đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș henri-lefebvre-right-to-the-city.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:47:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Right to the City Author: Henri Lefebvre Date: 1968 (*Le Droit Ă la ville*), 1996 (English translation as *The Right to the City*) Language: en Topics: right to the city, urbanism, Marxism, municipalism, grassroots organizing, community organizing, right to the city, dialectics, the city, revolution, libertarian marxism, not anarchist Source: Chapters 2â17 from *Writings on Cities*, Selected, translated and introduced by Eleonore Kofman and Elizabeth Lebas. Notes: The âright to the cityâ is an idea and a slogan that was first proposed by Henri Lefebvre in his 1968 book *Le Droit Ă la ville* and that has been reclaimed more recently by social movements, thinkers and several progressive local authorities alike as a call to action to reclaim the city as a to-created space â a place for life detached from the growing effects that commodification and capitalism have had over social interaction and the rise of spatial inequalities in worldwide cities throughout the last two centuries. While Lefebvre never identified with libertarian Marxism, his conceptual framework of Right to the City is of use to a libertarian Marxist reading.
Great things must be silenced or talked about with grandeur, that is,
with cynicism and innocence...
I would claim as property and product of man all the beauty, nobility,
which we have given to real or imaginary things...
â Frederic Nietzsche
This work will take an offensive form (that some will perhaps find
offending). Why?
Because conceivably each reader will already have in mind a set of ideas
systematized or in the process of being systematized. Conceivably, each
reader is looking for a âsystemâ or has found his âsystemâ. The System
is fashionable, as much in thought as in terminologies and language.
Now all systems tend to close off reflection, to block off horizon. This
work wants to break up systems, not to substitute another system, bur to
open up through thought and action towards possibilities by showing the
horizon and the road. Against a form of reflection which tends towards
formalism, a thought which tends towards an opening leads the struggle.
Urbanism, almost as much as the system, is fashionable. Urbanistic
questions and reflections are coming out of circles of technicians,
specialists, intellectuals who see themselves as at the âavant-gardeâ.
They enter the public domain through newspaper articles and writings of
diverse import and ambitions. At one and the same time urbanism becomes
ideology and practice. Meanwhile, questions relative to the city and to
urban reality are not fully known and recognized, they have not yet
acquired politically the importance and the meaning that they have in
thought (in ideology) and in practice (we shall show an urban strategy
already at work and in action). This little book does not only propose
to critically analyse thoughts and activities related to urbanism. Itâs
aim is to allow its problems to enter into consciousness and political
policies.
From the theoretical and practical situation of problems (from the
problematic) concerning the city, reality and possibilities of urban
life, let us begin by taking what used to the called a âcavalier
attitudeâ.
To present and give an account of the âurban problematicâ, the point of
departure must be the process of industrialization. Beyond any doubt
this process has been the dynamic of transformations in society for the
last century and a half. If one distinguishes between the inductor and
the induced, one can say that the process of industrialization is
inductive and that one can count among the induced, problems related to
growth and planning, questions concerning the city and the development
of the urban reality, without omitting the growing importance of leisure
activities and questions related in âcultureâ. Industrialization
characterizes modern society. This does not inevitably carry with it
terms of âindustrial societyâ, if we want to define it. Although
urbanization and the problematic of the urban figure among the induced
effects and not among the causes or inductive reason, the preoccupation
these words signify accentuate themselves in such a way that one can
define as an urban society the social reality which arises around us.
This definition retains a feature which becomes capital.
Industrialization provides the point of departure for reflection upon
our time. Now the city existed prior to industrialization. A remark
banal in itself but whose implications have not been fully formulated.
The most eminent urban creations, the most âbeautifulâ oeuvres of urban
life (we say âbeautiful,â because they are oeuvres rather than products)
date from epochs previous to that of industrialization. There was the
oriental city (linked to the Asiatic mode of production), the antique
city (Greek and Roman associated with the possession of slaves) and then
the medieval city (in a complex situation embedded in feudal relations
but struggling against a landed feudalism). The oriental and antique
city was essentially political; the medieval city, without losing its
political character, was principally related to commerce, crafts and
banking. It absorbed merchants, who had previously been quasi nomadic
and relegated outside the city.
When industrialization begins, and capitalism in competition with a
specifically industrial bourgeoisie is born, the city is already a
powerful reality. In Western Europe, after the virtual disappearance of
the antique city, the decay of Roman influence, the city took off again.
More or less nomadic merchants elected as centre of their activities
what remained of the antique urban cores. Conversely, one can suppose
that these degraded cores functioned as accelerators for what remained
of exchange economies maintained by wandering merchants. From the
growing surplus product of agriculture, to the detriment of feudal
lords, cities accumulate riches: objects, treasures, virtual capitals.
There already existed in these urban centres a great monetary wealth,
acquired through usury and and commerce. Crafts prosper there, a
production clearly distinct from agriculture. Cities support peasant
communities and the enfranchisement of the peasants, not without benefit
for themselves. In short, they are centres of social and political life
where not only wealth is accumulated, but knowledge (connaissances),
techniques, and oeuvres (works of art, monuments). This city is itself
âoeuvreâ, a feature which contrasts with the irreversible tendency
towards money and commerce, towards exchange and products. Indeed the
oeuvre is use value and the the product is exchange value. The eminent
use of the city, that is, of its streets and squares, edifices and
monuments, is la fĂȘte (a celebration which consumes unproductively,
without other advantage but pleasure and prestige and enormous riches in
money and objects).
A complex, but contradictory, reality. Medieval cities at the height of
their development centralize wealth: powerful groups invest
unproductively a large part of their wealth in the cities they dominate.
At the same time, banking and commercial capital have already made
wealth mobile and has established exchange networks enabling the
transfer of money. When industrialization begins with the pre-eminence
of a specific bourgeoisie (the entrepreneurs), wealth has ceased to be
mainly in real estate. Agricultural production is no longer dominant and
nor is landed property. Estates are lost to the feudal lords and pass
into the hands of urban capitalises enriched by commerce, banking,
usury. The outcome is that âsocietyâ as a whole, made up of the city,
the country and the institutions which regulate their relations, tend to
constitute themselves as a network of cities, with a certain division of
labour (technically, socially, politically) between cities linked
together by road, river and seaways and by commercial and banking
relations. One can think that the division of labour between cities was
neither sufficiently advanced nor sufficiently aware to determine stable
associations and put an end to to rivalries and competition. This urban
system was not able to establish itself. What is erected on chis base is
the State, or centralized power. Cause and effect of this particular
centrality, that of power, one city wins over the others: the capital.
Such a process takes place very unevenly, very differently in Italy,
Germany, France, Flanders, England, and Spain. The city predominates and
yet it is no longer the City-State of antiquity. There are three
different terms: society, State and city. In this urban system each city
tends to constitute itself as an enclosed self-contained,
self-functioning system. The city preserves the organic character of
community which comes from the village and which translates itself into
a corporate organization (or guild). Community life (comprising general
or partial assemblies) does not prohibit class struggle. On the
contrary. Violent contrasts between wealth and poverty, conflicts
between the powerful and the oppressed, do not prevent either attachment
to the city nor an active contribution to the beauty of the oeuvre. In
the urban context, struggles between fractions, groups and classes
strengthen the feeling of belonging. Political confrontations between
the âminuto popoloâ the âpopolo grossoâ, the aristocracy and the
oligarchy, have the city as their battle ground, their stake. These
groups are rivals in their love of the city. As for the rich and
powerful, they always feel threatened. They justify their privilege in
the community by somptuously spending their fortune: buildings,
foundations, palaces, embellishments, festivities. It is important to
emphasize this paradox, for it is not a well understood historical fact:
very oppressive societies were very creative and rich in producing
oeuvres. Later, the production of products replaced the production of
oeuvres and the social relations attached to them, notably the city.
When exploitation replaces oppression, creative capacity disappears. The
very notion of âcreationâ is blurred or degenerates by miniaturizing
itself into âmakingâ and âcreativityâ (the âdo-it-yourself,â etc.).
Which brings forth arguments to back up a thesis: city and urban reality
are related to use value. Exchange value and the generalization of
commodities by industrialization tend to destroy it by subordinating the
city and urban reality which are refuges of use value, the origins of a
virtual predominance and revalorization of use.
In the urban system we are attempting to analyse, action is exercized
over specific conflicts: between use value and exchange value, between
mobilization of wealth (in silver and in money) and unproductive
investment in the city, between accumulation of capital and its
squandering on festivities, between the extension of the dominated
territory and the demands of a strict organization of this territory
around the dominating city. The latter protects itself against all
eventualities by a corporate organization which paralyses the
initiatives of banking and commercial capitalism. The coporarion does
not only regulate a craft. Each enters into an organic whole: the
corporate system regulates the distribution of actions and activities
over urban space (streets and neighbourhoods) and urban time (timetables
and festivities). This whole tends to congeal itself into an immutable
structure. The outcome of which is that industrialization supposes the
destructuration of existing structures. Historians (since Marx) have
showed the fixed nature of guilds. What perhaps remains to be shown is
the tendency of the whole urban system towards a sort of crystallization
and fixation. Where this system consolidated itself, capitalism and
industrialization came late: in Germany, in Italy, a delay full of
consequences.
There is therefore a certain discontinuity between an emerging industry
and its historical conditions. They are neither the same thing nor the
same people. The prodigious growth of exchanges, of a monetary economy,
of merchant production, of the âworld of commoditiesâ which will result
from industrialization, implies a radical change. The passage of
commercial and banking capitalism as well as craft production to
industrial production and competitive capitalism is accompanied by a
gigantic crisis, well studied by historians, except for what relates to
the city and the âurban systemâ.
Emerging industry tends to establish itself outside cities. Not that it
is an absolute law. No law can be totally general and absolute. This
setting up of industrial enterprises, at first sporadic and dispersed,
depended on multiple local regional and national circumstances. For
example, printing seems to have been able in an urban context to go from
a craft to the private enterprise stage. It was, otherwise for the
textile industry, for mining, for metallurgy. The new industry
establishes itself near energy sources (rivers, woods then charcoal),
means of transport (rivers and canals, then railways), raw materials
(minerals), pools of labour power (peasant crahmen, weavers and
blacksmiths already providing skilled labour).
There still exist today in France numerous small textile centres
(valleys in Normandy and the Vosges, etc.) which survive sometimes with
difficulty. Is it not remarkable that a part of the heavy metallurgical
industry was established in the valley of the Moselle, between two old
cities, Nancy and Metz, the only real urban centres of this industrial
region? At the same time old cities are markets, sources of available
capital, the place where these capitals are managed (banks), the
residences of economic and political leaders, reservoirs of labour (that
is, the places where can subsist âthe reserve army of labourâ as Marx
calls it, which weighs on wages and enables the growth of surplus
value). Moreover, the city, as workshop, allows the concentration over a
limited space of the means of production: cools, raw materials, labour.
Since settlement outside of cities is not satisfactory for
âentrepreneursâ, as soon as it is possible industry comes closer to
urban centres. Inversely, the city prior to industrialization
accelerates the process (in particular, it enables the rapid growth of
productivity). The city has therefore played an important role in the
take-off of industry. As Marx explained, urban concentrations have
accompanied the concentration of capital. Industry was to produce its
own urban centres, sometimes small cities and industrial agglomerations
(le Creusot), at times medium-sized (Saint-Etienne) or gigantic (the
Ruhr, considered as a âconurbationâ). We shall come back to the
deterioration of the centrality and urban character in these cities.
This process appears, in analysis, in all its complexity, which the word
âindustrializationâ represents badly. This complexity becomes apparent
as soon as one ceases to think in terms of private enterprise on the one
hand and global production statistics (so many tons of coal, steel) on
the other â as soon as one reflects upon the distinction between the
inductor and the induced, by observing the importance of the phenomena
induced and their interaction with the inductors. Industry can do
without the old city (pre-industrial, precapitalist) but does so by
constituting agglomerations in which urban features are deteriorating.
Is this not the case in North America where âcitiesâ in the way they are
understood in France and in Europe, are few: New York, Montreal, San
Francisco? Nevertheless, where there is a pre-existent network of old
cities, industry assails it. It appropriates this network and refashions
it according to its needs. It also attacks the city (each city),
assaults it, takes it, ravages it. It tends to break up the old cores by
taking them over. This does not prevent the extension of urban
phenomena, cities and agglomerations, industrial towns and suburbs (with
the addition of shanty towns where industrialization is unable to employ
and fix available labour).
We have before us a double process or more precisely, a process with two
aspects: industrialization and urbanization, growth and development,
economic production and social life. The two âaspectsâ of this
inseparable process have a unity, and yet it is a conflictual process.
Historically there is a violent clash between urban reality and
industrial reality. As for the complexity of the process, it reveals
itself more and more difficult to grasp, given that industrialization
does not only produce firms (workers and leaders of private
enterprises), but various offices â banking, financial, technical and
political.
This dialectical process, far from being clear, is also far from over.
Today it still provokes âproblematicâ situations. A few examples would
be sufficient here. In Venice, the active population leaves the city for
the industrial agglomeration which parallels it on the mainland: Mestre.
This city among the most beautiful cities bequeathed to us from
pre-industrial times is threatened not so much by physical deterioration
due to the sea or to its subsidence, as by the exodus of its
inhabitants. In Athens a quite considerable industrialization has
attracted to the capital people from small towns and peasants. Modern
Athens has nothing more in common with the antique city covered over,
absorbed, extended beyond measure. The monuments and sites (agora,
Acropolis) which enable to locate ancient Greece are only places of
tourist consumption and aesthetic pilgrimage. Yet the organizational
core of the city remains very strong. Its surroundings of new
neighbourhoods and semi-shanty towns inhabited by uprooted and
disorganized people confer it an exorbitant power. This almost shapeless
gigantic agglomeration enables the holders of decision-making centres to
carry out the worst political ventures. All the more so that the economy
of the country closely depends on this network: property speculation,
the âcreationâ of capitals by this means, investments of these capitals
into construction and so on and so forth. It is this fragile network,
always in danger of breaking, which defines a type of urbanization,
without or with a weak industrialization, but with a rapid extension of
the agglomeration, of property and speculation; a prosperity falsely
maintained by the network.
We could in France cite many cities which have been recently submerged
by industrialization: Grenoble, Dunkirk, etc. In other cases, such as
Toulouse, there has been a massive extension of the city and
urbanization (understood in the widest sense of the term) with little
industrialization. Such is also the general case of Latin American and
African cities encircled by shanty towns. In these regions and countries
old agrarian structures are dissolving: dispossessed or ruined peasants
crowd into these cities to find work and subsistence. Now these peasants
come from farms destined to disappear because of world commodity prices,
these being closely linked to industrialized countries and âgrowth
polesâ. These phenomena are still dependent on industrialization.
An induced process which one could call the âimplosion-explosionâ of the
city is at present deepening. The urban phenomenon extends itself over a
very large part of the territory of great industrial countries. It
happily crosses national boundaries: the Megalopolis of Northern Europe
extends from the Ruhr to the sea and even to English cities, and from
the Paris region to the Scandinavian countries. The urban fabric of this
territory becomes increasingly tight, although not without its local
differentiations and extension of the (technical and social) division of
labour to the regions, agglomerations and cities. At the same time,
there and even elsewhere, urban concentrations become gigantic:
populations are heaped together reaching worrying densities (in surface
and housing units). Again at the same time many old urban cores are
deteriorating or exploding. People move to distant residential or
productive peripheries. Offices replace housing in urban centres.
Sometimes (in the United States) these centres are abandoned to the
âpoorâ and become ghettos for the underprivileged. Sometimes on the
contrary, the most affluent people retain their strong positions at the
heart of the city (around Central Park in New York, the Marais in
Paris).
Let us now examine the urban fabric. This metaphor is not clear. More
than a fabric thrown over a territory, these words designate a kind of
biological proliferation of a net of uneven mesh, allowing more or less
extended sectors to escape: hamlets or villages, entire regions. If
these phenomena are placed into the perspective of the countryside and
old agrarian structures, one can analyse a general movement of
concentration: from populations in boroughs and small and large towns â
of property and exploitation â of the organization of transports and
commercial exchanges, etc. This leads at the same time to the
depopulation and the âloss of the peasantryâ from the villages which
remain rural while losing what was peasant life: crafts, small local
shops. Old âways of lifeâ become folklore. If the same phenomena are
analysed from the perspective of cities, one can observe not only the
extension of highly populated peripheries but also of banking,
commercial and industrial networks and of housing (second homes, places
and spaces of leisure, etc.).
The urban fabric can be described by using the concept of ecosystem, a
coherent unity constituted around one or several cities, old and recent.
Such a description may lose what is essential. Indeed, the significance
of the urban fabric is not limited to its morphology. It is the support
of a more or less intense, more or less degraded, âway of lifeâ: urban
society. On the economic base of the urban fabric appear phenomena of
another order, that of social and âculturalâ life. Carried by the urban
fabric, urban society and life penetrate the countryside. Such a way of
living entails systems of objects and of values. The best known elements
of the urban system of objects include water, electricity, gas (butane
in the countryside), not to mention the car, the television, plastic
utensils, âmodernâ furniture, which entail new demands with regard to
âservicesâ. Among the elements of the system of values we can note urban
leisure (dance and song), suits, the rapid adoption of fashions from the
city. And also, preoccupations with security, the need to predict the
future, in brief, a rationality communicated by the city. Generally
youth, as an age group, actively contributes to this rapid assimilation
of things and representations coming from the city. These are
sociological trivialities which are useful to remember to show their
implications. Within the mesh of the urban fabric survive islets and
islands of âpureâ rurality, often (but not always) poor areas peopled
with ageing peasants, badly âintegratedâ, stripped of what had been the
nobility of peasant life in times of greatest misery and of oppression.
The âurban-ruralâ relation does not disappear. On the contrary, it
intensifies itself down to the most industrialized countries. It
interferes with other representations and other real relations: town and
country, nature and artifice, etc. Here and there tensions become
conflicts, latent conflicts are accentuated, and then what was hidden
under the urban fabric appears in the open.
Moreover, urban cores do not disappear. The fabric erodes them or
integrates them to its web. These cores survive by transforming
themselves. There are still centres of intense urban life such as the
Latin Quarter in Paris. The aesthetic qualities of these urban cores
play an important role in their maintenance. They do not only contain
monuments and institutional headquarters, but also spaces appropriated
for entertainments, parades, promenades, festivities. In this way the
urban core becomes a high quality consumption product for foreigners,
tourists, people from the outskirts and suburbanites. It survives
because of this double role: as place of consumption and consumption of
place. Thus centres enter more completely into exchange and exchange
value, not without retaining their use value due to spaces provided for
specific activities. They become centres of consumption. The
architectural and urbanistic resurgence of the commercial centre only
gives a dull and mutilated version of what was the core of the old city,
at one and the same time commercial, religious, intellectual, political
and economic (productive). The notion and image of the commercial centre
in fact date from the Middle Ages. It corresponds to the small and
medium-sized medieval city. But today exchange value is so dominant over
use and use value that it more or less suppresses it. There is nothing
original in this notion. The creation which corresponds to our times, to
their tendencies and (threatening) horizons is it not the centre of
decision-making? This centre, gathering together training and
information, capacities of organization and institutional
decision-making, appears as a project in the making of a new centrality,
chat of power. The greatest attention must be paid to this concept, the
practice which it denotes and justifies.
We have in fact a number of terms (at least three) in complex relations
with each other, definable by oppositions each on their own terms,
although not exhausted by these oppositions. There is the rural and the
urban (urban society). There is the urban fabric which carries this
âurbannessâ and centrality, old, renovated, new. Hence a disquieting
problematic, particularly if one wishes to go from analysis to
synthesis, from observations to a project (the ânormativeâ). Must one
allow the urban fabric (what does this word mean?) to proliferate
spontaneously? Is it appropriate to capture this force, direct this
strange life, savage and artificial at the same time? How can one
strengthen the centres? Is it useful or necessary? And which centres,
which centralities? Finally, what is to be done about islands of
ruralism?
Thus the crisis of the city can be perceived through distinct problems
and problematical whole. This is a theoretical and practical crisis. In
theory, the concept of the city (of urban reality) is made up of facts,
representations and images borrowed from the ancient pre-industrial and
precapitalist city, but in a process of transformation and new
elaboration. In practice the urban core (an essential part of the image
and the concept of the city) splits open and yet maintains itself:
overrun, often deteriorated, sometimes rotting, the urban core does not
disappear. If someone proclaims its end and its reabsorption into the
fabric, this is a postulate, a statement without proof. In the same way,
if someone proclaims the urgency of a restitution or reconstitution of
urban cores, it is again a postulate, a statement without proof. The
urban core has not given way to a new and well-defined ârealityâ, as the
village allowed the city to be born. And yet its reign seems to be
ending. Unless it asserts itself again even more strongly as centre of
power...
Until now we have shown how the city has been attacked by
industrialization, giving a dramatic and globally considered picture of
this process. This analytical attempt could lead us to believe that it
is a natural process, without intentions or volitions. There is
something like this, but that vision would be truncated. The ruling
classes or fractions of the ruling classes intervene actively and
voluntarily in this process, possessing capital (the means of
production) and managing not only the economic use of capital and
productive investments, but also the whole society, using part of the
wealth produced in âcultureâ, art, knowledge, ideology. Beside, or
rather, in opposition to, dominant social groups (classes and class
fractions), there is the working class: the proletariat, itself divided
into strata, partial groups, various tendencies, according to industrial
sectors and local and national traditions.
In the middle of the nineteenth century in Paris the situation was
somewhat like this. The ruling bourgeoisie, a non-homogenous class,
after a hard-fought struggle, has conquered the capital. Today the
Marais is still a visible witness to this: before the Revolution it is
an aristocratic quarter (despite the tendency of the capital and the
wealthy to drift towards the west), an area of gardens and private
mansions. It took but a few years, during the 1830s, for the Third
Estate to appropriate it. A number of magnificem houses disappear,
workshops and shops occupy others, tenements, stores, depots and
warehouses, firms replace parks and gardens. Bourgeois ugliness, the
greed for gain visible and legible in the streets takes the place of a
somewhat cold beauty and aristocratic luxury. On the walls of the Marais
can be read class struggle and the hatred between classes, a victorious
meanness. It is impossible to make more perceptible this paradox of
history which partially escaped Marx. The âprogressiveâ bourgeoisie
taking charge of economic growth, endowed with ideological instruments
suited to rational growth, moves towards democracy and replaces
oppression by exploitation, this class as such no longer creates â it
replaces the oeuvre, by the product. Those who retain this sense of the
oeuvre, including writers and painters, think and see themselves as ânon
bourgeoisâ. As for oppressors, the masters of societies previous to the
democratic bourgeoisie â princes, kings, lords, emperors â they had a
sense and a taste of the oeuvre, especially in architecture and urban
design. In fact the oeuvre is more closely related to use value than to
exchange value.
After 1848, the French bourgeoisie solidly entrenched in the city
(Paris) possesses considerable influence, but it sees itself hemmed in
by the working class. Peasants flock in, settling around the âbarriersâ
and entrances of the fortifications, the immediate periphery. Former
craftsmen and new proletarians penetrate right up to the heart of the
city. They live in slums but also in tenements, where the better-off
live on the ground floors and the workers on the upper ones. In this
âdisorderâ the workers threaten the âparvenusâ, a danger which became
obvious during the days of June 1848 and which the Commune was to
confirm. A class strategy is elaborated, aimed at the replanning of the
city, without any regard for reality, for its own life.
The life of Paris reaches its greatest intensity between 1848 and the
Haussmann period â not what is understood by âla vie parisienneâ, but
the urban life of the capital. It engages itself into literature and
poetry with great vigour and power. Then it will be over. Urban life
suggests meetings, the confrontation of differences, reciprocal
knowledge and acknowledgement (including ideological and political
confrontation), ways of living, âpatternsâ which coexist in the city.
During the nineteenth century, a democracy of peasant origins which
drove the revolutionaries could have transformed itself into an urban
democracy. It was and it is still for history one of the beliefs of the
Commune. As urban democracy threatened the privileges of the new ruling
class, that class prevented it from being born. How? By expelling from
the urban centre and the city itself the proletariat, by destroying
âurbanityâ.
Act One. Baron Haussmann, man of this Bonapartist State which erects
itself over society to treat it cynically as the booty (and not only the
stake) of the struggles for power. Haussmann replaces winding but lively
streets by long avenues, sordid but animated âquartiersâ by bourgeois
ones. If he forces through boulevards and plans open spaces, it is not
for the beauty of views. It is to âcomb Paris with machine gunsâ. The
famous Baron makes no secret of it. Later we will be greateful to him
for having opened up Paris to traffic. This was not the aim, the
finality of Haussmann âplanningâ. The voids have a meaning: they cry out
loud and dear the glory and power of the State which plans them, the
violence which could occur. Later transfers towards other finalities
take place which justify in another way these gashes into urban life. It
should be noted that Haussmann did not achieve his goal. One strong
aspect of the Paris Commune (1871) is the strength of the return towards
the urban centre of workers pushed out towards the outskirts and
peripheries, their reconquest of the city, this belonging among other
belongings, this value, this oeuvre which had been torn from them.
Act Two. The goal was to be attained by a much vaster manoeuvre and with
more important results. In the second half of the century, influential
people, that is rich or powerful, or both, sometimes ideologues (Le
Play) with ideas strongly marked by religions (Catholic and Protestant),
sometimes informed politicians (belonging to the centre right) and who
moreover do not constitute a coherent and unique group, in brief, a few
notables, discover a new notion. The Third Republic will insure its
fortune, that is, its realization on the ground. It will conceive the
notion of habitat. Until then, âto inhabitâ meant to take part in a
social life, a community, village or city. Urban life had, among other
qualities, this attribute. It gave the right to inhabit, it allowed
townsmen-citizens to inhabit. It is thus that âmortals inhabit while
they save the earth, while they wait for the gods ... while they conduct
their lives in preservation and useâ. Thus speaks the poet and
philosopher Heidegger of the concept to inhabit. Outside philosophy and
poetry the same things have been said sociologically in prose. At the
end of the nineteenth century the notables isolate a function, detach it
from a very complex whole which was and remains the city, to project it
over the ground, not without showing and signifying in this manner the
society for which they provide an ideology and a practice. Certainly
suburbs were created under the pressure of circumstances to respond to
the blind (although motivated and directed) growth of industrialization,
the massive arrival of peasants led to the urban centres by ârural
exodusâ. The process has none the less been oriented by a strategy.
A typical class strategy, does that mean a series of concerted actions,
planned with a single aim? No. Class character seems that much deeper
than several concerted actions, centered around several objectives, has
nevertheless converged towards a final result. It goes without saying
that all these notables were not proposing to open up a means to
speculation: some of them, men of good will, philanthropists, humanists,
seem even to wish the opposite. They have none the less mobilized
property wealth around the city, the entrance without restriction into
exchange and exchange value of the ground and housing. This had
speculative implications. They were not proposing to demoralize the
working classes, but on the contrary, to moralize it. They considered it
beneficial to involve the workers (individuals and families) into a
hierarchy clearly distinct from that which rules in the firm, that of
property and landlords, houses and neighbourhoods. They wanted to give
them another function, another status, other roles than those attached
to the condition of the salaried producers. They meant in this way to
give them a better everyday life than that of work. In this way they
conceived the role of owner-occupied housing. A remarkably successful
operation (although its political consequences were not always those
anticipated by its promoters). Nevertheless, a result was achieved,
predicted or otherwise, conscious or unconscious. Society orients itself
ideologically and practically towards other problems than that of
production. Little by little social consciousness ceased to refer to
production and to focus on everyday life and consumption. With
âsuburbanizationâ a process is set into motion which decentres the city.
Isolated from the city, the proletariat will end its sense of the
oeuvre. Isolated from places of production, available from a sector of
habitation for scattered firms, the proletariat will allow its creative
capacity to diminish in its conscience. Urban consciousness will vanish.
In France the beginnings of the suburb are also the beginnings of a
violently anti-urban planning approach; a singular paradox. For decades
during the Third Republic appeared documents authorizing and regulating
owner-occupied suburbs and plots. What could be more accurately referred
to here is the banlieue pavillonaire, a type of suburbanization begun in
this period in France characterized by small owner-occupied houing whose
nearest Anglo-Saxon equivalent in terms of typology and social relations
is the âbungalowâ.
A de-urbanized, yet dependent periphery is established around the city.
Effectively, these new suburban dwellers are still urban even though
they are unaware of it and believe themselves to be close to nature, to
the sun and to greenery. One could call it a de-urbanizing and
de-urbanized urbanization to emphasize the paradox.
Its excesses will slow this extension down. The movement it engenders
will carry along the bourgeoisie and the well-off who will establish
residential suburbs. City centres empty themselves for offices. The
whole then begins to struggle with the inextricable. But it is not
finished.
Act Three. After the Second World War it becomes evident that the
picture changes according to various emergencies and constraints related
to demographic and industrial growth and the influx of people from the
provinces to Paris. The housing crisis, acknowledged and proven, turns
into a catastrophe and threatens to worsen the political situation which
is still unstable. âEmergenciesâ overwhelm the initiatives of capitalism
and âprivateâ enterprise, especially as the latter is not interested in
construction, considered to be insufficiently profitable. The State can
no longer be content with simply regulating land plots and the
construction of informal suburban housing or fighting (badly) property
speculation. By means of intermediary organisms it takes charge of
housing construction and an era of ânouveaux ensemblesâ (large-scale
housing estates) and ânew townsâ begins.
It could be said that public powers take charge of what hitherto was
part of a market economy. Undoubtedly. But housing does not necessarily
become a public service. It surfaces into social consciousness as a
right. It is acknowledged in fact by the indignation raised by dramatic
cases and by the discontent engendered by the crisis. Yet it is not
formally or practically acknowledged except as an appendix to the
ârights of manâ. Construction taken in charge by the State does not
change the orientations and conceptions adopted by the market economy.
As Engels had predicted, the housing question, even aggravated, has
politically played only a minor role. Groups and parties on the Left
will be satisfied with demanding âmore housingâ. Moreover, what guides
public and semi-public initiatives is not a conception of urban
planning, it is simply the goal of providing as quickly as possible at
the least cost, the greatest possible number of housing units. The new
housing estates will be characterized by an abstract and functional
character: the concept of habitat brought to its purest form by a State
bureaucracy.
This notion of habitat is still somewhat âuncertainâ. Individual
owner-occupation will enable variations, particular or individual
interpretations of habitat. There is a sort of plasticity which allows
for modifications and appropriations. The space of the house â fence,
garden, various and available corners â leaves a margin of initiative
and freedom to inhabit, limited but real. State rationality is pushed to
the limit. In the new housing estate habitat is established in its
purest form, as a burden of constraints. Certain philosophers will say
that large housing estates achieve the concept of habitat by excluding
the notion of inhabit, that is, the plasticity of space, its modelling
and the appropriation by groups and individuals of the conditions of
their existence. It is also a complete way of living (functions,
prescriptions, daily routine) which is inscribed and signifies itself in
this habitat.
The villa habitat has proliferated in the suburban communes around
Paris, by extending the built environment in a disorderly fashion. This
urban, and at the same time non-urban, growth has only one law:
speculation on plots and property. The interstices !eh by this growth
have been filled by large social housing estates. To the speculation on
plots, badly opposed, was added speculation in apartments when these
were in to-ownership. Thus housing entered into property wealth and
urban land into exchange value. Restrictions were disappearing.
If one defines urban reality by dependency vis-a-vis the centre, suburbs
are urban. If one defines urban order by a perceptible (legible)
relationship between centrality and periphery, suburbs are de-urbanized.
And one can say that the âplanning thoughtâ of large social housing
estates has literally set itself against the city and the urban to
eradicate them. All perceptible, legible urban reality has disappeared:
streets, squares, monuments, meeting places. Even the cafe (the bistro)
has encountered the resentment of the builders of those large housing
estates, their taste for asceticism, the reduction of âto inhabitâ to
habitat. They had to go to the end of their destruction of palpable
urban reality before there could appear the demand for a restitution.
Then one saw the timid, slow reappearance of the cafe, the commercial,
centre, the street, âculturalâ amenities, in brief, a few elements of
urban reality.
Urban order thus decomposes into two stages: individual and
owner-occupied houses and housing estates. But there is no society
without order, signified, perceptible, legible on the ground. Suburban
disorder harbours an order: a glaring opposition of individually
owner-occupied detached houses and housing estates. This opposition
tends to constitute a system of significations still urban even into
de-urbanization. Each sector defines itself (by and in the consciousness
of the inhabitants) in relation to the other, against the ocher. The
inhabitants themselves have little consciousness of the internal order
of their sector, but the people from the housing estates see and
perceive themselves as not being villa dwellers. This is reciprocal. At
the heart of this opposition the people of the housing estates entrench
themselves into the logic of the habitat and the people of
owner-occupied houses entrench themselves into the make-believe of
habitat. For some it is the rational organization (in appearance) of
space. For others it is the presence of the dream, of nature, health,
apart from the bad and unhealthy city. But the logic of the habitat is
only perceived in relation to make-believe, and make-believe in relation
to logic. People represent themselves to themselves by what they are
lacking or believe to be lacking. In this relationship, the imaginary
has more power. It overdetermines logic: the fact of inhabiting is
perceived by reference to the owner-occupation of detached dwellings.
These dwellers regret the absence of a spatial logic while the people of
the housing estates regret not knowing the joys of living in a detached
house. Hence the surprising results of surveys. More than 80 per cent of
French people aspire to be owner-occupiers of a house, while a strong
majority also declare themselves to be âsatisfiedâ with social housing
estates. The outcome is not important here. What should be noted is that
consciousness of the city and of urban reality is dulled for one or the
other, so as to disappear. The practical and theoretical (ideological)
destruction of the city cannot but leave an enormous emptiness, not
including administrative and other problems increasingly difficult to
resolve. This emptiness is less important for a critical analysis than
the source of conflict expressed by the end of the city and by the
extension of a mutilated and deteriorated, but real, urban society. The
suburbs are urban, within a dissociated morphology, the empire of
separation and scission between the elements of what had been created as
unity and simultaneity.
Within this perspective critical analysis can distinguish three periods
(which do not exactly correspond to the distinctions previously made in
three acts of the drama of the city).
First period. Industry and the process of industrialization assault and
ravage pre-existing urban reality, destroying it through practice and
ideology, to the point of extirpating it from reality and consciousness.
Led by a class strategy, industrialization acts as a negative force over
urban reality: the urban social is denied by the industrial economic.
Second period (in part juxtaposed to the first). Urbanization spreads
and urban society becomes general. Urban reality, in and by its own
destruction makes itself acknowledged as socio-economic reality. One
discovers that the whole society is liable to fall apart if it lacks the
city and centrality: an essential means for the planned organization of
production and consumption has disappeared.
Third period. One finds or reinvents urban reality, but not without
suffering from its destruction in practice or in thinking. One attempts
to restitute centrality. Would this suggest that class strategy has
disappeared? This is not certain. It has changed. To the old
centralities, to the decomposition of centres, it substitutes the centre
of decision-making.
Thus is born or reborn urban thought. It follows an urbanism without
thought. The masters of old had no need for an urban theory to embellish
their cities. What sufficed was the pressure exercised by the people on
their masters and the presence of a civilization and style which enabled
the wealth derived from the labour of the people to be invested into
âoeuvresâ. The bourgeois period puts an end to this age-old tradition.
At the same time this period brings a new rationality, different from
the rationality elaborated by philosophers since ancient Greece.
Philosophical Reason proposed definitions of man, the world, history and
society which were questionable but also underpinned by reasonings which
had been given shape. Its democratic generalizations later gave way to a
rationalism of opinions and attitudes. Each citizen was expected to have
a reasoned opinion on every fact and problem concerning him, this wisdom
spurning the irrational. From the confrontation of ideas and opinions, a
superior reason was to emerge, a general wisdom inciting the general
will. It is fruitless to insist upon the difficulties of this classical
rationalism, linked to the political difficulties of democracy, and to
the practical difficulties of humanism. In the nineteenth and especially
in the twentieth century, organizing rationality, operation at various
levels of social reality, takes shape. Is it coming from the capitalist
firm and the management of units of production? Is it born at the level
of the State and planning? What is important is that it is an analytical
reason pushed to its extreme consequences. It begins from a most
detailed methodical analysis of elements â productive operation, social
and economic organization, structure and function. It then subordinates
these elements to a finality. Where does this finality come from? Who
formulates it and stipulates it? How and why? This is the gap and the
failure of this operational rationalism. Its tenets purport to extract
finality from the sequence of operations. Now, this is not so. Finality,
that is, the whole and the orientation of the whole, decides itself. To
say that it comes from the operations themselves, is to be locked into a
vicious circle: the analysis giving itself as its own aim, for its own
meaning. Finality is an object of decision. It is a strategy, more or
less justified by an ideology. Rationalism which purports to extract
from its own analyses the aim pursued by these analyses is itself an
ideology. The notion of system overlays that of strategy. To critical
analysis the system reveals itself as strategy, is unveiled as decision,
that is, as decided finality. It has been shown above how a class
strategy has oriented the analysis and division of urban reality, its
destruction and restitution; and projections on the society where such
strategic decisions have been taken.
However, from the point of view of a technicist rationalism, the results
on the ground of the processes examined above represent only chaos. In
the ârealityâ, which they critically observe â suburbs, urban fabric and
surviving cores â these rationalists do not recognize the conditions of
their own existence. What is before them is only contradiction and
disorder. Only, in fact, dialectical reason can master (by reflective
thought, by practice) multiple and paradoxically contradictory
processes.
How to impose order in this chaotic confusion? It is in this way that
organizational rationalism poses its problem. This is not a normal
disorder. How can it be established as norm and normality? This is
unconceivable. This disorder is unhealthy. The physician of modern
society see himself as the physician of a sick social space. Finality?
The cure? It is coherence. The rationalist will establish or
re-establish coherence into a chaotic reality which he observes and
which offers itself up to his action. This rationalist may not realize
that coherence is a form, therefore a means rather than an end, and that
he will systematize the logic of the habitat underlying the disorder and
apparent incoherence, that he will take as point of departure towards
the coherence of the real, his coherent approaches. There is in fact no
single or unitary approach in planning thought, but several tendencies
identifiable according to this operational rationalism. Among these
tendencies, some assert themselves against, others for rationalism by
leading it to extreme formulations. What interferes with the general
tendencies of those involved with planning is understanding only what
they can translate in terms of graphic operations: seeing, feeling at
the end of a pencil, drawing.
One can therefore identify the following:
(1) The planning of men of good will (architects and writers). Their
thinking and projects imply a certain philosophy. Generally they
associate themselves to an old classical and liberal humanism. This not
without a good dose of nostalgia. One wishes to build to the âhuman
scaleâ, for âpeopleâ. These humanists present themselves at one and the
same time as doctors of society and creators of new social relations.
Their ideology, or rather, their idealism often come from agrarian
models, adopted without reflection: the village, the community, the
neighbourhood, the townsman- citizen who will be endowed with civic
buildings, etc. They want to build buildings and cities to the âhuman
scaleâ, âto its measureâ, without conceiving that in the modern world
âmanâ has changed scale and the measure of yesteryear (village and city)
has been transformed beyond measure. At best, this tradition leads to a
formalism (the adoption of models which had neither content or meaning),
or to an aestheticism, that is, the adoption for their beauty of ancient
models which are then thrown as fodder to feed the appetites of
consumers.
(2) The planning of these administrators linked to the public (State)
sector. It sees itself as scientific. It relies sometimes on a science,
sometimes on studies which call themselves synthetic (pluri or
multidisciplinary). This scientism, which accompanies the deliberate
forms of operational rationalism, tends to neglect the so-called âhuman
factorâ. It divides itself into tendencies. Sometimes through a
particular science, a technique takes over and becomes the point of
departure; it is generally a technique of communication and circulation.
One extrapolates from a science, from a fragmentary analysis of the
reality considered. One optimizes information and communication into a
model. This technocratic and systematized planning, with its myths and
its ideology (namely, the primacy of technique), would not hesitate to
raze to the ground what is left of the city to leave way for cars,
ascendant and descendant networks of communication and information. The
models elaborated can only be put into practice by eradicating from
social existence the very ruins of what was the city.
Sometimes, on the contrary, information and analytical knowledge coming
from different sciences are oriented towards a synthetic finality. For
all that, one should not conceive an urban life having at its disposal
information provided by the sciences of society. These two aspects are
confounded in the conception of centres of decision-making, a global
vision, planning already unitary in its own way, linked to a philosophy,
to a conception of society, a political strategy, that is, a global and
total system.
(3) The planning of developers. They conceive and realize without hiding
it, for the market, with profit in mind. What is new and recent is that
they are no longer selling housing or buildings, but planning. With or
without ideology, planning becomes an exchange value. The project of
developers presents itself as opportunity and place of privilege: the
place of happiness in a daily life miraculously and marvellously
transformed. The make-believe world of habitat is inscribed in the logic
of habitat and their unity provides a social practice which does not
need a system. Hence these advertisements, which are already famous and
which deserve posterity because publicity itself becomes ideology. Parly
II (a new development) âgives birth to a new an of livingâ, a ânew
lifestyleâ. Daily life resembles a fairy tale. âLeave your coat in the
cloakroom and feeling lighter, do your shopping after having left the
children in the nurseries of the shopping mall, meet your friends, have
a drink together at the drugstore ...â Here is the fulfilled
make-believe of the joy of living. Consumer society is expressed by
orders: the order of these elements on the ground, the order to be
happy. Here is the context, the setting, the means of your happiness. If
you do not know how to grasp the happiness offered so as to make it your
own â donât insist!
A global strategy, that is, what is already an unitary system and total
planning, is outlined through these various tendencies. Some will put
into practice and will concertize a directed consumer society. They will
build not only commercial centres, but also centres of privileged
consumption: the renewed city. They will by making âlegibleâ an ideology
of happiness through consumption, joy by planning adapted to its new
mission. This planning programmes a daily life generating satisfactions
â (especially for receptive and participating women). A programmed and
computerized consumption will become the rule and norm for the whole
society. Others will erect decision-making centres, concentrating the
means of power: information, training, organization, operation. And
still: repression (constraints, including violence) and persuasion
(ideology and advertising). Around these centres will be apportioned on
the ground, in a dispersed order, according to the norms of foreseen
constraints, the peripheries, de-urbanized urbanization. All the
conditions come together thus for a perfect domination, for a refined
exploitation of people as producers, consumers of products, consumers of
space.
The convergence of these projects therefore entails the greatest
dangers, for it raises politically the problem of urban society. It is
possible that new contradictions will arise from these projects,
impeding convergence. If a unitary strategy was to be successfully
constituted, it might prove irretrievable.
Having contextualized the âcavalierâ attitude mentioned at the
beginning, particular aspects and problems concerning the urban can now
be emphasized. In order to take up a radically critical analysis and to
deepen the urban problematic, philosophy will be the starting point.
This will come as a surprise. And yet, has not frequent reference to
philosophy been made in the preceding pages? The purpose is not to
present a philosophy of the city, but on the contrary, to refute such an
approach by giving back to the whole of philosophy its place in history:
that of a project of synthesis and totality which philosophy as such
cannot accomplish. After which the analytical will be examined, that is,
the ways fragmentary sciences have highlighted or partitioned urban
reality. The rejection of the synthetic propositions of these
specialized, fragmentary, and particular sciences will enable us â to
pose better â in political terms â the problem of synthesis. During the
course of this progress one will find again features and problems which
will reappear more dearly. In particular, the opposition between use
value (the city and urban life) and exchange value (spaces bought and
sold, the consumption of products, goods, places and signs) will be
highlighted.
For philosophical meditation aiming at a totality through speculative
systematization, that is, classical philosophy from Plato to Hegel, the
city was much more than a secondary theme, an object among others. The
links between philosophical thought and urban life appear clearly upon
reflection, although they need to be made explicit. The city and the
town were not for philosophers and philosophy a simple objective
condition, a sociological context, an exterior element. Philosophers
have thought the city: they have brought to language and concept urban
life.
Let us leave aside questions posed by the oriental city, the Asiatic
mode of production, âtown and countryâ relations in this mode of
production, and lastly the formation of ideologies (philosophies) on
this base. Only the Greek and Roman antique city from which are derived
societies and civilizations known as âWesternâ will be considered. This
city is generally the outcome of a synoecism, the coming together of
several villages and tribes established on this territory. This unit
allows the development of division of labour and landed property (money)
without however destroying the collective, or rather âcommunalâ property
of the land. In this way a community is constituted at the heart of
which is a minority of free citizens who exercise power over other
members of the city: women, children, slaves, foreigners. The city links
its elements associated with the form of the communal property (âcommon
private propertyâ, or âprivatized appropriationâ) of the active
citizens, who are in opposition to the slaves. This form of association
constitutes a democracy, the elements, of which are strictly
hierarchical and submitted to the demands of the oneness of the city
itself. It is the democracy of non-freedom (Marx). During the course of
the history of the antique city, private property pure and simple (of
money, land and slaves) hardens, concentrates, without abolishing the
rights of the city over its territory.
The separation between town and country takes place among the first and
fundamental divisions of labour, with the distribution of tasks
according to age and sex (the biological division of labour), with the
organization of labour according to tools and skills (technical
division). The social division of labour between town and country
corresponds to the separation between material and intellectual labour,
and consequently, between the natural and the spiritual. Intellectual
labour is incumbent upon the city: functions of organization and
direction, political and military activities, elaboration of theoretical
knowledge (philosophy and sciences). The whole divides itself,
separations are established, including the separation between the
Physics and the Logos, between theory and practice, and in practice, the
separations between between praxis (action on human groups), poiesis
(creation of âoeuvresâ), techne (activities endowed with techniques and
directed towards product). The countryside, both practical reality and
representation, will carry images of nature, of being, of the innate.
The city will carry images of effort, of will, of subjectivity, of
contemplation, without these representations becoming disjointed from
real activities. From these images confronted against each other great
symbolisms will emerge. Around the Greek city, above it, there is the
cosmos, luminous and ordered spaces, the apogee of place. The city has
as centre a hole which is sacred and damned, inhabited by the forces of
death and life, times dark with effort and ordeals, the world. The
Apollonian spirit triumphs in the Greek city, although not without
struggle, as the luminous symbol of reason which regulates, while in the
Etruscan-Roman city what governs is the demonic side of the urban. But
the philosopher and philosophy attempt to reclaim or create totality.
The philosopher does not acknowledge separation, he does not conceive
that the world, life, society, the cosmos (and later, history) can no
longer make a Whole.
Philosophy is thus born from the city, with its division of labour and
multiple modalities. It becomes itself a specialized activity in its own
right. But it does not become fragmentary, for otherwise it would blend
with science and the sciences, themselves in a process of emerging. just
as philosophy refuses to engage in the opinions of craftsmen, soldiers
and politicians, it refutes the reasons and arguments of specialists. It
has totality as fundamental interest for its own sake, which is
recovered or created by the system, that is, the oneness of thought and
being, of discourse and act, of nature and contemplation, of the world
(or the cosmos) and human reality. This does not exclude but includes
meditation on differences (between Being and thought, between what comes
from nature and what comes from the city, etc.). As Heidegger expressed
it, the logos (element, context, mediation and end for philosophers and
urban life) was simultaneously the following: to put forward, gather
together and collect, then to recollect and collect oneself, speak and
say, disclose. This gathering is the harvest and even its conclusion.
âOne goes to collect things and brings them back. Here sheltering
dominates and with it in turn dominates the wish to preserve ... The
harvest is in itself a choice of what needs a shelter.â Thus, the
harvest is already thought out. That which is gathered is put in
reserve. To say is the act of collection which gathers together. This
assumes the presence of âsomebodyâ before which, for whom and by whom is
expressed the being of what is thus successful. This presence is
produced with clarity (or as Heidegger says, with ânon-mysteryâ). The
city linked to philosophy thus gathers by and in its logos the wealth of
the territory, dispersed activities and people, the spoken and the
written (of which each assumes already its collection and recollection).
It makes simultaneous what in the countryside and according to nature
takes place and passes, and is distributed according to cycles and
rhythms. It grasps and defends âeverythingâ. If philosophy and the city
are thus associated in the dawning logos (reason), it is not within a
subjectivity akin to the Cartesian âcogitoâ. If they constitute a
system, it is not in the usual way and in the current meaning of the
term.
To the organization of the city itself can be linked the primordial
whole of urban form and its content, of philosophical form and its
meaning: a privileged centre, the core of a political space, the seat of
the logos governed by the logos before which citizens are âequalâ, the
regions and distributions of space having a rationality justified before
the logos (for it and by it).
The logos of the Greek city cannot be separated from the philosophical
logos. The oeuvre of the city continues and is focused in the work of
philosophers, who gather opinions and viewpoints, various oeuvres, and
think them simultaneously and collect differences into a totality: urban
places in the cosmos, times and rhythms of the city and that of the
world (and inversely). It is therefore only for a superficial
historicity that philosophy brings to language and concept urban life,
that of the city. In truth, the city as emergence, language, meditation
comes to theoretical light by means of the philosopher and philosophy.
After this first interpretation of the internal link between the city
and philosophy, let us go to the European Middle Ages. It begins from
the countryside. The Roman city and the Empire have been destroyed by
Germanic tribes which are both primitive communities and military
organizations. The feudal property of land is the outcome of the
dissolution of this sovereignty (city, property, relations of
production). Serfs replace slaves. With the rebirth of cities there is
on the one hand the feudal organization of property and possession of
land (peasant communities having a customary possession and lords having
an âeminentâ domain as it will later be called), and on the other hand,
a corporate organization of crafts and urban property. Although at the
beginning seigneurial tenure of land dominates it, this double hierarchy
contains the demise of this form of property and the supremacy of wealth
in urban property from which arises a deep conflict, basic to medieval
society. âThe necessity to ally themselves against the plunderer lords
associated themselves together; the need for common market halls at a
time when industry was craft, when serfs in breach of their bondage and
in competition with each other were flooding to the increasingly rich
cities, the whole of feudal organization was giving birth to the
corporations (or guilds). Small capitals, slowly saved by isolated
craftsmen, their numbers stable in the middle of a growing population,
developed a system of journeymen and apprentices which established in
the cities a hierarchy similar to that of the countrysideâ (Marx). In
these conditions theology subordinates philosophy. The latter no longer
meditates on the city. The philosopher (the theologian) deliberates upon
the double hierarchy. He gives it shape, with or without raking
conflicts into account. The symbols and notions relative to the cosmos
(spaces, the hierarchy of matter in that space) and to the world (the
actualization of finished matter, hierarchies in time, descent or fall,
ascension and redemption) erase the consciousness of the city. From the
moment when there are not two but three hierarchies (feudal landed
property, guild organization, the king and his State apparatus), thought
takes again a critical dimension. The philosopher and philosophy find
themselves again, no longer having to choose between the Devil and the
Lord. Philosophy will not however recognize its link to the city,
although the rise of rationalism accompanies the rise of capitalism
(commercial and banking, then industrial), and the development of
cities. This rationalism is attached either to the State or to the
individual.
For Hegel, at the height of speculative, systematic and contemplative
philosophy, the unity between the perfect Thing, chat is, the Greek
city, and the Idea, which animates society and the State, this admirable
whole, has been irremediably broken by historic becoming. In modern
society, the State subordinates these elements and materials, including
the city. The latter, however remains as a sort of subsystem in the
total philosophico-political system, with the system of needs, that of
rights and obligations, and that of the family and estates (crafts and
guilds), that of art and aesthetics, etc.
For Hegel, philosophy and the ârealâ (practical and social) are not, or
rather, are no longer external to each other. Separations disappear.
Philosophy is not satisfied to meditate upon the real, to attempt the
link up of the real and the ideal: it fulfills itself by achieving the
ideal: the rational. The real is not satisfied with giving excuse to
reflection, to knowledge, to consciousness. During a history which has a
meaning â which has this meaning â it becomes rational. Thus the real
and the rational tend towards each other; each from their own side moves
towards an identity thus acknowledged. The rational is basically
philosophy, the philosophical system. The real is society and law and
the State which cements the edifice by crowning it. Consequently, in the
modern State, the philosophical system, becomes real: in Hegelâs
philosophy, the real acknowledge the rational. The system has a double
side, philosophical and political. Hegel discovers the historical moment
of this shift from the rational into the real and vice versa. He brings
to light identity at the moment when history produces it. Philosophy
achieves itself There is for Hegel, as Marx will articulate it, at one
and the same time a becoming of a philosophy of the world and a becoming
of the world of philosophy. An initial repercussion: there can no longer
be a divide between philosophy and reality (historical, social,
political). A second repercussion: the philosopher no longer has
independence: he accomplishes a public function, as do other officials.
Philosophy and the philosopher integrate themselves (by mediation of the
body of civil servants and the middle class) in this rational reality of
the State â no longer in the city, which was only a thing (perfect, it
is true, but only thing), denied by a higher and more inclusive
rationality.
One knows that Marx neither refuted nor refused the essential Hegelian
affirmation: Philosophy achieves itself. The philosopher no longer has a
right to independence vis-a-vis social practice. Philosophy inserts
itself into it. There is indeed a simultaneous becoming-philosophy of
the world and a becoming-world of philosophy, and therefore a tendency
towards wholeness (knowledge and acknowledgement of non-separation). And
yet Marx thrusts Hegelianism aside. History does not achieve itself.
Wholeness is not reached, nor are contradictions resolved. It is not by
and in the State, with bureaucracy as social support, that philosophy
can be realized. The proletariat has this historic mission: only it can
put an end to separations (alienations). Its mission has a double facet:
to destroy bourgeois society by building another society â abolish
philosophical speculation and abstraction, the alienating contemplation
and systematization, to accomplish the philosophical project of the
human being. It is from industry, from industrial production, from its
relation with productive forces and labour, not from a moral or
philosophical judgement, that the working class gets its possibilities.
One must tum this world upside down: the meeting of the rational and the
real will happen in another society.
The history of philosophy in relation to the city is far from being
accomplished within this perspective. Indeed, this history would also
suggest the analysis of themes whose emergence are linked to the
representation of nature and the earth, to agriculture, to the
sacralization of the land (and to its desacralization). Such themes,
once born, are displaced and represented sometimes far from their
starting points in time and space. The points of imputation and impact,
conditions, implications, consequences do not coincide. The themes are
enunciated and inserted into social contexts and categories different
from those which distinguish their emergence, inasmuch as one can speak
of âcategoriesâ. The urban problematic, for example that which refers to
the destiny of the Greek city, used to disengage itself or hide itself,
cosmic themes anterior or exterior to this city; the visions of a
cyclical becoming or of the hidden immobility of the human being. The
purpose of these remarks is to show that the relation considered has yet
to receive an explicit formulation.
What relation is there today between philosophy and the city? An
ambiguous one. The most emminent contemporary philosophers do not borrow
their themes from the city. Bachelard has left wonderful pages on the
house. Heidegger has meditated on the Greek city and the logos, and on
the Greek temple. Nevertheless the metaphors which resume Heideggerian
thought do not come from the city but from a primary and earlier life:
the âshepherds of beingâ, the âforest pathsâ. It seems that it is from
the Dwelling and the opposition between Dwelling and Wandering that
Heidegger borrows his themes. As for so-called âexistentialâ thought, it
is based on individual consciousness, on the subject and the ordeals of
subjectivity, rather than on a practical, historical and social reality.
However, it is not proven that philosophy has said its last word on the
city. For example, one can perfectly conceive of a phenomenological
description of urban life. Or construct a semiology of urban reality
which would correspond for the present city to what was the logos in the
Greek city. Only philosophy and the philosopher propose a totality, the
search for a global conception or vision. To consider âthe cityâ is it
not already to extend philosophy, to reintroduce philosophy into the
city or the city into philosophy? It is true that the concept of
totality is in danger of remaining empty if it is only philosophical.
Thus is formulated a problematic which does not reduce itself to the
city but which concerns the world, history, âmanâ.
Moreover, a certain number of contemporary thinkers have pondered on the
city. They see themselves, more or less clearly, as philosophers of the
city. For this reason these thinkers want to inspire architects and
planners, and make the link between urban preoccupations and the old
humanism. But these philosophers lack breadth. The philosophers who
claim to think the city and put forward a philosophy of the city by
extending traditional philosophy, discourse on the âessenceâ of the city
or on the city as âspiritâ, as âlifeâ or âlife forceâ, as being or
âorganic wholeâ. In brief, sometime as subject, sometime as abstract
system. This leads to nothing, thus a double conclusion. Firstly, the
history of philosophical thought can and must reclaim itself from its
relation with the city (the condition and content of this thought). It
is a way of putting this history into perspective. Secondly, this
articulation figures in the problematic of philosophy and the city
(knowledge, the formulation of the urban problematic, a notion of this
context, a strategy to envisage). Philosophical concepts are not
operative and yet they situate the city and the urban â and the whole of
society â as a totality, over and above analytical fragmentations. What
is proclaimed here of philosophy and its history could equally be
asserted for art and its history.
During the course of the nineteenth century, the sciences of social
reality are constituted against philosophy which strives to grasp the
global (by enclosing a real totality into a rational systematization).
These sciences fragment reality in order to analyse it, each having
their method or methods, their sector or domain. After a century, it is
still under discussion whether these sciences bring distinct
enlightenment to a unitary reality, or whether the analytical
fragmemation chat they use corresponds to objective differences,
articulations, levels and dimensions.
One cannot claim that the city has escaped the researches of historians,
economists, demographers and sociologists. Each of these specialities
contributes to a science of the city. It has already been ascertained
and corroborated that history elucidates better the genesis of the city,
and especially identifies better than any other science, the problematic
of urban sociecy. Inversely, there is also no doubt that the knowledge
of urban reality can relate to the possible (or possibilities) and not
only to what is finished or from the past. If one wishes to build a
commercial or cultural centre, taking into account functional and
functioning needs, the economist has his word to say. In the analysis of
urban reality, the geographer, the climatologist, the botanist also
intervene. The environment, global and confused concept, fragments
itself according to these specialities. In relation to the future and
the conditions of the future, mathematical calculations provide
essential evidence. Yet, what gathers these facts together? A project,
or in other words, a strategy. On the other hand, a doubt remains and is
even confirmed. Is the city the sum of indices and facts, of variables
and parameters, of correlations, this collection of facts, of
descriptions, of fragmentary analyses, because it is fragmentary? These
analytical divisions do not lack rigour, but as has already been said,
rigour is uninhabitable. The problem coincides with the general
questioning of the specialist sciences. On the one hand, the only
approach which seeks to find the global reminds us strangely of
philosophy when it is not openly philosophical. On the ocher hand, the
partial offers more positive but scattered facts. Is it possible to
extract from fragmentary sciences a science of the city? No more than a
holistic science of society, or of âmanâ, or of human and social
reality. On the one hand, a concept without content, on the other,
content or contents without concept. Either one declares that the
âcityâ, the urban reality as such, does not exist but is only a series
of correlations. The âsubjectâ is suppressed. Or the continues to assert
the existence of the global: one approaches and locates it, either by
extrapolations in the name of a discipline, or by wagering on an
âinterdisciplinaryâ tactic. One does not grasp it except by an approach
which transcends divisions.
Upon closer examination, one realizes that specialists who have studied
urban reality have almost always (except in the case of a logically
extremist positivism) introduced a global representation. They can
hardly go without a synthesis, settling for a quantity of knowledge, of
dividing and splitting urban reality. As specialists, they then claim to
be able to go legitimately from their analyses to a final synthesis
whose principle is borrowed from their speciality. By means of a
discipline or interdisciplinary endeavour, they see themselves as âmen
of synthesisâ. More often, they conceptualize the city (and society) as
an organism. Historians have frequently linked these entities to an
âevolutionâ or to an âhistorical developmentâ: cities. Sociologists have
conceptualized them as a âcollective beingâ, as a âsocial organismâ.
Organicism, evolutionism, continuism, have therefore dominated
representations of the city elaborated by specialists who believed
themselves to be scholars and only scholars. Philosophers without
knowing it, they leapt, without legitimizing their approach, from the
partial to the global as well as from fact to right.
Is there a dilemma? An impasse? Yes and no. Yes, there is an obstacle,
or if one wants another metaphor, a hole is dug. No. One should be able
to cross the obstacle because there is a quite recent practice which
already spills over the speculative problem, or the partial facts of the
real problem, and which tends to become global by gathering all the
facts of experience and knowledge, namely, planning. What is involved
here is nor a philosophical view on praxis, but the face that so-called
planning thought becomes practice at a global level. For a few years now
planning has gone beyond partial techniques and applications (regulation
and administration of built space) to become a social practice
concerning and of interest to the whole of society. The critical
examination of this social practice (the focus being on critique) cannot
not allow theory to resolve a theoretical difficulty arising from a
theory which has separated itself from practice.
As social practice, planning (which it becomes without having reached a
level of elaboration and action, which indeed it can only reach through
confrontation with political strategies) has already crossed the initial
stage, namely, the confrontation and communication of experts, and the
gathering of fragmentary analyses, in brief, what is called the
interdisciplinary. Either the planner is inspired by the practice of
partial knowledge which he applies, or he puts into action hypotheses or
projects at the level of a global reality. In the first case, the
application of partial knowledge gives results which can determine the
relative importance of this knowledge: these results, experimentally
revealing absences and lacunae, enable us to specify on the ground what
is lacking. In the second case, the failure (or success) allows the
discernment of what is ideological in the presuppositions, and to
identify what they define at the global level. Thus, what is effectively
involved is a critical examination of the activity called âplanningâ,
and not a belief in the word of planners or the unchallenged acceptance
of their propositions and decisions. In particular, the displacements
and distortions between practice and theory (ideology), between partial
knowledge and results, come to the fore instead of being hidden. As does
the questioning over use and users.
In order to formulate the problematic of the city (to articulate
problems by linking them), the following must be clearly distinguished:
speculatively as whole by defining the âhomo urbanicusâ as man in
general, the world or the cosmos, society, history.
structures).
defined by strategic and political decisions).
knowledge, justifying its application and raising these (by
extrapolation) to a poorly based or legitimated totality.
The aspects or elements which this analysis distinguishes do not appear
separately in various works; they interest, reiforcing or neutralizing
each other. Plato proposes a concept of the city and ideal town in
Critias. In The Republic and The Laws, Platonic utopia is tempered by
very concrete analyses. It is the same for Aristodeâs political writings
which study the constitution of Athens and other Greek cities.
Today, Lewis Mumford and G. Bardet among others still imagine a city
made up not of townspeople, but of free citizens, free from the division
of labour, social classes and class struggles, making up a community,
freely associated for the management of this community. As philosophers,
they make up a model of the ideal city. They conceive freedom in the
twentieth century according to the freedom of the Greek city (this is an
ideological travesty: only the city as such possessed freedom and not
individuals and groups). Thus they think of the modern city according to
a model of the antique city, which is at the same time identified with
the ideal and rational city. The agora, place and symbol of a democracy
limited to its citizens, and excluding women, slaves and foreigners,
remains for a particular philosophy of the city the symbol of urban
society in general. This is a typically ideological extrapolation. To
this ideology these philosophers add partial knowledge, this purely
ideological operation consisting in a passage (a leap), from the partial
to the whole, from the elementary to the total, from the relative to the
absolute. As for Le Corbusier, as philosopher of the city he describes
the relationship between the urban dweller and dwelling with nature,
air, sun, and trees, with cyclical time and the rhythms of the cosmos.
To this metaphysical vision, he adds an unquestionable knowledge of the
real problems of the modern city, a knowledge which gives rise to a
planning practice and an ideology, a functionalism which reduces urban
society to the achievement of a few predictable and prescribed functions
laid out on the ground by the architecture. Such an architect sees
himself as a âman of synthesisâ, thinker and practitioner. He believes
in and wants to create human relations by defining them, by clearing
their environment and decor. Within this well-worn perspective, the
architect perceives and imagines himself as architect of the world,
human image of God the Creator.
Philosophy of the city (or if one wanes, urban ideology), was born as a
superstructure of society into which structures entered a certain type
of city. This philosophy, precious heritage of the past, extends itself
into speculations which often are travesties of science just because
they integrate a few bits of real knowledge.
Planning as ideology has acquired more and more precise definitions. To
study the problems of circulation, of the conveying of orders and
information in the great modern city, leads to real knowledge and to
technical applications. To claim that the city is defined as a network
of circulation and communication, as a centre of information and
decision-making, is an absolute ideology; this ideology proceeding from
a particularly arbitrary and dangerous reduction-extrapolation and using
terrorist means, see itself as total truth and dogma. It leads to a
planning of pipes, of roadworks and accounting, which one claims to
impose in the name of science and scientific rigour. Or even worse!
This ideology has two interdependent aspects, mental and social.
Mentally, it implies a theory of rationality and organization whose
expression date from around 1910, a transformation in contemporary
society (characterized by the beginning of a deep crisis and attempts to
resolve it by organizational methods, firstly the scale of the firm, and
then on a global scale). It is then that socially the notion of space
comes to the fore, relegating into shadow time and becoming. Planning as
ideology formulates all the problems of society into questions of space
and transposes all that comes from history and consciousness into
spatial terms. It is an ideology which immediately divides up. Since
society does not function in a satisfactory manner, could there not be a
pathology of space? Within this perspective, the virtually official
recognition of the priority of space over time is not conceived of as
indication of social pathology, as symptom among others of a reality
which engenders social disease. On the contrary, what are represented
are healthy and diseased spaces. The planner should be able to
distinguish between sick spaces and spaces linked to mental and social
health which are generators of this health. As physician of space, he
should have the capacity to conceive of an harmonious social space,
normal and normalizing. Its function would then be to grant to this
space (perchance identical to geometrical space, that of abstract
topologies) preexisting social realities.
The radical critique of philosophies of the city as well as of ideology
is vital, as much on the theoretical as on the practical level. It can
be made in the name of public health. However, it cannot be carried out
without extensive research, rigorous analyses and the patient study of
texts and contexts.
A philosophy of the city answered questions raised by social practice in
precapiralisr societies (or if one prefers this terminology, in
pre-industrial societies). Planning as technique and ideology responds
to demands arising from this vast crisis of the city already referred
to, which starts with the rise of competitive and industrial capitalism
and which has never stopped getting deeper. This world crisis gives rise
to new aspects of urban reality. It sheds light on what was little or
poorly understood; it unveils what had been badly perceived. It forces
the reconsideration of not only the history of the city and knowledge of
the city, but also of the history of philosophy and that of an. Until
recently, theoretical thinking conceived the city as an entity, as an
organism and a whole among others, and this in the best of cases when it
was not being reduced to a partial phenomenon, to a secondary,
elementary or accidental aspect, of evolution and history. One would
elms see in it a simple result, a local effect reflecting purely and
simply general history. These representations, which are classified and
are given well-known terms (organicism, evolutionism, continuism), have
been previously criticized. They did not contain theoretical knowledge
of the city and did not lead to this knowledge; moreover, they blocked
at a quite basic level the enquiry; they were ideologies rather than
concepts and theories.
Only now are we beginning to grasp the specificity of the city (of urban
phenomena). The city always had relations with society as a whole, with
its constituting elements (countryside and agriculture, offensive and
defensive force, political power, States, etc.), and with its history.
it changes when society as a whole changes. Yet, the cityâs
transformations are not the passive outcomes of changes in the social
whole. The city also depends as essentially on relations of immediacy,
of direct relations between persons and groups which make up society
(families, organized bodies, crafts and guilds, etc.). Furthermore, it
is not reduced to the organization of these immediate and direct
relations, nor its metamorphoses to their changes. It is situated at an
interface, half-way between what is called the near order (relations of
individuals in groups of variable size, more or less organized and
structured and the relations of these groups among themselves), and the
far order, that of society, regulated by large and powerful institutions
(Church and State), by a legal code formalized or not, by a âcultureâ
and significant ensembles endowed with powers, by which the far order
projects itself at this âhigherâ level and imposes itself. Abstract,
formal, supra-sensible and transcending in appearances, it is not
conceptualized beyond ideologies (religious and political). It includes
moral and legal principles. This far order projects itself into the
practico-material reality and becomes visible by writing itself within
this reality. It persuades through and by the near order, which confirms
its compelling power. It becomes apparent by and in immediacy. The city
is a mediation among mediations. Containing the near order, it supports
it; it maintains relations of production and property; it is the place
of their reproduction. Contained in the far order, it supports it; it
incarnates it; it projects it over a terrain (the site) and on a plan,
that of immediate life; it inscribes it, prescribes it, writes it. A
text in a context so vast and ungraspable as such except by reflection.
And thus the city is an oeuvre, closer to a work of art than to a simple
material product. If there is production of the city, and social
relations in the city, it is a production and reproduction of human
beings by human beings, rather than a production of objects. The city
has a history; it is the work of a history, chat is, of dearly defined
people and groups who accomplish this oeuvre, in historical conditions.
Conditions which simultaneously enable and limit possibilities, are
never sufficient to explain what was born of them, in them, by them. It
was in this way that the city created by the Western Middle Ages was
animated and dominated by merchants and bankers, this city was their
oeuvre. Can the historian consider it as a simple object of commerce, a
simple opportunity for lucre? Absolutely not, precisely not. These
merchants and bankers acted to promote exchange and generalize it, to
extend the domain of exchange value; and yet for them the city was much
more use value than exchange value. These merchants of Italian, Flemish,
English and French cities loved their cities like a work of art and
adorned them with every kind of works of an. So that, paradoxically, the
city of merchants and bankers remains for us the type and model of an
urban real icy whereby use (pleasure, beauty, ornamentation of meeting
places) still wins over lucre and profit, exchange value, the
requirements and constraints of markets. At the same time, wealth
arising from commerce in goods and money, the power of gold, the
cynicism of this power, are also inscribed in this city and in it
prescribe an order. So that, as such it still remains for some model and
prototype.
By taking âproductionâ in its widest sense (the production of oeuvres
and of social relations), there has been in history the production of
cities as there has been production of knowledge, culture, works of art
and civilization, and there also has been, of course, production of
material goods and practico-material objects. These modalities of
production cannot be disjointed unless one has the right to confuse them
by reducing differences. The city was and remains object, but not in the
way of particular, pliable and instrumental object: such as a pencil or
a sheet of paper. Its objectivity, or âobjectalityâ, might rather be
closer to that of the language which individuals and groups receive
before modifying it, or of language (a particular language, the work of
a particular society, spoken by particular groups). One could also
compare this âobjectalityâ to that of a cultural reality, such as the
written book, instead of old abstract object of the philosophers or the
immediate and everyday object. Moreover, one must take precautions. If I
compare the city to a book, to a writing (a semiological system), I do
not have the right to forget the aspect of mediation. I can separate it
neither from what it contains nor from what contains it, by isolating it
as a complete system. Moreover, at best, the city constitutes a
sub-system, a sub-whole. On this book, with this writing, are projected
mental and social forms and structures. Now, analysis can achieve this
context from the text, but it is not given. Intellectual operations and
reflective approaches are necessary to achieve it (deduction, induction,
translation and transduction). The whole is not immediately present in
this wrinen text, the city. There are other levels of reality which do
not become transparent by definition. The city writes and assigns, that
is, it signifies, orders, stipulates. What? That is to be discovered by
reflection. This text has passed through idealogies, as it also
âreflectsâ them. The far order projects itself in/on the near order.
However, the near order does not reflect transparently the far order.
The later subordinates the immediate through mediations. it does not
yield itself up. Moreover, it hides itself without discovering itself.
This is how it acts without one having the right to speak of a
transcendence of order, the Global or the Total.
If one considers the city as oeuvre of certain historical and social
âagentsâ, the action and the result, the group (or groups) and their
âproductâ can be clearly identified without separating them. There is no
oeuvre without a regulated succession of acts and actions, of decisions
and conduces, messages and codes. Nor can an oeuvre exist without
things, without something to shape, without practico-material reality,
without a site, without a ânatureâ, a countryside, an environment.
Social relations are achieved from the sensible. They cannot be reduced
to this sensible world, and yet they do not float in air, they do not
disappear into transcendence. If social reality suggests forms and
relations, if it cannot be conceived in a way homologous to the
isolated, sensible or technical object, it does not survive without
ties, without attachment to objects and things. We must insist on this
methodologically and theoretically important point. There is cause and
reason to distinguish between material and social morphologies. We
should perhaps here introduce a distinction between the city, a present
and immediate reality, a practico-material and architectural fact, and
the urban, a social reality made up of relations which are to be
conceived of, conscructed or reconstructed by thought. This distinction
none the less reveals itself to be dangerous and the designation
proposed cannot be handled without risk. Thus designated, the urban
seems not to need land and material morphology and is outlined according
to a speculative mode of existence of entities, spirits and souls, freed
from attachments and inscriptions; a kind of imaginary transcendence. If
one adopts this terminology, the relations between the city and the
urban will have to be determined with the greatest care, by avoiding
separation as well as confusion, and metaphysics as well as reduction to
the immediate and tangible. Urban life, urban sociecy, in a word, the
urban, cannot go without a practico-material base, a morphology. They
have it and do not have it. If they do not have it, if the urban and
urban society are conceived without this basis, it is that they are
perceived as possibilities, it is chat the virtualities of actual
society are seeking, so to speak, their incorporation and incarnation
through knowledge and planning thought: through our âreflectionsâ. If
they do not find them, these possibilities go into decline and are bound
to disappear. The urban is not a soul, a spirit, a philosophical entity.
Organicism and its implications, namely the simplifying evolutionism of
many historians and the naive continuism of many sociologists, has
disguised the specific features of urban reality. The acts or events
âproducersâ of this reality as formation and social oeuvre escaped
knowledge. In this sense, to produce is to create: to bring into being
âsomethingâ which did nor exist before the productive activity. For a
long time knowledge has hesitated in the face of creation. Either
creation appears to be irrational, spontaneity swelling up from the
unknown and the unknowable. Or else it is denied and what comes to be is
reduced to what was already existing. Science wants itself to be a
science of determinisms, a knowledge of constraints. It abandons to
philosophers the exploration of births, of decline, transitions,
disappearances. In this, those who challenge philosophy abandon the idea
of creation. The study of urban phenomena is linked to overcoming these
obstacles and dilemmas, to the solution of these internal conflicts by
reason which knows.
As much in the past as now, history and sociology conceived as an
organicist model have not known better how to apprehend differences.
Abusive reductions take place to the detriment of these differences and
to the detriment of creation. It is quite easy to grasp the link between
these reductive operations. The specific flees before simplifying
schematas. In the rather troubled light shed by many confused crises
(such as the city and the urban), among the crevices of a ârealityâ
which too often one believes to be as full as an egg or as a entirely
written page, analysis can now perceive why and how global processes
(economic, social, political, cultural) have formed urban space and
shaped the city, without creative action arising instantaneously and
deductively from these processes. Indeed, if they have influenced urban
rhythms and spaces, it is by enabling groups to insert themselves, to
cake charge of them, to appropriate them; and this by inventing, by
sculpting space (to use a metaphor), by giving themselves rhythms. Such
groups have also been innovative in how to live, to have a family, to
raise and educate children, to leave a greater or lesser place to women,
to use and transmit wealth. These transformations of everyday life
modified urban reality, not without having from it their motivations.
The city was at one and the same rime the place and the milieu, the
theatre and the stake of these complex interactions.
The introduction of temporal and spatial discontinuities in the theory
of the city (and the urban), in history and sociology, does not give one
the right to abuse it. Separations must not be substituted for
organicism and continuism by consecrating them by theory. If the city
appears as a specific level of social reality, general processes (of
which the most important and accessible were the generalization of
commercial exchanges, industrialization in such a global context, the
formation of competitive capitalism), did not take place above this
specific mediation. Moreover, the level of immediate relations, personal
and interpersonal (the family, the neighbourhood, crafts and guilds, the
division of labour between crafts, etc.) is only separated from urban
reality through an abstraction: the correct approach of knowledge cannot
change this abstraction into separation. Reflection emphasizes
articulations so that delineations do not disarticulate the real but
follow articulations. The methodological rule is to avoid confusion in
an illusory continuity as well as separations or absolute
discontinuities. Consequently, the study of articulations between the
levels of reality enables us to demonstrate the distortions and
discrepancies between levels rather than to blurr them.
The city is transformed not only because of relatively continuous
âglobal processesâ (such as the growth of material production over a
long period of time with its consequences for exchanges, or the
development of rationality) but also in relation to profound
transformations in the mode of production, in the relations between
âątown and countryâ, in the relations of class and property. The correct
approach consists in going from the most general knowledge to that which
concerns historical processes and discontinuities, their projection or
refraction onto the city and conversely, particular and specific
knowledge of urban reality to its global context.
The city and the urban cannot be understood without institutions
springing from relations of class and property. The city itself,
perpetual oeuvre and act, gives rise to specific institutions: that is,
municipal institutions. The most general institutions, those which
belong to the State, to the dominant religion and ideology have their
seat in the political, military and religious city. They coexist with
properly urban, administrative, and cultural institutions. Hence a
number of remarkable continuities through changes in society.
One knows that there was and there still is the oriental city,
expression and projection on the ground, effect and cause, of the
Asiatic mode of production; in this mode of production State power,
resting on the city, organizes economically a more or less extensive
agrarian zone, regulates and controls water, irrigation and drainage,
the use of land, in brief, agricultural production. There was in the era
of slavery, a city which organized its agricultural zone through
violence and by juridical rationality, but which undermined its own base
by replacing free peasants (landowners) with latifundial type
properties. In the West there was also the medieval city, rooted in a
feudal mode of production where agriculture was predominant, but which
was also place of commerce, theatre of class struggle between an
emerging bourgeoisie and territorial feudalism, the point of impact and
lever of royal State action. Finally, in the West, and in North America,
there has been the capitalist, commercial and industrial city, more or
less delimited by the political State whose formation accompanied the
rise of capitalism and whose bourgeoisie knew how to appropriate the
management of the whole of society.
Discontinuities are not only situated between urban formations, but also
between the most general of social relations, and the immediate
relations of individuals and groups (between codes and sub-codes). The
medieval city has however lasted for almost eight centuries. The rupture
of the big city tends to disintegrate urban cores of medieval origins,
although these persist in many small or medium-sized towns. Many urban
centres, which today perpetuate or protect the image of centrality
(which might have disappeared without them) are of very ancient origins.
This can explain without inasmuch legitimizing the illusion of
continuism and evolutionary ideology. This illusion and this ideology
have disguised the dialectical movement in the metamorphoses of cities
and the urban, and particularly in the relations of
âcontinuity-discontinuityâ. In the course of development some forms
change themselves into functions and enter structures which take them
back and transform them. Thus the extension of commercial exchanges from
the European Middle Ages onwards, contributes to this extraordinary
formation, the merchant city (integrating completely the merchants
established around the market square and market hall). Since
industrialization these local and localized markets have only one
function in urban life, in the relations of the city with the
surrounding countryside. A form which has become function enters into
new structures. And yet, planners have recently come to believe that
they have invented the commercial centre. Their thinking progressed from
that of a denuded space, reduced to a residential function, to that of a
commercial centrality which brought a difference, an enrichment. But
planners were only rediscovering the medieval city laid bare of its
historical relation to the countryside, of the struggle between the
bourgeoisie and feudalism, of the political relation with a royal and
despotic State, and as a consequence reduced to the unifunctionality of
local exchanges.
Forms, structures, urban functions (in the city, in the relations of the
city to the territory influenced or managed by it, in the relations with
society and State) acted upon each other modifying themselves, a
movement which thought can now reconstruct and master. Each urban
formation knew an ascent, an apogee, a decline. Its fragments and debris
were later used for/in other formations. Considered in its historical
movement, at its specific level (above and beyond global
transformations, hut above immediate and locally rooted relations, often
linked to the consecration of the ground, and therefore durable and
quasi-permanent in appearance), the city has gone through critical
periods. Destructurations and restructurations are followed in time and
space, always translated on the ground, inscribed in the
practico-material, written in the urban text, but coming from elsewhere:
from history and becoming. Not from the supersensible, but from another
level. Local acts and agents left their mark on cities, but also
impersonal relations of production and property, and consequently, of
classes and class struggles, that is, ideologies (religious and
philosophical, that is, ethical, a esthetical, legal, etc.). The
projection of the global on the ground and on the specific plane of the
city were accomplished only through mediations. In itself mediation, the
city was the place, the product of mediations, the terrain of their
activities, the object and objective of their propositions. Global
processes, general relations inscribed themselves in the urban text only
as transcribed by ideologies, interpreted by tendencies and political
strategies. It is this difficulty upon which one must now insist, that
of conceiving the city as a semantic system, semiotic or semiological
system arising from linguistics, urban language or urban reality
considered as grouping of signs. In the course of its projection on a
specific level, the general code of society is modified: the specific
code of the urban is an incomprehensible modulation, a version, a
translation without the original or origins. Yes, the city can be read
because it writes, because it was writing. However, it is not enough to
examine this without recourse to context. To write on this writing or
language, to elaborate the metalanguage of the city is not to know the
city and the urban. The context, what is below the text to decipher
(daily life, immediate relations, the unconscious of the urban, what is
little said and of which even less is written), hides itself in the
inhabited spaces â sexual and family life â and rarely confronts itself,
and what is above this urban text (institutions, ideologies), cannot be
neglected in the deciphering. A book is not enough. That one reads and
re-reads it, well enough. That one goes as far as to undertake a
critical reading of it, even better. It asks from knowledge questions
such as âwho and what? how? why? for whom?â These questions announce and
demand the restitution of the context. The city cannot therefore be
conceived as a signifying system, determined and closed as a system. The
taking into consideration the levels of reality forbids, here as
elsewhere, this sytematization. None the less, the city has this
singular capacity of appropriating all significations for saying them,
for writing them (to stipulate and to âsignifyâ them), including those
from the countryside, immediate life, religion and political ideology.
In the cities, monuments and festivities had this meaning.
During each critical period, when the spontaneous growth of the city
stagnates and when urban development oriented and characterized by
hitherto dominant social relations ends, then appears a planning
thought. This is more a symptom of change than of a continuously
mounting rationality or of an internal harmony (although illusions on
these points regularly reproduce themselves), as this thinking merges
the philosophy of the city in search of a with the divisive schemes for
urban space. To confuse this anxiety with rationality and organization
it is the ideology previously denounced. Concepts and theories make a
difficult path through this ideology.
At this point the city should be defined. If it is true that the concept
emerges little by little from these ideologies which convey it, it must
be conceived during this progress. We therefore here propose a first
definition of the city as a projection of society on the ground, chat
is, not only on the actual site, but at a specific level, perceived and
conceived by thought, which determines the city and the urban. Long-term
controversies over this definition have shown its lacunae. Firstly, it
requires more accuracy. What is inscribed and projected is not only a
far order, a social whole, a mode of production, a general code, it is
also a time, or rather, times, rhythms. The city is heard as much as
music as it is read as a discursive writing. Secondly, the definition
calls for supplements. It brings to light certain historical and generic
or genetic differences, but leaves aside other real differences: between
the cypes of cities resulting from history, between the effects of the
division of labour in the cities, between the persistent
âcity-territoryâ relations. Hence another definition which perhaps does
not destroy the first: the city as the ensemble of differences between
cities. In turn, this definition reveals itself to be insufficient, as
it places emphasis on particularities rather than on generalities,
neglecting the singularities of urban life, the ways of living of the
city, more properly understood as to inhabit. Hence another definition,
of plurality, coexistence and simultaneity in the urban of patterns,
ways of living urban life (the small house, the large social housing
estates, to-ownership, location, daily life and its changes for
intellectuals, craftsmen, shopkeepers, workers, etc.).
These definitions (relative to the levels of social reality), are not in
themselves exhaustive and do not exclude other definitions. If a
theoretician sees in the city the place of confrontations and of
(conflictual) relations between desire and need, between satisfactions
and dissatisfactions, if he goes as far as to describe the city as âsite
of desireâ, these determinations will be examined and taken into
consideration. It is not certain that they have a meaning limited to the
fragmentary science of psychology. Moreover, there would be the need to
emphasize the historical role of the city: the quickening of processes
(exchange and the market, the accumulation of knowledge and capitals,
the concentration of these capitals) and site of revolutions. Today, by
becoming a centre of decision-making, or rather, by grouping centres of
decision-making, the modern city intensifies by organizing the
exploitation of the whole society (not only the working classes, but
also other non-dominant social classes). This is not the passive place
of production or the concentration of capitals, but that of the urban
intervening as such in production (in the means of production).
The preceding considerations are sufficient to show that the analysis of
urban phenomena (the physical and social morphology of the city, or if
one prefers, the city, the urban and their connexion) requires the use
of all the methodological tools: form, function, structure, levels,
dimensions, text, context, field and whole, writing and reading, system,
signified and signifier, language and metalanguage, institutions, etc.
One also knows that none of these terms can attain a rigorous purity, be
defined without ambiguity, or escape multiple meaning. Thus the word
form takes on various meanings for the logician, for the literary
critic, for the aesthetician, and for the linguist.
The theoretician of the city and the urban will say that these terms are
defined as form of simultaneity, as field of encounters and exchanges.
This acceptance of the word form must be clarified. Let us again
consider the term function. The analysis distinguishes the functions
internal to the city, the functions of the city in relation to territory
(countryside, agriculture, villages and hamlets, smaller towns
subordinated within a network), and lastly, the functions of the city â
each city â in the social whole (the technical and social division of
labour between cities, various networks of relations, administrative and
political hierarchies). It is the same for structures. There is the
structure of the city (of each city, morphologically, socially,
topologically and topically), then the urban structure of society, and
finally the social structure of town-country relations. Hence a muddle
of analytical and partial determinations and the difficulties of a
global conception. Here as elsewhere three terms most often meet, whose
conflictual and (dialectical) relations are hidden under term by term
oppositions. There is the countryside, and the city and society with the
State which manages and dominates it (in its relations with the class
structure of that society). There is also as we have attempted to show,
general (and global) processes, the city as specificity and intermediary
level, then relations of immediacy (linked to a way of life, to
inhabiting, and to regulating daily life). This requires therefore more
precise definitions of each level, which we will not be able to separate
or confuse, but of which we shall have to show the articulations and
disarticulations, the projections of one upon the other, and the
different connections.
The highest level is found at the same time above and in the city. This
does not simplify the analysis. The social structure exists in the city,
makes itself apparent, signifies an order. Inversely, the city is a part
of the social whole; it reveals, because contains and incorporates them
within sentient matter, institutions and ideologies. Royal, imperial and
presidential buildings are a part of the city: the political part (the
capital). These buildings do not coincide with institutions, with
dominant social relations. And yet, these relations act upon them, by
representing social efficacy and âpresenceâ. At its specific level, the
city also contains the projection of these relations. To elucidate this
analysis by a particular case, social order in Paris is represented at
the highest level in/by the Ministry of the Interior, and at the
specific level by the prefecture of police and also by neighbourhood
police stations, without forgetting various police agencies acting
either at a global level, or in the subterranean shadow. Religious
ideology is signified at the highest level by the cathedral, by seats of
large religious organizations of the Church, and also by neighbourhood
churches and presbyteries, various local investments of
institutionalized religious practice.
At this level, the city manifests itself as a group of groups, with iu
double morphology (practico-sensible or material, on the one hand,
social on the other), It has a code of functioning focused around
particular institutions, such as the municipality with its services and
its problems, with its channels of information, its networks, its powers
of decision-making. The social structure is projected on this plane, but
this does not exclude phenomena unique to the city, to a particular
city, and the most diverse manifestations of urban life. Paradoxically,
taken at this level, the city is made up of uninhabited and even
uninhabitable spaces: public buildings, monuments, squares, streets,
large or small voids. It is so true that âhabitatâ does not make up the
city and that it cannot be defined by this isolated function.
At the ecological level, habitation becomes essential. The city envelops
it; it is form, enveloping chis space of âprivateâ life, arrival and
departure of networks of information and the communication of orders
(imposing the far order to the near order).
Two approaches arc possible. The first goes from the most general to the
most specific (from institutions to daily life) and then uncovers the
city as specific and (relatively) privileged mediation. The second
starts from this plan and constructs the general by identifying the
elements and significations of what is observable in the urban. It
proceeds in this manner to reach, from the observable, âprivateâ, the
concealed daily life: its rhythms, its occupations, its spatio-temporal
organization, its clandestine âcultureâ, its underground life.
Isotopies are defined at each level: political, religious, commercial,
etc. space. In relation to these isotopies, other levels are uncovered
as heterotopies. Meanwhile, at each level spatial oppositions are
uncovered which enter in chis relationship of isotopy-heterotopy. For
example, the opposition between social and owner-occupied housing.
Spaces at the specific level can also be classified according to the
criterion of isotopy-heterotopy, the city as a whole being the most
expanded isotopy, embracing others, or rather, superimposing itself over
others (over the spatial sub-wholes which are at one and the same time
subordinated and constitutive). Such a classification by opposition
should not exclude the analysis of levels, nor that of the movement of
the whole with its conflictual aspects (class relations among others),
At the ecological level, that of inhabiting, are constituted significant
ensembles, partial systems of signs, of which the âworld of the detached
houseâ offers a particularly interesting case. The distinction between
levels (each level implying in tum secondary levels) has the greatest
use in the analysis of essential relations, for example in understanding
how the âvalues of detached housingâ in France become the reference
point of social consciousness and the âvaluesâ of other types of
housing. Only the analysis of relations of inclusion-exclusion, of
belonging or non-belonging to a particular space of the city enables us
to approach these phenomena of great importance for a theory of the
city.
On its specific plane the city can appropriate existing political,
religious and philosophical meanings. It seizes them to say them, to
expose them by means â or through the voice â of buildings, monuments,
and also by streets and squares, by voids, by the spontaneous
theatricalization of encounters which take place in it, not forgetting
festivities and ceremonies (with their appropriate and designated
places). Beside the writing, there is also the even more important
utterance of the urban, these utterances speaking of life and death, joy
or sorrow. The city has this capacity which makes of it a significant
whole. None the less, to stress a previous remark, the city does not
accomplish this task gracefully or freely. One does not ask it.
Aestheticism, phenomenon of decline, comes later. Such as planning! In
the form of meaning, in the form of simultaneity and encounters, in the
form, finally of an âurbanâ language and writing, the city dispatches
orders. The far order is projected into the near order. This far order
is never or almost never unitary. There is religious order, political
order, moral order, each referring to an ideology with its practical
implications. Among these orders the city realizes on its plane a unity,
or rather, a syncretism. It dissimulates and veils their rivalries and
conflicts by making them imperative. It translates them as instructions
for action, as time management. It stipulates (signifies) with the
management of time a meticulous hierarchy of place, moments,
occupations, people. Moreover, it refracts these imperatives in a style,
inasmuch as there is a genuine urban life. This style characterizes
itself as architectural and is associated to art and the study of art
objects.
Therefore the semiology of the city is of greatest theoretical and
practical interest. The city receives and emits messages. These messages
are or are not understood (that is, are or are not coded or decoded).
Therefore, it can be apprehended from concepts derived from linguistics:
signifier and signified, signification and meaning. Nevertheless, it is
not without the greatest reservation or without precautions that one can
consider the city as a system, as a unique system of significations and
meanings and therefore of values. Here as elsewhere, there are several
systems (or if one prefers, several sub-systems). Moreover, semiology
does not exhaust the practical and ideological reality of the city. The
theory of the city as system of significations tends towards an
ideology; it separates the urban from its morphological basis and from
social practice, by reducing it to a âsignifier-signifiedâ relation and
by extrapolating from actually perceived significations. This is not
without a great naivety. If it is true that a Bororo village signifies,
and that the Greek city is full of meaning, are we to build vast Bororo
villages full of signs of Modernity? Or restore the agora with its
meaning at the centre of the new town?
The fetishization of the formal âsignifier-signifiedâ relationship
entails more serious inconveniences. It passively accepts the ideology
of organised consumption. Or rather, it contributes to it. In the
ideology of consumption and in ârealâ consumption (in quotations), the
consumption of signs plays an increasing role. It does not repress the
consumption of âpureâ spectacles, without activity and participation,
without oeuvre or product. It adds to it and superimposes itself upon it
as a determination. It is thus that advertising of consumer goods
becomes the principal means of consumption; it tends to incorporate art,
literature, poetry and to supplant them by using them as rhetoric. It
thus becomes itself the ideology of society; each âobjectâ, each âgoodâ
splits itself into a reality and an image, this being an essential part
of consumption. One consumes signs as well as objects: signs of
happiness, of satisfaction, of power, of wealth, of science, of
technology, etc. The production of these signs is integrated to global
production and plays a major integrative role in relation to other
productive and organizing social activities. The sign is bought and
sold; language becomes exchange value. Under the appearance of signs and
significations in general, it is the significations of this society
which are handed over to consumption. Consequently, he who conceives the
city and urban reality as system of signs implicitly hands them over to
consumption as integrally consumable: as exchange value in its pure
state. Changing sites into signs and values, the practice â material
into formal significations, this theory also changes into pure consumer
of signs he who receives them. Would not the Paris bis or ter conceived
by developers be the centres of consumption promoted to a superior level
by the intensity of the consumption of signs? Urban semiology is in
danger of placing itself at their service if it loses its naivety.
In truth, semiological analysis must distinguish between multiple levels
and dimensions. There is the utterance of the city: what happens and
takes place in the street, in the squares, in the voids, what is said
there. There is the language of the city: particularities specific to
each city which are expressed in discourses, gestures, clothing, in the
words and use of words by the inhabitants. There is urban language,
which one can consider as language of connotations, a secondary system
and derived within the denotative system (to use here Hjemslev and
Greimasâs terminology). Finally, there is the writing of the city: what
is inscribed and prescribed on its walls, in the layout of places and
their linkages, in brief, the use of time in the city by its
inhabitants.
Semiological analysis must also distinguish between levels, that of
semantemes or signifying elements (straight or cured lines, writing,
elementary forms of entry, doors and windows, corners, angles, etc.),
morphemes or signifying objects (buildings, streets, ere.) and lastly,
significant ensembles or super-objects, of which the city irself.
One must study how the global is signified (the semiology of power), how
the city is signified (that is the properly urban semiology) and how are
signified ways of living and inhabiting (that is the semiology of daily
life, of to inhabit and habitat). One cannot confuse the city as it
apprehends and exposes significations coming from nature, the country
and the landscape (the tree for example) and the city as place of
consumption of signs. That would be to confuse festivities with ordinary
consumption.
Let us not forget dimensions. The city has a symbolic dimension;
monuments but also voids, squares and avenues, symbolizing the cosmos,
the world, society, or simply the State. It has a paradigmatical
dimension; it implies and shows oppositions, the inside and the outside,
the centre and the periphery, the integrated and non-integrated to urban
society. Finally, it also possesses the syntagmatic dimension: the
connection of elements, the ariculation of isotopies and heterotopies.
At its specific level, the city presents itself as a privileged
sub-system because it is able to reflect and expose the other
sub-systems and to present itself as a âworldâ, a unique whole, within
the illusion of the immediate and the lived. In this capacity resides
precisely the charm, the tonicity, and the tonality specific to urban
life. But analysis dissipates this impression and unveils a number of
systems hidden in the illusion of oneness. The analyst has no right to
share this illusion and to consolidate it by maintaining himself at an
urban level. He must uncover instead the features of a greater
knowledge.
We have not finished making an inventory of sub-systems of
significations, and therefore of what semiological analysis can bring to
an understanding of the city and the urban. If we consider the sector of
owner-occupation and that of new social housing estates, we already know
that each of them constitutes a (partial) system of significations, and
that another system which overdetermines each of them is established
from their opposition. This is how the owner-occupiers of small houses
perceive and conceive themselves in the make-believe of habitat, and in
turn, the estates establish the logic of habitat and perceive themselves
according to this coercive rationality. At the same time and at the same
stroke, the sector of owner-occupation becomes the reference by which
habitat and daily life are appreciated; that practice is cloaked in
make-believe and signs.
Among systems of significations, those of architects deserve the
greatest critical attention. It often happens that talented men believe
themselves to be at the centre of knowledge and experience whereas they
remain at the centre of systems of writing, projections on paper,
visualizations. Architects tending on their part towards a system of
significations which they often call âplanningâ, it is not impossible
for analysts of urban reality, grouping together their piecemeal facts,
to constitute a somewhat different system of significations that they
can also baptize planning while they leave its programming to machines.
Critical analysis dissipates the privilege of the lived in urban
society. It is only a âplaneâ, or a level. Yet analysis does not make
this plane disappear. It exists â as a book. Who reads this open book?
Who crosses over its writing? It is not a well-defined subject and yet a
succession of acts and encounters constitute on this plane itself urban
life, the urban. This urban life tends to turn against themselves the
messages, orders and constraints coming from above. It attempts to
appropriate time and space by foiling dominations, by diverting them
from their goal, by deceit. It also intervenes more or less at the level
of the city and the way of inhabiting. In this way the urban is more or
less the oeuvre of its citizens instead of imposing itself upon them as
a system, as an already dosed book.
A theme which has been used and over-used, hyperinflated and
extrapolated, namely, ânature and cultureâ, originates from the relation
between town and country and deflects it. There are three terms in this
relation. In the same way, there are three terminologies in existing
reality (rurality, urban fabric, centrality) whose dialectical relations
are hidden beneath term to term oppositions, but also come to reveal
themselves in them. Nature as such escapes the hold of rationally
pursued action, as well as from domination and appropriation. More
precisely, it remains outside of these influences: it âisâ what flees:
it is reached by the imaginary; one pursues it and it flees into the
cosmos, or in the underground depths of the world. The countryside is
the place of production and oeuvres. Agricultural production gives birth
to products: the landscape is an oeuvre. This oeuvre emerges from the
earth slowly moulded, linked originally to the groups which occupy it by
a reciprocal consecration, later to be desecrated by the city and urban
life (which capture this consecration, condense it, then dissolve it
over through the ages by absorbing it into rationalicy). Where does this
ancient consecration of the ground to the tribes, peoples and nations
come from? From the obscure and menacing presence/absence of nature?
From the occupation of the ground which excludes strangers from this
possessed ground? From the social pyramid, which has its basis on this
ground and which exacts many sacrifices for the maintenance of a
threatened edifice? One does not prevent the other. What is important is
the complex movement by which the political city uses this sacred-damned
character of the ground, so that the economic (commercial) city can
desecrate it.
Urban life includes original mediations between town, country and
nature. As the village, whose relationship with the city, in history and
in actuality, is far from being well known. As are parks, gardens,
channelled waters. These mediations cannot be understood as such by city
dwellers without symbolisms and representations (ideological and
imaginary) of nature and the countryside.
The town and country relation has changed deeply during the course of
history, according to different periods and to modes of production. It
has been sometimes profoundly conflictual, and at other times appeased
and close to an association. Moreover, during the same period, very
different kinds of relations are manifested. Thus in Western feudalism,
the territorial lord threatens the re-emerging city, where the merchants
find their meeting place, their homebase, the place of their strategy.
The city responds to this action of landed power, and a class struggle
ensues, sometimes quiescent, sometimes violent. The city liberates
itself, not by integrating itself by becoming an aristocracy of
commoners, but by integraring itself with the monarchic State (for which
it provided an essential condition). On the other hand, during the same
period, in so far as one can speak of an Islamic feudalism, the âlordâ
rules over the city of craftsmen and shopkeepers and from it, over a
surrounding countryside, often reduced to gardens and to sparse and
insignificant cultivations. In such a relationship, there is neither the
kernel nor the possibility of a class struggle. From the outset this
takes away any historical dynamism and future from this social
structure, although not without conferring upon it other charms, those
of an exquisite urbanism. The class struggle, creative, productive of
oeuvres and new relations, takes place with a certain barbarism which
characterizes the West (including the most âbeautifulâ of its cities).
Today, the town and country relation is changing, an important aspect of
a general transformation. In industrial countries, the old exploitation
by the city, centre of capital accumulation, of the surrounding
countryside, gives way to more subtle forms of domination and
exploitation, the city becoming centre of decision-making and apparently
also of association. However that may be, the expanding city attacks the
countryside, corrodes and dissolves it. This is not without the
paradoxical effects already mentioned. Urban life penetrates peasant
life, dispossessing it of its traditional features: crafts, small
centres which decline to the benefit of urban centres (commercial,
industrial, distribution networks, centres of decision-making, etc.).
Villages become ruralized by losing their peasant specificity. They
align themselves with the city but by resisting and sometimes by
fiercely keeping themselves to themselves.
Will the urban fabric, with its greater or lesser meshes, catch in its
nets all the territory of industrialized countries? Is this how the old
opposition between town and country is overcome? One can assume it, but
not without some critical reservations. If a generalized confusion is
thus perceived, the countryside losing itself into the heart of the
city, and the city absorbing the countryside and losing itself in it,
this confusion can be theoretically challenged. Theory can refute all
strategies resting on this conception of the urban fabric. Geographers
have coined to name this confusion an ugly but meaningful neologism: the
rurban. Within this hypothesis, the expansion of the city and
urbanization would cause the urban (the urban life) to disappear. This
seems inadmissible. In other words, the overcoming of opposition cannot
be conceived as a reciprocal neutralization. There is no theoretical
reason to accept the disappearance of centrality in the course of the
fusion of urban society with the countryside. The âurbanity-ruralityâ
opposition is accentuated rather than dissipated, while the town and
country opposition is lessened. There is a shifting of opposition and
conflict. What is more, we all know that worldwide, the town and country
conflict is far from being resolved. If it is true that the town and
country separation and contradiction (which envelops without reducing to
itself the opposition of the two terms) is part of the social division
of labour, it must be acknowledged that this division is neither
overcome nor mastered. Far from it. No more than the separation of
nature and society, and that of the material and the intellectual
(spiritual). Overcoming this today cannot not take place from the
opposition between urban fabric and centrality. It presupposes the
invention of new urban forms.
As far as industrial countries are concerned, one can conceive
polycentric cities, differentiated and renovated centralities, even
mobile centralities (cultural ones for example). The critique of
planning as ideology can be about such and such a conception of
centrality (for example, the distinction between the urban and the
centres of information and decision-making). Neither traditional city
(separated from the countryside to better dominate it), nor the
Megalopolis without form or fabric, without woof or warp, would be the
guiding idea. The disappearance of centrality is neither called for
theoretically nor practically. The only question that can be asked is
this one: âWhat social and political forms, what theory will one entrust
with the realization on the ground of a renovated centrality and fabric,
freed from their degradations?â
Let us trace hypothetically from left to right an axis going from zero
point in urbanization (the non-existence of the city, the complete
predominance of agrarian life, agricultural production and the
countryside) to full urbanization (the absorption of the countryside by
the city and the total predominance of industrial production, including
agriculture). This abstract picture momentarily places the
discontinuities in parentheses. To a certain extent it will enable us to
locate the critical points, that is, the breaks and discontinuities
themselves. Quite quickly on the axis, quite near to the beginning, let
us mark the political city (in effect achieved and maintained in the
Asiatic mode of production) which organizes an agrarian environment by
dominating it. A little further, let us mark the appearance of the
commercial city, which begins by relegating commerce to its periphery (a
heterotopy of outlying areas, fairs and markets, places assigned to
foreigners, to strangers specialized in exchanges) and which later
integrates the market by integrating itself to a social structure based
on exchanges, expanded communications, money and movable wealth. There
then comes a decisive critical point, where the importance of
agriculrure retreats before the importance of craft and industrial
production, of the market, exchange value and a rising capitalism. This
critical point is located in Western Europe around the sixteenth
century. Soon it is the arrival of the industrial city, with its
implications (emigration of dispossed and disaggregated peasant
populations cowards the city â a period of great urban concentration).
Urban society is heralded long after society as a whole has tilted
towards the urban. Then there is the period when the expanding city
proliferates, produces far-flung peripheries (suburbs), and invades the
countryside. Paradoxically, in this period when the city expands
inordinately, the form (the practicomaterial morphology, the form of
urban life) of the traditional city explodes. This double process
(industrialization-urbanization) produces the double movement:
explosion-implosion, condensation-dispersion (the explosion already
mentioned). It is therefore around this critical point that can be found
the present problematic of the city and urban reality.
[]
The phenomena which unfold around the situation of crisis are nor less
complex than the physical phenomena which accompany the breaking of the
sound barrier (to use a simple metaphor). It is to this end â the
analysis in the proximity of the critical point â that we have
previously attempted to assemble the essential conceptual tools.
Knowledge which would dissociate itself from this situation would fall
back into blind speculation or myopic specialization.
Too badly placed, the critical points, breaks and lacunae can have as
serious consequences as organicist, evolutionist or continuist
negligence. Today, sociological thinking and political strategy, and
so-called planning thought, tend to jump from the level of habitat and
to inhabit (ecological level, housing, buildings, neighbourhood and thus
the domain of the architect), to the general level (scale of land use
planning, planned industrial production, global urbanization), passing
over the city and the urban. Mediation is placed into parentheses and
the specific level is omitted. Why? For significant reasons related
firstly to the disregard of the critical point.
The rational planning of production, land use planning, global
industrialization and urbanization are essential aspects of the
âsocialization of societyâ. Let us pause for a moment on these words. A
Marxist tradition with reformist inflections uses them to designate the
complexification of society and social relations, the rupture of
cornpartimentalization, the growing multiplicity of connexions,
communications and information, the fact that an accentuated technical
and social division of labour implies a stronger unity in branches of
industry, market functions and production itself. This approach insists
on exchanges and places of exchange: it emphasizes the quantity of
economic exchanges and leaves aside quality, the essential difference
between use value and exchange value. In this perspective, the exchanges
of merchandise and of consumer goods level and align direct exchanges to
themselves, that is, communications which do not go through existing
networks, and through institutions (namely at the âinferiorâ level, the
immediate relations, and at the âsuperiorâ level, the political
relations resulting from knowledge). The answer given to reformist
continuism is the thesis of disconrinuism and radical revolutionary
voluntarism: a rupture, a break, are essential for the social character
of productive labour to abolish relations of production linked to
private ownership of these means of production. However, the thesis of
the âsocialization of societyâ, an evolutionist, continuist and
reformist interpretation, takes on another meaning if one observes that
these words refer to, badly and incompletely, the urbanization of
society. The multiplication and complexification of exchanges in the
widest sense of the term cannot take place without the existence of
privileged places and moments, without these places and moments of
meeting freeing themselves from the constraints of the market, without
the law of exchange value being mastered, and without the relations
which condition profits be altered. Until then culture dissolves,
becoming an object of consumption, an opportunity for profit, production
for the market: the âculturalâ dissimulates more than one trap. Until
now a revolutionary interpretation has not taken into account these new
elements. Would it not be possible that the more rigorous definition of
the relations between industrialization and urbanization, in the
situation of crisis, and around the critical point, will help to
overcome the contradiction of absolute continuism and discontinuism, of
reformist evolutionism and total revolution? If one wants to go beyond
the market, the law of exchange value, money and profit, is it not
necessary to define the place of this possibility: urban society, the
city as use value?
The paradox of this critical situation, a crucial element of the
problem, is that the crisis of the city is world-wide. It presents
itself as a dominant aspect of universality in progress as do technology
and the rational organization of industry. Yet, the practical causes and
ideological reasons of this crisis vary according to political regimes,
the societies, and even the countries concerned. A critical analysis of
these phenomena could only be legitimated by comparison, but many
elements of this comparison are missing. In underdeveloped countries,
highly industrialized capitalist countries, socialist countries unevenly
developed, everywhere the city explodes. The traditional form of
agrarian society is transforming itself, but differently. In a number of
poor countries, shanty towns are a characteristic phenomenon, while in
highly industrialized countries, the proliferation of the city into
âurban fabricâ, suburbs, residential areas, and its relation with urban
life is what causes the problem.
How gather together the elements of such a comparison? In the United
States, the difficulties of Federal administration, its conflicts with
local authorities, the terms of reference of âurban governmentâ, divided
among the manager, the political boss and the mayor and his
municipality, cannot be explained in the same way as the power conflicts
(administrative and juridical) in Europe and in France, where the
consequences of industrialization besiege and explode urban cores dating
from precapitalist or pre-industrial times. In the United States, the
urban core hardly exists except in some privileged cities, yer local
authorities have greater legal guarantees and more extensive powers than
in France where monarchical centralization attacked these urban
âfreedomsâ very early on. In Europe, as elsewhere, one cannot attribute
only to the growth of cities, or only to problems of traffic,
difficulties which are both different and comparable. Here and there,
from one part or another, the whole society is questioned one way or
another. As it is preoccupied (through ideologues and statesmen) to
principally plan industry and organize enterprise, modern society
appears little able to give solutions to the urban problematic and to
act otherwise than by small technical measures which only protract the
current state of affairs. Everywhere the relation between the three
levels analysed above becomes confused and conflictual, the dynamic
element of the contradiction changing according to the social and
political context. In so-called developing countries, the breakdown of
agrarian structure pushes dispossessed peasants, ruined and eager for
change, towards the cities. The shanty town welcomes them and becomes
the (inadequate) mediator between town and country, agricultural and
industrial production. It often consolidates itself and offers a
substitute of urban life, miserable and yet intense, to those which it
shelters. In other countries, particularly in socialist countries,
planned urban growth attracts labour to the cities recruited from the
countryside resulting in overcrowding, the construction of
neighbourhoods or residential sectors whose relation to urban life is
not always discernible. To sum up, a world-wide crisis in agriculture
and traditional peasant life accompanies, underlies and aggravates a
world-wide crisis of the traditional city. This is a change on a
planetary scale. The old rural animal and urban animal (Marx), disappear
together. Do they leave room to âmanâ? That is the basic problem. The
major theoretical and practical difficulty comes from the fact that the
urbanization of industrial society does not happen without the breakup
of what we still call âthe cityâ. Given that urban society is built on
the ruins of the city, how can we grasp the breadth and manifold
contradictions of these phenomena? That is the critical point. The
distinction between the three levels (global process of
industrialization and urbanization â urban society, the specific scale
of the city-ways of living and conditions of daily life in the urban)
tends to become blurred as does the distinction between town and
country. And yet, this difference between the three levels is more than
ever crucial to avoid confusion and misunderstandings, to combat
strategies which find in this conjuncture an opportunity to disintegrate
the urban into industrial and or residential planning.
Yes, this city which has gone through so much adversity and so many
metamorphoses, since its archaic cores so dose to the village, this
admirable social form, this exquisite oeuvre of praxis and civilization,
unmakes and remakes itself under our very eyes. The urgency of the
housing question in conditions of industrial growth has concealed and
still conceals the problems of the city. Political strategists, more
attentive to the immediate, perceived and still perceive only these
issues. When these overall problems emerged, under the name of planning,
they have been subordinated to the general organization of industry.
Attacked both from above and below, the city is associated to industrial
enterprise: it figures in planning as a cog: it becomes the material
device apt to organize production, control the daily life of the
producers and the consumption of products. Having been reduced to the
status of device, it extends this management to the consumers and
consumption; it serves to regulate, to lay one over the other, the
production of goods and the destruction of products with that devouring
activity, âconsumptionâ. It did not have, it has no meaning but as an
oeuvre, as an end, as place of free enjoyment, as domain of use value.
Or, it is subjugated to constraints, to the imperatives of an
âequilibriumâ within narrowly restrictive conditions; it is no more than
the instrument of an organization which moreover is unable to
consolidate itself by determining its conditions of stability and
equilibrium, an organization according to whose catalogue and teleguide
individual needs are satisfied by annihilating catalogued objects whose
probability of durability (obsolescence) is itself a scientific field.
In the past, reason had its place of birth, its seat, its home in the
city. In the face of rurality, and of peasant life gripped by nature and
the sacralized earth full of obscure powers, urbanity asserted itself as
reasonable. Today, rationality seems to be (or appears to be, or
pretends to be) far from the city, above it, on a national or
continental scale. It refuses the city as a moment, as an element, as a
condition; it acknowledges it only as an instrument and a means. In
France and elsewhere, State bureaucratic rationalism and that of
industrial organization supported by the demands of large private
enterprises, are going the same way. Simultaneously there is enforced a
simplifying functionalism and social groups which go beyond the urban.
The organism disappears under the guise of organization, so that
organicism coming from the philosophers appears as an ideal model. The
statutes of urban âzonesâ and âareasâ are reduced to a juxtaposition of
spaces, of functions, of elements on the ground. Sectors and functions
are tightly subordinated to centres of decision-making. Homogeneity
overwhelms the differences originating from nature (the site), from
peasant surroundings (territory and the soil), from history. The city,
or what remains of it, is built or is rearranged, in the likeness of a
sum or combination of elements. Now, as soon as the combination is
conceived, perceived and anticipated as such, combinations are not
easily recognizable; the differences fall into the perception of their
whole. So chat while one may rationally look for diversity, a feeling of
monotony covers these diversities and prevails, whether housing,
buildings, alleged urban centres, organized areas are concerned. The
urban, not conceived as such but attacked face on and from the side,
corroded and gnawed, has lost the features and characteristics of the
oeuvre, of appropriation. Only constraints are projected on the ground,
in a state of permanent dislocation. From the point of view of housing,
the ordering and arrangement of daily life, the massive use of the car
(âprivateâ means of transpon), mobility (besides contained and
insufficient), and the influence of the mass media, have detached from
site and territory individuals and groups (families, organized bodies).
Neighbourhood and district fade and crumble away: the people (the
âinhabitantsâ) move about in a space which tends towards a geometric
isotopy, full of instructions and signals, where qualitative differences
of places and moments no longer matter. Certainly these are inevitable
processes of dissolution of ancient forms, but which produce contempt,
mental and social misery. There is a poverty of daily life as soon as
nothing has replaced the symbols, the appropriations, the styles, the
monuments, the times and rhythms, the different and qualified spaces of
the traditional city. Urban society, because of the dissolution of this
city submitted to pressures which it cannot withstand, tends on the one
hand to blend with the planned land use of the territory into the âurban
fabricâ determined by the constraints of traffic, and on the other hand,
into dwelling units such as those of the detached house and the housing
estates. The extension of the city produced suburbs, then the suburb
engulfed the urban core. The problems have been inversed, when they are
not misunderstood. Would it not be more coherent, more rational and
agreeable to work in the suburbs and live in the city rather than work
in the city while living in a hardly habitable suburb? The centralized
management of âthingsâ and of âcultureâ tries to avoid this intermediary
tier, the city. And more: the State, centres of decision-making, the
ideological, economic and political powers, can only consider with a
growing suspicion this social form which tends towards autonomy, which
can only live specifically, which comes between them and the
âinhabitantâ, worker or not, productive or unproductive worker, but man
and citizen as well as city dweller. Since the last century, what is the
essence of the city for power? It ferments, full of suspect activities,
of delinquence, a hotbed of agitation. State powers and powerful
economic interests can think only of one strategy: to devalorize,
degrade, destroy, urban society. In the course of these processes, there
are determinisms, there are strategies, spontaneities and concened acts.
Subjective and ideological contradictions, âhumanistâ worries impede but
do not halt these strategic actions. The city prevents the powers that
be from manipulating at will the citizen-city dweller, individuals,
groups, bodies. As a result, the crisis of the city is linked not to
rationality as such, definable from a philosophical tradition, it
relates to explicit forms of rationality: state, bureaucratic, economic,
or rather, âeconomisticâ, economism being an ideology endowed with an
apparatus. This crisis of the city is accompanied here and there with a
crisis of urban institutions (municipal) due to the double pressure from
the State and industrial enterprise. Sometimes the State, sometimes
private enterprise, sometimes both (rivals in competition, but often
associates) tend to commandeer the functions, duties, and prerogatives
of urban society. In certain capitalist countries, does âprivateâ
enterprise leave to the State, to institutions, and âpublicâ bodies any
other thing than what it refuses to assume because it is too costly?
And yet, it is on this shaky foundation that urban society and the urban
persist and even intensify. Social relations continue to become more
complex, to multiply and intensify through the most painful
contradictions. The form of the urban, its supreme reason, namely
simultaneity and encounter, cannot disappear. Urban reality, at the very
heart of its dislocation, persists and becomes more dense in the centres
of decision-making and information. The inhabitants (which ones? â itâs
up to research and researchers to find them!) reconstitute centres,
using places to restitute even derisory encounters. The use (use value)
of places, monuments, differences, escape the demands of exchange, of
exchange value. A big game is played before us, with various episodes
whose meaning is not always evident. The satisfaction of basic needs is
unable to kill the disaffectation of fundamental desires (or of the
fundamental desire). As a place of encounters, focus of communication
and information, the urban becomes what it always was: place of desire,
permanent disequilibrium, seat of the dissolution of normalities and
constraints, the moment of play and of the unpredictable. This moment
includes the implosion-explosion of latent violence under the terrible
constraints of a rationality which identifies itself with the absurd.
From this situation is born a critical contradiction: a tendency towards
destruction of the city, as well as a tendency towards the
intensification of the urban and the urban problematic.
This critical analysis calls for a decisive addition. To attribute the
crisis of the city to a confining rationality, productivism and
economism, and to a planning centralization first and foremost concerned
with growth, to the bureaucracy of State and enterprise is not
incorrect. Yet, this viewpoint does not go much beyond the horizon of
the most classical philosophical rationalism, that of liberal humanism.
He who wishes to propose the form of a new urban society by
strengthening this kernel, the urban, which survives in the fissures of
planned and programmed order, must go further. If one wants to conceive
an âurban manâ no longer in the image of classical humanism, theoretical
elaboration owes it to itself to refine concepts. Until now, in theory
as in practice, the double process of industrialization and of
urbanization has not been mastered. The incomplete teachings of Marx and
Marxist thought have been misunderstood. For Marx himself,
industrialization contained its finality and meaning, later giving rise
to the dissociation of Marxist thought into economism and philosophism.
Marx did not show (and in his time he could not) that urbanization and
the urban contain the meaning of industrialization. He did not see that
industrial production implied the urbanization of society, and that the
mastery of industrial potentials required specific knowledge concerning
urbanization. Industrial production, after a certain growth, produces
urbanization, providing it with conditions, and possibilities. The
problematic is displaced and becomes that of urban development. The
works of Marx (notably Capital) contained precious indications on the
city and particularly on the historical relations between town and
country. They do not pose the urban problem. In Marxâs time, only the
housing problem was raised and studied by Engels. Now, the problem of
the city is immensely greater than that of housing. The limits of
Marxist thought have not been really understood. Supporters as well as
adversaries have sowned trouble, by poorly assimilating the
methodological and theoretical principles of this thought. Neither
criticism from the right, nor criticism from the left have assessed the
contributions and the limits. These limits have not yet been overtaken
by an approach which does not reject, but deepens acquired knowledge.
The implicit sense of industrialization has therefore been badly
clarified. In theoretical reflection chis process has not acquired its
meaning. Moreover, one has looked for meaning elsewhere, or one has
abandoned the meaning and the research of meaning.
The âsocialization of societyâ, misunderstood by reformists has
prevented urban transformation (in, by, for, the city). It has not been
understood chat this socialization has urbanization as its essence. What
has been âsocializedâ? By turning them over to consumption, signs. Signs
of the city, of urban life, as the signs of nature and the countryside,
as those of joy and happiness, delivered to consumption without an
effective social practice enabling the urban to enter daily life. Urban
life faces needs only reluctantly, through the poverty of social needs
of âsocialized societyâ, through daily consumption and its own signs in
advertising, fashion, aestheticism. At this new moment of analysis, is
thus conceived the dialectical movement which carries the forms, the
contours, the determinisms and the constraints, the servitudes and the
appropriations towards a troubled horizon.
Urban life, urban society and the urban, detached by a particular social
practice (whose analysis will continue) from their half ruined
morphological base, and searching for a new base, these are the contexts
of the critical point. The urban cannot be defined either as attached to
a material morphology (on the ground, in the practicomaterial), or as
being able to detach itself from it. It is not an intemporal essence,
nor a system among ocher systems or above other systems. It is a mental
and social form, that of simultaneity, of gathering, of convergence, of
encounter (or rather, encounters). It is a quality born from quantities
(spaces, objects, products). It is a difference, or rather, an ensemble
of differences. The urban contains the meaning of industrial production,
as appropriation contains the sense of technical domination over nature,
the latter becoming absurd without the former. It is a field of
relations including notably the relation of time (or of times; cyclical
rhythms and linear durations) with space (or spaces: isotopics and
heterotopies). As place of desire and bond of times, the urban could
present itself as signifiers whose signified we are presently looking
for (that is, practico-material ârealitiesâ which would enable, with an
adequate morphological and material base, to realize it in space).
Lacking adequate theoretical elaboration, the double process
(industrialization- urbanization) has been severed and its aspects
separated, to be therefore consigned to the absurd. Grasped by a higher
and dialectical rationality, conceived in its duality and
contradictions, this process could not leave the urban aside. On the
contrary: it understands it. Therefore, what should be incriminated is
not reason, but a particular rationalism, a constricted rationality, and
its limits. The world of merchandise has its immanent logic of money and
exchange value generalized without limits. Such a form, that of exchange
and equivalence, is indifferent towards urban form; it reduces
simultaneity and encounters to those of the exchanges and the meeting
place to where the contract or quasi-contract of equivalent exchange is
concluded: the market. Urban society, a collection of acts taking place
in time, privileging a space (site, place) and privileged by it, in turn
signifiers and signified, has a logic different from that of
merchandise. It is another world. The urban is based on use value. This
conflict cannot be avoided. At most, economic and productivist
rationality seeks to push beyond all limits the production of products
(exchangeable objects of exchange value) by suppressing the oeuvre, this
productivist rationality makes itself out to be knowledge, while
containing an ideological component tied to its very essence. Maybe it
is only ideology, valorizing constraints, those which come from existing
determinisms, those of industrial production and the market of products,
those coming from its fetishism of policy. Ideology presents these real
constraints as rational. Such a rationality is not innocuous. The worse
danger which it harbours comes from it wanting itself and calling itself
synthetical. It purports to lead to synthesis and make âmen of
synthesisâ (either from philosophy, or from science, or lastly, from an
âinterdisciplinaryâ research). Now, this is an ideological illusion. Who
has right of synthesis? Certainly not a civil servant of synthesis,
accomplishing this function in a way guaranteed by institutions.
Certainly not he who extrapolates from an analysis or several analyses.
Only the practical capacity of realization has the right to collect the
theoretical elements of synthesis, by doing it. Is it the role of
political power? Maybe, but not any political force: not the political
State as an institution or sum of institutions, not statesmen as such.
Only the critical examination of strategies enables us to give an answer
to this questioning. The urban can only be confined to a strategy
prioritizing the urban problematic, the intensification of urban life,
the effective realization of urban society (that is, its morphological,
material and practice-material base).
The ambiguity, or more exactly, the polysemy or plurality of meanings,
of this term, âformâ, has already been remarked upon. It was not really
necessary, being obvious. The same goes for the polysemy of the terms
âfunctionâ, âstructureâ etc. None the less we cannot rest there and
accept the situation. How many people believe they have said and
resolved everything when they use one of these fetish words! The
plurality and confusion of the meanings serve an absence of thought and
poverty which takes itself for wealth.
The only way to clarify the meaning of the term is to begin from its
most abstract acceptance. Only scientific abstraction without contents,
distinguished from verbal abstraction and opposed to speculative
abstraction, enables transparent definitions. Therefore, to define form,
one must begin from formal logic and logico-mathematical structures. Not
so as to isolate or fetishize them, but, on the contrary, to catch their
relation to the ârealâ. This is not without some difficulties and
disadvantages. The transparency and clarity of âpureâ abstraction are
not accessible to all. Most people are either myopic or blind to it. A
âcultureâ is necessary not only to understand the abstract, but far more
to attain the disturbing frontiers which at one and the same time
distinguish and unite the concrete and the abstract, knowledge and art,
mathematics and poetry. To elucidate the meaning of the word âformâ, one
will have to refer to a very general, very abstract theory, the theory
of forms. It is dose to a philosophical theory of knowledge, extending
it and yet very different, since on the one hand it designates its own
historical and âculturalâ conditions and on the other it rests upon
difficult logico-mathematical considerations.
Proceeding by stages a socially recognized âformâ will be examined; for
example, the contract. There are many kinds of contracts: the marriage
contract, the work contract, the sales contract, etc. The contents of
social acts defined as contractual are therefore very different.
Sometimes they relate to the regulation of relations between two
individuals of different sexes (the sexual relationship taking second
place in the social regulation of assets and their transmission as they
relate to children and inheritance). Sometimes they relate to the
regulation of relations between two individuals of different social and
even class status: employer and employee, boss and worker. Sometimes
what is involved is the submission to a social regularity of the
relationship between seller and buyer, etc. These particular situations
have none the less a common feature: reciprocity in a socially
constituted and instituted engagement. Each engages himself vis-a-vis
the other to accomplish a certain sort of action explicitly or
implicitly stipulated. Moreover, one knows that this reciprocity entails
some fiction, or rather, that as soon as it is concluded, it reveals
itself to be fictional, inasmuch as it does not fall into contractual
stipulation and under the rule of law. Sexual reciprocity between
spouses becomes social and moral fiction (the âconjugal dutyâ). The
reciprocity of engagement between boss and worker establishes them on
the same level only fictionally. And so on and so forth. Nevertheless,
these fictions have a social existence and influence. They are the
various contents of a general juridical form with which jurists operate
and which become the codification of social relations: the civil code.
It is the same for reflective thought which has extremely diverse
contents: objects, situations, activities. From this diversity emerge
more or less fictional or real domains: science, philosophy, art, etc.
These many objects, these domains somewhat small in number, relate to a
logical formulation. Reflection is codified by a form common to all
contents, which is born out of their differences.
Form detaches itself from content, or rather, contents. Thus freed, it
emerges pure and transparent: intelligible. That much more intelligible
as decanted from content, âpurerâ. Bte here is the paradox. As such, in
its purity, it has no existence. It is not real, it is not. By detaching
itself from its content, form detaches itself from the concrete. The
summit, the crest of the real, the key to the real (of its penetration
by knowledge and the action which changes it), it places itself outside
the real. Philosophers have tried to understand for two thousand years.
None the less, philosophy brings the theoretical elements to this
knowledge. The approach is in several stages and has a strategic
objective. That is to grasp through the movement of reflection which
purifies forms and its own form, and which codifies and formalizes the
inherent and hidden movement of the relation between form and content.
There is no form without content. No content without form. What offers
itself to analysis is always a unity of form and content. Analysis
breaks this unity. It allows the purity of form to appear, and form
refers back to content. Yet, this indissoluble unity, broken by
analysis, is conflictual (dialectical). By turns thought goes from
transparent form to the opacity of contents, of the substantiality of
these contents to the inexistence of âpureâ form, in a ceaseless if not
momentary movement. Nevertheless, on the one hand, reflection tends to
dissociate forms (and its own logical form) from contents, by
constituting absolute âessencesâ, by establishing the reign of essences.
And on the other hand, practice and empiricism tend to ascertain
contents, to be satisfied with such certitude, to sojourn in the opacity
of various contents, accepted in their differences. For dialectical
reason, contents overflow form and form gives access to contents. Thus
form has a double âexistenceâ. It is and is not. It has reality only in
contents, and yet detaches itself from them. It has a mental and a
social existence. Mentally the contract is defined by a form quite close
to logic: reciprocity. Socially, this form regulates countless
situations and activities; it confers upon them a structure, it
maintains them and even valorizes them, including as form an evaluation
and involving a âconsensusâ. As for the logico-mathematical form, its
mental existence is obvious. What is less obvious is that it involves a
fiction: the purely reflective disembodied theoretical man. As for its
social existence, it should be shown at length. Indeed, to this form are
attached multitudinous social activities: to count, define, classify
(objects, situations, activities), rationally organized, predicted,
planned and even programmed.
Reflection which (in new terms) extends the long meditation and the
problematic of philosophers, can elaborate a scheme of forms. It is a
sort of analytical grid to decipher the relations between the real and
thought. This (provisional and modifiable) grid moves from the most
abstract to the most concrete, and therefore from the least to the most
immediate. Each form presents itself in its double existence as mental
and social.
I. Logical form
Mentally: it is the principle of identity: A=A. It is void essence
without content. In its absolute purity it is supreme transparency
(difficult to grasp, for reflection can neither hold it or keep itself
within it and yet it has tautology as its point of departure and
return). Indeed, this tautology is what all propositions have in common
which otherwise have nothing in common with each other by content, or
the designated (designatum, denoted). As Wittgenstein has shown, this
tautology A=A is the centre, emptied of substance of all enunciated, of
all propositions.
Socially: understanding and the conventions of understanding over and
above misunderstandings. The impossible possibility to make effective
stopping, to define everything, to say everything and to agree on the
rules of understanding. But also, verbalism, verbiage, repetitions, pure
talk. But again pleonasms, vicious circles (including the great social
pleonasms, for bureaucracy which engenders bureacracy to maintain the
bureaucratic form â social logics which tend towards their pure
maintenance to the extent of destroying their content and thus
themselves, showing their emptiness).
II. Mathematical form
Mentally: identity and difference, equality in difference. Enumeration
(of the elements of a whole, etc). Order and measure.
Socially: distributions and classifications (in space, generally
privileged as such, but also in time). Scheduling. Quantification and
quantitative rationality. Order and measure subordinating to themselves
desires and desire, quality and qualities.
III. Form of language
Mentally: coherence, the capacity to articulate distinct elements, to
confer to them significations and meanings, to emit and decipher
messages according to their coded conventions.
Socially: the cohesion of relations, their subordination to the demands
and constraints of cohesion, the ritualization of relations, their
formalization and codification.
IV. Form of exchange
Mentally: confrontation and discussion, comparison and adjustments of
activities, needs, produces of labour, etc., that is, equivalence.
Socially: exchange value, the commodity form (as identified, formulated
and formalized by Marx in chapter I of Capital, with an implicit
reference to formal logic and to logico-mathemacical formalism).
V. Contractual form
Mentally: reciprocity.
Socially: the codification of social relations based on murual
engagement.
VI. Form of the practico-material object
Mentally: incernal equilibrium perceived and conceived as âobjectiveâ
(or âobjectalâ) property. Symmetry.
Socially: the anticipation of this equilibrium and this symmetry,
demanded by objects or denied (including among living and thinking
âbeing;â), as well as social objects such as houses, buildings, utensils
and instruments, etc.
VII. Written form
Mentally: recurrence, synchronic fixation of what has occurred over
time, going backwards and returning along a fixed becoming.
Socially: the accumulation in time on the basis of fixation and the
conversation of what is acquired, the constraint of writing and
writings, terror before the written and the scruggle of the spirit
against the letter, the power of speech against the inscribed and the
prescribed, the becoming against the immutable and the reified.
VIII. Urban form
Mentally: simultaneity (of events, perceptions, and elements of a whole
in the ârealâ).
Socially: the encounter and the concentration of what exists around, in
the environment (assets and products, acts and activities, wealth) and
consequently, urban society as privileged social site, as meaning of
productive and consuming activities, as meeting between the oeuvre and
the product.
We will leave aside repetition which some (among them Nietzsche), have
considered to be the supreme form, existential form, or form of
existence.
It is almost evident that in so~called modern society, simultaneity is
intensified and becomes more dense, that the capacities for encounter
and assembly become strengthened. Communications speed up to
quasi-instantaneity. Ascendent or descendent circuits of information
flow and are diffused from this centrality. This aspect of the
âsocialization of societyâ has already been emphasized (reservations
having been made about the âreformistâ nature of this well-known
formulation).
It is just as evident that under the same conditions dispersion
increases: the division of labour is pushed to the extreme segregation
of social groups and material and spiritual separations. These
dispersions can only be conceived or appreciated by reference to the
form of simultaneity. Without this form, dispersion and separation are
purely and simply glimpsed, accepted, confirmed as facts. Thus form
enables us to designate the content, or rather, contents. Movement in
its emergence reveals a hidden movement, the dialectical (conflictual)
movement of content and urban form: the problematic. The form in which
is inscribed this problematic asks questions which are a part of it.
Before whom and for whom is simultaneity established, the contents of
urban life assembled?
In fact, the rationality we see used in practice (including applied
planning), this limited rationality is exercised especially according to
the modalities of a very advanced and prepared analytical intelligence,
endowed with great means of pressure. This analytical intellect endows
itself with the privileges and prestige of synthesis. In this way it
hides what it conceals: strategies. One could impute it with the
peremptory concern of the functional, or rather, the unifunctional, as
well as the subordination of details minutely inventoried for the
representation of a social globality. Thus disappear mediations between
an ideological ensemble assumed to be rational (technologically or
economically) and detailed measures, objects of tactics and prediction.
This placing in parenthesis of theoretical, practical, social and mental
mediations does not lack black humour in a society where intermediaries
(shopkeepers, financiers, publicists, etc.) have immense privileges. One
covers the other! Thus a gulf is dug between the global (which hovers
over the void) and the manipulated and repressed partial, upon which
institutions weigh.
What is questioned here is not an uncertain âglobalityâ, it is an
ideology and the class strategy which uses and supports this ideology.
After a sort of âspectralâ analysis of social elements, the already
mentioned use of analytical intelligence is related as much to extreme
fragmentation of work and specialization pushed to the limits (including
specialized planning studies), as projection on the ground. Segregation
must be highlighted, with its three aspects, sometimes simultaneous,
sometimes successive: spontaneous (coming from revenues and ideologies)
â voluntary (establishing separate spaces) â programmed: under the guise
of planning and the plan).
There are unquestionably strong tendencies in all countries opposing
segregationist tendencies. One cannot state that the segregation of
groups, ethnic groups, social strata and classes comes from a constant
and uniform strategy of the powers, nor that one should see in it the
efficient projection of institutions or the will of political leaders.
Moreover, there exist the will and organized actions to combat it. And
yet, even where separation of social groups does not seem to be patently
evident on the ground, such a pressure and traces of segregation appear
under examination. The extreme case, the last instance, the ghetto. We
can observe that there are several types of ghetto: those of Jews and
the blacks, and also those of intellectuals or workers. In their own way
residential areas are also ghettos; high status people because of wealth
or power isolate themselves in ghettos of wealth. Leisure has its
ghettos. Wherever an organized action has attempted to mix social strata
and classes, a spontaneous decantation soon follows. The phenomenon of
segregation must be analysed according to various indices and criteria:
ecological (shanty towns, slums, the rot in the heart of the city),
formal (the deterioration of signs and meanings of the city, the
degradation of the urban by the dislocation of its architectural
elements), and sociological (standards of living and life styles, ethnic
groups, cultures and sub-cultures, etc.)
Anti-segregationist tendencies would be rather more ideological. They
sometimes relate to liberal humanism, sometimes to a philosophy of the
city considered as âsubjectâ (as a community or social organism).
Despite good humanist intentions and philosophical goodwill, practice
tends towards segregation. Why? For theoretical reasons and by virtue of
social and political causes. At the theoretical level, analytical
thought separates and delineates. It fails when it wants to reach a
synthesis. Socially and politically (conscious or unconscious) class
strategies aim for segregation.
In democratic countries public powers cannot overtly decree segregation
as such. Therefore they often adopt a humanist ideology which in the
most old-fashioned sense becomes a utopia, when it does not become a
demagogy. Segregation always wins over, even in those parts of social
life more or less easily and more or less thoroughly controlled by
public powers. Let us say that the State and private enterprise strive
to absorb and suppress the city as such. The State proceeds rather from
above and private enterprise from below (by ensuring housing and the
function of inhabiting in workersâ towns and housing estates, which
depending on a âsocietyâ and also assuring leisure, even culture and
social promotion). Despite their differences and sometimes their
conflicts, the State and private enterprise both converge towards
segregation.
Let us leave open the issue of knowing whether the political forms of
the State (capitalist, socialist or in transition, etc.), engender
different strategies cowards the city. Let us not attempt for the time
being to know where or how, at whom and with whom these strategies are
developed. We substantiate strategies by observing them as significant
orientations. Segregations which morphologically destroyed the city and
threaten urban life cannot be passed off as the effect of hazards or
local conjunctures. Let us be contented with the notion that the
democratic character of a regime is identifiable by its attitude towards
the city, urban âlibertiesâ and urban reality, and therefore towards
segregation. Among the criteria to retain would nor this one be one of
the most important? It is fundamental in what concerns the city and its
problematic. Nevertheless one must distinguish between political power
and social pressures which can annihilate the effects of (good or bad)
will of politicians. With regards to private enterprise, let us also
leave this an open question. What are the relations between (ideological
and practical) rationality in general, between (general and urban)
planning on the one hand, and on the other the rational management of
large firms? We can nevertheless put forward a hypothesis and research
direction. Rationality in the firm always implies an analysis pushed to
the extreme of tasks, operations and sequences. In addition, the reasons
and causes of class strategy are fully played out in the capitalist
firm. It is therefore highly probable that the firm as such favours the
extreme segregation, acts accordingly and applies social pressure when
this is not a decision.
The State and the firm seek to appropriate urban functions and to assume
and ensure them by destroying the form of the urban. Can they? Do not
these strategic objectives exceed their strengths, combined or not? It
would be most interesting to investigate this point. The conditions and
modalities of the crisis of the city are gradually uncovered and
accompanied by a city-wide institutional crisis of urban jurisdiction
and administration. What was specific to the city (the municipality,
local expenditures and investments, schools and educational programmes,
universities, etc.) fall increasingly under the control of the State,
and by institutionalizing itself in a global context, the city tends to
disappear as a specific institution. This abolishes it as an oeuvre of
original groups which were themselves specific. However, can the powers
and institutions at the top dispense with this relay, this mediation,
the city? This, of course, would need to be shown by researches into
juridical, economic, cultural and administrative sociology. Can they
abolish the urban? It is at this level that daily life, governed by
institutions which regulate it from above, consolidated and set up
according to multiple constraints, constitutes itself. Productivist
rationality which tends to suppress the city at the level of general
planning rediscovers it in the controlled and organized consumption of a
supervised market. After having been kept away from the global level of
decision-making, the city is reconstituted at the level of executions
and application, by institutions of power. The outcome â inasmuch as
such a situation in France and elsewhere can make sense â is an
incredible entanglement of measures (all reasonable), regulations (all
very complicated), and constraints (all motivated). The functioning of
bureaucratic rationality becomes confused with its own presuppositions
and consequences which overcome and elude it. Conflicts and
contradictions resurface, giving rise to âstructuringâ activities and
âconcertedâ actions aimed at their revocation. It is here on the ground
that the absurdity of a limited rationality of bureaucracy and
technocracy becomes evident. Here is grasped the falsehood of an
illusory identification between the rational and the real in the State,
and the true identity between the absurd and a certain authoritarian
rationalism.
On our horizon, the city and the urban are outlined as virtual objects,
as projects of a synthetic reconstitution. Critical analysis confirms
the failure of an analytical but uncritical thought. What does chis
analytical practice retain of the city and the urban whose results one
can detect on the ground? Aspects, elements and fragments. It places
before our eyes the spectre, the spectral analysis of the city. When we
speak of spectral analysis, its meaning is almost literal and not
metaphorical. Before our eyes, under our gaze, we have the âspectreâ of
the city, that of urban society and perhaps simply of society. If the
spectre of Communism no longer haunts Europe, the shadow of the city,
the regret of what has died because it was killed, perhaps guilt, have
replaced the old dread. The image of urban hell in the making is not
less fascinating, and people rush cowards the ruins of ancient cities to
consume them touristically, in the belief that they will heal their
nostalgia. Before us, as a spectacle (for spectators âunconsciousâ of
what is before their âconscienceâ) are the dissociated and inert
elements of social life and the urban. Here are âsocial housing estatesâ
without teenagers or old people. Here are women dozing while the men
work far away and come home exhausted. Here are private housing
developments which form a microcosm and yet remain urban because they
depend on centres of decision-making and each house has a television.
Here is a daily life well divided into fragments: work, transport,
private life, leisure. Analytical separation has isolated them as
ingredients and chemical elements, as raw materials (whereas they are
the outcome of a long history and imply an appropriation of
materiality). It is not finished. Here is the dismembered and
dissociated human being. Here are the senses of smell, taste, sight,
touch, hearing â some atrophied, some hypertrophied. Here is functioning
separately perception, intelligence and reason. Here is speech,
discourse and writing. Here is daily life and celebration, the latter
moribund. It is obvious, urgently. Synthesis then becomes an item on the
order of the day, the order of the century. But this synthesis, with its
analytical intellect, appears only as a combination of separate
elements. But combination is not and can never be synthesis. The city
and the urban cannot be recomposed from the signs of the city, the
semanthemes of the urban, although the city is a signifying whole. The
city is not only a language, but also a practice. Nobody therefore, and
we have no fear to repeat it, is entitled to pronounce or announce this
synthesis. No more is the sociologist or community worker than the
architect, the economist, the demographer, the linguist or semiologist.
Nobody has the power or the right. Only the philosopher might perhaps
have the right, if philosophy in the course of the centuries had not
demonstrated its incapacity to attain concentrate totalities (although
it has always aimed at totality and has posed global and general
questions). Only a praxis, under conditions to be determined, can take
charge of the possibility and demand of a synthesis this objective: the
gathering together of what gives itself as dispersed, dissociated,
separated, and this in the form of simultaneity and encounters.
We have here therefore before us, projected separately on the ground,
groups, ethnic groups, ages and sexes, activities, tasks and functions,
knowledge. Here is all that is necessary to create a world, an urban
society, or the developed urban. But this world is absent, this society
is before us only in a state of virtuality. It may perish in the bud.
Under existing conditions, it dies before being born. The conditions
which give rise to possibilities can also sustain them in a virtual
state, in presence-absence. Would this not be the root of this drama,
the point of emergence of nostalgia? The urban obsesses those who live
in need, in poverty, in the frustration of possibilities which remain
only possibilities. Thus the integration and participation obsess the
non-participants, the non-integrated, those who survive among the
fragments of a possible society and the ruins of the past: excluded from
the city, at the gates of the urban. The road travelled is staked out
with contradictions between the total (global) and the partial, between
analysis and synthesis. Here is a new one which reveals itself, high and
deep. It does interest theory but practice. The same social practice,
that of society today (in France, in the second half of the twentieth
century) offers to critical analysis a double character which cannot be
reduced to a significant opposition, although it signifies.
On the one hand, chis social practice is integrative. It attempts to
integrate its elements and aspects into a coherent whole. Integration is
accomplished at different levels and according to various modalities.
The market, the âworld of commoditiesâ, that is, by consumption and
ideology of consumption, by âcultureâ, put forward as unitary and
global; by âvaluesâ, including art; by the actions of the State,
including national consciousness and the political options and
strategies at national level. This integration is firstly aimed at the
working class, but also the intelligentsia and intellectuals, and
critical thought (not excluding Marxism). Planning could well become
essential to this integrative practice.
At the same time this society practices segregation. This same
rationality which sees itself as global (organizing, planning, unitary
and unifying) concretizes itself at the analytical level. On the ground
it projects separation. It tends (as in the United States), to form
ghettos or parking lots, those of workers, intellectuals, students (the
campus), foreigners, and so forth, not forgetting the ghetto of leisure
or âcreativityâ, reduced to miniaturization or hobbies. Ghetto in space
and ghetto in time. In planning, the term âzoningâ already implies
separation, segregation, isolation in planned ghettos. The fact becomes
rationality in the project.
This society wants itself and sees itself as coherent. It seeks
coherence, linked to rationality both as feature of efficient
organizational action, and as value and criterion. Under examination the
ideology of coherence reveals a hidden but none the less blatant
incoherence. Would coherence not be the obsession of an incoherent
society, which searches the way towards coherence by wishing to stop in
a conflictual situation denied as such?
This is not the only obsession. Integration also becomes an obsessional
theme, an aimless aspiration. The term âintegrationâ used in all its
meanings, appears in texts (newspapers, books, and speeches) with such
frequency that it must reveal something. On the one hand, this term
designates a concept concerning and enclosing social practice divulging
a strategy. On the other, it is a social connotator, without concept,
objective or objectivity, revealing an obsession with integrating (to
this or that, to a group, an ensemble or a whole). How could it be
otherwise in a society which superimposes the whole to the pans,
synthesis to analysis, coherence to incoherence, organization to
dislocation? It is from the city that the urban problematic reveals this
constitutive duality with its conflictual content. What results from
this? Without a doubt paradoxical phenomena of disintegrating
integration which refer particularly to urban reality.
This does not mean that this society is disintegrating and falling
apart. No. It is functionning. How? Why? That creates a problem. It must
also mean that this functioning is not without an enormous malaise â its
obsession. Another obsessional theme is participation, linked to
integration. This is not a simple obsession. In practice, the ideology
of participation enables us to have the acquiescence of interested and
concerned people at a small price. After a more or less elaborate
pretence at information and social activity, they return to their
tranquil passivity and retirement. Is it not clear that real and active
participation already has a name? It is called self-management. Which
poses other problems.
Very powerful forces tend to destroy the city. A particular kind of
planning projects on the ideological terrain a practice whose aim is the
death of the city. These social and political forces ravage the urban in
the making. This kernel, so powerful, in its own way, can it grow in the
cracks which still subsist between these masses? Does science, or
rather, scientificity, which puts itself at the service of existing
rationality, legitimize these masses of the State, private enterprise,
culture which allow the city to perish while offering its images and
âoeuvresâ for consumption sentence. âDoes science ... legitimize these
masses ... for consumption?â Construction is? Could urban life recover
and strengthen its capacities of integration and participation of the
city, which are almost entirely lost, and which cannot be stimulated
either by authoritarian means or by administrative prescription, or by
the intervention of specialists? The foremost theoretical problem can be
formulated thus. The political meaning of class segregation is clear,
whether it is a âsubjectâ for analysis, whether it is the end result of
a series of unplanned actions, or whether it is the effect of a will.
For the working class, victim of segregation and expelled from the
traditional city, deprived of a present or possible urban life, there is
a practical and therefore political problem even if it is not posed
politically and even if until now the housing question has for it and
its representatives concealed the problematic of the city and the urban.
Theoretical thought sees itself compelled to redefine the forms,
functions and structures of the city (economic, political, cultural,
etc.) as well as the social needs inherent to urban society. Until now,
only those individual needs, motivated by the so-called society of
consumption (a bureaucratic society of managed consumption) have been
prospected, and moreover manipulated rather than effectively known and
recognized. Social needs have an anthropological foundation. Opposed and
complimentary, they include the need for security and opening, the need
for certainty and adventure, that of organization of work and of play,
the needs for the predictable and the unpredictable, of similarity and
difference, of isolation and encounter, exchange and investments, of
independence (even solitude) and communication, of immediate and
long-term prospects. The human being has the need to accumulate energies
and to spend them, even waste them in play. He has a need to see, to
hear, to touch, to taste and the need to gather these perceptions in a
âworldâ. To these anthropological needs which are socially elaborated
(that is, sometimes separated, sometimes joined together, here
compressed and there hypertrophied), can be added specific needs which
are not satisfied by those commercial and cultural infrastructures which
are somewhat parsimoniously taken into account by planners. This refers
to the need for creative activity, for the oeuvre (not only of products
and consumable material goods), of the need for information, symbolism,
the imaginary and play. Through these specified needs lives and survives
a fundamental desire of which play, sexuality, physical activities such
as sport, creative activity, art and knowledge are particular
expressions and moments, which can more or less overcome the fragmentary
division of tasks. Finally, the need of the city and urban life can only
be freely expressed within a perspective which here attempts to become
clearer and to open up the horizon. Would not specific urban needs be
those of qualified places, places of simultaneity and encounters, places
where exchange would not go through exchange value, commerce and profit?
Would there not also be the need for a time for these encounters, these
exchanges?
At present, an analytical science of the city, which is necessary, is
only at the outline stage. At the beginning of their elaboration,
concepts and theories can only move forward with urban reality in the
making, with the praxis (social practice) of urban society. Now, not
without effort, the ideologies and practices which blocked the horizon
and which were only bottlenecks of knowledge and action, are being
overcome.
The science of the city has the city as object. This science borrows its
methods, approaches and concepts from the fragmentary sciences, but
synthesis escapes it in two ways. Firstly, because this synthesis which
would wish itself as total, starting from the analytic, can only be
strategic systematization and programming. Secondly, because the object,
the city, as consummate reality is falling apart. Knowledge holds in
front of itself the historic city already modified, to cut it up and put
it together again from fragments. As social text, this historic city no
longer has a coherent set of prescriptions, of use of time linked to
symbols and to a style. This text is moving away. It takes the form of a
document, or an exhibition, or a museum. The city histocically
constructed is no longer lived and is no longer understood practically.
It is only an object of cultural consumption for tourists, for a
estheticism, avid for spectacles and the picturesque. Even for those who
seek to understand it with warmth, it is gone. Yet, the urban remains in
a state of dispersed and alienated actuality, as kernel and virtuality.
What the eyes and analysis perceive on the ground can at best pass for
the shadow of a future object in the light of a rising sun. It is
impossible to envisage the reconstitution of the old city, only the
construction of a new one on new foundations, on another scale and in
other conditions, in another society. The prescription is: there cannot
be a going back (towards the traditional city), nor a headlong flight,
towards a colossal and shapeless agglomeration. In other words, for what
concerns the city the object of science is not given. The past, the
present, the possible cannot be separated. What is being studied is a
virtual object, which thought studies, which calls for new approaches.
The career of the old classical humanism ended long ago and badly. It is
dead. Its mummified and embalmed corpse weighs heavily and does not
smell good. It occupies many spaces, public or otherwise, thus
transforms into cultural cemeteries under the guise of the human:
museums, universities, various publications, not to mention new towns
and planning procedures. Trivialities and platitudes are wrapped up in
this âhuman scaleâ, as they say, whereas what we should take charge of
are the excesses and create âsomethingâ to the scale of the universe.
This old humanism died during the World Wars, during the demographic
growth which accompanied great massacres, and before the brutal demands
of economic growth and competition and the pressure of poorly controlled
techniques. It is not even an ideology, barely a theme for official
speeches.
Recently there have been great cries of âGod is dead, man tooâ as if the
death of classical humanism was that of man. These formulae spread in
best-sellers, and taken in by a publicity not really responsible, are
nothing new. Nietzschean meditation, a dark presage for Europeâs culture
and civilization, began a hundred years ago during the 1870â1
Franco-Prussian war. When Nietzsche announced the death of God and man,
he did not leave a gaping hole, or fill this void with makeshift
material, language or linguistics. He was also announcing the Superhuman
which he thought was to come. He was overcoming the nihilism he was
identifying. Authors transacting these theoretical and poetic treasures,
but with a delay of a century, plunge us back into nihilism. Since
Nietzsche, the dangers of the Superhuman have been cruelly evident.
Moreover, this ânew manâ emerging from industrial production and
planning rationality has been more than disappointing. There is still
another way, that of urban society and the human as oeuvre in this
society which would be an oeuvre and not a product. There is also the
simultaneous overcoming of the old âsocial animalâ and man of the
ancient city, the urban animal, towards a polyvalent, polysensorial,
urban man capable of complex and transparent relations with the world
(the environment and himself). Or there is nihilism. If man is dead, for
whom will we build? How will we build? It does not matter that the city
has or has not disappeared, that it must be thought anew, reconstructed
on new foundations or overcome. It does not matter whether terror
reigns, that the atomic bomb is dropped or that Planet Earth explodes.
What is important? Who thinks? Who acts? Who still speaks and for whom?
If meaning and finality disappear and we cannot even declare them in a
praxis, nothing matters. And if the capacities of the âhuman beingâ,
technology, science, imagination and art, or their absence, are erected
as autonomous powers, and that reflective thought is satisfied with this
assessment, the absence of a âsubjectâ, what to reply? What to do?
Old humanism moves away and disappears. Nostalgia lessens and we turn
back less and less often to see its shape lying across the road. It was
the ideology of the liberal bourgeoisie, with its Greek and Latin quotes
sprinkled with Judeo-Christianity, which bent over the people and human
sufferings and which covered and supported the rhetoric of the clear
consciences of noble feelings and of the sensitive souls. A dreadful
cocktail, a mixture to make you sick. Only a few intellectuals (from the
âLeftâ â but are there still any intellectuals on the âRightâ?) who are
neither revolutionary nor openly reactionary, nor Dionysiacs or
Apollonians, still have a taste for this sad potion.
We thus must make the effort to reach out towards a new humanism, a new
praxis, another man, that of urban society. We must avoid those myths
which threaten this will, destroy those ideologies which hinder this
project and those strategies which divert this trajectory. Urban life
has yet to begin. What we are doing now is to complete an inventory of
the remains of a millenarian society where the countryside dominated the
city, and whose ideas, values, taboos and prescriptions were largely
agrarian, with rural and ânaturalâ dominant features. A few sporadic
cities hardly emerged from a rustic ocean. Rural society was (still is),
a society of scarcity and penury, of want accepted or rejected, of
prohibitions managing and regulating privations. It was also the society
of the fĂȘte, of festivities. But that aspect, the best, has been lost
and instead of myths and limitations, this is what must be revitalized!
A decisive remark: for the crisis of the traditional city accompanies
the world crisis of agrarian civilization, which is a so traditional. It
is up to us to resolve this double crisis, especially by creating with
the new city, a new life in the city. Revolutionary societies (among
which the USSR ten or fifteen years after the October Revolution),
intimated the development of society based on industry. But they only
intimated.
The use of âweâ in the sentences above has only the impact of a metaphor
to mean those concerned. The architect, the planner, the sociologist,
the economist, the philosopher or the politician cannot out of
nothingness create new forms and relations. More precisely, the
architect is no more a miracle-worker than the sociologist. Neither can
create social relations, although under certain favourable conditions
they help trends to be formulated (to take shape). Only social life
(praxis) in its global capacity possesses such powers â or does not
possess them. The people mentioned above can individually or in teams
dear the way; they can also propose, cry out and prepare forms. And also
(and especially), through a maieutic nurtured by science, assess
acquired experience, provide a lesson from failure and give birth to the
possible.
At the point we have arrived there is an urgent need to change
intellectual approaches and tools. It would be indispensable to take up
ideas and approaches from elsewhere and which are still not very
familiar.
Transduction. This is an intellectual operation which can be
methodically carried out and which differs from classical induction,
deduction, the construction of âmodelsâ, simulation as well as the
simple statement of hypothesis. Transduction elaborates and constructs a
theoretical object, a possible object from information related to
reality and a problematic posed by this reality. Transduction assumes an
incessant feed back between the conceptual framework used and empirical
observations. Its theory (methodology), gives shape to certain
spontaneous mental operations of the planner, the architect, the
sociologist, the politician and the philosopher. It introduces rigour in
invention and knowledge in utopia.
Experimental utopia. Who is not a utopian today? Only narrowly
specialized practitioners working to order without the slightest
critical examination of stipulated norms and constraints, only these not
very interesting people escape utopianism. All are utopians, including
those futurists and planners who project Paris in the year 2,000 and
those engineers who have made Brasilia! But there are several
utopianisms. Would not the worst be that utopianism which does not utter
its name, covers itself with positivism and on this basis imposes the
harshest constraints and the most derisory absence of technicity?
Utopia is to be considered experimentally by studying its implications
and consequences on the ground. These can surprise. What are and what
would be the most successful places? How can they be discovered?
According to which criteria? What are the times and rhythms of daily
life which are inscribed and prescribed in these âsuccessfulâ spaces
favourable to happiness? That is interesting.
There are other indispensable intellectual approaches to identify
without dissociating them the three fundamental theoretical concepts of
structure, function and form, and to know their import, the spheres of
their validity, their limits and their reciprocal relations. To know
that they make a whole bur that the elements of this whole have a
certain independence and relative autonomy. To not privilege one over
the other, otherwise this gives an ideology, that is, a closed and
dogmatic system of significations: structuralism, formalism,
functionalism. To be used equally and in turn for the analysis of the
real (an analysis which is never exhaustive or without residue), as well
as for that operation known as âtransductionâ. It is important to
understand chat a function can be accomplished by means of different
structures, and that there is no unequivocal link between the terms.
That is, that functions and structures clothe themselves with forms
which reveal and veil them â chat the triplicity of these aspects make a
whole which is more than these aspects, elements and parts.
We have among our intellectual tools one which deserves neither disdain
nor privilege of the absolute: that of system (or rather sub-system of
significations.
Policies have their systems of significations â ideologies â which
enable them to subordinate to their strategies social acts and events
influenced by them. Ac the ecological level, the humble inhabitant has
his system (or rather, his sub-system) of significations. The fact of
living here or there involves the reception, adoption and transmission
of such a system, for example that of owner-occupied housing. The system
of significations of the inhabitant cells of his passivities and
activities: he is received but changed by practice. He is perceived.
Architects seem to have established and dogmatized an ensemble of
significations, as such poorly developed and variously labelled as
âfunctionâ, âformâ, âstructureâ, or rather, functionalism, formalism,
and structuralism. They elaborate them not from the significations
perceived and lived by those who inhabit, but from their interpretation
of inhabiting. It is graphic and visual, tending towards metalanguage.
It is graphism and visualization. Given that these architects form a
social body, they attach themselves to institutions, their system tends
to close itself off, impose itself and elude all criticism. There is
cause to formulate this system, often put forward without any other
procedure or precaution, as planning by extrapolation.
This theory which one could legitimately call planning. dose to the
meanings of that old practice of to to inhabit (that is, the human)
which would add to these partial facts a general theory of urban
time-spaces, which would reveal a new practice emerging from this
elaboration can be envisaged only as the practical application of a
comprehensive theory of the city and the urban which could go beyond
current scissions and separations, particularly those existing between
philosophy and the sciences of the city, the global and the partial.
Current planning projects could figure in this development â but only
within an unwavering critique of their ideological and strategic
implications. Inasmuch as we can define it, our object â the urban â
will never today be entirely present in our reflections. More than any
another object, it possesses a very complex quality of totality in act
and potential the object of research gradually uncovered, and which will
be either slowly or never exhausted. To take this object as a given
truth is operate a mythifying ideology. Knowledge must envisage a
considerable number of methods to grasp this object, and cannot fasten
itself onto a particular approach. Analytical configurations will follow
as closely as possible the internal articulations of this âthingâ which
is not a thing; they will be accompanied by reconstructions which will
never be realized. Descriptions, analyses and attempts at synthesis can
never be passed off as being exhaustive or definitive. All these
notions, all these batteries of concepts will come into play: form,
structure, function, level, dimension, dependent and independent
variables, correlations, totality, ensemble, system, etc. Here as
elsewhere, but more than elsewhere, the residue reveals itself to be
most precious. Each âobjectâ constructed will in turn be submitted to
critical examination. Within the possible, this will be accomplished and
submitted to experimental verification. The science of the city requires
a historical period to make itself and to orient social practice.
This science is necessary but not sufficient. We can perceive its limits
at the same time as its necessity. Planning thought proposes the
establishment or reconstitution of highly localized, highly
particularized and centralized social units whose linkages and tensions
would re-establish an urban unity endowed with a complex interior order,
with its hierarchy and a supple structure. More specifically,
sociological thought seeks an understanding and reconstitution of the
integrative capacities of the urban as well as the conditions of
practical participation. Why not? But only under one condition: never to
protect these fragmented and therefore partial attempts from criticism,
practical assessment and global preoccupation.
Knowledge can therefore construct and propose models. In this sense each
object is but a model of urban reality. Nevertheless, such a reality
will never become manageable as a thing and will never become
instrumental even for the most operational knowledge. Who would not hope
that the city becomes again what it was â the act and oeuvre of a
complex thought? But it cannot remain at the level of wishes and
aspirations and an urban strategy is not defined. An urban strategy
cannot cake into account existing strategies and acquired knowledge:
science of the city, with its disposition towards the planning of growth
and the control of development. Whoever says âstrategiesâ says the
hierarchy of âvariablesâ to be considered, some having a strategic
capacity and others remaining at the tactical level â and says also the
power to realize these strategies on the ground. Only groups, social
classes and class fractions capable of revolutionary initiative can take
over and realize to fruition solutions to urban problems. It is from
these social and political forces that the renewed city will become the
oeuvre. The first thing to do is to defeat currently dominant strategies
and ideologies. In the present society that there exist many divergent
groups and strategies (for example between the State and the private)
does not alter the situation. From questions of landed property to
problems of segregation, each project of urban reform questions the
structures, the immediate (individual) and daily relations of existing
society, but also those that one purports to impose by the coercive and
institutional means of what remains of urban reality. In itself
reformist, the strategy of urban renewal becomes âinevitablyâ
revolutionary, not by force of circumstance, but against the established
order. Urban strategy resting on the science of the city needs a social
support and political forces to be effective. It cannot act on its own.
It cannot but depend on the presence and action of the working class,
the only one able to put an end to a segregation directed essentially
against it. Only this class, as a class, can decisively contribute to
the reconstruction of centrality destroyed by a strategy of segregation
and found again in the menacing form of centres of decision-making. This
does not mean that the working class will make urban society all on its
own, but that without it nothing is possible. Without it integration has
no meaning and disintegration will continue under the guise of nostalgia
and integration. There is there not only an option but an horizon which
opens or doses. When the working class is silent, when it is quiescent
and cannot accomplish what theory has defined as its âhistorical
missionâ, then both the âsubjectâ and âobjectâ are lacking. Reflection
confirms this absence, which means that it is appropriate to consider
two series of propositions:
1. A political programme of urban reform not defined by the framework
and the possibilities of prevailing society or subjugated to a
ârealismâ, although based on the study of realities. In other words,
reform thus understood is not limited to reformism. This programme will
therefore have a singular and even paradoxical character. It will be
established to be proposed to political forces, parties. One could even
add that preferentially it would be presented to âleftâ parties,
political formations representing or wishing to represent the working
class. But it would not be established as a function of these forces and
formations. It will have in relation to them a specific character which
comes from knowledge, a scientific part. It will be proposed (free to be
altered) by those who take control of it. Let political forces take
their responsibilities. In this domain which engages the future of
modern society and that of producers, ignorance and misunderstanding
entail responsibilities before history.
2. Mature planning projects which consist of models and spatial forms
and urban times without concern for their current feasibility or their
utopian aspect. It does not seem possible that these models result
either from a simple study of existing cities and urban typologies, or
from a combination of elements. Other than contrary to experience, the
forms of space and time will be invented and proposed to praxis. That
imagination be deployed, not the imaginary of escape and evasion which
conveys ideologies, but the imaginary which invests itself in
appropriation (of time, space, physiolocal life and desire). Why not
oppose ephemeral cities to the eternal city, and movable centrality to
stable centres? All audacities can be premissed. Why limit these
propositions only to the morphology of time and space? They could also
include the way of living in the city and the development of the urban
on this basis.
In these two series there will also be long, medium and short-term
propositions constituting urban strategy understood as such.
The society in which we live appears to tend towards plenitude â or at
least towards fullness (durable goods and objects, quantity,
satisfaction and rationality). In face it allows a colossal gulf to be
dug into which ideologies agitate themselves and the fog of rhetoric
spreads. Having left speculation and contemplation, incomplete knowledge
and fragmentary divisions, one of the greatest projects active thought
can propose for itself is to fill this lacuna â and not only with
language.
In a period during which ideologists pronounce abundantly on structures,
the destructuration of the city manifests the depth of phenomena, of
social and cultural disintegration. Considered as a whole, this society
finds itself incomplete. Between the sub-systems and the structures
consolidated by various means (compulsion, terror, and ideological
persuasion), there are holes and chasms. These voids are not there due
to chance. They are the places of the possible. They contain the
floating and dispersed elements of the possible, but not the power which
could assemble them. Moreover, structuring actions and the power of the
social void tend to prohibit action and the very presence of such a
power. The conditions of the possible can only be realized in the course
of a radical metamorphosis.
In this conjuncture, ideology claims to provide an absolute quality to
âscientificityâ, science appertaining to the real, dissecting it,
reconstituting it, and by this fact isolating it from the possible and
closing the way. Now, in such a conjuncture science which is fragmentary
science can only have a programmatic impact. It brings elements to a
programme. If one concedes that these elements already constitute a
totality, and one wishes to execute this programme literally, one treats
the virtual object as a pre-existent technical object. A project is
accomplished without criticism and this project fulfills an ideology by
projecting it on the ground â that of the technocrats. Although
necessary, policy is not enough. It changes during the course of its
implementation. Only social force, capable of investing itself in the
urban through a long political experience, can take charge of the
realization of a programme concerning urban society. Conversely, the
science of the city brings to this perspective a theoretical and
critical foundation, a positive base. Utopia controlled by dialectical
reason serves as a safe-guard supposedly scientific fictions and visions
gone astray. Besides, this foundation and base prevent reflection from
losing itself in pure policy. Here the dialectical movement presents
itself as a relation between science and political power, as a dialogue
which actualizes relations of âtheory-practiceâ and âcritical
positive-negativeâ.
As necessary as science, but not sufficient, art brings to the
realization of urban society its long meditation on life as drama and
pleasure. In addition and especially, art resticutes the meaning of the
oeuvre, giving it multiple facets of appropriated time and space;
neither endured nor accepted by a passive resignation, metamorphosed as
oeuvre. Music shows the appropriation of time, painting and sculpture
that of space. If the sciences discover partial determinisms, art and
philosophy show how a totality grows out of partial determinisms. It is
incumbent on the social force capable of creating urban society to make
efficient and effective the unity of art, technique and knowledge. As
much the science of the city, art and the history of art are part of a
meditation on the urban which wants to make efficient the images which
proclaim it. By overcoming this opposition, chis meditation striving for
action would thus be both utopian and realistic. One could even assert
that the maximum of utopianism could unite with the optimum of realism.
Among the contradictions characteristic of our time there are those
(particularly difficult ones) between the realities of society and the
facts of civilization. On the one hand, genocide, and on the other,
medical and other interventions which enable a child to be saved or an
agony prolonged. One of the latest but not lease contradictions has been
shown in this essay: between the socialization of society and
generalized segregation. There are many others, for example, the
contradiction between the label of revolutionary and the attachment to
an obsolete productivist rationalism. The individual, at the centre of
social forces due to the pressure of the masses, asserts himself and
does not die. Rights appear and become customs or prescriptions, usually
followed by enactments. And we know how, through gigantic destructions,
World Wars, and the terror of nuclear threats, that these concrete
rights come to complete the abstract rights of man and the citizen
inscribed on the front of buildings by democracy during its
revolutionary beginnings: the rights of ages and sexes (the woman, the
child and the elderly), rights of conditions (the proletarian, the
peasant), rights to training and education, to work, to culture, to
rest, to health, to housing. The pressure of the working class has been
and remains necessary (but not sufficient) for the recognition of these
rights, for their entry into customs, for their inscription into codes
which are still incomplete.
Over the last few years and rather strangely, the right to nature
entered into social practice thanks to leisure, having made its way
through protestations becoming commonplace against noise, fatigue, the
concentrationary universe of cities (as cities are rotting or
exploding). A strange journey indeed! Nature enters into exchange value
and commodities, to be bought and sold. This ânaturalityâ which is
counterfeited and traded in, is destroyed by commercialized,
industrialized and institutionally organized leisure pursuits. âNatureâ,
or what passes for it, and survives of it, becomes the ghetto of leisure
pursuits, the separate place of pleasure and the retreat of
âcreativityâ. Urban dwellers carry the urban with them, even if they do
not bring planning with them! Colonized by them, the countryside has
lost the qualities, features and charms of peasant life. The urban
ravages the countryside: this urbanized countryside opposes itself to a
dispossessed rurality, the extreme case of the deep misery of the
inhabitant, the habitat, of to inhabit. Are the rights to nature and to
the countryside not destroying themselves?
In the face of this pseudo-right, the right to the city is like a cry
and a demand. This right slowly meanders through the surprising detours
of nostalgia and tourism, the return to the heart of the traditional
city, and the Call of existent or recently developed centralities. The
claim to nature, and the desire to enjoy it displace the right to the
city. This latest claim expresses itself indirectly as a tendency to
flee the deteriorated and unrenovated city, alienated urban life before
at last, âreallyâ living. The need and the ârightâ to nature contradict
the right to the city without being able to evade it. (This does not
mean that it is not necessary to preserve vase ânaturalâ spaces).
The right to the city cannot be conceived of as a simple visiting right
or as a return to traditional cities. It can only be formulated as a
transformed and renewed right to urban life. It does not matter whether
the urban fabric encloses the countryside and what survives of peasant
life, as long as the âurbanâ, place of encounter, priority of use value,
inscription in space of a time promoted to the rank of a supreme
resource among all resources, finds its morphological base and its
practico-material realization. Which presumes an integrated theory of
the city and urban society, using the resources of science and art. Only
the working class can become the agent, the social carrier or support of
this realization. Here again, as a century ago, it denies and contests,
by its very existence, the class strategy directed against it. As a
hundred years ago, although under new conditions, it gathers the
interests (overcoming the immediate and the superficial) of the whole
society and firstly of all those who inhabit. Who can ignore that the
Olympians of the new bourgeois aristocracy no longer inhabit. They go
from grand hotel to grand hotel, or from castle to castle, commanding a
fleet or a country from a yacht. They are everywhere and nowhere. That
is how they fascinate people immersed into everyday life. They transcend
everyday life, possess nature and leave it up to the cops to contrive
culture. Is it essential to describe at length, besides the condition of
youth, students and intellectuals, armies of workers with or without
white collars, people from the provinces, the colonized and
semi-colonized of all sorts, all those who endure a well-organized daily
life, is it here necessary to exhibit the derisory and untragic misery
of the inhabitant, of the suburban dweller and of the people who stay in
residential ghettos, in the mouldering centres of old cities and in the
proliferations lost beyond them? One only has to open oneâs eyes to
understand the daily life of the one who runs from his dwelling to the
station, near or far away, to the packed underground train, the office
or the factory, to return the same way in the evening and come home to
recuperate enough to start again the next day. The picture of this
generalized misery would not go without a picture of âsatisfactionsâ
which hides it and becomes the means to elude it and break free from it.
Since its beginnings, classical philosophy, which has had as social base
and theoretical foundation the city, thought the city, and endeavours to
determine the image of the ideal city. The Critias of Plato sees in the
city an image of the world, or rather of the cosmos, a microcosm. Urban
time and space reproduce on earth the configuration of the universe as
the philosopher discovers it.
If today one wants a representation of the âidealâ city and of its
relations to the universe, one will not find this image with the
philosophers and even less in an analytical vision which divides urban
reality into fractions, sectors, relations and correlations. One has to
find it among the writers of science fiction. In science fiction novels,
every possible and impossible variation of future urban society has been
foreseen. Sometimes the old urban cores agonize, covered with an urban
fabric more or less thick, more or less sclerosed or cancerous, which
proliferates and spreads over the planet. In these cores destined to
disappearance after a long decline, live or vegetate failures, artists,
intellectuals and gangsters. Sometimes colossal cities reconstitute
themselves and carry onto a higher level former struggles for power. In
Azimovâs magistral work, The Foundation, an entire planet is covered by
a giant city, Tremor, which has all the means of knowledge and power
with which it dominates, as a centre of decision·making, a whole galaxy.
After many gigantic episodes, Trentor saves the universe and brings it
to its end, that is, to the âreign of endingsâ, joy and happiness, for
excesses are finally overcome and the time of the world finally
appropriated in a cosmic space. Between these two extremes, the
visionaries of science fiction have also their intermediary versions:
the city ruled by a powerful computer, the city of a highly specialized
and vital production which moves among planetary systems and galaxies,
etc.
Is it necessary to explore so far ahead the horizon of horizons? The
ideal city, the New Athens, is already there to be seen in the image
which Paris and New York and some other cities project. The centre of
decision-making and the centre of consumption meet. Their alliance on
the ground based on a strategic convergence creates an inordinate
centrality. We already know that this decision-making centre includes
all the channels of information and means of cultural and scientific
development. Coercion and persuasion converge with the power of
decision-making and the capacity to consume. Strongly occupied and
inhabited by these new Masters, this centre is held by them. Without
necessarily owning it all, they possess this privileged space, axis of a
strict spatial policy. Especially, they have the privilege to possess
time. Around them, distributed in space according to formalized
principles, there are human groups which can no longer bear the name of
slaves, serfs, vassals or even proletarians. What could they be called?
Subjugated, they provide a multiplicity of services for the Masters of
this State solidly established on the city. These Masters have around
for them every cultural and other pleasure, from nightclubs to the
splendours of the opera â not excluding remote controlled amusements.
Could this not be the true New Athens, with its minority of free
citizens, possessing and enjoying social spaces, dominating an enormous
mass of subjugated people, in principle free, genuinely and perhaps
voluntarily servants, treated and manipulated according to rational
methods? Are not the scholars, sociologists leading, in this very
different from ancient philosophers, not themselves the servants of
State and Order, under the pretence of empiricism and rigour, of
scientificity? The possibilities can even be assessed. Directors, heads,
presidents of this and that, elites, leading writers and artists,
well-known entertainers and media people, make up one per cent, or just
under half a million of the new notables in France in the twenty-first
century, each with their family and their following, and their own
âfirmâ. The domination of and by centrality in no way denies the
possession of secondary domains â the enjoyment of nature, the sea, the
mountains, ancient cities (available through trips, hotels, etc.). Next
are about four per cent of executives, administrators, engineers and
scholars. After selection, the most eminent of these are admitted into
the heart of the city. For this selection, incomes and society rituals
might be sufficient. State capitalism has carefully organized for other
privileged subordinates domains distributed according to a rational
plan. Before reaching this goal State capitalism has carefully prepared
it. Without omitting the realization of several urban ghettos, it has
organized for scholars and for science a severely competitive sector: in
the universities and laboratories, scholars and intellectuals have
confronted each other on a purely competitive basis, with a zeal worthy
of a better job, for the best interest of the Masters, the economic and
political, for the glory and joy of the Olympians. Indeed, these
secondary elites are assigned to residence in science parks, university
campuses â ghettos for intellectuals. The mass, under pressure from many
constraints, spontaneously houses itself in satellite cities, planned
suburbs, and other more or less residential ghettos. There is for it
only carefully measured space. Time eludes it. It leads it daily life
bound (perhaps unwittingly), to the requirement of the concentration of
powers. But this is not a concentrationary universe. All this can quite
do without the ideology of freedom under the pretence of rationality,
organization, and programming. These masses who do not deserve the name
of people, or popular classes, or working class live relatively well.
Apart from the fact that their daily life is remote-controlled and the
permanent threat of unemployment weighs heavily on them, contributing to
a latent and generalized terror.
If someone smiles at this utopia, he is wrong. But how to prove it? When
his eyes will open, it will be too late. He demands proof. How do you
show light to a blind person, or the horizon to a myopic one â even if
he knows the theory of wholes, or of âclustersâ, the finesses of
variance analysis, or the precise charms of linguistics?
Since the Middle Ages, each epoch of European civilization has had its
image of the possible, its dream, its fantasies of hell and paradise.
Each period, and perhaps each generation has had its representation of
the best of all possible worlds, or of a new life, an important, if not
essential part of all ideologies. In order to accomplish this function,
the eighteenth century, seemingly so rich, had only the rather feeble
image of the noble savage and exotic islands. To this exoticism, some
men of that century added a closer but somewhat prettified
representation of England. In relation to them, we are richly endowed.
By we is meant a poorly defined crowd, generally intellectuals, living
and thinking in France at the beginning of the second half of the
twentieth-century. We have many models, horizons, and avenues which do
not converge to imagine the future: the USSR and the United States,
China, Yugoslavia, Cuba, Israel, even Sweden or Switzerland â and
without forgetting the Bororos.
While French society is becoming urbanized and Paris is being
transformed, and certain powers, if not State power, are modelling
France of the year 2,000, nobody is thinking about the ideal city or
what is happening to the real city. Utopia attaches itself to numerous
more or less distant and unknown or misunderstood realities, but no
longer to real and daily life. It is no longer begotten in the absences
and lacunae which cruelly puncture surrounding reality. The gaze turns
away, leaves the horizon, loses itself in the clouds, elsewhere. Such is
the power of diversion of ideologies, at the exact moment when we no
longer believe in ideology, but in realism and rationalism!
Previously, by refuting partial disciplines and their interdisciplinary
attempts, one was also asserting that synthesis belongs to the political
(that is, that all synthesis of analytical faces about urban reality
conceals under philosophy or an ideology a strategy). Statesmen, experts
and specialists should certainly not be given control of decision-
making. The term political is not here used so narrowly. Such a
proposition must be understood in the opposite way to what has been
expressed here. The capacity of synthesis belongs to political forces
which are in fact social forces (classes and fractions of classes,
groupings or class alliances). They exist or not, they manifest and
express themselves or not. They speak or do not speak. It is up to them
to indicate social needs, to influence existing institutions, to open
the horizon and lay claims to a future which will be their oeuvre. If
the inhabitants of various categories and strata allow themselves to be
manoeuvred and manipulated, displaced anywhere under the pretext of
social mobility, if they accept the conditions of an exploitation more
refined and extensive than before, too bad for them. If the working
class is silent, if it does not act, either spontaneously or by the
mediation of its institutional representatives and mandatories,
segregation will continue resulting again in a vicious circle.
Segregation is inclined to prohibit protest, contest, action, by
dispersing those who protest, contest, and act. In this perspective
political life will either challenge or reaffirm the centre of political
decision-making. For parties and men, this option is the criterion of
democracy.
The politician needs a theory to help him determine its course but this
presents some great difficulties. How can there be a theory of urban
society, the city and the urban, of realities and possibilities, without
synthesis?
Two dogmatic disciplines, philosophical systematization and
systematization from partial analyses under the pretence of such
disciplines or of so-called interdisciplinary research have already been
rejected. There can be no possibility of an analysis accomplished in the
context of knowledge. The unity outlined is defined by a convergence
which only practice can actualize between:
the impossible, that is, what is possible here and now, to what is
impossible today, but will become possible tomorrow in the course of
this very action
that is, the ensemble of knowledge brought into play during the course
of political action, ordered, used and dominated by this action
new light, as its history inscribes itself in another perspective â
philosophical meditation transforming itself according to reality or
rather, the realization to accomplish.
transform reality, to appropriate at the highest level the facts of the
âlivedâ, of time, space, the body and desire.
From this convergence, one can define the preceding conditions. It is
essential to consider no longer industrialization and urbanization
separately, but to perceive in urbanization the meaning, the goal and
the finality of industrialization. In other words, it is essential to
aim no longer for economic growth for its own sake, and economistic
ideology which entails strategic objectives, namely, superprofit and
capitalist overexploitation, the control of the economic (which fails
precisely because of this) to the advantage of the State. Concepts of
economic equilibrium, harmonious growth, structural maintenance
(structuredâstructuring relations being existing relations of production
and property) must be subordinated to more powerful concepts potentially
of development, and of concrete rationality emerging from conflicts.
In other words, growth must be guided. Very common formulations which
pass for democratic (growth, well-being for all, the general interest)
lose their meaning and this applies to liberalism as economistic
ideology as much as to centralized State planning. Such an ideology,
whether or not prospective, reduces the outlook on such issues as the
increase of wages and the better distribution of national revenue, or
even on the review and adjustment of the capital-labour relation.
To direct growth towards development, therefore towards urban society,
means firstly to prospect new needs, knowing chat such needs are
discovered in the course of their emergence and are revealed in the
course of their prospection. They do not pre-exist as objects. They do
not feature in the ârealâ described by market studies and studies of
âindividualâ motivation. Consequently, this means substituting social
planning whose theory is hardly elaborated. Social needs lead to the
production of new âgoodsâ which are not this or that object, but social
objects in space and time. Man of urban society is already a man rich in
needs: the man of rich needs awaiting their objectification and
realization. Urban society overtakes the old and the new poverty, as
much the destitution of isolated subjectivity as that humdrum old need
for money with its worn symbols of the âpureâ gaze, the âpureâ sign, the
âpureâ spectacle.
Thus, direction is not defined by an effective synthesis, but by a
convergence, a virtuality which is outlined but realized only at the
limit. This limit is not somewhere in the infinite, and yet it be can
reached by successive leaps and bounds. It is impossible to settle in it
and to establish it as an accomplished reality. Hence this is the
essential feature of the method already considered and named
âtransductionâ, the construction of a virtual object approached from
experimental facts. The horizon opens up and calls for actualization.
The orientation reacts upon researched facts. In this way research
ceases to be either indeterminate, that is, empiricist, or a simple
confirmation of a thesis, that is, dogmatist. In this light, philosophy
and its history, art and its metamorphoses appear transformed.
As for the analytical aspect of urban research, it modifies itself by
the fact that research has already found âsomethingâ at the outset and
that the direction or orientation influences the hypothesis. There is no
more question of isolating the points of space and time, of considering
separately activities and functions, or of studying apart from each
other behaviours or images, distributions and relations. These various
aspects of social production, that of the city and urban society, are
situated in relation to a framework of explanation and forecasting.
Since method consists as much in overcoming ecological description as
structural and functional analysis, in order to reach out to the
concrete of urban drama, formal evidence could be provided by the
general theory of forms. According to this theory, there is a form of
the city: assembly, simultaneity, encounter. Transduction is the
intellectual approach linked to these operations which codifies them or
supports them methodologically.
Scientifically speaking, the distinction between strategic variables and
tactical variables seems fundamental. The first ones, as soon as they
are identified, subordinate the second. Increase of wages? Better
distribution of national revenue? Nationalization of this or that? Very
well. But these are tactical variables. In the same way the suppression
of urban related constraints would affect the municipalization,
nationalization or socialization of building plots. Fine and well. But
for what purpose? The increase of rates and rhythms of growth between
strategic variables, given that quantitative growth already poses
qualitative problems of finality and development. The issue is not only
rates of growth, production and revenues, bur distribution. Which part
of increased production and global revenue will be attributed to social
needs, to âcultureâ, to urban reality? Is not the transformation of
daily life part of strategic variables? One could think it so. To take
an example, flexible working hours are of interest. This is only a
minuscule tactical action. The creation of new networks concerning the
life of children and adolescents (crĂšches, playing fields and sports,
etc.), the constitution of a very simple apparatus of social pedagogy,
which would inform as much social life itself as sexual life, the art of
living and art tout court. Such an institution would have much more
impact: it would mark the passage from the tactical to the strategic in
this field.
The variables of projects elaborated by economists also depend on
generally poorly defined strategies. Against class strategies which
often use very powerful scientific instruments and which tend to abuse
science (no: scientificity â a rigid and coercive ideological apparatus)
as means to persuade and impose, what is needed is to turn knowledge
around by putting it back on its feet.
Socialism? Of course, that is what it is about. But what socialism?
According to which concept and theory of socialist society? Is the
definition of this society by the planned organization of production
enough? No. Socialism today can only be conceived as production oriented
towards social needs, and consequently, towards the needs of urban
society. The goals borrowed from simple industrialization are being
overtaken and transformed. Such is the thesis or hypothesis formulated
here. Conditions and preconditions? We know them: a high level of
production and productivity (by breaking with an exploitation reinforced
by a relatively decreasing minority of highly productive manual and
intellectual workers), and a high technical and cultural level. In
addition, the institution of new social relations, especially between
governing and governed, between âsubjectsâ and âobjectsâ of
decision-making. These conditions have virtually been realized in
advanced industrial countries. Their formulation does not arise from the
possible, even if this possible seems far from real and is really far
away.
Possibilities relate to a double examination: the scientific (project
and projection, variations of projects, predictions) and the imaginary
(at the limit, science fiction). Why should the imaginary enter only
outside the real instead of nurturing reality? When there is a loss of
thought in and by the imaginary, it is being manipulated. The imaginary
is also a social fact. Do not specialists claim for themselves the
intervention of imagination and the imaginary when they acclaim the âman
of synthesisâ, or when they are disposed to welcome the ânexialistâ or
the âgeneralistâ?
For two centuries, industrialization has been promoting commodities â
which although they pre-existed, were limited by agrarian and urban
structures. It has enabled the virtually unlimited extension of exchange
value. It has shown how merchandise is not only a way of putting people
in relation to each other, but also a logic, a language, and a world.
Commodities have swept away barriers. And this process is not over: the
car, the current pilot-object in the world of commodities, is overcoming
this last barrier â the city. It was therefore the time of political
economy and the two variations of its rule: liberal and state economis.
Today the overtaking of economism is being outlined. Towards what?
Towards an ethic or an aesthetic, a moralism or an aestheticism? Towards
new âvaluesâ? No. What is at stake is an overtaking by and in practice
of a change in social practice. Use value, subordinated for centuries to
exchange value, can now come first again. How? By and in urban society,
from this reality which still resists and preserves for us use value,
the city. A weakened but true vision of this truth is an urban reality
for âusersâ and not for capitalist speculators, builders and
technicians.
Here we can envisage a strategic variable: to limit the importance of
the car industry in the economy of a country and the place of the
âcar-objectâ in daily life. To substitute the car for other techniques,
other objects, other means of transport such as public ones. This is a
rather simple and trivial example but demonstrates the subordination of
the ârealâ to a strategy.
The problem of leisure forces one to think even more dearly of a
strategy. To define it in its full scope, it is important to firstly
destroy a few fantasies mixed up with ideology. The social imaginary
furnished by ideology and advertising, as well as the sad reality of
âhobbiesâ and miniaturized âcreativityâ blocks the horizon. Neither
holidays, nor industrialized cultural production, nor leisure in or
outside daily life resolve this problem. Their images prevent it from
being posed. The problem is to put an end to the separations of âdaily
life â leisureâ or âdaily life â festivityâ. It is to restitute the fĂȘte
by changing daily life. The city was a space occupied at one and the
same time by productive labour, by oeuvres, and by festivities. It
should find again this function beyond functions, in a metamorphosed
urban society. One of the strategic aims can be formulated in this way,
although it is only a formulation of what is happening today without
grace or splendour in cities which attempt to recreate the fĂȘte with
festivities and festivals.
Each type of society and each mode of production has had its type of
city. The relative discontinuity of modes of production defines the
history of urban reality, although this is not exclusive and other
periodization are possible. Another periodization resting on a specific
centrality would show more closely the succession of urban types but
would not coincide completely with the primary periodization.
The oriental city, reason and result of the Asiatic mode of production,
offers its triumphal way for gatherings and meetings. Armies which
protect and oppress the agricultural territories administered by the
city leave and return through chis way on which are deployed military
parades and religious processions. The palace of the prince, the
umbilical, the omphalos, is the centre of the world, the point of
departure and arrival. The sacred enclosure captures and condenses
sacredness diffused over the whole of the territory. It manifests the
eminent right of the sovereign, inseparable possession and sacredness.
The triumphal way penetrates into the enclosure through a door, monument
among monuments. It is the door of the true urban centre, the centre of
the world not open to gatherings. Around the door are gathered guards,
caravaneers, vagrants and robbers. The tribunal sits here and gathers
the inhabitants for spontaneous assemblies. It is the place of urban
order and disorder, of revolts and repressions.
In the Greek and Roman antique city, centrality is attached to an empty
space, the agora and the forum. It is a place for assembly. There is an
important difference between the agora and the forum. Prohibitions
characterize the latter and buildings will quickly cover it up, taking
away from it its character of open space. It is not disjointed from the
centre of the world: the hole, the sacredâdamned mundus, the place from
which souls leave, where the condemned and unwanted children are thrown.
The Greeks did not put emphasis on horror, on the links between urban
centrality and the underworld of the dead and the souls. Their thought
of their city is related to the Cosmos, a luminous distribution of
places in space, rather than to the world, passage to darkness and of
underworld wanderings. This shadow, more Roman than Hellenic, weighs
over the West.
For its part, the medieval city soon integrated merchants and
commodities and established them in its centre; the market-place. A
commercial centre characterized by the proximity of the church and the
exclusion of the enclosure â a heterotopy of territory. The symbolism
and the functions of this enclosure are different from that of the
oriental or antique city. The territory belongs to the lords, peasants,
vagrants and plunderers. Urban centrality welcomes produce and people.
It forbids its access to those who threaten its essential and economic
function, thus heralding and preparing capitalism. Nevertheless,
centrality thus functionalized and structured remains the object of all
attentions. It is embellished. The smallest hamlet, the smallest
barbican have their arcades, the possibly sumptuous monumental hall and
municipal buildings which are places of pleasure. The church blesses
commerce and gives a good conscience to the busy citizens. Within the
limits of commercial rationality, gatherings which are part of this
double feature of the religious and the rational take place in the
square, between the church and the market. How these two features
associate by colliding together in combination or in conflict, is
another story.
The capitalist city has created the centre of consumption. Industrial
production did not constitute centrality as such, except in the special
cases â if one can say that â of big enterprise around which a workersâ
city was erected. We already know the double character of the capitalist
city: place of consumption and consumption of place. Businesses densify
in the centre, and attract expensive shops, luxury foodstuffs and
products. The establishment of this centraliry is partial to the old
cores, the spaces appropriated during the course of a previous history.
It cannot go without it. In these privileged sites, the consumer also
comes to consume space; the collection of objects in the windows of
boutiques becomes the reason and the pretext for the gathering of
people. They look, they see, they talk and talk with each other. And it
is the place of encounters amongst the collection of things. What is
said and written, comes before everything else: it is the world of
commodities, of the language of commodities, of the glory and the
extension of exchange value. It tends to absorb use value in exchange
and exchange value. Yet, use and use value resist irreducibly. This
irreducibility of the urban centre plays an essential role in this
argument.
It is neo-capitalism which superimposes, without denying or destroying
it, the centre of consumption upon the centre of decision-making It no
longer gathers together people and things, but data and knowledge. It
inscribes in an eminently elaborated form of simultaneity the conception
of the whole incorporated into an electronic brain, using the
quasi-instantaneity of communications, thus overcoming obstacles such as
the loss of information, the meaningless accumulations of elements,
redundancies, etc. With a disinterested aim? Certainly not. Since the
problem is political, those who constitute specific centrality aim for
power or are its instruments. The issue is not simply to âmaster
techniqueâ in general, but to master clearly defined techniques with
socio-political implications. What is at stake is to control the
potential masters: those whose power appropriates all possibilities.
The controversy has been taken up again and pushed towards new
conclusions to propose and defend another centrality. The possibility of
an urban society here outlined cannot be satisfied with centralities of
the past, although it does not destroy them and appropriates them by
altering them. What to project? There is something barren about cultural
centrality. It easily allows itself to be organized, institutionalized,
and later, bureaucratized. There is nothing more derisive than the
bureaucrat of culture. The educational is attractive, but neither
seduces nor enchants. Pedagogy implies localized practices, not
socialized centrality. Moreover, there is nothing to prove chat there is
âoneâ or âaâ culture. Subordinated to this entity, âcultureâ and its
ideology, âculturalismâ, theatre, the greatest of games, is threatened
with boredom. The elements of a superior unit, the fragments and aspects
of âcultureâ, the educational, the formative and the informational, can
be collected together. But from where can the contents of the principle
of assembly be derived? From play, ludo, a term which muse be understood
here in its broadest and deepest meaning. Sport is play and so is the
theatre, in a way more involving than the cinema. Fairs, collective
games of all sorts, survive at the interfaces of an organized consumer
society, in the holes of a serious society which perceives itself as
structured and systematical and which claims to be technical. As for the
old places of assembly, they are largely devoid of meaning: the fĂȘte
dies or leaves it. That they should find a meaning again does not
preclude the creation of places appropriate to a renewed fĂȘte
fundamentally linked to play.
No doubt that so-called consumer society suggests this direction.
Leisure centres, leisure societies, cities of luxury and pleasures,
holiday places, show this eloquently with the particular rhetoric of
advertising. Therefore, all that is needed is to give form to this
tendency which is still subordinated to the industrial and commercial
production of culture in this society. The proposition of this project
is to gather together by subordinating to play rather than to
subordinate play to the âseriousnessâ of culturalism and scientificism,
although this does not exclude âculturalâ elements. On the contrary. It
collects them together by restoring them in their truth. Only relatively
recently and through institutions has the theatre become âculturalâ,
while play has lost its place and value in society. Would culture not be
the accommodation of the oeuvre and style to exchange value, thus
allowing for its commercialization, its production and consumption as
specific product?
There are implications to the centrality of play which is the
restoration of the meaning of the oeuvre that philosophy and art can
bring so as to prioritize time over space, not forgetting that time
comes to inscribe itself and to be written in a space â and thus replace
domination by appropriation.
The space of play has coexisted and still coexists with spaces of
exchange and circulation, political space and cultural space. Projects
within quantified and accounted âsocial spaceâ which lose their
qualitative and differentiated spaces relate to a schizophrenia which is
concealed under the veils of precision, scientificity and rationality.
We have shown above the inevitable outcome of an analytical thought
which without safeguards perceives itself as global. This globality is
the formalized space of social pathology. There is a continuous path
from the concept of habitat to schizophrenic space projected as social
model. The orientation envisaged here does not consist in suppressing
qualified spaces as existing historical differences. On the contrary.
These already complex spaces can be further articulated, by emphasizing
differences and contrasts, and by stressing quality which implies and
overdetermines quantities. To these spaces, one can apply formalized
principles of differences and articulation, of superimpositions of
contrasts. Thus conceived, social spaces are related to social times and
rhythms which are prioritized. One understands more clearly how and up
to what point in urban reality elements distribute themselves over a
period of time. It is the truth of urban time which lucidly reclaims
this role. To inhabit finds again its place over habitat. The quality
which is promoted presents and represents as playful. By playing with
words, one can say that there will be play between the parts of the
social whole (plasticity) â to the extent that play is proclaimed as
supreme value, eminently solemn, if not serious, overtaking use and
exchange by gathering them together. And if someone cries out that this
utopia has nothing in common with socialism, the answer is that today
only the working class still knows how to really play, feels like
playing, over and above the claims and programmes, of economism, and
political philosophy. How is this shown? Sport and the interest shown in
sport and games, including, in television and elsewhere, the degraded
forms of ludic life. Already, to city people the urban centre is
movement, the unpredictable, the possible and encounters. For them, it
is either âspontaneous theatreâ or nothing.
To the extent that the contours of the future city can be outlined, it
could be defined by imagining the reversal of the current situation, by
pushing to its limits this inverted image of the world upside down.
There are currently attempts to establish fixed structures, âequilibrium
structuresâ, stabilities submitted to systematization, and therefore to
existing power, At the same time there is a tactical wager on the
accelerated obsolescence of consumer goods, ironically known as
âdurablesâ. The ideal city would involve the obsolescence of space: an
accelerated change of abode, emplacements and prepared spaces. It would
be the ephemeral city, the perpetual oeuvre of the inhabitants,
themselves mobile and mobilized for and by this oeuvre. Time comes
first. There is no doubt that technology makes possible the ephemeral
city, the apogee of play and supreme oeuvre and luxury. One can cite the
world exhibition in Montreal among other examples! In Montreal.
To put art at the service of the urban does not mean to prettify urban
space with works of arc. This parody of the possible is a caricature.
Rather, this means that time-spaces become works of art and that former
art reconsiders itself as source and model of appropriation of space and
rime. Art brings cases and examples of appropriate âtopicsâ: of temporal
qualities inscribed in spaces. Music shows how expression and lyricism
uses numbering, order and measure. fr shows that time, tragic or
serious, can absorb and reabsorb calculation. With less force but more
precision than music, this is the same for sculpture and painting. Let
us not forget that gardens, parks, and landscapes were part of urban
life as much as the fine arts, or that the landscape around cities were
the works of art of these cities. For example, the Tuscan landscape
around Florence, inseparable from its architecture, plays an immense
role in Renaissance arts. Leaving aside representation, ornamentation
and decoration, art can become praxis and poiesis on a social scale: the
art of living in the city as work of art. Coming back to style and m the
oeuvre, that is, to the meaning of the monument and the space
appropriated in the fĂȘte, art can create âstructures of enchantmentâ.
Architecture taken separately and on its own, could neither restrict nor
create possibilities. Something more, something better, something else,
is needed. Architecture as art and technique also needs an orientation.
Although necessary, it could not suffice. Nor could architecture set and
define its own aims and strategy. In other words, the future of art is
not artistic, but urban, because the future of âmanâ is not discovered
in the cosmos, or in the people, or in production, but in urban society.
In the same way art and philosophy must reconsider itself in relation to
this perspective. The problematic of the urban renews the problematic of
philosophy, its categories and methods. Without a need to break or
reject them, these categories accept something else new: a meaning.
The right to the city manifests itself as a superior form of rights:
right to freedom, to individualization in socialization, to habitat and
to inhabit. The right to the oeuvre, to participation and appropriation
(clearly distinct from the right to property), are implied in the right
to the city.
With regards to philosophy, three periods are identifiable. This is a
periodization which is particular among those which mark the continuum
of becoming. In the first stage, philosophy meditates on the city as
partial whole at the heart of totality, world and cosmos. In the second,
philosophy reflects on a transcending totality of the city: history,
âmanâ, society, State. It accepts and even confirms several separations
in the name of totalicy. It sanctions the analytical hold by believing
it is refuting or overcoming it. In the third period philosophy competes
for the promotion of a rationality and a practice which transform
themselves into urban rationality and planning practice.
Let us take up again the thread of the argument and show its continuity
to its conclusions. Knowledge is in an untenable situation. Philosophy
wanted to reach the total but passed by it, unable to grasp it and even
less to realize it. By giving it a representation which was
systematized, speculative and contemplative, in its own way it mutilated
totality. And yet, only philosophy had and still has the sense of the
total. Partial and fragmentary knowledge claimed to have achieved
certainties and realities, but have only delivered fragments. They
cannot go without synthesis, yet cannot legitimize their right to it.
From its beginnings Greek philosophy linked itself to greatness, and
also the miseries and limitations of the Greek city â slavery and the
subordination of the individual to the Polis. Two thousand years later,
Hegel declared the realization of philosophical rationality released by
centuries of reflection and meditation, but in and by the State. How to
get our of these quandaries? How to resolve contradictions? Industrial
production has upset notions concerning the social capacity to act, to
create anew, and to master material nature. Philosophy could no longer
sustain its traditional mission, nor the philosopher his vocation, to
define man, the human, society and the world while taking charge of the
creation of man by his effort, his will, his struggle against
determinisms and hazards. Science and the sciences, technology, the
organization and rationalization of industry were coming onto the scene.
Were 2,000 years of philosophy to go to the grave? No. Industry
contributes new means but has no purpose or meaning in itself. it throws
products into the world. Philosophy (with art and works of art), a
supreme oeuvre, says what is appropriation, nor the technical mastery of
material nature which produces products and exchange values. Therefore,
the philosopher must speak, say the meaning of industrial production, as
long as he does not speculate on it and use it as a theme to prolong the
old manner of philosophizing. Instead he must take it as means of
realizing philosophy, that is, the philosophical project of man in the
world: desire and reason, spontaneity and reflection, vitality and
containment, domination and appropriation, determinisms and liberties.
Philosophy cannot realize itself without art (as model of appropriation
of time and space), accomplishing itself fully in social practice and
without science and technology, as means, not being fully used, without
the proletarian condition being overcome.
This theoretical revolution begun by Marx was later obscured, industrial
production, economic growth, organizational rationality, the consumption
of products, becoming ends rather than means, subordinated to a superior
end. Today, the realization of philosophy can take up again its meaning,
that is, give a meaning as much to history as to actuality. The thread
interrupted for a century is renewed. The theoretical situation is
released and the gulf is filled between the total and the partial or
fragmentary, between the uncertain whole and the all too certain
fragments. From the moment that urban society reveals the meaning of
industrialization, these concepts play a new role. Theoretical
revolution continues and urban revolution (the revolutionary side of
urban reform and urban strategy), comes to the fore. Theoretical
revolution and political change go together.
Theoretical thought aims at the realization of humanity ocher than that
of a society of low productivity (chat of the epochs of non-abundance,
or rather, of the non-possibility of abundance), and that of a
productivist society. In a society and an urban life delivered from its
ancient limitations, those of rarity and economism, technologies, art
and knowledge come to the service of daily life so as to metamorphose
it. Thus can be defined the realization of philosophy. It is no longer a
question of a philosophy of the city and of an historico-social
philosophy alongside a science of the city. The realization of
philosophy gives a meaning to the sciences of social reality. At the
outset, it refutes the accusation of âsociologismâ which will no doubt
be made against the hypotheses and theses expressed here. Neither
philosophism, nor scienticism, nor pragmatism nor sociologism, nor
psychologism, nor economism. Something else is proclaimed.
(1) Two groups of questions and two orders of urgency have disguised the
problems of the city and urban society: questions of housing and the
âhabitatâ (related to a housing policy and architectural technologies)
and those of industrial organization and global planning. The first from
below, the second from above, have produced, hidden from attention, a
rupture of the traditional morphology of cities, while the urbanization
of society was taking place. Hence, a new contradiction adding to other
unresolved contradictions of existing society, aggravating them and
giving them another meaning.
(2) These two groups of problems have been and are posed by economic
growth and industrial production. Practical experience shows that there
can be growth without social development (that is, quantitative growth
without qualitative development). In these conditions, changes in
society are more apparent than real. ·Fetishism and ideology of change
(in other words, the ideology of modernity) conceal the stagnation of
essential social relations. The development of society can only be
conceived in urban life, by the realization of urban society.
(3) The double process of industrialization and urbanization loses all
meaning if one does not conceive urban society as aim and finality of
industrialization, and if urban life is subordinated to industrial
growth. The latter provides the conditions and the means of urban
society. To proclaim industrial rationality as necessary and sufficient
is to destroy the sense (the orientation, the goal) of the process. At
first industrialization produces urbanization negatively (the breakup of
the traditional city, of its morphology, of its practico-material
reality) and then is ready to get down to work. Urban society begins on
the ruins of the ancient city and its agrarian environment. During these
changes, the relation between industrialization and urbanization is
transformed. The city ceases to be the container the passive receptacle
of products and of production. What subsists and is strengthened of
urban reality in its dislocation, the centre of decision-making,
henceforth enters into the means of production and the systems of
exploitation of social labour by those who control information, culture
and the powers of decision-making themselves. Only one theory enables
the use of these practical facts and the effective realization of urban
society.
(4) For this realization, neither the organization of private
enterprise, nor global planning, although necessary, suffice. A leap
forward of rationality is accomplished. Neither the State, nor private
enterprise can provide indispensable models of rationality and reality.
(5) The realization of urban society calls for a planning oriented
towards social needs, chose of urban society. It necessitates a science
of the city (of relations and correlations in urban life). Although
necessary, these conditions are not sufficient. A social and political
force capable of putting these means into oeuvres is equally
indispensable.
(6) The working class suffers the consequences of the rupture of ancient
morphologies. It is victim of a segregation, a class strategy licensed
by this rupture. Such is the present form of the negative situation of
the proletariat. In the major industrial countries the old proletarian
immiseration declines and tends to disappear. But a new misery spreads,
which mainly affects the proletariat without sparing other social strata
and classes: the poverty of the habitat that of the inhabitant submitted
to a daily life organized (in and by a bureaucratized society of
organized consumption). To those who would still doubt its existence as
class, what identifies the working class on the ground is segregation
and the misery of its âto inhabitâ .
(7) In these difficult conditions, at the heart of a society which
cannot completely oppose them and yet obstructs them, rights which
define civilization (in, but often against society â by, but often
against culture) find their way. These rights which are not well
recognized, progressively become customary before being inscribed into
formalized codes. They would change reality if they entered into social
practice: right to work, to training and education, to health, housing,
leisure, to life. Among these rights in the making features the right to
the city (not to the ancient city, but to urban life, to renewed
centrality, to places of encounter and exchange, to life rhythms and
time uses, enabling the full and complete usage of these moments and
places, etc.). The proclamation and realization of urban life as the
rule of use (of exchange and encounter disengaged from exchange value)
insist on the mastery of the economic (of exchange value, the market,
and commodities) and consequently is inscribed within the perspectives
of the revolution under the hegemony of the working class.
(8) For the working class, rejected from the centres towards the
peripheries, dispossessed of the city, expropriated thus from the best
outcomes of its activity, this right has a particular bearing and
significance. It represents for it at one and the same time a means and
an end, a way and a horizon: but this virtual action of the working
class also represents the general interests of civilization and the
particular interests of all social groups of âinhabitantsâ, for whom
integration and participation become obsessional without making their
obsession effective.
(9) The revolutionary transformation of society has industrial
production as ground and lever. This is why it had to be shown that the
urban centre of decision-making can no longer consider itself in the
present society (of neo-capitalism or of monopoly capilaism associated
to the State), outside the means of production, their property and their
management. Only the taking in charge by the working class of planning
and its political agenda can profoundly modify social life and open
another era: that of socialism in neo-capitalist countries. Until then
transformations remain superficial, at the level of signs and the
consumption of signs, language and metalanguage, a secondary discourse,
a discourse on previous discourses. Therefore, it is not without
reservations that one can speak of urban revolution. Nevertheless, the
orientation of industrial production on social needs is not a secondary
fact. The finality thus brought to plans transforms them. In this way
urban reform has a revolutionary bearing. As in the twentieth century
agrarian reform gradually disappears from the horizon, urban reform
becomes a revolutionary reform. It gives rise to a strategy which
opposes itself to class strategy dominant today.
(10) Only the proletariat can invest its social and political activity
in the realization of urban society. Equally, only it can renew the
meaning of productive and creative activity by destroying the ideology
of consumption. It therefore has the capacity to produce a new humanism,
different from the old liberal humanism which is ending its course â of
urban man for whom and by whom the city and his own daily life in it
become oeuvre, appropriation, use value (and not exchange value), by
using all the means of science, art, technology and the domination over
material nature.
(11) Nevertheless, difference persists between product and oeuvre. To
the meaning of the production of products (of the scientific and
technical mastery of material nature) must be added, to later
predominate, the meaning of the oeuvre, of appropriation (of time,
space, the body and desire). And this in and by urban society which is
beginning. Now, the working class does not spontaneously have the sense
of the oeuvre. It is dimmed, having almost disappeared along with crafts
and skills and âqualityâ. Where can be found this precious deposit, this
sense of the oeuvre? From where can the working class receive it to
carry it to a superior degree by uniting it with productive intelligence
and dialectic practical reason? Philosophy and the whole of
philosophical tradition on one hand, and on the other all of art (not
without a radical critique of their gifts and presents) contain the
sense of the oeuvre.
(12) This calls for, apart from the economic and political revolution
(planning oriented towards social needs and democratic control of the
State and self-management), a permanent cultural revolution.
There is no incompatibility between these levels of total revolution, no
more than between urban strategy (revolutionary reform aiming at the
realization of urban society on the basis of an advanced and planned
industrialization) and strategy aiming at the transformation of
traditional peasant life by industrialization. Moreover in most
countries today the realization of urban society goes through the
agrarian form and industrialization. There is no doubt that a world
front is possible, and equally that it is impossible today. This utopia
projects as it often does on the horizon a âpossible-impossibleâ.
Happily, or otherwise, rime, that of history and social practice,
differs from the time of philosophies. Even if it does not produce the
irreversible, it can produce the difficult to repair. Marx wrote that
humanity does not only ask itself problems that it can resolve. Some
today believe chat men now only ask themselves insoluble problems. They
deny reason. None the less, there are perhaps problems which are easy to
resolve, whose solutions are near, very near, and that people do not ask
themselves.
Paris 1967 â centenary of Capital