youth movement that
has been seminal throughout this revolt. As Samir Amin notes, Egyptian
Wahhabism is likely the influence of twentieth-century Saudi Arabian oil
wealth and the propagation of reactionary views throughout the
countryside by the landowning classes. Amin opposes the practice of
Egyptian Wahhabismâindisputably violent and oppressive, as can be seen
in Wahhabite attacks on Copts in the weeks predating January 25, as in
the Islamist collaboration with the military during its October 2011
attacks on Coptsâto the historical tradition of Egyptian Sufism, a less
hierarchical interpretation of the religion.[428] This relationship to
Sufism also seems to exist in Pakistan, another society that has met
with undue Saudi Wahhabite interference in recent decades, thereby
following the pernicious tendency toward fundamentalist Islamization,
which is itself a response to the decline of nationalist and socialist
movements throughout southwestern and South Asia.[429]
In India, the worldâs largest country by population, a multitude of
resistance projects have held sway for some time, from the 1857 Sepoy
Mutiny to the decolonization movement and the postcolonial Naxalite
insurrection. The communist revolt in the Telangana region of the state
of Hyderabad shortly after formal independence sought to bring about a
Red India by mobilizing the countryâs impoverished mass of
peasants.[430] The land redistribution schemes engaged in by the
Telengana rebels in favor of the peasantry were seminal for the later
development of the Naxalite movement, as were B. R. Ambedkarâs efforts
to organize in favor of Indiaâs Dalits, not to mention that of the Dalit
Panthers themselves.[431] The Communist Partyâs rule in the states of
West Bengal and Kerala is perceived as having provided a more
egalitarian, less environmentally destructive approach to development
after independence; womenâs rights in particular appear to be more
respected specifically in Kerala than elsewhere in the country, as are
the rights of the poor.
This situation contrasts markedly with that of the countryâs center and
east, home to the indigenous adivasi peoples whose very lands and lives
are threatened by unprecedented planned mining projects that seek to
remove the trillions of dollarsâ worth of bauxite from the mountains in
which they reside.[432] Binayak Sen, imprisoned in 2007 by the Indian
state for his activism in favor of the adivasis, is not mistaken in
claiming such plans to be genocidal. Qualified support thus should be
given to the Naxalite movement, a Maoist grouping comprised of adivasis
and middle-class Hindus alike that has taken up arms against the Indian
state in defense of the impoverished and marginalized. However
problematic the politics of the movementâs founder, Charu Mazumdar, who
advocated terroristic annihilation campaigns directed against Indiaâs
privileged, its historical ties to Chinese Communism, which resulted in
silence on its part regarding Chinaâs dispossession of Tibet and the
ravaging of Bangladesh by Chinaâs ally Pakistan, and its undeniable
violent excesses, it has established a countersociety within the
Dandakaranya forest in which the landless are afforded land and women
are granted more respect.[433] Beyond this, it is a symbol of dignity
and self-respect for the oppressed of India, quite similar in this sense
to the EZLN or PKK. As Roy writes, the Naxalites have âkept the dream of
revolution real and present in India.â[434] Without that dream, she
implies, matters would be far more bleak than they areâgiven that there
are more impoverished people in eight of Indiaâs states than in the
twenty-six countries that comprise Africa south of the Sahel, that 1.5
million Indian children die in their first year of life, and that
hundreds of thousands of peasants have committed suicide in recent years
to escape their debts.[435]
Beyond these contemporary and historical examples lies the lived
experience of what Bookchin terms âorganic societies,â or those groups
derided by anthropological racism as âprimitive.â As anthropologists
Marshall Sahlins, Lewis Henry Morgan, and Pierre Clastres have shown
convincingly, many such societies have instituted maxims radically
different than those that prevail within capitalist societies: acephaly
(the absence of hierarchy), individual autonomy, and substantive time
freed from work. Engelsâs exploration of generalized sexual promiscuity
and group marriage before the familyâs historical rise is an important
recognition of radical social alternatives within human culture.[436]
Bookchinâs enthusiasm for the ethics of complementarity and an
irreducible minimum identified by Paul Radin as practiced in some
organic societiesâthe irreducible minimum referring to the inviolable
provisioning of the basic necessities of life to each member of a given
social group without regard to oneâs productive contribution, or Marxâs
âprimitive communismââhardly seems misplaced today in light of the
radical mass deprivation overseen by capitalism as well as that which
catastrophic climate change would bring about. That there is little
evidence for the existence of war prior to the rise of agriculture and
statesâwar being defined in Douglas Fryâs review on the question as
political violence directed against out-groupsâis also encouraging.[437]
Albert Einstein is then right to celebrate the socioeconomic practices
exercised by many indigenous and organic social groups as demonstrating
that âhuman beings are not condemned, because of their biological
constitution, to annihilate each other or to be at the mercy of a cruel,
self-inflicted fate.â[438]
Considered together with the efforts of political resistance groupings,
the historical and contemporary existence of such societies shows, in
Adornoâs words, that âthis hell ... cannot be the last word.â[439]
Clastres speculates that stateless humanity prevented the emergence of
the state for hundreds of thousands of years by murdering those
individuals who aspired to hierarchical power. Yet such an approach
likely would be problematic if applied as a means of addressing the
present situation. As Agamben argues, âNo ethics can claim to exclude a
part of humanity, no matter how unpleasant or difficult that humanity is
to see.â[440]
However unpalatable political murder may be, some means of overthrowing
prevailing power arrangements must be taken desperately soon. Borrowing
from Michel Foucault, we must symbolically cut off the kingâs head while
also metaphorically destroying the guillotine, as the Parisian
Communards did promptly after taking power in March 1871.[441] Toward
this end, it should be self-evident that a mere exodus from statist
domination on the model of the nonhierarchical societies established by
fugitive state captives fleeing the rice-growing kingdoms of lowland
Southeast Asia for the stateless highlands known as Zomia, or runaway
Brazilian slaves setting up quilombos, are insufficient strategies, for
they erroneously assume that one can escape capitalism without directly
confronting it with the aim of also abolishing it.[442] Whether progress
toward the end of instituting revolution would demand a temporary
withdrawal into an undergroundâas modeled, for example, historically by
the neo-Zapatistas during the decade of preparation before January 1994
and speculatively by the liberatory resistance movements imagined in
Robinsonâs Mars trilogyâis not something that can be resolved here,
other than to note that there likely is not enough time left,
environmentally speaking, for dissident organizers and thinkers to break
ties with the rest of society for any significant period. What can be
said is that presently constituted power must be overthrown. Capital
accumulation, as Harvey declares outrightly, âwill have to be stopped,â
and the capitalist class, âwhich will never willingly surrender its
power,â necessarily will have to be dispossessed of its âproperty,
wealth, and powers.â[443]
The radical violence, alienation, and destructiveness overseen and
directed by prevailing power is but the continuation of long-standing
social trends that have gone on for millenniaâtotalitarianism grew out
of imperialism and capitalism, while hierarchy has been sustained by
patriarchy and religion.[444] Most important is the understanding that
the current forms of world alienation, humanityâs âsocietal
constitution,â jeopardize its very existence. Considering this
situation, openness to historical alternatives becomes a necessity,
given the consequences that will follow without the institution of
social relations radically different than present ones. The impetus to
remake the world along different lines is now the only means by which
total catastrophe can reasonably be avoided.
As this work has examined, though, the prospect that humanity will fail
to radically reconstruct global society on humane ecological grounds
within the near term is entirely within the realm of possibility.
Catastrophic climate change threatens humanityâs well-being in a manner
perhaps even more extreme than that posed by nuclear armsâand the threat
of a synergy between these two forces is decidedly more frightening than
consideration of either of the two alone. Nevertheless, barring
mechanical failures or mistakes, the offensive employment of nuclear
weapons ultimately depends on human choice at a certain point, whereas
the laws of atmospheric physics have no such potential fail-safe
mechanism. The atmosphere, as is correctly observed by Earth scientist
Andrew Glikson, is not âwaiting for human decision.â[445] It responds to
humanityâs mutilated forms in keeping with scientific predictions based
on the laws of chemistry and physics; it has been subjected to
destabilization processes graver than those imagined by even the most
pessimistic accounts. While sectors of humanity continue to blind
themselves to the realities of climate change and the relatively
privileged fail radically to act in the interests of well-being, reason,
and survival, âglaciers continue to retreat, new hazards keep emerging,
and water sources dwindle.â[446] In short, world alienation barrels life
on toward the abyss.
This world alienation, a term first used by Arendt to describe
capitalist wealth accumulation processes that demand as a precondition
of their functioning that âthe world and the very worldliness of
[humankind] are sacrificed,â follows from the historical rise of the
capitalist mode of production, the division of Earthâs territory into
sovereign states, and the historical failure to date to overturn the
monstrous system that upholds both such interrelated systems.[447] Given
such conditions, one may succumb to overwhelming despair regarding the
human prospect and thus withdraw from engagement with politics entirely.
It has been the argument advanced hereâindeed, one of the very bases of
the writing of this bookâthat such despair should not be total. As
Adorno writes, âThe worldâs course is not absolutely conclusive, nor is
absolute despair; rather, despair is its conclusiveness.â[448] Human
society after all is the product of its myriad constituent parts, which
are not limited to capital and the state. These barbaric forms do not
have the final word.
The prospect of an exit from social and environmental barbarism depends
critically on the autonomous action of the subordinated. This social
force has a responsibility to resist dominant socialization processes
that would perpetuate existing relations in favor of realizing the
imperative for social revolutionâthe only means by which humanity as a
whole can come to be treated as an end in itself and by which climate
catastrophe can be averted.
[1] Suzanne Goldenberg, âLast Year Was Joint Warmest on Record, Say
Climatologists,â Guardian, January 12, 2011.
[2] John Vidal, âCarbon Levels Hit New Peak, Research Shows,â Guardian,
May 31, 2011.
[3] Peter D. Ward, The Flooded Earth: Our Future in a World without Ice
Caps (New York: Basic Books, 2010), 63.
[4] Fiona Harvey, âWorst Ever Carbon Emissions Leave Climate on the
Brink,â Guardian, May 29, 2011.
[5] Steve Connor and Michael McCarthy, âWorld on Course for Catastrophic
6° Rise, Reveal Scientists,â Independent, November 18, 2009.
[6] Gaia Vince, âOne Last Chance to Save Mankind,â New Scientist,
January 23, 2009.
[7] Jenny Fyall, âWarming Will âWipe Out Billions,ââ Scotsman News,
November 29, 2009.
[8] David Harvey, The Enigma of Capital (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2009), 185.
[9] Imperial College London, âAsteroid Killed Off the Dinosaurs, Says
International Scientific Panel,â Science Daily, March 4, 2010; Juliette
Jowitt, âHumans Driving Extinction Faster Than Species Can Evolve, Say
Experts,â Guardian, March 7, 2010.
[10] Suzanne Goldenberg, âPlanet Earth is Home to 8.7 Million Species,
Scientists Estimate,â Guardian, August 23, 2011.
[11] George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World
History: Introduction, trans. Hugh Bar Nisbet (1828; repr., Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1975), 118, 131â40; FĂ©lix Guattari, The
Three Ecologies, trans. Ian Pindar and Paul Sutton (London: Athlone,
2000), 28.
[12] Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment:
Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (1947; repr., Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 2002), xviii, 1.
[13] Guattari, The Three Ecologies, 45.
[14] Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964),
16; Karl Marx, introduction to Contribution to the Critique of Hegelâs
Philosophy of Right, ed. Joseph OâMalley (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1982) (translation modified; emphasis in original).
[15] Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New
York: Schocken Books, 2003), 259.
[16] Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World History, 69 (translation
modified).
[17] Albert Camus, Caligula and Three Other Plays, trans. Stuart Gilbert
(New York: Vintage, 1958), 245.
[18] Steve Connor, âMelting Greenland Glacier May Hasten Rise in Sea
Level,â Independent, July 25, 2005.
[19] Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vol. 1, ed.
Frederick Engels, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (1867; repr.,
New York: Modern Library, 1906), 709.
[20] Ciro PĂ©rez Silva, âAnuncia CalderĂłn programa para sustituir los
focos incandescentes por ahorradores,â La Jornada, December 7, 2010.
[21] âNo se descuidarĂĄn los patrullajes en la ciudad: Seguridad
PĂșblica,â Por Esto! de Quintana Roo, November 27, 2010.
[22] âEquipan a la policĂa municipal,â Por Esto! de Quintana Roo,
November 28, 2010.
[23] Mike Gonzalez, âEvo Moralesâs Defence of Mother Earth Rings Hollow
in Bolivia,â Guardian, October 3, 2011.
[24] Polly Higgins, Eradicating Ecocide (London: Shepheard-Walwyn,
2010); see also Polly Higgins, âWhy We Need a Law on Ecocide,â Guardian,
January 5, 2011.
[25] Christos Filippidis, âThe Polis-Jungle, Magical Densities, and the
Survival Guide of the Enemy Within,â in Revolt and Crisis in Greece, ed.
Antonis Vradis and Dimitris Dalakoglu (Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2011), 69.
[26] Hegel, Lectures, 69; Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (1963; repr., New
York: Penguin, 2006), 62.
[27] John Vidal, âClimate Change Will Devastate Africa, Top UK Scientist
Warns,â Guardian, October 28, 2009; Ward, The Flooded Earth, 106; Mike
Davis, âLiving on the Ice Shelf: Humanityâs Melt Down,â in The Green
Zone: The Environmental Costs of Militarism, ed. Barry Sanders (Oakland,
CA: AK Press, 2009), 7â17.
[28] Jason Samson, Dominique Berteaux, Brian J. McGill, and Murray M.
Humphries, âGeographic Disparities and Moral Hazards in the Predicted
Impacts of Climate Change on Human Populations,â Global Ecology and
Biogeography 20, no. 4 (July 2011): 537.
[29] Justin Sheffield and Eric F. Wood, Drought: Past Problems and
Future Scenarios (London: Earthscan, 2011), 180â83.
[30] John Vidal, âGlobal Warming Causes 300,000 Deaths a Year, Says Kofi
Annan Thinktank,â Guardian, May 29, 2009.
[31] Dara and Climate Vulnerable Forum, Climate Vulnerability Report
2010, available at
http://daraint.org/wp-content/uploads/2010/12/CVM1.pdf
.
[32] Noam Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2010),
133.
[33] Albert Memmi, The Colonizer and the Colonized (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1965), 62.
[34] Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951; repr., San
Diego, CA: Harcourt, 1968); Herbert Marcuse, Negations: Essays in
Critical Theory, trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968),
19.
[35] Max Horkheimer, âDie Juden in Europa,â Zeitschrift fĂŒr
Sozialforschung 8 (1939): 115 (translation from Fredric Jameson, Late
Marxism: Adorno, or the Persistence of the Dialectic [London: Verso,
1990], 113).
[36] Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life,
trans. E.F.N. Jephcott (1951; repr., London: Verso, 1974), 80; Dara and
Climate Vulnerable Forum, Climate Vulnerability Report 2010.
[37] Karl Marx, âLetter from Marx to Arnold Ruge,â in Karl Marx and
Frederick Engels: Collected Works (Moscow: International Publishers,
1975), 1:393â95.
[38] Theodor W. Adorno, Critical Models, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New
York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 298.
[39] âFamine Spreads to Sixth Region of Somalia,â Al Jazeera English,
September 5, 2011, available at
http://www.aljazeera.com/news/africa/2011/09/201195104317598222.html;
Camus, Caligula and Three Other Plays, 134.
[40] Franz Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National
Socialism, 1933â1944 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1944), 167.
[41] Walter Benjamin, âOn the Concept of Historyâ (1940), available at
http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/benjamin/1940/history.htm
.
[42] Ulrike Meinhof, Everybody Talks about the Weather ... We Donât, ed.
Karin Bauer (New York: Seven Stories Press, 2008), 118.
[43] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton
(London: Routledge, 1973), 218.
[44] Chronis Polychroniou, âInterview with Professor Minqi Li,â
Eleftherotypia 13 (November 2009), available at
http://www.econ.utah.edu/~mli/CV/Interview%20with%20Minqi%20Li_Greece%20111309.pdf
.
[45] Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Humanism and Terror, trans. John OâNeill
(1947; repr., Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), 156; Theodor W. Adorno,
âProgress,â in Benjamin: Philosophy, Aesthetics, History, ed. Gary Smith
(1962; repr., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 85â86.
[46] Walter Benjamin, Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt (New York:
Harcourt, 1968), 38; Adorno, Critical Models, 190.
[47] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 405.
[48] Samir Amin, âAn Arab Springtime?â Monthly Review, June 2, 2011,
available at
http://monthlyreview.org/commentary/2011-an-arab-springtime; Immanuel
Wallerstein, âThe Contradictions of the Arab Spring,â Al Jazeera
English, November 14, 2011.
[49] Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Part One, ed.
C. J. Arthur (New York: International Publishers, 2004), 57.
[50] Adorno, Critical Models, 267â68.
[51] Theodor W. Adorno, Prisms, trans. Samuel Weber and Shierry Weber
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1967), 117.
[52] Raoul Vaneigem, âBasic Banalities,â in Situationist International
Anthology, ed. Ken Knabb (Berkeley: Bureau of Public Secrets, 2006),
117â30.
[53] Adorno, âProgress,â in Benjamin: Philosophy, Aesthetics, History,
ed. Gary Smith (1962; repr., Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1989), 96.
[54] Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1958), 246.
[55] Giorgio Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the
Archive, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (New York: Zone Books, 2002), 121.
[56] Noam Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival: Americaâs Quest for Global
Dominance (New York: Owl Books, 2004), 216.
[57] Jonathan Schell, The Fate of the Earth (1982; repr., Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 2000), 21, 168.
[58] Charles Fourier, Design for Utopia: Selected Works of Charles
Fourier (New York: Schocken Books, 1971); Theodor W. Adorno, Critical
Models, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press,
2005), 273.
[59] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 115, xxvi, 118.
[60] Ibid., 110, 148.
[61] Ibid., 130â32, 95; Hannah Arendt, The Promise of Politics, ed.
Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken Books, 2005), 191; GĂŒnther Anders, âOne
World or No World,â in Hiroshima in Memoriam and Today: A Testament of
Peace for the World (Asheville, NC: Biltmore Press, 1971), 210.
[62] Schell, The Abolition, 46.
[63] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 178.
[64] Ibid., 188.
[65]
P. D. James, The Children of Men (New York: Warner Books, 1992), 308.
[66] Schell, The Abolition, 123; Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 110, 94,
186.
[67] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 148, 184.
[68] Ibid., 161.
[69] Ibid., 135, 226.
[70] Ibid., 161, 135, 226, 177, 184, 173, 162, 188, 219, 122, 231, 223;
Schell, The Abolition, 74.
[71] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 136, 173, 174, 177.
[72] Ibid., 170, 225.
[73] Ibid., 210, 218, 186, 219â31.
[74] Bryan Farrell, âThe Power of Nonviolent Movements,â Yes Magazine,
January 14, 2010.
[75] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 196, 169; Schell, The Abolition, 21.
[76] Schell, The Fate of the Earth, 231; Schell, The Abolition, 11.
[77] Walter Benjamin, On Hashish, ed. Howard Eiland (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2006), 101.
[78] Noam Chomsky, âOccupy the Future,â In These Times, November 1,
2011.
[79] James Hansen, Storms of My Grandchildren (New York: Bloomsbury,
2009), ix, 277.
[80] David Spratt and Philip Sutton, Climate Code Red: The Case for
Emergency Action (Melbourne: Scribe, 2008), 82.
[81] Gwynne Dyer, Climate Wars (Toronto: Vintage Canada, 2009), 87â95;
Mark Lynas, Six Degrees: Our Future on a Hotter Planet (Washington, DC:
National Geographic, 2008), 274â75.
[82] James Hansen, Makiko Sato, Pushker Kharecha, David Beerling,
Valerie Masson-Delmotte, Mark Pagani, Maureen Raymo, Dana L. Royer, and
James C. Zachos, âTarget Atmospheric CO2: Where Should Humanity Aim?â
available at
http://www.columbia.edu/~jeh1/2008/TargetCO2_20080407.pdf
.
[83] Spratt and Sutton, Climate Code Red, 120â32.
[84] Steve Connor, âExtreme Weather Link âCan No Longer Be Ignored,ââ
Independent, July 1, 2011.
[85] âPakistan Floods in Numbers,â Al Jazeera English, August 30, 2010;
Reena Saeed Khan, âThe Floods in Pakistan Show Our Vulnerability to
Climate Chaos,â Guardian, November 10, 2010; Ali Ismail, âPakistan
Floods Unleash Desperate Economic Crisis,â World Socialist Web Site, 26
August 26, 2010.
[86] Declan Walsh, Shehryar Mufti, Lindsay Poulton, and Ziad Zafar,
âPakistan Floods: Feudals under Fire in Punjab,â Guardian, October 3,
2010.
[87] Tom Peters, âInternational Aid for Pakistan Flood Victims Grossly
Inadequate,â World Socialist Web Site, September 24, 2010.
[88] Declan Walsh, âPakistan Flood Crisis as Bad as African Famines, UN
Says,â Guardian, January 27, 2011.
[89] âMillions Affected by Deadly Pakistan Floods,â Al Jazeera English,
September 9, 2011.
[90] Rob Crilly, âStrong Evidence Climate Change Caused Devastating
Pakistan Floods,â Scotsman News, October 14, 2010.
[91] Bill McKibben, âWhy Has Extreme Weather Failed to Heat Up Climate
Debate?â Guardian, August 18, 2010.
[92] Mark Tran, âGlobal Response to Pakistan Floods Inadequate, Claims
Report,â Guardian, July 24, 2011.
[93] âNigerâs Silent Crisis,â BBC News Online, June 21, 2010; Mike
Pflanz, âMillions of West Africans Need Urgent Food Aid after Failed
Harvests,â Telegraph, June 21, 2010.
[94] Henry Foy, âMillions Face Starvation in West Africa, Aid Agencies
Warn,â Guardian, June 21, 2010.
[95] âFood Crisis Emergency in Niger,â ReliefWeb, June 21, 2010.
[96] Connor, âExtreme Weatherâ; Tom Parfitt, âVladimir Putin Bans Grain
Exports as Drought and Wildfires Ravage Crops,â Guardian, August 5,
2010.
[97] Katie Allen, âAfghanistan and African Nations at Greatest Risk from
World Food Shortages,â Guardian, August 19, 2010.
[98] Jason Burke, âHundreds Die in Indian Heat Wave,â Guardian, May 30,
2010; John Vidal and Declan Walsh, âTemperatures Reach Record High in
Pakistan,â Guardian, June 1, 2010.
[99] Karen McVeigh, âSri Lankan Floods Could Leave 400,000 Children
without Enough Food,â Guardian, January 20, 2011; âSri Lanka Floods
Destroy Crops,â Al Jazeera English, January 23, 2011.
[100] Tom Phillips, âDrought Brings Amazon Tributary to Lowest Level in
a Century,â Guardian, October 26, 2010; Damian Carringon, âMass Tree
Death Prompts Fears of Amazon âClimate Tipping Point,ââ Guardian,
February 3, 2011.
[101] University of Colorado at Boulder, âArctic Sea Ice Reaches Lowest
2010 Extent, Third Lowest in Satellite Record,â Science Daily, September
16, 2010; Steve Connor, âArctic Ice Set to Match All-time Record Low,â
Independent, September 7, 2011; Stephen Leahy, âArctic Ice in Death
Spiral,â Inter Press Service, September 20, 2010.
[102] John Vidal, âEnvironment World Review of the Year: â2011 Rewrote
the Record Books,ââ Guardian, December 22, 2011; Fiona Harvey, âEngland
Sees Driest Spring in a Century as Drought Hits UK,â Guardian, June 10,
2011.
[103] Jonathan Watts, âChina Crisis over Yangtze River Drought Forces
Drastic Dam Measures,â Guardian, May 25, 2011.
[104] David Randall, Simon Murphy, and Daud Yussuf, âStarvation Returns
to the Horn of Africa,â Independent, July 3, 2011.
[105] Emily Dugan, âMore Than Half of Somalis Now Face Starvation,â
Independent, September 4, 2011; Emily Dugan, âTwo Million East African
Infants Are Now Starving,â Independent, August 7, 2011.
[106] âSomalia Famine: UN Warns of 750,000 Deaths,â BBC News Online,
September 5, 2011.
[107] Susan Solomon, Dahe Qin, Michael Manning, Zhenlin Chen, Melinda
Marquis, Kristen B. Averyt, Melinda Tignor, and Henry L. Miller,
Contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007), 310â12.
[108] Collectif Argos, Climate Refugees (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
2010), 273; Priestley Habru, âThe View from beneath the Waves: Climate
Change in the Solomon Islands,â Guardian, November 9, 2010.
[109] Kathy Marks, âSinking Pacific Island Kiribati Considers Moving to
a Man-made Alternative,â Independent, September 8, 2011; Kit Gillet,
âVietnamâs Rice Bowl Threatened by Rising Seas,â Guardian, August 21,
2011.
[110] Collectif Argos, Climate Refugees, 93; Daniel Howden, âRecord Heat
Recorded for Africaâs Greatest Lake,â Independent, 18 May 18, 2010.
[111] Robin McKie, âOcean Acidification Is Latest Manifestation of
Global Warming,â Observer, May 29, 2011.
[112] Jayashree Nandi, âIsro: 75% of Himalayan Glaciers Retreating,â
Times of India, May 16, 2011.
[113] Jonathan Watts, âTibet Temperature âHighest since Records Beganâ
Say Chinese Climatologists,â Guardian, February 2, 2010.
[114] Nikolas Kozloff, No Rain in the Amazon (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2010), 9.
[115] Steve Connor, âWeather Disasters in the Poorest Nations âHave
Trebled since 1980s,ââ Independent, May 23, 2011.
[116] Edward S. Herman and David Peterson, The Politics of Genocide (New
York: Monthly Review Press, 2010), 42.
[117] Michael McCarthy, âRevealed: Climate Quirk That Doubles Risk of
War,â Independent, August 25, 2011.
[118] Mike Davis, Late Victorian Holocausts: El Niño Famines and the
Making of the Third World (London: Verso, 2000), 7.
[119] Solomon, Qin, Manning, Chen, Marquis, Averyt, Tignor, and Miller,
Contribution of Working Group I, 790.
[120] James Hansen, Pushker Kharecha, Makiko Sato, Paul Epstein, Paul J.
Hearty, Ove Hoegh-Guldberg, Camille Parmesan, Stefan Rahmstorf, Johan
Rockstrom, Eelco J. Rohling, Jeffrey Sachs, Peter Smith, Konrad Steffen,
Karina von Schuckmann, and James C. Zachos, âThe Case for Young People
and Nature: A Path to a Healthy, Natural, Prosperous Future,â available
at http://
www.columbia.edu/~jeh1/mailings/2011/20110505_CaseForYoungPeople.pdf
.
[121] Lynas, Six Degrees, 25â70, 73â119.
[122] Simon Hales, âEstimating Human Population Health Impacts in a 4+°C
Worldâ (paper presented at the Oxford University 4 Degrees and Beyond
International Climate Change Conference, Oxford, September 28, 2009).
[123] Dyer, Climate Wars, 62.
[124] Lynas, Six Degrees, 123â81.
[125] Hans Joachim Schellnhuber, âTerra Quasi-Incognita: Beyond the 2ÂșC
Lineâ (paper presented at the Oxford University 4 Degrees and Beyond
International Climate Change Conference, Oxford, September 28, 2009).
[126] Peter D. Ward, The Flooded Earth: Our Future in a World Without
Ice Caps (New York: Basic Books, 2010).
[127] Steve Connor, âMelting of the Arctic âWill Accelerate Climate
Change within Twenty Years,ââ Independent, May 30, 2011.
[128] AFP, âRussia May Lose 30% of Permafrost by 2050: Official,â
Independent, July 31, 2011.
[129] David Chandler, âClimate Change Odds Much Worse Than Thought,â MIT
News Office, May 19, 2009.
[130] Dyer, Climate Wars, 90.
[131] Jane B. Reece, Lisa A. Urry, Michael L. Cain, Steven A. Wasserman,
Peter V. Minorsky, and Robert B. Jackson, Campbell Biology (Boston:
Benjamin Cummings, 2011), 521â23.
[132] Hansen, Storms of My Grandchildren, 223â36.
[133] Herbert Marcuse, Counterrevolution and Revolt (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1972), 60.
[134] Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor
(1970; repr., London: Continuum, 2002), 66.
[135] Theodor W. Adorno, History and Freedom, trans. Rodney Livingstone
(1964â65; repr., London: Polity Press, 2006), 45; Max Horkheimer and
Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments,
trans. Edmund Jephcott (1947; repr., Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press, 2002), 165.
[136] Steven Best, âMinding the Animals: Ethology and the Obsolescence
of Left Humanism,â International Journal of Inclusive Democracy 5, no. 2
(Spring 2009), available at
http://www.inclusivedemocracy.org/journal/vol5/vol5_no2_best_minding_animals_PRINTABLE.htm
.
[137] Christopher Boehm, Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of
Egalitarian Behavior (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).
[138] Cited in Murray Bookchin, The Ecology of Freedom (1982; repr.,
Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2005), 93.
[139] Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and
the State (1891; repr., New York: Pathfinder, 1972), 54.
[140] Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization: A Philosophical Inquiry
into Freud (Boston: Beacon Press, 1966), 109.
[141] Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 212.
[142] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton
(London: Routledge, 1973), 355.
[143] Peter Kropotkin, Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution (1902; repr.,
Westford, MA: Porter Sargent, 1976).
[144] Collectif Argos, Climate Refugees (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
2010), 9, 14.
[145] Ibid., 28, 60, 97.
[146] James D. Cockcroft, Mexicoâs Revolution Then and Now (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 2010), 141.
[147] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 377â78.
[148] John Bellamy Foster, Marxâs Ecology (New York: Monthly Review,
2000); John Bellamy Foster, The Ecological Revolution (New York: Monthly
Review, 2009).
[149] Cited in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: Collected Works (Moscow:
International Publishers, 1975), 12:132; Karl Marx, Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, trans. Martin Milligan, ed. Dirk J.
Struik (New York: International Publishers), 112.
[150] Rosa Luxemburg, The Rosa Luxemburg Reader, ed. Peter Hudis and
Kevin B. Anderson (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2004), 394, 390â91.
[151] Ernst Bloch, The Principle of Hope, trans. Neville Plaice, Stephen
Plaice, and Paul Knight (1959; repr., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986),
286.
[152] Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, 65.
[153] Bill McKibben, Eaarth: Making a Life on a Tough New Planet (New
York: Times Books, 2010), 101, 78, 52.
[154] Ibid., 27.
[155] Noam Chomsky, âCrisis and Hope: Theirs and Oursâ (comments at the
Brecht Forum, Riverside Church, New York, June 12, 2009).
[156] McKibben, Eaarth, 35.
[157] Ibid., 52.
[158] Walter Benjamin, Selected Writings, Volume 4: 1938â1940, trans.
Edmund Jephcott, ed. Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 402.
[159] Marcuse, Counterrevolution and Revolt, 64.
[160] Ibid., 65, 69.
[161] Ibid., 67; Marcuse, Eros and Civilization, 178.
[162] Marcuse, Counterrevolution and Revolt, 164, 178.
[163] Leo Hickman, âJames Lovelock: Humans Are Too Stupid to Prevent
Climate Changeâ and âJames Lovelock on the Value of Sceptics and Why
Copenhagen Was Doomed,â Guardian, March 29, 2010; see also Micah White,
âAn Alternative to the New Wave of Ecofascism,â Guardian, September 16,
2010.
[164] Susanna Rustin, âHas the Green Movement Lost Its Way?â Guardian,
July 1, 2011.
[165] James C. Scott, The Art of Not Being Governed (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 2009), 293.
[166] Ernst Bloch, The Principle of Hope, trans. Neville Plaice, Stephen
Plaice, and Paul Knight (1959; repr., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986),
189.
[167] Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Commonwealth (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2009), 198.
[168] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton
(London: Routledge, 1973), 398; Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and
Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken Books, 2003), 164.
[169] Theodor W. Adorno, Critical Models, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New
York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 272â73.
[170] Hannah Arendt, On Violence (San Diego: Harcourt, 1969), 48.
[171] Theodor W. Adorno, Can One Live After Auschwitz? A Philosophical
Reader (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003), 18.
[172] Noam Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects (Chicago: Haymarket Books,
2010), 165.
[173] Noam Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival: Americaâs Quest for Global
Dominance (New York: Owl Books, 2004), 1â2; Chomsky, Hopes and
Prospects, 175.
[174] Mark Achbar and Peter Wintonick, Manufacturing Consent: Noam
Chomsky and the Media (Montreal: Necessary Illusions/National Film Board
of Canada, 1992); Noam Chomsky, âCrisis and Hope: Theirs and Oursâ
(comments at the Brecht Forum, Riverside Church, New York, June 12,
2009).
[175] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 218, 222.
[176] Ibid., 225â27.
[177] Ibid., 228.
[178] Ibid., 228; Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 85.
[179] Bill Van Auken, âObama Administration Spending Billions on New
Global Strike Weapons,â World Socialist Web Site, April 24, 2010; Alok
Jha, âUS Military to Launch Fastest-Ever Plane,â Guardian, August 10,
2011, available at
http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/aug/10/us-military-fastest-plane-falcon.
[180] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 229.
[181] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 27, 108.
[182] Noam Chomsky, âHuman Intelligence and the Environment,â
International Socialist Review 76 (May 2011), 45.
[183] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 111â12.
[184] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 234â35.
[185] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 112.
[186] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 235.
[187] Ibid., 36; Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 4â7.
[188] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 97; Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects,
37.
[189] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 55, 116; Noam Chomsky, New World of
Indigenous Resistance, ed. Lois Meyer and BenjamĂn Maldonado Alvarado
(San Francisco: City Lights Books, 2010), 53.
[190] Nick Nesbitt, Universal Emancipation: The Haitian Revolution and
the Radical Enlightenment (Charlottesville: University of Virginia
Press, 2008), 195.
[191] Scott, The Art of Not Being Governed; Hannah Arendt, On Revolution
(1963; repr., New York: Penguin, 2006), 237, 256â58.
[192] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 38.
[193] Ibid., 228; Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 29.
[194] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 38; Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects,
121.
[195] Jacques RanciĂšre, Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy, trans.
Julie Rose (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
[196] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 112, 215.
[197] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 182; Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects,
156.
[198] Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival, 216.
[199] Wilhelm Reich, The Mass Psychology of Fascism (New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux, 1970), xxxi. On autonomous Marxism, see Antonio
Negri, Marx Beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse, trans. Harry Cleaver
(South Hadley, MA: Bergin and Garvey Publishers, 1984); John Holloway,
Crack Capitalism (London: Pluto Press, 2010); Chomsky, Hopes and
Prospects, 167.
[200] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 118.
[201] Noam Chomsky, âAll Students Should Become Anarchists,â June 14,
2011, available at http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20110614_en.htm;
Chomsky, New World of Indigenous Resistance, 361.
[202] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 135â36.
[203] Fidel Castro, âEl Invierno Nuclearâ La Jornada, August 23, 2010.
[204] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 135â36.
[205] Ibid., 166; Chomsky,, âHuman Intelligence and the Environment,â
49.
[206] Chomsky, âHuman Intelligence and the Environment,â 51.
[207] Theodor W. Adorno, Problems of Moral Philosophy, trans. Rodney
Livingstone (1963; repr., Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,
2001), 14; Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged
Life, trans. E.F.N. Jephcott (1951; repr., London: Verso, 1974), 39
(translation modified); Theodor W. Adorno, âProgress,â in Benjamin:
Philosophy, Aesthetics, History, ed. Gary Smith (1962; repr., Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1989), 84â85.
[208] Theodor W. Adorno, History and Freedom, trans. Rodney Livingstone
(1964â65; repr., London: Polity Press, 2006), 4.
[209] Ibid., 47, 8; Adorno, Problems of Moral Philosophy, 10.
[210] Adorno, Can One Live After Auschwitz? 244, 13.
[211] Theodor W. Adorno, Prisms, trans. Samuel Weber and Shierry Weber
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1967), 257.
[212] Adorno, Problems of Moral Philosophy, 99, 167.
[213] Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto?
trans. Rodney Livingstone (1989; repr., London: Verso, 2011), 37.
[214] Adorno, âProgress,â 84 (translation modified).
[215] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 40.
[216] Adorno, History and Freedom, 143.
[217] Adorno, âProgress,â 85.
[218] Adorno, History and Freedom, 145.
[219] Mikhail Bakunin, âMan, Society, and Freedom,â from Bakunin on
Anarchy, trans. Sam Dolgoff (New York: Knopf, 1972), 237 and Adorno,
Minima Moralia, 173.
[220] Simone de Beauvoir, Ethics of Ambiguity, trans. Bernard Frechtman
(New York: Philosophical Library, 1948), 91.
[221] Adorno, âProgress,â 85.
[222] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 48.
[223] Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951; repr., San
Diego, CA: Harcourt, 1968), xx; Adorno, âProgress,â 94.
[224] Walter Benjamin, âOn the Concept of Historyâ (1940), available at
http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/benjamin/1940/history.htm
; Adorno, âProgress,â 36.
[225] Adorno, History and Freedom, 181.
[226] Murray Bookchin, Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Oakland, CA: AK Press,
2004).
[227] Adorno, History and Freedom, 62, 182.
[228] Adorno, âProgress,â 94.
[229] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 47; Adorno,
History and Freedom, 111.
[230] Adorno, âProgress,â 99â101.
[231] Adorno, History and Freedom, 150; Adorno, Problems of Moral
Philosophy, 103.
[232] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto?, 52.
[233] Adorno, âProgress,â 85 (translation modified).
[234] Ibid., 90â91.
[235] Ibid., 96.
[236] Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 100, x, 194.
[237] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 404.
[238] Theodor W. Adorno, The Culture Industry (London: Routledge, 1991),
196.
[239] Adorno, Critical Models, 269; Theodor W. Adorno, Guilt and
Defense: On the Legacies of National Socialism in Postwar Germany,
trans. and ed. Jeffrey K. Olick and Andrew J. Perrin (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2010), 169â84.
[240] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 36.
[241] Max Horkheimer, âThe End of Reason,â in The Essential Frankfurt
School Reader, ed. Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt (New York: Continuum,
1997), 48.
[242] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 43; Adorno,
Negative Dialectics, 320.
[243] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 47.
[244] Adorno, Critical Models, 150 (translation modified).
[245] Robert L. Heilbroner, An Inquiry into the Human Prospect (New
York: W. W. Norton, 1980).
[246] Ibid., 43.
[247] Ibid., 22, 42â46, 97.
[248] Ibid., 50â55, 150, 109.
[249] Ibid., 93, 91.
[250] Ibid., 57, 77, 93, 91, 94, 98â104, 109, 153, 109.
[251] Ibid., 130â35.
[252] Ibid., 157, 110, 155, 130â35, 165.
[253] Max Horkheimer, Dawn and Decline: Notes, 1926â1931 and 1959â1969,
trans. Michael Shaw (New York: Seabury Press, 1978), 202.
[254] Heilbroner, Inquiry, 165â66, 184.
[255] Ronald Aronson, Dialectics of Disaster: A Preface to Hope (New
York: Schocken Books, 1984), 3, 191.
[256] Ibid., 35â45, 77, 142, 169, 262.
[257] Ibid., 262, 266, 286, 288, 303.
[258] Ibid., 302, 292, 210, 17, 304, 289.
[259] Fidel Castro, âLa Paz con la Paz Se Paga,â September 3, 2010,
available at
http://www.cubadebate.cu/noticias/2010/09/03/fidel-castro-la-paz-con-la-paz-se-paga
.
[260] RanciĂšre, Disagreement, 83.
[261] McKibben, Eaarth, xv.
[262] Heilbroner, Inquiry, 159.
[263] Bloch, Principle of Hope, 232.
[264] Chomsky, New World of Indigenous Resistance, 362.
[265] Cornelius Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, trans. and ed.
David Ames Curtis (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 107.
[266] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto?, 45, 39, 61.
[267] Franz Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National
Socialism, 1933â1944 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1944), 464.
[268] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto?, 42.
[269] Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects, 195; Bill Van Auken, âObama
Administration Spending Billions on New Global Strike Weapons,â World
Socialist Web Site, April 24, 2010.
[270] George Monbiot, âThe Western Appetite for Biofuels Is Causing
Starvation in the Poor World,â Guardian, November 6, 2007.
[271] Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto? 45; Gareth Porter,
âReport Slams Pakistan Drone Attacks,â Al Jazeera English, November 3,
2010.
[272] Bloch, The Principle of Hope; Holloway, Crack Capitalism.
[273] Adorno, History and Freedom, 149; David Harvey, The Enigma of
Capital (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 226â27.
[274] Adorno, History and Freedom, 7.
[275] Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism, 437.
[276] Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of Reason (1947; repr., London: Continuum,
2004), 115; Henry A. Giroux, âIn the Twilight of the Social State:
Rethinking Walter Benjaminâs Angel of History,â Truth-out, January 4,
2011, available at
http://www.truth-out.org/in-twilight-social-state-rethinking-walter-benjamins-angel-history66544.
[277] Walter Benjamin, Benjamin: Philosophy, Aesthetics, History, ed.
Gary Smith (1962; repr., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989),
64.
[278] Chris Hedges, âZero Point of Systemic Collapse,â Adbusters,
February 8, 2010.
[279] Benjamin, Benjamin, 66.
[280] Adorno, Problems of Moral Philosophy, 176.
[281] RanciĂšre, Disagreement, 14; Adorno and Horkheimer, Towards a New
Manifesto?, 36.
[282] Horkheimer, âThe Authoritarian State,â in The Essential Frankfurt
School Reader, ed. Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt (New York: Continuum,
1997), 117.
[283] Holloway, Crack Capitalism, 192.
[284] Ibid., 79; Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, 257.
[285] Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1958), 247; de Beauvoir, Ethics of Ambiguity, 91.
[286] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton
(London: Routledge, 1973), 365.
[287] Franciszek Piper, âThe Number of Victims,â in Anatomy of the
Auschwitz Death Camp, ed. Yehuda Bauer, Raul Hilberg, and Franciszek
Piper (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), 61â62.
[288] Daniel Jonah Goldhagen, Hitlerâs Willing Executioners: Ordinary
Germans and the Holocaust (New York: Vintage, 1996), 157; J. M.
Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001), 409.
[289] Theodor W. Adorno, Critical Models, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New
York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 191.
[290] Karl Jaspers, Kant, ed. Hannah Arendt, trans. Ralph Manheim (San
Diego: Harcourt, 1962), 65.
[291] Adorno, Critical Models, 191.
[292] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 365.
[293] Bernstein, Adorno, 387; quoted in Peter M. R. Stirk, Max
Horkheimer: A New Interpretation (Hertfordshire, UK: Harvester
Wheatsheaf, 1992), 190.
[294] Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment:
Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (1947; repr., Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 2002), 165; Adorno, Minima Moralia, 240.
[295] Emmanuel Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, or Beyond Essence, trans.
Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1998).
[296] Bernstein, Disenchantment and Ethics, 382.
[297] Bernstein, Adorno, 382, 394.
[298] Edmund Stillman and William Pfaff, The Politics of Hysteria (New
York: Harper and Row, 1964), 30â31.
[299] Zygmunt Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1989), 17.
[300] Ibid., 384; Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 362; Max Weber, From Max
Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970), 214â15.
[301] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 362.
[302] Adorno, Critical Models, 305.
[303] Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust, xiii.
[304] Rosa Luxemburg, The Rosa Luxemburg Reader, ed. Peter Hudis and
Kevin B. Anderson (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2004), 242â45; Hannah
Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism (1951; repr., San Diego, CA:
Harcourt, 1968), 206.
[305] Pierre Clastres, Society against the State (1974; repr., New York:
Zone Books: 1989), 99.
[306] Aimé Césaire, Discourse on Colonialism, trans. Joan Pinkham (1955;
repr., New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001), 36â37.
[307] Luxemburg, The Rosa Luxemburg Reader, 244â45; Mike Davis, Late
Victorian Holocausts: El Niño Famines and the Making of the Third World
(London: Verso, 2000).
[308] Fredric Jameson, Late Marxism: Adorno, or the Persistence of the
Dialectic (London: Verso, 1990), 4â5, 7.
[309] Gilbert Achcar, The Arabs and the Holocaust, trans. G. M.
Goshgarian (New York: Metropolitan, 2009), 132.
[310] Adorno, Critical Models, 192, 268.
[311] Theodor W. Adorno and Herbert Marcuse, âCorrespondence on the
German Student Movement,â New Left Review 1, no. 233 (JanuaryâFebruary
1999): 127.
[312] Theodor W. Adorno, Metaphysics: Concepts and Problems, trans.
Edmund Jephcott, ed. Rolf Tiedemann (1965; repr., Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press, 2000), 101.
[313] Claude Eatherly and GĂŒnther Anders, Burning Conscience (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 1962), 5.
[314] Franz Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National
Socialism, 1933â1944 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1944), 202.
[315] Goldhagen, Hitlerâs Willing Executioners, 59, 63.
[316] Norman G. Finkelstein and Ruth Bettina Birn, A Nation on Trial:
The Goldhagen Thesis and Historical Truth (New York: Henry Holt, 1998),
18â46.
[317] Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust, 73â74, 31, 78â79, 107â10.
[318] Nicolas Holliman, âNotes from the Steam Room: On the Origins of
Industrialised Killing during WWII,â Principia Dialectica, September 9,
2011.
[319] Richard A. Koenigsberg, Nations Have the Right to Kill (New York:
Library of Social Science, 2009).
[320] Adorno, Critical Models, 203; Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in
Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (1963; repr., New York:
Penguin, 2006), 21.
[321] Wilhelm Reich, The Mass Psychology of Fascism (New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux, 1970), 48â67, 104â14.
[322] Adorno, Critical Models, 201.
[323] Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem, 98; Ingrid Strobl, Partisanas
(1989; repr., Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2008).
[324] Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx: The State of Debt, the Work of
Mourning, and the New International, trans. Peggy Kamuf (New York:
Routledge, 1994), 106.
[325] Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto?,
trans. Rodney Livingstone (1989; repr., London: Verso, 2011), 47.
[326] Adorno, Critical Models, 192.
[327] Bill McKibben, Eaarth: Making a Life on a Tough New Planet (New
York: Times Books, 2010), 25.
[328] Maia Ramnath, introduction to Perspectives on Anarchist Theory 12,
no. 2 (Fall 2010): 4.
[329] Jean AmĂ©ry, At the Mindâs Limits: Contemplations by a Survivor on
Auschwitz and Its Realities, trans. Sidney Rosenfeld and Stella P.
Rosenfeld (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1980), 9; Giorgio
Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive, trans.
Daniel Heller-Roazen (New York: Zone Books, 2002), 41â86, 166â71.
[330] Wolfgang Sofsky, quoted in Bernstein, Adorno, 373.
[331] âU.S. Vows Sharp CO2 Cuts, But Will Not Pay Climate
âReparations,ââ Yale Environment 360, December 9, 2009; quoted in
Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem, 24.
[332] Quoted in Simon McGee, âAnger at Delegateâs Holocaust Jibe against
Climate Dealâas His Country Shares ÂŁ62bn Bonanza [sic],â Daily Mail,
December 20, 2009.
[333] Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 43.
[334] Noam Chomsky, Profit over People: Neoliberalism and Global Order
(New York: Seven Stories Press, 1999).
[335] Hannah Arendt, The Promise of Politics, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York:
Schocken Books, 2005), 120.
[336] Noam Chomsky and Ilan Pappé, Gaza in Crisis: Reflections on
Israelâs War against the Palestinians (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2010),
101.
[337] See, for example, Gideon Polya, âG8 Failure Means Climate Genocide
for Developing World,â Countercurrents, July 11, 2009; see also
http://sites.google.com/site/climategenocide/home
; quoted in Gwynne Dyer, Climate Wars (Toronto: Vintage Canada, 2009),
59.
[338] Violeta Davoliute and Ugur Ămit Ăngör, âGenocides?â Eurozine, July
7, 2011.
[339] Noam Chomsky, ââThe Evil Scourge of Terrorismâ: Reality,
Construction, Remedyâ (comments at the International Erich Fromm
Society, Stuttgart, March 23, 2010).
[340] Quoted in Ronald Aronson, Dialectics of Disaster: A Preface to
Hope (New York: Schocken Books, 1984), 164. The International War Crimes
Tribunal was orgnized by Bertrand Russell and hosted by Sartre.
[341] Giorgio Agamben, The Coming Community, trans. Michael Hardt
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993), 65.
[342] Damian Carrington, âClimate Change Concern Tumbles in US and
China,â Guardian, August 30, 2011; Suzanne Goldenberg, âMost Americans
Donât Believe Humans Responsible for Climate Change, Study Finds,â
Guardian, July 9, 2009; Suzanne Goldenberg, âNumber of Americans Who
Believe in Climate Change Drops, Survey Shows,â Guardian, October 22,
2009.
[343] Chris Hedges, Empire of Illusion (New York: Nation Books, 2009),
73.
[344] Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 167.
[345] Cornelius Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, trans. and ed.
David Ames Curtis (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 311, 340; Marcuse,
Negations, 14.
[346] Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust, 24.
[347] David Orr, Down to the Wire: Confronting Climate Collapse (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2009), 9.
[348] Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 404; Herbert Marcuse, The Aesthetic
Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1978), 73.
[349] Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Commonwealth (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2009), 212.
[350] Max Horkheimer, Between Philosophy and Social Science: Selected
Early Writings, trans. G. Frederick Hunter, Matthew S. Kramer, and John
Torpey (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), 25.
[351] Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust, 74â76.
[352] Albert Camus, The Rebel, trans. Anthony Bower (New York: Alfred
Knopf, 1956), 22.
[353] Neumann, Behemoth, 476.
[354] Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2001), 123.
[355] Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, ed. Leslie White Beck (1795;
repr., Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1957), appendix 1.
[356] Albert Memmi, The Colonizer and the Colonized (Boston: Beach
Press, 1965), 128.
[357] Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem, 233.
[358] Bernstein, Adorno, 407.
[359] Dyer, Climate Wars, 46.
[360] Reich, The Mass Psychology of Fascism, 326, 345, 282, 216, 32
(emphasis in original).
[361] Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New
York: Schocken Books, 2003), 147, 164, 180.
[362] Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem, 279.
[363] Arendt, The Promise of Politics, 99, 120, 43.
[364] Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, 189.
[365] Adorno, Critical Models, 195.
[366] John Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London: Pluto Press, 2010), 169.
[367] Max Horkheimer, Dawn and Decline: Notes, 1926â1931 and 1959â1969,
trans. Michael Shaw (New York: Seabury Press, 1978), 39.
[368] Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Humanism and Terror, trans. John OâNeill
(1947; repr., Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), 129.
[369] Herbert Marcuse, Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, trans.
Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968), 156.
[370] Yevgeny Zamyatin, We, trans. Clarence Brown (1924; repr., New
York: Penguin, 1993), 168.
[371] Bertolt Brecht, The Days of the Commune, trans. Clive Barker and
Arno Reinfrank (1955; repr., London: Methuen, 1978), 72.
[372] Walter Benjamin, Benjamin: Philosophy, Aesthetics, History, ed.
Gary Smith (1962; repr., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989),
66; Cornelius Castoriadis, The Rising Tide of Insignificancy (The Big
Sleep), 13, available at
http://www.notbored.org/RTI.pdf
.
[373] Noam Chomsky and Michel Foucault, The Chomsky-Foucault Debate: On
Human Nature (New York: New Press, 2006), 50.
[374] Theodor W. Adorno, History and Freedom, trans. Rodney Livingstone
(1964â65; repr., London: Polity Press, 2006), 149; Cornelius
Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, trans. and ed. David Ames Curtis
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 241.
[375] David Harvey, Enigma of Capital (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2009), 227; David Harvey, Spaces of Hope (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2000), 260â63.
[376] Takis Fotopoulos, âDirect Democracy and De-Growth,â International
Journal of Inclusive Democracy 6, no. 4 (Fall 2010).
[377] Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life,
trans. E.F.N. Jephcott (1951; repr., London: Verso, 1974), 156, 103
(translation modified).
[378] Arthur Schopenhauer, Suffering, Suicide, and Immortality: Eight
Essays from the Parerga, trans. T. Bailey Saunders (Mineola, NY: Dover,
2006), 16â17.
[379] Jean-Jacques Rousseau, âDiscourse on the Origin and Foundations of
Inequality among Men,â in Modern Political Thought: Readings from
Machiavelli to Nietzsche, ed. David Wootton (1755; repr., Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1996), 426.
[380] Noam Chomsky, Hegemony or Survival: Americaâs Quest for Global
Dominance (New York: Owl Books, 2004), 236.
[381] Renfrey Clark, âThe 350 ppm Carbon Dioxide Challenge and How to
Achieve It,â Links: International Journal of Socialist Renewal, January
14, 2010.
[382] Poorva Joshipura, âThis Earth Day, Go Vegan,â Guardian, April 22,
2010.
[383] Herbert Marcuse, Counterrevolution and Revolt (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1972), 265.
[384] Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization: A Philosophical Inquiry
into Freud (Boston: Beacon Press, 1966), 5.
[385] Brian Tokar, âMovements for Climate Action: Toward Utopia or
Apocalypse?â in Perspectives on Anarchist Theory 12, no. 2 (Fall 2010):
65.
[386] James Hansen, Storms of My Grandchildren (New York: Bloomsbury,
2009), 172â222.
[387] Minqi Li, The Rise of China and the Demise of the Capitalist World
Economy (New York: Monthly Review, 2008), 171â73.
[388] Hans Joachim Schellnhuber, âTerra Quasi-Incognita: Beyond the 2ÂșC
Lineâ (paper presented at the Oxford University 4 Degrees and Beyond
International Climate Change Conference, Oxford, September 28, 2009);
Ted Trainer, Renewable Energy Cannot Sustain a Consumer Society
(Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer, 2007), 126.
[389] Peter D. Schwartzman and David D. Schwartzman, A Solar Transition
Is Possible (London: Institute for Policy Research and Development,
2011).
[390] Lester Brown, World on the Edge: How to Prevent Environmental and
Economic Collapse (New York: W. W. Norton, 2011), 116â35.
[391] Mark Jacobson and Mark Delucchi, âA Plan to Power 100 Percent of
the Planet with Renewables,â Scientific American, October 26, 2009;
Fiona Harvey, âRenewable Energy Can Power the World, Says Landmark IPCC
Study,â Guardian, May 9, 2011.
[392] Justin McCurry, âJapan Doubles Fukushima Radiation Leak Estimate,â
Guardian, June 7, 2011.
[393] Dahr Jamail, âFukushima: Itâs Much Worse Than You Think,â Al
Jazeera English, June 16, 2011.
[394] David Schwartzman, âSolar Communism,â Science and Society 60, no.
3 (Fall 1996): 307â31.
[395] Trainer, Renewable Energy.
[396] Elizabeth Kolbert, Field Notes from a Catastrophe: Man, Nature,
and Climate Change (New York: Bloomsbury, 2006); Kim Stanley Robinson,
Red Mars (New York: Bantam Spectra, 1993).
[397] Murray Bookchin, The Ecology of Freedom (1982; repr., Oakland, CA:
AK Press, 2005), 349.
[398] Murray Bookchin, Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Oakland, CA: AK Press,
2004), iii, ix; Murray Bookchin, Toward an Ecological Society (Montreal:
Black Rose, 1980), 67.
[399] George Monbiot, Heat: How to Stop the Planet from Burning
(Cambridge, MA: South End Press, 2009), 170â88; âSolar-Powered Blimp Set
to Fly across Channel,â Guardian, July 8, 2009; âSolar Impulse Completes
24-Hour Flight,â Guardian, July 8, 2010.
[400] âSolar-Powered Boat TĂŒranor Raises Hopes of a Sun-Fuelled Future,â
Guardian, April 1, 2010.
[401] Jason Adams, âNon-Western Anarchisms: Rethinking the Global
Contextâ (Johannesburg: Zabalaza Books), 118; Paul Sharkey, The
Federacion Anarquista Uruguaya (FAU): Crisis, Armed Struggle and
Dictatorship, 1967â1985 (Berkeley, CA: Kate Sharpley Library, 2009).
[402] Noam Chomsky, Hopes and Prospects (Chicago: Haymarket Books,
2010), 118.
[403] Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2000), 413.
[404] Noam Chomsky, âStudents Should Become Anarchists,â June 14, 2011,
available at http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20110614_en.htm.
[405] On grain requisition, see Orlando Figes, A Peopleâs Tragedy: The
Russian Revolution, 1891â1924 (New York: Penguin, 1996), 775â80. On the
repression of anarchists, see Emma Goldman, My Two Years in Russia
(Saint Petersburg, FL: Red and Black Publishers, 1924), 199â209; Paul
Avrich, The Russian Anarchists (1967; repr., Oakland, CA: AK Press,
2005), 222â25. On the fate of the soviets, see Figes, A Peopleâs
Tragedy, 684â90. On Kronstadt and the Makhnovshchina, see Paul Avrich,
Kronstadt 1921 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970); Paul
Avrich, The Russian Anarchists (New York: W. W. Norton, 1980), 220â21;
Alexandre Skirda, Nestor MakhnoâAnarchyâs Cossack: The Struggle for Free
Soviets in the Ukraine, 1917â1921 (Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2003).
[406] Subcomandante Insurgente Marcos, Nuestra Arma es Nuestra Palabra,
ed. Juana Ponce de LeĂłn (New York: Siete Cuentos Editorial, 2001), 103.
[407] Quoted in Hannah Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism (1951; repr.,
San Diego: Harcourt, 1968), 473.
[408] Arundhati Roy and David Barsamian, The Checkbook and the Cruise
Missile (Cambridge, MA: South End Press, 2004), 156.
[409] Derrida, Specters of Marx, 106â7.
[410] Georg LukĂĄcs, Destruction of Reason (Torfaen, Wales: Merlin Press,
1980), 850â52.
[411] C.L.R. James, The Black Jacobins (1938; repr., London: Penguin,
2001), 215.
[412] Robert W. Stookey, South Yemen: A Marxist Republic in Arabia
(Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1982); Fred Halliday, Revolution and
Foreign Policy: The Case of South Yemen, 1967â1987 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990).
[413] Glenn Greenwald, âWikileaks Cables and the Iraq War,â Salon,
October 23, 2011.
[414] Nick Davies, âAfghanistan War Logs: Task Force 373âSpecial Forces
Hunting Top Taliban,â Guardian, July 25, 2010; Damian Carrington,
âWikiLeaks Cables Reveal How US Manipulated Climate Accord,â Guardian,
December 3, 2010; âWikiLeaks Cables Reveal U.S. Efforts to Defend
Cluster Bombs around the World,â Democracy Now! September 19, 2011.
[415] Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of Reason (1947; repr., London: Continuum,
2004), 108; see also Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, 251; Warner
Sachs, âGlobal Ecology and the Shadow of âDevelopment,ââ in Global
Ecology: A New Arena of Political Conflict (London: Zed, 1993), 3â21.
[416] Andrew Cornell, Oppose and Propose! Lessons from Movement for a
New Society (Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2011).
[417] âIndia Anti-nuclear Protest Turns Violent,â Al Jazeera English,
April 20, 2011; âProtest against Koodankulam Nuclear Plant in Pictures,â
Countercurrents, September 19, 2011; Nirmala Ganapathy, âAnti-nuclear
Protests Gain Strength in India,â Asia News Network, November 14, 2011.
[418] Helen Pidd, âGermany to Shut All Nuclear Reactors,â Guardian, May
30, 2011.
[419] Murray Bookchin, The Philosophy of Social Ecology: Essays on
Dialectical Naturalism (Montreal: Black Rose, 1990), 132; Murray
Bookchin and Janet Biehl, âAdvisory Board Resignation Letter,â Democracy
and Nature 3, no. 3 (1997).
[420] A.G. Schwarz, Tasos Sagris, and Void Network, eds., We Are an
Image from the Future: The Greek Revolt of December 2008 (Oakland, CA:
AK Press, 2010), 334.
[421] Adorno, Minima Moralia, 60.
[422] Hannah Arendt, The Promise of Politics, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York:
Schocken Books, 2005), 96.
[423] Ramor Ryan, Zapatista Spring (Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2011), 48,
208â11; Niels Barmeyer, Developing Zapatista Autonomy (Albuquerque:
University of New Mexico Press, 2009).
[424] Aliza Marcus, Blood and Belief: The PKK and the Kurdish Fight for
Independence (New York: New York University Press, 2007), 222.
[425] Ibid., 89â96, 111, 172â74, 301â5.
[426] Rabindra Ray, The Naxalites and Their Ideology (Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1988), 230.
[427] Samir Amin, â2011: An Arab Springtime?â Monthly Review, June 2,
2011, available at
http://monthlyreview.org/commentary/2011-an-arab-springtime.
[428] Ibid.
[429] Gilbert Achcar, The Arabs and the Holocaust, trans. G. M.
Goshgarian (New York: Metropolitan, 2009), 244â45.
[430] Ramachandra Guha, India after Gandhi: The History of the Worldâs
Largest Democracy (New York: HarperCollins, 2007), 108â10.
[431] Ibid., 423â27.
[432] Samarendra Das and Felix Patel, Out of This Earth: East India
Adivasis and the Aluminum Cartel (New Delhi: Orient BlackSwan, 2010).
[433] Ray, The Naxalites; Arundhati Roy, Broken Republic (New Delhi:
Penguin, 2011).
[434] Roy, Broken Republic, 121.
[435] Jason Burke, âMore of Worldâs Poor Live in India Than in All
Sub-Saharan Africa, Says Study,â Guardian, July 26, 2010.
[436] Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and
the State (1891; repr., New York: Pathfinder, 1972), 61â83.
[437] Douglas Fry, Beyond War: The Human Potential for Peace (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007).
[438] Albert Einstein, âWhy Socialism?â Monthly Review, May 1949.
[439] Theodor W. Adorno, Problems of Moral Philosophy, trans. Rodney
Livingstone (1963; repr., Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,
2001), 150.
[440] Pierre Clastres, Archeology of Violence, trans. Jeanine Herman
(1980; repr., New York: Semiotext[e], 1994); Giorgio Agamben, Remnants
of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen
(New York: Zone Books, 2002), 63â64.
[441] Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other
Writings, 1972â1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon Books, 1980),
121.
[442] James C. Scott, The Art of Not Being Governed (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 2009).
[443] Harvey, Enigma of Capital, 260, 248.
[444] Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism; Wilhelm Reich, Mass Psychology
of Fascism (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1970).
[445] Andrew Glikson, âThe Atmosphere Is Not Waiting for Human
Decision,â Countercurrents, November 30, 2009.
[446] Mark Carey, In the Shadow of Melting Glaciers: Climate Change and
Andean Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 18.
[447] Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1958), 256.
[448] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton
(London: Routledge, 1973), 404.