💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › crimethinc-breaking-with-consensus-reality.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:22:33. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Breaking With Consensus Reality Author: CrimethInc. Date: 2012 Language: en Topics: consensus, organizing, reality, direct action, revolution, consent Source: Retrieved on 9th September 2020 from https://crimethinc.com/2013/04/23/breaking-with-consensus-reality-from-the-politics-of-consent-to-the-seduction-of-revolution Notes: This text is excerpted from the publication TERROR INCOGNITA, a meditation on desire, insurrection, and the unknown.
We who fight to create a freer world face a fundamental contradiction.
On one hand, we don’t want to become a vanguard, “leading” or imposing
our will on others, as that would run counter to our anti-authoritarian
values. On the other hand, we believe with good justification that our
political goals—including the destruction of capitalism, the state, and
hierarchy—can’t be accomplished without strategies that are currently
unpalatable to most of our fellow citizens. The impoverishment of
millions and the destruction of our ecosystems demand that we act
decisively. What criteria will equip us to challenge these systems
without resorting to the authoritarian means we condemn?
Some of us have developed a practice of prioritizing consent as a
provisional answer to this dilemma. This discourse comes to us through
educators who promote it as a tool for fostering mutually respectful
sexuality in the midst of a rape culture. Applying this model in our
intimate relationships and beyond, we seek to respect others’ autonomy
by not subjecting them to actions that violate their consent—that is, by
staying within the boundaries of others’ desires as they determine and
articulate them. We reject coercion of any form, whether physical,
verbal, economic, or otherwise, and assert our self-determination to
participate in or abstain from whatever we choose.
Yet outside of the sexual realm, consent discourse doesn’t always offer
a sufficient framework with which to evaluate direct action tactics and
strategy. Knowing whether an action is consensual may not suffice to
indicate whether it is effective or worthwhile. Aware that most people
oppose some of our tactics, we don’t plan our actions on the basis of
consent, yet we don’t aspire to become a vanguard, either. Furthermore,
since we can only desire on the basis of what we know, we’re unlikely to
achieve liberation from simply fulfilling the desires we have now
without changing the conditions that produced them. So how else might we
conceive of our political project, if not through the lens of consent?
A close examination of our activities reveals that in setting out to
foment insurrection and transform society, we appear to be operating
according to a logic of seduction. Are we prepared to accept the
implications of this reframing? Let’s begin by examining the politics of
consent and their limitations.
At first glance, the notion of basing our political practice on a theory
of consent makes intuitive sense. What’s our critique of the state? It’s
a body that wields power over us even to the point of life and death,
and yet no one ever asked us if we wanted to be governed. Elections
don’t even begin to offer us the meaningful alternatives true consent
would require. It’s been said before: our desires will never fit in
their ballot boxes. We promote the principle of voluntary
association—the freedom to form whatever groups and collectives we want
without being compelled to participate in any. We never had the chance
to say no to capitalism, to government, to police, to all the systems of
hierarchy that impose their rule—so clearly those can’t be consensual in
any meaningful way. As we do away with the coercive systems that
dominate our lives, we can reconstruct new social relations based on
consent: a world in which no one controls anyone else, in which we can
determine our own destinies.
It makes sense … doesn’t it? Certainly, this discourse of consent offers
a compelling way to imagine the world we want to live in. But how does
it serve as a strategy for dislodging this one? It’s difficult to
envision a political practice that stringently respects the consent of
all people while simultaneously destroying the fabric of our
hierarchical society. If we insist on the unity of means and ends, we
have to dismantle coercive institutions and social relationships through
non-coercive processes to build a non-coercive society. Abandoning this
vision could undermine the very basis of our anarchism. Yet if we don’t
succeed in dislodging capitalism and the state, the bases of economic
and political coercion, we’ll never arrive at a society in which a
consent-based framework could actually be tenable.
How can we resolve these dilemmas? Let’s look more closely at what we
mean by consent, and how it operates in our society and in our
movements.
Power and consent are critically intertwined. Power imbalances make it
difficult or impossible to give consent freely. Can a much older person
have consensual sex with a very young person? Can someone who is
subjected to another’s economic control freely consent to that person’s
desires? For consent to be meaningful, it must be possible to say no,
any time and for any reason, on one’s own terms. When the state
monopolizes the use of force and the economy controls access to our very
means of survival, we cannot meaningfully choose. We call the boundaries
enclosing our ability to consent under these conditions consensus
reality.
Consensus reality is the range of possible thought and action within a
system of power relations. It is enforced not only through traditional
institutions of control—such as mass media, religion, and the family—but
also through the innumerable subtle norms manifested in common sense,
civil discourse, and day-to-day life. It isn’t simply the aggregate of
all our desires, melded together in a great compromise that allows us
all to get along, as democratic mythology would have it. Consensus
reality constitutes the ruling class’s coordinated attempt to uphold
their dominance and our exploitation as efficiently as possible.
Capitalist democracy secures that efficiency; it is the system that
currently provides the largest number of people with incentive to
participate in their own exploitation. It offers us a series of
meaningless options to disguise a profound lack of agency over our
lives. The trump card of capitalist democracy is the idea that
everyone’s consent is respected in a marketplace of ideas within which
desires can be freely expressed and influenced.
We can argue that this marketplace isn’t truly free—corporations control
the mass media, some views get more airtime than others, thus the
consent is not fully informed—but this doesn’t get at the heart of
things. Obviously, equal access to means of influence on a level playing
field is impossible in capitalist society. But it is the systems of
power, not just speech, that determine the framework within which we
experience reality. All political systems—whether anarchist, fascist, or
democratic—produce particular patterns of social relations. Mere
discussion of these systems does not; it cannot transcend the framework
in which it occurs.[1] Free speech discourse offers each of us our own
box of colored chalk to decorate the cement blocks around our feet, and
calls that freedom; whether we can walk away doesn’t even enter into the
picture. Our experience of what we are and aren’t able to do determines
our sense of what is possible far more than our ideas and discourses. To
shift the boundaries of our imagination and desires, we have to find
ways to make new experiences possible beyond the bounds of consensus
reality.
Take, for example, the debates about violence and nonviolence that rage
in every organizing coalition and Occupy movement. What is violence? At
first glance, the term seems to have no more coherence than the Supreme
Court definition of obscenity: I can’t define it, but I know it when I
see it. This makes it an especially dangerous tool when wielded by
liberals to control group norms. But recalling that violence springs
from the same root as violation helps us get at the meaning behind how
the word is used. What is called violence is any violation of norms
about legitimate use of force, norms dictated by the state and
incorporated into our consensus reality. The debate about violence is
really a coded discourse in which nonviolence stands in for consent;
when we attempt to make space for autonomy and diversity of tactics, our
opponents perceive us as disregarding consent simply for opposing the
terms of consensus reality.
Observe how an anxious liberal from our local Occupy movement, dismayed
by an illegal building occupation undertaken by autonomous occupiers,
strives to distance the Occupy group from the occupation. He says to a
reporter: “Our movement is nonviolent, it is peaceful, and it does not
break the law.” The building occupation involved no physical violence,
nor damage to property, nor anything that could be construed as violent
even within his own definition, whereas the eviction by rifle-wielding
thugs was violent enough to shock people across the political spectrum.
How can we make sense of this seeming contradiction?
It seems that the meaningful sense of violence here is a rupture of
consensus reality. This liberal wishes to communicate that the building
occupation felt like a violation of his consent. Why? Because it was
related to a current in which he felt invested, yet he had not been
invited to participate in decision-making, and it involved actions that
he personally disdained. Of course, we undertook the occupation
autonomously precisely for that reason: we knew we could never achieve
consensus in the public general assemblies to do something that so
dramatically challenged consensus reality. Whether or not the occupation
hurt anyone was beside the point: its “violence” had less to do with its
literal effects than its challenge to consensus reality. To him, such a
challenge constituted a violation of collective consent.
Let’s call this liberal consent: the notion that we must adhere
tactically to the most conservative common denominator or else violate
others’ consent. We all have to put up with this system, so the logic
goes, whether we chose it or not, because any violation would put us all
at risk. This goes beyond a critique of representation—you shouldn’t
carry out an action on my behalf without my consent—to a critique of
autonomy, since literally any action that presumes affinity with others
is subject to the boundaries dictated by consensus reality.
This is the risk of embracing a framework of political consent. Within
this logic, the most moderate elements of any group or coalition will
dominate by virtue of their alignment with consensus reality. What’s OK
for anybody is based on what’s OK for everybody, which makes our
strategies for changing this world look suspiciously similar to the
world we’re trying to change. If we do in fact desire a radical break
with what exists, let’s not trap ourselves in a framework aligned with
the systems we want to destroy.
Nonviolence is the only ideology that can comprehensively protect
consensus reality against the antagonism of all who would transform it.
By preemptively condemning anything that exceeds the parameters of civil
discourse, it ensures that any resistance will ultimately strengthen the
underlying framework of authority, and even passes responsibility for
policing on to the loyal opposition. Liberal complicity with violent
systems of control can be “nonviolent” according to this logic, because
they accept the boundaries of legitimacy decreed by consensus reality.
Just as every pacifist condemns armed struggle and insurrection against
the state, the gains of every “nonviolent” movement and revolution they
cite, from Dr. King to Gandhi, rested on a foundation of explicit or
threatened state violence. We shake our heads at liberal reluctance to
acknowledge that the state is fundamentally rather than incidentally
violent, but that violence is woven so seamlessly into consensus reality
that it simply doesn’t register.
The violence so anxiously opposed by liberals is, by definition, that
which ruptures consensus reality. And this is precisely why we consider
that violence necessary: framing resistance as registering our “dissent”
does not attack consensus reality but merely identifies our position
within it. There are not opposing partisans within consensus
reality—Republicans and Democrats, activists and reactionaries—but only
partisans of consensus reality and partisans against it.
In short, the liberal notion of consent is a barrier to revolution. By
definition, breaking consensus reality cannot be consensual. We have to
move beyond political consent discourse to imagine liberating strategies
for transforming reality.
So liberal consent is a tool for defending consensus reality, useless to
our project of liberation. But that doesn’t necessarily mean we have to
give up on the discourse of consent itself. Are there ways to respond to
these objections within a consent-based framework? Let’s explore some of
the possible responses to liberal consent rhetoric.
Decision-making should be weighted to prioritize the most affected.
According to this principle, the greater the impact a decision will have
on a person, the more leverage he or she should have in the
decision-making process. For instance, the opinions of a poor
neighborhood’s long-term residents should count for more than those of
developers or wealthier newcomers when determining whether to build new
condominiums. Thus, how consensual an action is depends not on whether
every citizen, equal under the law, would check yes or no about it on a
ballot; rather, individuals’ feelings are weighted proportionally
according to how the consequences will impact them.
This sidesteps some of the problems of negotiating political consent
across power differentials; it looks attractive as a way to navigate
conflicting priorities in a society based on values beyond the profit
motive. But does this principle offer us useful guidance on how to get
there? We can’t easily determine who will be most affected by strategies
intended to create unpredictable situations so as to open up the horizon
for transformation. Some activists see those most vulnerable to the
potential consequences of militant tactics as the most impacted by any
escalation beyond the confines of consensus reality politics. In
practice, this concern can function to impose a tactical conservatism,
reproducing the effect of liberal consensus and creating a dichotomy
between resisting effectively and prioritizing others’ safety.[2]
On the other hand, in trying to legitimize our efforts according to this
principle, we sometimes fall into the trap of using the example of a few
individuals who support an action to stand in for an entire imagined
demographic. We ascribe a mythical authenticity to specific local,
working-class, indigenous, or other people who express enthusiasm for
our activities, implicitly writing off those who don’t. We make such
supporters into a sort of prosthesis for ourselves that entitles us to
act against the ostensible majority, imagining our chosen comrades to
represent the most affected. Every activist has a preferred imaginary
friend, whether the workers favored by IWW organizers, the West Virginia
locals courted by opponents of mountaintop removal, or the extras in hip
hop videos that insurrectionists hope will join them in the streets.
This is not only tokenizing, but dangerous, as it can lead us to
overestimate popular support for our actions. Yet it is supported by a
variety of rationalizations: just because we don’t see public support
doesn’t mean it isn’t there; the people who are most marginalized—who,
we assume, are most likely to support our unpopular actions—are the
least free to express that support publicly; and so on. There is some
truth in these arguments. But when we gamble on this imaginary-friend
fantasy as an effort to weigh by proxy the consent of the
unrepresented—now represented by our presumed affinity with them—we’re
just deluding ourselves.
Decision-making must be broadened to include all the people impacted.
Often, many of those who will be impacted by supposedly consensual
decisions do not have appropriate leverage on them. For instance, the
university’s board of governors can decide by consensus to raise
tuition, but what kind of consensus is that without the participation of
the students who’ll be paying it? If decisions included all stakeholders
and elites couldn’t impose them by force, wouldn’t there be hope for a
politics of consent?
Unfortunately, this framework is more useful for preventing actions or
challenging their validity after the fact than for initiating them. The
impacts of our actions ripple out far beyond our ability to trace them
or the range of lives they will touch. We cannot even hope to be aware
of every person who would be impacted by a decision, much less solicit
meaningful input from each of them to confirm or deny consensus. In
practical terms, expanding the participation in decision-making to
everyone affected would either require resorting to majority-rule
democracy—not a consent-based framework—or accepting the impossibility
of ever making decisions.
Here we have to confront the reality that broad consensus on many issues
will never exist. We might be able to agree about what to cook for
dinner, but on the real questions about how to organize society and
distribute resources, no consensus is possible today. In a class society
stratified by white supremacy and patriarchy, our interests are
fundamentally in conflict. Certainly we share many interests in common,
and we can imagine worlds in which people aren’t pitted against one
another in contests for status and survival. But we will not be able to
desert this world by consensus.[3]
We’re acting in self-defense. As this reasoning goes, the operation of
oppressive institutions constitutes an attack on us, and we don’t need
the consent of our attackers to defend ourselves. This harm isn’t always
on a literal, direct, individual level, as in that specific Starbucks
window makes my individual life increasingly precarious and impossible.
In a hopelessly complex global economy that masks the root causes of the
harm it creates, nearly any attempt to launch a defensive counterattack
will seem either symbolic or misdirected. Still, in this sense, direct
action can be framed as defending ourselves against violations of our
consent by state and capital.
But the rhetoric of direct action as self-defense doesn’t offer us much
guidance for how to move forward. In this model, state and capital are
the protagonists, and the various formulations of we that we self-defend
the mere objects of their actions. We can only react, not strategize new
initiatives. Furthermore, the framework of self-defense is based in the
terms of liberal individualism, with our private personal rights
beginning where those of another end. What is it that we’re defending?
Our role in society as defined under capitalism and patriarchy? Our
rights as dictated by the democratic state? To get free, we should be
fighting to destroy our selves! Not our bodies and lives, of course, but
our selfhood as it’s constituted by state and capital.
If selfhood extends as far as the bank windows, if our selves overlap so
extensively, we need another framework—we’re not just defending
ourselves. At best, self-defense is a justification, not a praxis; at
worst, it’s a disingenuous smokescreen that leaves us without a
framework to evaluate our effectiveness.
Consent has to be informed. In all consent-based ethical systems,
medical, sexual, and otherwise, authentic consent requires full
knowledge of the implications of a decision. On the political level,
this criticism goes, if we all had access to complete information, we
would make decisions differently. This is the basic hypothesis of
liberalism: the best of all possible worlds will result when people have
access to all relevant information and the means to discuss it openly in
order to make rational decisions.
The fatal flaw in this reasoning is that it fails to take power dynamics
into account. When access to money and property determines our ability
to act, under the rule of a state that reserves the sole right to employ
violence, knowledge is not in fact power. Furthermore, it seems to
demand a politics of total transparency, which would either preclude
illegal activity or consign us all to the certainty of prison. An
informed consent framework neither enables us to imagine how to achieve
a consensus for revolution nor suffices to determine how much
information to share with whom about the actions we take to fight for
it.
In concluding that the consent framework can’t accommodate our political
needs, we’re not endorsing the violation of consent. Rather, we’re
acknowledging that the consent framework has not been sufficient to
transcend the self-defeating dichotomy between either respecting consent
to such an extent that we can’t overthrow capitalism or disregarding it
entirely. The point is to come up with a framework that solves those
problems, not to throw out what gains we’ve made already.[4]
In fact, our basis for opposing capitalism and hierarchy goes far beyond
the claim that these systems operate without our consent. Ultimately, we
fight for new worlds out of desire, and in order to move beyond the
limitations of political consent discourse we have to look more closely
at what desire is.
What is desire? Let’s conceive of desires not as internal elements
emanating from within individuals, but as autonomous forces that flow
through them. Individuals don’t desire things; whole societies produce
and circulate desires, even if those desires remain submerged in most
people. The fundamental unit of our analysis is not the individual human
being, but the desire, with humans as the medium.
How can we conceive of desire and selfhood as they relate to consent and
political action? The existing consent discourse presupposes static
notions of self and desire. It presumes that desire is monolithic,
composed of a single thrust rather than multiple pulls in different
directions. When we have multiple desires, the desire that garners the
plurality in our internal electoral process is assumed to be the only
one that counts. Consent discourse presumes that what we want is
knowable and can be articulated within the framework of our shared
reality.
In reality, the desires we experience are not fixed or unitary. They
shift constantly based on our experiences and contexts. They are
multiple, contradictory, and divergent, surprising us with their
diversity, frustrating us with their mutability. They resist our
attempts to confine or domesticate them. They simply can’t fit into a
two-dimensional binary model of consent, wherein we either want
something or we don’t. This realization is terrifying, but it opens up
new ways of understanding the revolutionary project in relation to the
consensus reality arrayed against us.
The nature of desire is complex and centrifugal, in contrast to the
simplifying and centripetal nature of interests. The traditional
approach of the left is for organizers to assist constituencies in
winning victories that build power, which will presumably be deployed
towards increasingly radical ends. The goals of these victories are
generally framed in terms of the interests of the constituency, not
their desires. This is a clever trick: as interests appear to be an
objective rather than subjective matter, it is easier for an outside
managerial class to get away with defining and representing them.
Interests can be framed as unitary, coherent, and integrative, whereas
desires are multiple, inchoate, contradictory. Identity groups share
interests; friends and lovers share desires. Interests are composed of
calcified blocks of desire standardized to make sense within consensus
reality.
Not only is desire far more complex and unstable than our discourses
allow, it’s also shaped by the conditions of our misery and
exploitation. Even amid contradictions and chaos, the range of what it
is possible to desire rarely escapes the confines of consensus reality.
Who really imagines that in a free world, we’d dream of ergonomic chairs
for our cubicles, more TV channels and brands of detergent, longer
chains and softer cages? This is not to demean the struggles of those
who fight for better conditions within this system. It’s just to say
that we would be paltry revolutionaries indeed if we based our programs
merely on the consensus desires of groups whose allies we want to be.
The task of the revolutionary is not the task of the ally. We are not
here to make the dreams of the proletariat come true. The proletariat is
produced by capitalism, which we want to destroy. The task of the
revolutionary is to shift our collective sense of the possible, so that
our desires and the realities they drive us to create can shift in turn.
We are here to transform reality beyond where our notions of consent can
lead us. We need a different discourse to imagine the transformations
that can open pathways out of consensus reality.
There’s another framework that seems to be implied by our current
practice, whether or not we acknowledge it. That framework is seduction.
What is seduction? It’s a rather unsavory concept, bringing to mind
manipulative attempts to induce others to let themselves to be used for
one’s own ends. In a sexual context, it can imply either a romantic,
charismatic, persuasive use of charm to propose a sexual encounter, or a
way to trick someone into succumbing to one’s advances. The connotations
are discomfiting, but the salient factor is the implication that the
seducer creates a desire, rather than simply unearthing it. It is this
sense that we find most interesting in considering the problems of
desire and consensus reality on the political level.
When we seduce, we present someone who ostensibly doesn’t want something
with a new situation in which they may want it after all. Whereas
consent focuses on obtaining the go-ahead for an external action—“Is
this OK?”—seduction focuses internally, on desire: “Could you want
this?” Our practices of seduction don’t aim to induce others to do
things they don’t want to do, but to induce others to want to do them,
in the most meaningful sense: to want to take on all the risks and
pleasures they entail.
Again, we don’t believe that we can persuade everyone to consent to our
dreams of anarchist revolution; not only is the deck stacked against us,
but the dealer, the table, and the whole house. We don’t buy into the
idea that our goals are what everybody “really” wants, nor do we assume
that everyone would adopt our views if only they had access to all the
right information. We don’t claim to represent anyone beyond ourselves,
nor to stand in for any silent majority; in that sense, anarchist
revolution is not a democratic project. Nor do we, despairing of those
things, decide that to be true to our principles we must give up on
transforming society altogether and retreat into isolation among the few
comrades with whom we can establish meaningful self-determined
consensus. We don’t think it’s hopeless to resist in the face of the
stranglehold of consensus reality. We want a different path forward, one
that doesn’t assume desire to be fixed, that doesn’t rely on liberal
consent.
We neither wish to impose our will on others by force, nor to disregard
their desires. Instead, we want to perform a kind of magic, an
alchemical operation. We want to induce desires, not simply fulfill
them.[5]
As anarchists, our greatest strength lies not in the coherence and
reason of our ideology, but in the passionate actions we undertake and
the ungovernable lives we lead. Let’s not try to convert people to
anarchism; let’s set out, with mischievous glee, to infect everyone
around us with the anarchy that flows in our veins. Let’s produce
situations in which anarchy is possible, even likely—even desirable to
those who might not feel any inclination towards it today.
How did you become an anarchist? Did you emerge from the womb in a black
hoodie? Did you “always know” you were going to crave riots, stale
bagels, and photocopy scams? If not, chances are you had some sort of
experience that opened you to a sense of possibility you hadn’t
previously been able to imagine. For me, it came at age 18, during the
height of the anti-Iraq war protests, when I heard a vague rumor that I
should show up at a certain concert. I did, and lo and behold, when it
ended a group of maniacs appeared with drums and banners, and before I
knew it I’d joined 200 others marching in the street, permits be damned.
We were unstoppable. The blood boiled in my veins and I howled
ecstatically until I lost my voice. Things were never the same again.
Now, I’d participated in polite permitted marches before. If you’d asked
me if I desired to go on a feisty unpermitted midnight march, I probably
would have thought it sounded cool. But I didn’t actively desire it
beforehand; if I’d been forthrightly invited, I might have declined out
of anxiousness or indifference. The desire was generated by the context,
the mystery, and the experience itself. I suspect that the key was that
it was unexpected and illicit: it took me beyond myself, opening some
door of desire that couldn’t be shut. Had someone asked me in advance
whether I would consent to participate, that might have undermined the
very sense of liberation I experienced.
Trust me, I’m as uncomfortable with the implications of this as you are.
But we need to look honestly at the transformative experiences that
opened the door for us into radical politics and think about how we can
construct and open those types of doors for others. If we’re not going
to be a vanguard and we’re not going to convince everyone to join us
through mere rational discourse, this might be what we’ve got to work
with.
How does seduction work? We hypothesize that seduction unfolds via three
processes: transformation, invitation, and contagion. We transform
circumstances, creating space for new possibilities and thus new desires
to flourish; we invite others to participate in these new situations, to
experiment with different modes of action and desire; and we infect
others with curiosity, an insatiable desire for freedom, and the means
to experiment towards it.
We strive for transformation because if we desire on the basis of what
we know, we can only induce new desires that exceed the confines of our
current reality by shifting the conditions in which we live. Sometimes
it can be as simple as doing things in the street without permits, or
using a park or building for an entirely new purpose. Disobedience is
crucial to transformation; nothing opens up a sense of possibility like
literally breaking the rules. But our behavior is constrained by far
more than traffic laws and zoning regulations; social norms, gender
roles, and innumerable other systems shape how we act, and each way
we’re constrained provides new terrain for transformation. The key lies
in challenging what’s taken for granted in a way that opens up the
possibility to act differently, and to imagine how the world would be
different if those rules and borders were no longer fixed.
Invitation requires neither persuasion via rational discourse nor
imposition by force. Here we maintain the spirit of consent discourse,
asserting our respect for the wishes of others and opposition to
coercion. We aspire to a world based on voluntary association, in which
participation is based on our own free choice rather than force or
manipulation, and thus we aim to prefigure that world through our
methods of creative resistance.
This can take many forms: leaving the doors open in the occupied
building, modeling mutual aid at public Really Really Free Markets,
offering black bandanas and cans of paint as the march leaves the show.
Of course, we can’t literally invite others to participate in many
actions beforehand, either because they have to be organized
clandestinely or because we honestly don’t know what will happen. But we
can shape our actions to maximize the agency of potential participants.
Seduction casts the invitee as the protagonist, the one whose agency
counts—in contrast to consent discourse, which merely seeks permission.
The whole point is for people to discover new desires, to want to do
something they didn’t want before; they have to be in the driver’s seat
for that to be possible. In this sense, we are using seduction to mean
the opposite of its traditional negative connotation of trying to get
something from people against their will or at their expense.
Finally, we aspire to invite others into practices that will prove
contagious: ideas that self-replicate, models that can be applied in a
variety of circumstances, attitudes that prove infectious. Contagion
ensures that rebellion isn’t restricted to activists, scenesters, or any
other particular group. Only when revolt spreads so widely that it can
no longer be quarantined to a specific demographic will anarchy move
permanently beyond the anarchists. We succeed when others emerge from
the spaces we create feeling more powerful. We win when the ruptures of
possibility we open prove impossible to close.
Unfortunately, our actions don’t always achieve these goals. Sometimes
we try to cast spells of transformation and they fail.
One way our efforts can go awry is when they position the organizing
cabal as the protagonists rather than the invitees we hope to seduce
into participation. In these cases, our actions don’t spread, but remain
the province of a distinct group. For partisans of transformation, what
counts is the circulation and contagion of subversive ideas and
practices, not the power of a specific social body—be it anarchists or
the Party.
Sometimes when our seductions fail, those we’ve attempted to invite feel
used rather than seduced. Over the years, this has proved one of the
primary causes of the unpopularity of unilateral militant activity. It’s
flattering to be offered a role as a protagonist in an exciting story,
but it isn’t so pleasant to feel that others are trying to take
advantage of you. When people speak with frustration in a debriefing
conversation about the lack of consent implicit in how an action played
out, we must understand that as a failure of seduction. When they speak
of consent, they’re describing their reaction to the actions that took
place; our analysis of seduction treats the desires underlying these as
the center of gravity.
Perhaps we can best understand such conflicts by reframing them: they
are not merely contests between people with different desires, but
contests between different desires playing out between people as well as
within individuals. The failure of an unpopular action doesn’t stem from
the fact that it failed to meet the desires of participants or
bystanders. Rather, the action failed to enable subversive desires to
arise or flow into new hosts. Critics who frame their objections in
consent discourse may not be fundamentally opposed to the tactics in
question after all; they may simply not feel that they had the chance to
become protagonists in their own stories of rebellion.
What are anarchists good for? We don’t see ourselves as “the”
revolutionary subject, nor its vanguard or representative. But that
doesn’t mean we’re irrelevant to the struggles and upheavals around us.
We up the ante and rep the anti; we call bluffs and take dares; we
discover lines of flight out of consensus reality. We take risks to
induce others to share them with us; we take care of each other so we
can be dangerous together.
Ultimately, the politics of seduction don’t rely on rational
argumentation to influence people. We dive headlong into the terrifying
fires of transformation, allowing strange passions to seize us. It’s not
that these desires are “ours”; rather, we are theirs. We become
lightning rods that crackle with flows of charged desire.
Let’s not forget the importance of seducing ourselves with our actions.
It’s frighteningly easy for activism to ossify into dreary, repetitive
routines. Actions that don’t emerge out of our own desires are unlikely
to seduce us or anyone else. Sure, some kids will be radicalized by the
Food Not Bombs run by four burnt-out punks who resent every Sunday they
spend in the kitchen. But we forge our deepest relationships of struggle
in collectively experiencing the new, the exciting, the terrifying. It’s
not only beautiful but strategic to live lives that push to the
outermost edges of what’s possible.
The stakes are high. From consent discourse, we retain the
prioritization of caring for others and paying attention to their needs.
We must never disregard the well-being of those we invite into zones of
transformation; yet neither can we play it safe and allow consensus
reality to dictate our range of possible dreams and actions. We cannot
promise safety, but we can share in the danger of the unknown, in its
pleasures and its risks.
[1] For instance, within capitalist democracy, the very ability to speak
“freely” seems to offer proof of the system’s justice by virtue of the
state ensuring “free speech.” In anarchic social relations, our ability
to speak freely justifies itself, needing no state to “protect” it or
define its limits. When we frame expressing our desires as “exercising a
right,” we define our legitimacy to act in terms of our relationship to
the state, rather than asserting that our desires are inherently valid.
[2] This has happened again and again, from the post-inauguration march
through Adams Morgan in Washington DC in 2005 to the Oscar Grant riots,
any time collective action isn’t peaceful, legal, and fully pacified.
People who are more vulnerable to state violence or other potential
consequences of escalation—and, more often, self-appointed spokespeople
whose privilege enables them to feel entitled to represent others—speak
out against militant tactics. Since many anarchist agitators are
shielded in part by the privileges of white skin, a male body, no
children, and legal citizenship, it is held to be irresponsible to raise
the stakes without the input of more vulnerable people who may be
affected. Anarchists often counter that those shielded by privilege are
precisely the ones who should put their bodies on the line. But in large
mixed crowds with a potential for explosive conflict, the question of
consent inevitably rears its head. Self-righteous leftists assume that
the purpose of massing in the streets is simply to “speak truth to
power,” but the rest of us have to grapple with how to precipitate
conflict in ways that don’t reinforce the wedges our enemies would drive
between us “bad protestors” and our potential comrades.
[3] One of the implications of this analysis is that we must
unflinchingly recognize conflict as a reality. The vision we’re putting
forward aims not just to create a world in which all is consensual. We
strive to prioritize each other’s consent as much as possible, while
recognizing that sometimes we really are in conflict, and we have to
acknowledge conflicts rather than sweeping them under the rug of an
imposed consensus. Our ideal is not a world without conflict, but a
world in which conflicts don’t produce hierarchies and oppression. We
envision associations that can come together and break apart according
to our desires; unlike the state, these would require no imposed
consensus.
[4] Also, what does this imply in the realm of sexuality? Remember, our
goal in acknowledging the limitations of consent discourse is not to
discard it entirely but to determine where it can take us and where else
we need to go. Consent provides us with crucial tools for treating each
other with care in sexual interactions. At the same time, we can
challenge simplistic notions of desire: some of our most deeply erotic
moments occur not when we finally achieve a desire previously fixed
within us, but when we experience unexpected and unprecedented forms of
pleasure. Perhaps insights from our discourse of political seduction can
offer perspective on our sexuality, but we maintain our allegiance to
consent discourse in sex. Our critique of political consent discourse
isn’t abstract, but based on its tactical shortcomings, the limitations
of what it allows us to do and imagine. By contrast, sexual consent
discourse has proven its utility in our daily lives, inducing us to
examine our desires and transform how we relate to each other
erotically.
[5] Wait, there’s nothing liberating about attempting to induce desires
in others. That’s the function of the advertising industry, the lever of
demand that has driven capitalism over the past century. Democracy
purports to be a marketplace of ideas where we can all talk about what
we want and then decide; different configurations of desire are
constantly at war. Ad firms don’t just create specific desires, they
enforce a mode of desiring that can be routed through the consumer
economy. Propaganda, subliminal messaging, induced addiction, outright
violence: these comprise a brutal arsenal aimed at us every moment of
the day. Around the globe, the military clears the path for neoliberal
pillaging, while NGOs get into the business of inducing people to want
to be successful at generating currencies that can be exchanged on the
global market. Ought we not be suspicious of a project framed in such
transparently manipulative terms? As grim as it looks, this vista
reveals that if we are not partisans of certain modes of desiring, we
will remain objects rather than subjects within these desiring wars. We
cannot retreat into essentialist notions of unearthing our “true”
desires from some internal vault, nor a pseudo-Buddhist project of
extinguishing desire on an individual level while the world burns. What
sets us apart is that we strive to create a world in which every person
can realize her unique potential on her own terms, rather than simply
pushing for this or that option within the current conditions.