💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › jesse-cohn-what-is-postanarchism-post.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:13:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: What is Postanarchism "Post"?
Author: Jesse Cohn
Date: 2002
Language: en
Topics: review, post-anarchism, Saul Newman, John Zerzan, Murray Bookchin, Max Stirner
Source: http://pmc.iath.virginia.edu/issue.902/13.1cohn.html#foot1

Jesse Cohn

What is Postanarchism "Post"?

Newly resurgent anarchist movements, shaking the streets from Seattle to

Genoa, are caught in a field of tension between two magnetic poles:

Eugene, Oregon, and Plainfield, Vermont. Eugene is the home of John

Zerzan, author of Future Primitive (1994), who has pushed anarchist

theory in the direction of an all-encompassing negation of

"civilization." At the Institute for Social Ecology in Plainfield in

1995, Murray Bookchin issued his much debated challenge to the

"anti-civilizational" anarchists, Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm. Bookchin's "social anarchism" is in

the tradition of the anarcho-communism theorized by Peter Kropotkin,

calling for the replacement of nations and markets with a decentralized

federation of self-managing communities. Zerzan's "primitivism" calls

for the destruction of the "totality," including the abolition of

technology, language, and history itself, in favor of a wild, primordial

freedom (Future Primitive 129).[1] The "chasm" between Eugene and

Plainfield is wide, certainly. Zerzan and Bookchin agree on one thing,

however: both hate postmodernism.

Bookchin calls it a form of "nihilism" tailored to "yuppie" tastes (19).

"Postmodernism leaves us hopeless in an unending mall," Zerzan

complains, "without a living critique; nowhere" (134). For Bookchin,

theorists such as Foucault and Derrida simulate a kind of

individualistic rebellion while vitiating social anarchist commitments

to reason, realism, and ethical universals (9-10). For Zerzan, on the

contrary, they bolster the reigning order by liquidating any notion of

the autonomous individual: "the postmodern subject, what is presumably

left of subject-hood, seems to be mainly the personality constructed by

and for technological capital" (110).

This dispute is one of the significant contexts in which Saul Newman's

From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and the Dislocation of

Power arrives. Another is the rediscovery by the academy of the

anarchist theoretical tradition, where until recently anarchism had

endured an official oblivion even longer and deeper than its erasure

from public memory. The rediscovery of anarchist theory is a timely gift

for theorists such as Todd May (The Political Philosophy of

Poststructuralist Anarchism, 1994), who are eager to politicize

poststructuralism but leery of bolting their concepts onto ready-made

Marxist frameworks. Both May and Newman see Marxism, in all its

varieties, as an ineluctably "strategic" philosophy (to use May's term),

perpetually drawn to the postulate of a "center" from which power must

emanate (May 7; 10).

"In contrast to Marxism," writes Newman, "anarchism was revolutionary in

analyzing power in its own right, and exposing the place of power in

Marxism itself--its potential to reaffirm state authority" (6). Mikhail

Bakunin and Karl Marx tore the First International asunder in 1872 over

the question of the State: was it a mere instrument of ruling-class

power, as Marx thought, in which case it could be seized and used by the

proletariat, or was it an "autonomous and independent institution with

its own logic of domination," as Bakunin argued, in which case any

"transitional" State would merely constitute a new reigning regime

(Newman 21)? History has given a poignant weight to Bakunin's

premonitions of a "red bureaucracy," of course, but for a

poststructuralist rereading, his importance lies in his challenge to

Marx's method--the "strategic thinking" for which "all problems can be

reduced to the basic one" (May 10). Anarchist critique undermines the

confident assumption that power is merely an "epiphenomenon of the

capitalist economy or class relations," which in turn opens the way to a

post-Foucauldian apprehension of the ubiquity of power relations--the

"dispersed, decentered" power which comes from everywhere (Newman 2;

78).

At the same time, Newman and May concur, classical anarchism ditches its

own best insight: "anarchism itself falls into the trap of the place of

power" (Newman 6). Both Bakunin and Kropotkin found resistance on a

certain notion of human nature as an "outside" to power--a pure origin

of resistance. Power, as incarnated in the State, represses and distorts

the goodness of humanity; once it is eradicated by the revolution,

"human essence will flourish" and power will disappear (Newman 13). For

Newman, however, power is ineradicable, and any essentialist notion of

"human nature" is the basis for a new domination.

From the diagnosis, the prescription: for anarchism to become meaningful

once again, it must be detached from its investment in essentialist

conceptions of power and human identity, made to face the reality that

power is everywhere. But how to do so while avoiding the gloomy

conclusion that because power is everywhere, resistance is nowhere? If

"resistance to power cannot be conceptualized without thinking in terms

of an outside to power," how can this "outside" be thought without

resorting to yet another equally foundationalist theory of "the place of

power" (97)? Overcoming this "logical impasse" is the task Newman sets

for himself in the following chapters, as he scours the resources of

poststructuralism for "a non-essentialist notion of the Outside" (6).

But what does Newman mean by "power" when he seeks its "Outside"? It's

not always clear what Newman means by this key term. Throughout the

book, he seems to engage in a certain code-switching--sometimes

conscious and clearly marked, sometimes surreptitious or

unconscious--alternating between at least two senses of the word. In the

first chapter, Newman alerts us to the possibility of confusion; while

thus far he has used "power," "domination," and "authority" as synonyms,

"by the time we get to Foucault, 'power' and 'domination' have somewhat

different meanings," and often Newman seems to follow Foucault in

defining "power" as "inevitable in any society," while characterizing

"domination" as "something to be resisted," At other times, he retains

the definition of "power" as "domination" (12). Leaving this ambiguity

open weakens the argument that follows.

A second weakness stems from a misreading of classical anarchist theory.

Newman's argument is premised, in the first place, on his reading of

Bakunin and Kropotkin as wedded to the notion that the human subject is

naturally opposed to "power." He then notes that they also have recourse

to a characterization of this human subject as fatally prone to "a

'natural' desire for power." From this, he draws the conclusion that

classical anarchism is riven by a fundamental inconsistency, a "hidden

contradiction" (48-9). The unstated assumption which warrants this move

from premise to conclusion is that these two representations of the

human subject are mutually exclusive--that Bakunin and Kropotkin cannot

possibly intend both.

This assumption should raise the question: why not? A close reading of

Bakunin and Kropotkin would more strongly support a different

conclusion--that for both of these thinkers, the human subject itself,

and not their representation of the subject, is the site of what

Kropotkin calls a "fundamental contradiction" between "two sets of

diametrically opposed feelings which exist in man" (22). In other words,

as Dave Morland has explained, these thinkers' "conception of human

nature" is not statically unified, but dialectically "double-barreled":

human beings are possessed of equal potentials for "sociability" and

"egoism" (12). Since neither of these potentials is necessarily more

likely to be expressed than the other, ceteris paribus, neither

constitutes a species destiny: "history is autonomous" (21).

The (arguably mistaken) discovery of a "hidden contradiction" at the

core of anarchist discourse prompts Newman's fear that classical

anarchism is dangerously open to the potential for domination, which in

turn forms the rationale for the rest of his project. Errors propagate

through this system, as the logic of an undertheorized

"anti-essentialism" prompts him to ask the wrong questions and get the

wrong answers, or to ask the right questions without looking for answers

at all. If "humans have an essential desire for power," Newman argues,

"then how can one be sure that a revolution aimed at destroying power

will not turn into a revolution aimed at capturing power? How can one be

sure, in other words, that an anarchist revolution will be any different

from a Marxist vanguard revolution?" (49).

There are a number of problems with this question. First of all,

depending on which version of "power" Newman is referring to, the

question may depend on a false assumption. If "power" as an endless play

of mutual influence, action, and reaction is distinguished from

"domination," then neither Bakunin nor Kropotkin have any pretensions

about "destroying power" per se. Indeed, to a surprising extent, both

are aware of the ubiquity of "social power," which no revolution can

(nor should) abolish; both understand that it is a "natural" product of

human subjects, rather than an artificial imposition from outside; and

both distinguish it from force, coercion, or domination, while

acknowledging its potential to generate these effects, particularly when

it is allowed to accrete (Bakunin, God and the State 43n).

Apart from its problematic premise, however, Newman's question is also

needlessly framed as merely rhetorical or unanswerable, when it really

does admit of an answer in political practice. Anarchist practices,

conditioned by a theoretical emphasis on the immanence of ends within

means, are distinguished from those of "a Marxist vanguard revolution"

by the insistence that the immediate form of revolution (direct action,

direct democracy, egalitarian self-management, the leaderless group,

etc.) be its future content. Thus the anarcho-syndicalist Industrial

Workers of the World union named as their project "forming the structure

of the new society within the shell of the old" (Renshaw, frontispiece).

Newman, however, focuses more on theory than on practice. And this is

why he fails to ask the following question: if classical anarchist

theory is so wedded to this notion of the natural harmony of human

subjects in society, why is it so deeply preoccupied with questions of

action and organization? Why bother to organize, to intervene, unless

something is in need of this intervention, i.e. unless it is

disorganized? In fact, these theorists do not regard anarchy as

something merely spontaneous, natural, biological, given, but as

something that had to be evoked, elicited, created, made from the

materials of history and biology. What "every individual inherits at

birth," according to Bakunin, is "not ideas and innate sentiments, as

the idealists claim, but only the capacity to feel, to will, to think,

and to speak"--a set of "rudimentary faculties without any content";

this content must be supplied by the social milieu (Bakunin 240-41).

Nature is a set of potentials, not a telos; social construction is the

determining factor. In this sense, classical anarchist theory goes

beyond the binary opposition of essentialism/non-essentialism.

Rather than dwelling on the ostensible limitations of anarchism as

articulated by its most influential theorists, Newman turns his

attention to what he sees as the untapped potential of a relatively

marginal figure in anarchist history: Max Stirner, the fellow "Young

Hegelian" whom Marx so viciously assails in The German Ideology. In his

1845 Der Einzige und sein Eigentum (variously translated as "The Ego and

His Own" or "The Unique One and Its Property"), Stirner uses the stick

of nominalism to beat every philosophy built on abstract ideals or

categories, including not only the religious submission to God but also

the fetishization of "Man" in liberalism and communism: "no concept

expresses me, nothing that is designated as my essence exhausts me; they

are only names" (490). The self in Stirner is a subject to which all

"predicates" are merely properties, so that it cannot be said to have an

identity or essence (450)--leaving, as Newman sees it, 'a radical

opening which the individual can use to create his own subjectivity,"

unhampered by essentialisms.

This proto-Nietzschean insight excites Newman: "The importance of

Stirner's notion of becoming for politics, particularly

poststructuralist politics, is great indeed: he has shown that

resistance to power will never succeed if it remains trapped within

fixed, essential identities" (68). Ultimately, Stirner provides Newman

with a non-essentialist account of how the self, rather than

encountering a power which is imposed upon it, actually produces the

power to which it submits by binding itself to "fixed ideas" (ideologies

and essentialist identities) and annuls this power by dissolving these

abstract chains through analysis (Newman 64).

Newman does consider the charge, leveled at Stirner by numerous

anarchist critics, that Stirner's "unique one," abstracted from all

history, disembedded from every relationship, and detached from all

context, simply constitutes a new "essentialist identity" (and a

mystified one at that) but he does not really spell out why this

critique is mistaken (71). Not only does the Einzige closely resemble

Sartre's classless, genderless, cultureless, ahistorical cogito a little

too closely--it also bears some resemblance to the protagonist of

laissez-faire marketplace economics, the Rational Actor, whose infinite

desire and arbitrary caprice (i.e. "selfishness") are likewise purported

to be the very measure of freedom.

None of this prevents Newman from moving forward with his project--the

reconstruction of anarchist theory within a poststructuralist framework.

Four chapters provide a creative, suggestive, and relatively accessible

rereading of work by Foucault, Deleuze, Guattari, Derrida, and Lacan as

Newman searches for a "non-essentialist notion of the Outside."

Foucauldian genealogy and Deleuzo-Guattarian schizoanalysis extend

Stirner's insight into the abstract nature of the State, "whose

formidable omnipresence exists mostly in our minds and in our

subconscious desire to be dominated," by demonstrating that "the

individual represses himself," and that "we subordinate ourselves to

signifying regimes all around us" (79; 83; 100). Derridean

deconstruction adds a "strategy" for "undermining the metaphysical

authority of various political and philosophical discourses," releasing

action from its obligation to any "founding principle" or arché (130).

In the end, Newman stakes his money on Lacan as presenting the most

persuasive "non-essentialist figure of resistance" (111).

Here, I suspect, will lie one of the primary points of interest for

readers of poststructuralist theory, as Newman draws on Lacan's account

of how "the subject is constituted through its fundamental inability to

recognize itself in the symbolic order" to explain how this apparently

omnipresent and omnipotent order creates its own other--its own utopia,

actually: a non-originary origin or "nonplace" (ou-topos) of resistance,

blossoming in the heart of power itself (139). This nonplace is the

"leftover" which is continually and necessarily generated by the

operation of "the Law," which "produces its own transgression" (140;

144). In effect, Newman uses Lacan to clarify what Foucault seemed to

have left mysterious--the logic whereby power never appears without

resistance appearing as well.

But wait--isn't this a little too close to Bakunin's declaration, which

Newman cites as evidence of his "essentialism," that "there is something

in the nature of the state which provokes rebellion" (qtd. in Newman

48)? If Newman argues that these two antagonists, the "state" which

provokes and the "subject" who rebels, could not "exist without each

other" (48), how can he avoid concluding that this goes double for the

Lacanian struggle between the constitutive "Law" and the "transgression"

it produces? Moreover, one might ask what it has meant to discover this

"concept" or "figure" if what anarchism opposes is not "power" but

"domination." Was the quest in vain? Has all of this culminated in yet

another insurgent subject which just can't seem to do without the power

that dominates it?

These important questions remain unresolved. More important for

anarchist readers, however, is the question of what practical

consequences might ensue from the "postanarchism" which Newman

formulates in his final chapter (157). How can a politics, which

presupposes cooperation and joint action, found itself on Stirner's

notion that my unique ego has literally nothing in common with yours?

Newman calls attention to Stirner's proposal for a "union of egoists," a

merely voluntary and instrumental association between individuals, as

opposed to a "community" which one is "forced" to participate in (70),

but this amounts to a universalization of the instrumentalist logic of

capitalism: "For me," Stirner writes, "no one is a person to be

respected, not even the fellow-man, but solely, like other beings, an

object in which I take an interest or else do not, an interesting or

uninteresting object, a usable or unusable person" (414-15). Indeed, for

Stirner, "we have only one relation to each other, that of usableness,

of utility, of use"; everything else is ideology (394). While Newman

wants to read Stirner as "not necessarily against the notion of

community itself" (70), it is hard to avoid the conclusion that Stirner

himself flatly declares: "community . . . is impossible" (414). This is

precisely the hyper-individualism that placed Stirner outside the

mainstream of the anarchist movement, which remained committed to

community and collective practice, constituting itself as "social

anarchism" rather than mere individualism. "Needless to say," Newman

admits in a footnote, "some modern anarchists do not exactly embrace

this postmodern logic of uncertainty and dislocation" (175 n7).

In any case, it's a relief to find someone willing to think seriously

about the political outside of the confines of Marxism, rather than

continually fiddling around with Marxist texts in yet another attempt to

take Marx beyond Marx (as Antonio Negri has put it) or else completely

scrapping that urge to "change the world" in favor of some ironic or

nihilistic embrace of the world as it is (the Baudrillard solution).

Post-Marxist theorists have stripped away one key concept after another

(historical stages, centrality of class conflict, "progressive"

colonial/ecocidal teleology, productivism, materiality/ideality binary,

ideology, alienation, totality, etc.), peeling away the layers of the

onion, driving Marxism further and further in the direction of its old

repressed Other, anarchism--protesting all the while that "we are not

anarchists" (Hardt and Negri 350).

As refreshing as it is to step outside this endless Marxist monster

movie, with its perennial Frankfurtian pronunciations of death, periodic

Frankensteinian re-animations, and perpetual "spectres," I would argue

that anarchism has more to offer poststructuralism than Newman and May

seem to recognize, and that poststructuralism affords other and better

resources for the development of anarchist theory than their example

would imply. In fact, it could do much to redress the damage done to the

core ethos of social anarchism, as cataloged by Bookchin, by post-1960s

theoretical tendencies which regard all structure, organization, and

coherence as repressive. It offers a weapon for the Plainfield social

anarchists against the politically and intellectually sterile

primitivism of Eugene.

Foucault's demonstration of the poverty of the "repressive hypothesis"

and of the positive potential of self-structuring askesis could be used

to neutralize the influence of left-Freudian theories of liberation as

antisocial "de-repression" (Benello 63). The wisdom of Derrida's "there

is nothing outside the text"--as Zerzan is well aware (116-17)--could be

marshaled against the primitivist quest for a pure pre-social origin.

Even Lacanian psychoanalysis, with its narrative of the construction of

the self in and through the Symbolic, could reinforce Bookchin's

distinction between "individual autonomy" and "social freedom" (4).

From Bakunin to Lacan is overly eager to get from Bakunin to Lacan--a

perhaps too uncritical teleological trajectory--but at least it inquires

about the way from one point to the other, which is a siginificant

contribution in itself. As anarchist movements, roused from their long

slumber, attempt to orient themselves in a world of globalizing

capitalism, sporadic ethno-religious violence, and growing ecological

crisis, they will find themselves in need of more such contributions.

Works Cited

Bakunin, Mikhail. Bakunin on Anarchy: Selected Works by the

Activist-Founder of World Anarchism. Ed. and trans. Sam Dolgoff. New

York: Knopf, 1972.

---. God and the State. New York: Dover, 1970.

Benello, C. George. From The Ground Up: Essays on Grassroots and

Workplace Democracy. Boston: South End, 1992.

Bookchin, Murray. Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An

Unbridgeable Chasm. Edinburgh, Scotland: AK, 1995.

Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,

2000.

Kropotkin, Peter. Ethics: Origin and Development. Trans. Louis S.

Friedland and Joseph R. Piroshnikoff. Dorset: Prism, 1924.

May, Todd. The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism.

University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State UP, 1994.

Morland, Dave. "Anarchism, Human Nature and History: Lessons for the

Future." Twenty-First Century Anarchism. Ed. Jon Purkis and James Bowen.

London: Cassell, 1997. 8-23.

Renshaw, Patrick. The Wobblies: The Story of Syndicalism in the United

States. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1967.

Stirner, Max. The Ego and His Own. Trans. Steven T. Byington. New York:

Benj. R. Tucker, 1907. May 18, 2002.

<http://flag.blackened.net/daver/anarchism/stirner/theego0.html>

Zerzan, John. Elements of Refusal. Seattle: Left Bank, 1988.

---. Future Primitive and Other Essays. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia, 1994.

[1] See Zerzan's Elements of Refusal, particularly chapters 1-5, for the

full extent of his "anti-civilizational" project.