đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș brian-morris-anthropology-and-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:02:09. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anthropology and Anarchism Author: Brian Morris Date: 1998 Language: en Topics: AJODA, AJODA #45, John Zerzan, PĂ«tr Kropotkin, Murray Bookchin, Taoism, agriculture, anarcho-capitalism, anarcho-communism, anarcho-primitivism, anthropology, capitalism, democracy, gatherer-hunters, green anarchism, nature, religion, the state Source: Retrieved on 1st November 2018 from https://archive.org/details/AnarchyAJournalOfDesireArmedNoOne/page/n11 Notes: From Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed #45, Spring/Summer 1998, Vol. 16, No. 1, held in Spirit of Revolt Archive, Glasgow.
There is, in many ways an âelective affinityâ between anthropology and
anarchism. Although anthropologyâs subject matter has been diverse, and
its conspectus rather broadâas a study of human culture, historically it
has always had a rather specific focusâon the study of pre-state
societies. But it is quite misleading to portray the anthropology of the
past as being simply the study of so-called âprimitiveâ people or the
âexoticâ other, and thus largely engaged in a kind of âsalvageâ
operation of âdisappearingâ cultures. This is a rather biased and
inaccurate portrait of anthropology, for the discipline has a long
tradition of âanthropology at home,â and many important anthropological
studies have their location in India, China and Japan. It is thus
noteworthy that James Clifford and George Marcus (1986) in what many
have regarded as the founding text of literary or post-modern
anthropology, are not only rather dismissive of feminist anthropology,
but ignore entirely the ethnographic studies of non-âWesternâ
scholarsâSrinivas, Kenyatta, Fei and Aiyappan. But in an important sense
anthropology is the social science discipline that has put a focal
emphasis on those kinds of societies that have been seen as exemplars of
anarchy, a society without a state. Indeed, Evans- Pritchard, in his
classic study of The Nuer (1940), described their political system as
âordered anarchy.â Harold Barclayâs useful and perceptive little book
People without government (1992) is significantly subtitled âThe
Anthropology of Anarchism,â and Barclay makes the familiar distinction
between anarchy, which is an ordered society without government, and
anarchism, which is a political movement and tradition that became
articulated during the 19^(th) century.
Many anthropologists have had affinities with anarchism. One of the
earliest ethnographic texts was a book by Elie Reclus called Primitive
Folk. It was published in 1903, and carries the sub-title âStudies in
Corporative Ethnology.â It is based on information derived from the
writings of travellers and missionaries, and it has the evolutionary
flavour of books written at the end of the 19^(th) century, but it
contains lucid and sympathetic accounts of such people as the Apaches,
Nayars, Todas and Inuits. Reclus declares the moral and intellectual
equality of these cultures with that of âso-called civilised statesâ,
and it is of interest that Reclus used the now familiar term Inuit,
which means âpeople,â rather than the French term Eskimo. Elie Reclus
was the elder brother, and lifetime associate, of Elisée, the more
famous anarchist geographer.
Another French anthropologist with anarchist sympathies was Celestin
Bougle, who wrote not only a classical study of the Indian caste system
(1908)âwhich had a profound influence on Louis Dumontâbut also an
important study of Proudhon. Bougle was one of the first to affirm, then
(1911) controversially, that Proudhon was a sociological thinker of
standing. There was in fact a close relationship between the French
sociological tradition, focussed around Durkheim, and both socialism and
anarchism, even though Durkheim himself was antagonistic to the
anarchist stress on the individual. Durkheim was a kind of guild
socialist, but his nephew Marcel Mauss wrote a classical study on The
Gift (1925) which focussed on reciprocal or gift exchange among
pre-litcrate cultures. This small text is not only in some ways an
anarchist tract, but it is one of the foundation texts of anthropology,
one read by every budding anthropologist. British anthropologists have
less connection with anarchism, but it is worth noting that one of the
so-called âfathersâ of British anthropology, A.R. Radcliffe-Brown was an
anarchist in his early years.
Alfred Brown was a lad from Birmingham. He managed, with the help of his
brother, to get to Oxford University. There two influences were
important to him. One was the process philosopher Alfred Whitehead,
whose organismic theory had a deep influence on Radcliffe-Brown. The
other was Kropotkin, whose writings he imbibed. In his student days at
Oxford Radcliffe-Brown was known as âAnarchy Brown.â Alas! Oxford got to
him. He later became something of an intellectual aristocrat, and
changed his name to the hyphenated âA.R. Radcliffe-Brown.â But, as Tim
Ingold has written (1986), Radcliffe-Brownâs writings are permeated with
a sense that social life is a process, although like most Durkheimian
functionalists he tended to play down issues relating to conflict, power
and history.
Although anarchism has had a minimal influence on anthropologyâthough
many influential anthropologists can be described as radical liberals
and socialists (like Boas, Radin, and Diamond), anarchist writers have
drawn extensively on the work of anthropologists. Indeed there is a real
contrast between anarchists and Marxists with respect to anthropology,
for while anarchists have critically engaged themselves with
ethnographic studies, Marxist attitudes to anthropology have usually
been dismissive. In this respect Marxists have abandoned the broad
historical and ethnographic interests of Marx and Engels. The famous
study of Engels on The origin of the Family, Private Property and the
State (1884) is, of course, based almost entirely on Lewis Morganâs
anthropological study of Ancient Society (1877). If one examines the
writings of all the classical MarxistsâLenin, Trotsky, Gramsci,
Lukacsâthey are distinguished by a wholly Eurocentric perspective, and a
complete disregard for anthropology. The entry under âAnthropologyâ in A
Dictionary of Marxist Thought (Bottomore, 1983), significantly has
nothing to report between Marx and Engels in the 19^(th) century, and
the arrival on the scene of French Marxist anthropologists in the 1970s
(Godelier, Meillassoux). Equally amazing is that one Marxist text,
specifically on Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production (Hindness and Hirst,
1975), not only suggested that the âobjectsâ of theoretical discourses
did not existâand so rejected history as a worthwhile subject of study,
but completely bypassed anthropological knowledge. This is matched of
course by the dismissive attitude towards anarchism by Marxist
scholarsâPerry Anderson, Wallerstein and E.P. Thompson are examples.
Kropotkin is well known. But being a geographer as well as an anarchist,
and having travelled widely in Asia, Kropotkin had wide ethnographic
interests. This is most clearly expressed in his classic text Mutual Aid
published in 1903. In this book Kropotkin attempted to show that both
organic and social life was not an arena where laissez-faire competition
and conflict and the âsurvival of the fittestâ was the only norm, but
rather these domains were characterized by âmutualityâ and âsymbiosis.â
It was the ecological dimension of Darwinâs thought, expressed in the
last chapter of On the Origin ofSpecies, that was crucial for Kropotkin;
co-operation not struggle was the important factor in the evolutionary
process. This is exemplified by the ubiquitous lichen, one of the most
basic forms of life and found practically everywhere. Kropotkinâs book
gives lengthy accounts of mutual aid not only among hunter-gatherers and
such people as the Buryat and Kabyle (now well-known through Bourdieuâs
writings), but also in the medieval city and in contemporary European
societies. In a A.S.A. monograph on socialism (edited by Chris Hann,
1993) two articles specifically examine anarchy among contemporary
people. Alan Barnard looks at the issues of âprimitive communismâ and
âmutual aidâ among the Kalahari hunter-gatherers, while Joanna Overing
discusses âanarchy and collectivismâ among the horticultural Piaroa of
Venezuela. Barnardâs essay has the sub-title âKropotkin visits the
Bushmen,â indicating that anarchism is still a live issue among some
anthropologists.
Kropotkin was concerned to examine the âcreative geniusâ of people
living at what he described as the âclan periodâ of human histoiy, and
the development of institutions of mutual aid. But this did not entail
the repudiation of individual self-assertion, and, unlike many
contemporary anthropologists, Kropotkin made a distinction between
individuality and self-affirmation, and individualism.
Murray Bookchin is a controversial figure. His advocacy of citizenâs
councils and municipal self management, his emphasis on the city as a
potential ecological community, and his strident critiques of the
misanthropy and eco-mysticism of the deep ecologists are perhaps well
known, and the centre of many debatesâmuch of it acrimonious. But
Bookchinâs process-oriented dialectical approach and his sense of
historyâalive to the achievements of the human spiritâinevitably led
Bookchin to draw on anthropological studies. The main influences on his
work were Paul Radin and Dorothy Lee, both sensitive scholars of native
American culture. In his The Ecology of Freedom (1982), Bookchin devotes
a chapter to what he describes as âorganic society,â emphasizing the
important features of early human tribal-society: a primordial equality
and the absence of coercive and domineering values, a feeling of unity
between the individual and the kin community, a sense of communal
property and an emphasis on mutual aid and usufruct rights, and a
relationship with the natural world which is one of reciprocal harmony
rather than of domination. But Bookchin is concerned that we draw
lessons from the past, and learn from the culture of pre-literate
people, rather than romanticising the life of hunter-gatherers. Still
less, that we should try to emulate them.
Pierre Clastres was both an anarchist and an anthropologist. His minor
classic, on the Indian communities of South Americaâspecifically the
forest Guayaki (Ache)âis significantly titled Society Against the State
(1977). Like Tom Paine and the early anarchists, Clastres makes a clear
distinction between society, as a pattern of social relations, and the
state, and argues that the essence of what he describes as âarchaicâ
societiesâwhether hunter-gatherers or horticultural (neolithic)
peoplesâis that effective means are institutionalized to prevent power
being separated from social life. He bewails the fact that western
political philosophy is unable to see power except in terms of
âhierarchized and authoritarian relations of command and obedience,â
(p.9) and thus equates power with coercive power. Reviewing the
ethnographic literature of the people of South Americaâapart from the
Inca StateâClastres argues that they were distinguished by their âsense
of democracy and taste for equality,â and that even local chiefs lacked
coercive power. What constituted the basic fabric of archaic society,
according to Clastres, was exchange, coercive power, in essence, being a
negation of reciprocity. He contends that the aggressiveness of tribal
communities has been grossly exaggerated, and that a subsistence economy
did not imply an endless struggle against starvation, for in normal
circumstances there was an abundance and variety of things to eat. Such
communities were essentially egalitarian, and people had a high degree
of control over their own lives and work activities. But the decisive
âbreakâ for Clastres, between âarchaicâ and âhistoricalâ societies was
not the neolithic revolution and the advent of agriculture, but the
âpolitical revolutionâ involving the intensification of agriculture and
the emergence of the state.
The key points of Clastresâ analysis have recently been affirmed by John
Gledhill (1994, pp.13â15). It provides a valuable critique of western
political theory which identifies power with coercive authority; and it
suggests looking at history less in terms of typologies than as a
process in which human activities have maintained their own autonomy and
resisted the centralizing intrusions and exploitation inherent in the
state.
While for Clastres and Bookchin political domination and hierarchy begin
with the intensification of agriculture, and the rise of the state, for
John Zerzan the domestication of plants and animals heralds the demise
of an era when humans lived an authentic, free life. Agriculture, per
se, is a form of alienation; it implies a loss of contact with the world
of nature and a controlling mentality. The advent of agriculture thus
entails the âend of innocenceâ and the demise of the âgolden ageâ as
humans left the âGarden of Eden,â though Eden is identified not with a
garden but with hunter-gathering existence. Given this advocacy of
âprimitivism,â it is hardly surprising that Zerzan (1988, 1994) draws on
anthropological data to validate his claims, and to portray
hunter-gatherers as egalitarian, authentic, and as the âmost successful
and enduring adaptation ever achieved by humankindâ (1988, p.66). Even
symbolic culture and the shamanism associated with hunter-gatherers is
seen by Zerzan as implying an orientation to manipulate and control
nature or other humans. Zerzan presents an apocalyptic, even a gnostic
vision. Our hunter-gatherer past is described as an idyllic era of
virtue and authentic living. The last eight thousand years or so of
human historyâafter the fall (agriculture)âis seen as one of tyranny,
hierarchical control, mechanized routine devoid of any spontaneity, and
as involving the anesthetization of the senses. All those products of
the human creative imaginationâfarming, art, philosophy, technology,
science, urban living, symbolic cultureâare viewed negatively by
Zerzanâin a monolithic sense. The future we are told is âprimitive.â How
this is to be achieved in a world that presently sustains almost six
billion people (for evidence suggests that the hunter-gather lifestyle
is only able to support 1 or 2 people per sq. mile), or whether the
âfuture primitiveâ actually entails, in gnostic fashion, a return not to
the godhead, but to hunter-gathering subsistence, Zerzan does not tell
us. While radical ecologists glorify the golden age of peasant
agriculture, Zerzan follows the likes of Van Der Post in extolling
hunter-gatherer existenceâwith a selective culling of the
anthropological literature. Whether such âillusory images of Green
primitivismâ are, in themselves, symptomatic of the estrangement of
affluent urban dwellers and intellectuals, from the natural (and human)
worldâas both Bookchin (1995) and Ray Ellen (1986) suggestâI will leave
others to judge.
The term anarchy comes from the Greek, and essentially means âno ruler.â
Anarchists are people who reject all forms of government or coercive
authority, all forms of hierarchy and domination. They are therefore
opposed to what the Mexican anarchist Flores Magon called the âsombre
trinityââstate, capital and the church. Anarchists are thus opposed to
both capitalism and to the state, as well as to all forms of religious
authority. But anarchists also seek to establish or bring about by
varying means, a condition of anarchy, that is, a decentralized society
without coercive institutions, a society organized through a federation
of voluntary associations. Contemporary right-wing âlibertarians,â like
Milton Friedman, Rothbard and Ayn Rand, who are often described as
âanarcho-capitalists,â and who fervently defend capitalism, are not in
any real sense anarchists.
In an important sense anarchists support the rallying cry of the French
revolution: liberty, equality and fraternityâand strongly believe that
these values are inter-dependent. As Bakunin remarked: âFreedom without
socialism is privilege and injustice; and socialism without freedom is
slavery and brutality.â Needless to say anarchists have always been
critical of soviet communism, and the most powerful and penetrating
critiques of Marx, Marxist-Leninism, and the Soviet regime have come
from anarchists: people like Berkmanl Goldman, and Maximoff. The
latterâs work was significantly entitled: The Guillotine at Work (1940).
Maximoff saw the politics of Lenin and Trotsky as similar to that of the
Jacobins in the French revolution, and equally reactionary.
With the collapse of the Soviet regime, Marxists are now in a state of
intellectual disarray, and are floundering around looking for a safe
political anchorage. They seem to gravitate either towards Hayek or
towards Keynes; whichever way their socialism gets lost in the process.
Conservative writers like Roger Scruton take great pleasure in berating
Marxists for having closed their eyes to the realities of the Soviet
regime: they themselves, however, have a myopia when it comes to
capitalism. The poverty, famine, sickening social inequalities,
political repression and ecological degradation that is generated under
capitalism is always underplayed by apologists like Scruton and
Fukuyama. They see these as simply âproblemsâ that need to be
overcomeânot as intrinsically related to capitalism itself.
Anarchism can be looked at in two ways.
On the one hand it can be seen as a kind of âriver,â as Peter Marshall
describes it in his excellent history of anarchism. It can thus be seen
as a âlibertarian impulseâ or as an âanarchist sensibilityâ that has
existed throughout human history: an impulse that has expressed itself
in various waysâin the writings of Lao Tzu and the Taoists, in classical
Greek thought, in the mutuality of kin-based societies, in the ethos of
various religious sects, in such agrarian movements as the Diggers in
England and the Zapatistas of Mexico, in the collectives that sprang up
during the Spanish civil war, and currentlyâin the ideas expressed in
the ecology and feminist movements. Anarchist tendencies seem to have
expressed themselves in all religious movements, even in Islam. One
Islamic sect, the Najadat, believed that âpower belongs only to god.â
They therefore felt that they did not really need an imam or caliph, but
could organize themselves mutually to ensure justice. Many years ago I
wrote an article on Lao Tzu, suggesting that the famous Tao Te Ching
(âThe Way and its Power,â as Waley translates it) should not be seen as
a mystical religious tract (as it is normally understood), but rather as
a political treatise. It is, in fact, the first anarchist tract. For the
underlying philosophy of the Tao Te Ching is fundamentally anarchist, as
Rudolf Rocker long ago noted. On the other hand anarchism may be seen as
a historical movement and political theory that had its beginnings at
the end of the 18^(th) century. It was expressed in the writings of
William Godwin, who wrote the classic anarchist text An Enquiry
Concerning Political Justice (1798), as well as in the actions of the
sans-culottes and the enrages during the French revolution, and by
radicals like Thomas Spence and William Blake in Britain. The term
âanarchistâ was first used during the French revolution as a term of
abuse in describing the sans-culottesââwithout breechesââthe working
people of France who during the revolution advocated the abolition of
government.
Anarchism, as a social movement, developed during the 19^(th) century.
Its basic social philosophy was formulated by the Russian revolutionary
Michael Bakunin. It was the outcome of his clashes with Karl Marx and
his followersâwho advocated a statist road to socialismâduring meetings
of the International Working Menâs Association in the 1860s. In its
classical form, therefore, as it was expressed by Kropotkin, Goldman,
Reclus and Malatesta, anarchism was a significant part of the socialist
movement in the years before the first World War, but its socialism was
libertarian not Marxist. The tendency of writers like David Pepper
(1996) to create a dichotomy between socialism and anarchism is, I
think, both conceptually and historically misleading.
Of all political philosophies anarchism has had perhaps the worst press.
It has been ignored, maligned, ridiculed, abused, misunderstood, and
misrepresented by writers from all sides of the political
spectrumâMarxists, liberals, democrats and conservatives. Theodore
Roosevelt, the American president, described anarchism as a âcrime
against the whole human raceââand it has been variously judged as
destructive, violent and nihilistic. A number of criticisms have been
lodged against anarchism, and I will deal briefly with eight.
rosy a picture of human nature. It is said that, like Rousseau, they
have a romantic view of human nature which they see as essentially good
and peace-loving. But of course real humans are not like this; they are
cruel and aggressive and selfish, and so anarchy is just a pipe dream.
It is an unrealistic vision of a past golden age that never really
existed. This being so, some form of coercive authority is always
necessary. The truth is that anarchists do not follow Rousseau. In fact,
Bakunin was scathing in his criticisms of the 18^(th) century
philosopher. Most anarchists tend to think humans have both good and bad
tendencies. If they did think humans all goodness and light, would they
mind being ruled? It is because they have a realistic rather than a
romantic view of human nature, that they oppose all forms of coercive
authority. In essence, anarchists oppose all power which the French
describe as âpuissanceâââpower overâ (rather than âpouvoir,â the power
to do something), and believeâlike Lord Actonâthat power corrupts, and
absolute power corrupts absolutely. As Paul Goodman wrote: â...the issue
is not whether people are âgood enoughâ for a particular type of
society; rather it is a matter of developing the kind of social
institutions that are most conducive to expanding the potentialities we
have for intelligence, grace, sociability and freedom.â
in fact, how people often use the term. But anarchy, as understood by
most anarchists, means the exact opposite of this. It means a society
based on order. Anarchy means not chaos, or a lack of organisation, but
a society based on the autonomy of the individual, on co-operation, one
without rulers or coercive authority. As Proudhon put it: liberty is the
mother of order. But equally anarchists do not denounce chaos, for they
see chaos and disorder as having inherent potentialityâas Bakunin put
it: to destroy is a creative act.
Anarchism, it is said, is all about terrorist bombs and violence. And
there is a book currently in the bookshops entitled The Anarchistsâ
Cookbook all about how to make bombs and dynamite. But as Alexander
Berkman wrote: the resort to violence against oppression or to obtain
certain political objectives has been practiced throughout human
history. Acts of violence have been committed by the followers of every
political and religious creed: nationalists, liberals, socialists,
feminists, republicans, monarchists, Buddhists, Muslims, Christians,
democrats, conservatives, fascists...and every government is based on
organized violence. Anarchists who have resorted to violence are no
worse than anybody else. But most anarchists have been against violence
and terrorism, and there has always been a strong link between anarchism
and pacifism. Yet anarchists go one step further: they challenge the
violence that most people do not recognize and which is often of the
worst possible kind; this is lawful violence.
theoretical blockheads, of being anti-intellectual, or of making a cult
of mindless action. But as a perusal of the anarchist movement will
indicate, many anarchists or people with anarchist sympathies have been
among the finest intellects of their generations, truly creative people.
Moreover, anarchists have produced many seminal texts outlining their
own philosophy and their own social doctrines. These are generally free
of the jargon and the pretension that passes as scholarship amongst many
liberal scholars, Marxists and post-modernists.
being apolitical, and a doctrine of inaction. Anarchists, according to
the ex-doyen of the Green Party in Britain, Jonathan Porritt, do nothing
but contemplate their navels. Because they do not engage in party
politics, he even suggests that anarchists do not live in the âreal
world.â All the essential themes of the Green Party manifestoâthe call
for a society that is decentralized, equitable, ecological,
co-operative, with flexible institutionsâare of course simply an
unacknowledged appropriation of what anarchists like Kropotkin had long
ago advocatedâbut with Porritt this vision is simply hitched to party
politics. As a media figure Porritt completely misunderstands what
anarchismâand a decentralized societyâis all about. Anarchism is not
non-political. Nor does it advocate a retreat into prayer,
self-indulgence or meditation, whether or not one contemplates oneâs
navel or chants mantras. It is simply hostile to parliamentary or party
politics. The only democracy it thinks valid, is participatory
democracy, and considers putting an X on a piece of paper every four or
five years is a sham. It serves only to give ideological justification
to power holders in a society that is fundamentally hierarchical and
undemocratic. Anarchists are of many kinds. They have therefore
suggested various ways of challenging and transforming the present
system of violence and inequalityâthrough communes, passive resistance,
syndicalism, municipal democracy, insurrection, direct action and
education. One of the reasons why some anarchists have put a lot of
emphasis on publishing propaganda and education, is that they have
always eschewed party organization as well as violence. Anarchists have
always been critical of the notion of a vanguard party, seeing it as
inevitably leading to some form of despotism. And with regard to both
the French and Russian revolutions history has proved their premonitions
correct.
utopian and romantic, a peasant or petty-bourgeois ideology, or an
expression of millennial dreams. Concrete historical studies by John
Hart on anarchism and the Mexican working class (1978) and by Jerome
Mintz on the anarchists of Casas Viejas in Spain (1982) have more than
adequately refuted some of the distortions about anarchism. The
anarchist movement has not been confined to peasants: it has flourished
among urban workers where anarcho- syndicalism developed. Nor is it
utopian or millennial. Anarchists have established real collectives, and
have always been critical of religion. Nobody among the early anarchists
expected some immediate or cataclysmic change to occur through
âpropaganda by deedâ or the âgeneral strikeââas the writings of Reclus
and Berkman attest. They realised it would be a long haul.
politics: that it sees the state as the fount of all evil, ignoring
other aspects of social and economic life. This is a misrepresentation
of anarchism. It partly derives from the way anarchism has been defined,
and partly because Marxist historians have tried to exclude anarchism
from the broader socialist movement. But when one examines the writings
of classical anarchists like Kropotkin, Goldman, Malatesta and Tolstoy,
as well as the character of anarchist movements in such places as Italy,
Mexico, Spain and France, it is clearly evident that it has never had
this limited vision. It has always challenged all forms of authority and
exploitation, and has been equally critical of capitalism and religion
as it has of the state. Most anarchists were feminists, and many spoke
out against racism, as well as defending the freedom of children. A
cultural and ecological critique of capitalism has always been an
important dimension of anarchist writings. This is why the writings of
Tolstoy, Reclus and Kropotkin still have contemporary relevance.
never work. The market socialist David Miller expresses this view very
well in his book on Anarchism (1984). His attitude to anarchism is one
of heads I win, tails you lose. He admits that communities based on
anarcho-communist principles have existed, and âgiven a chanceâ have had
some degree of âunexpected success.â But due to lack of popular support
and state intervention and repression they have, he writes, always been
âfailures.â On the other hand he also argues that societies could not
exist anyway without some form of centralized government. Miller seems
oblivious to the fact that what Stanley Diamond called âkin-communitiesâ
have long existed within and often in opposition to state systems, and
that trading networks have existed throughout history, even among
hunter-gatherers, without any state control. The state, in any case, is
a recent historical phenomena, and in its modern nation-state form has
only existed for a few hundred years. Human communities have long
existed without central or coercive authority. Whether a complex
technological society is possible without centralized authority is not a
question easily answered; neither is it one that can be lightly
dismissed. Many anarchists believe that such a society is possible,
though technology will have to be on a âhuman scale.â Complex systems
exist in nature without there being any controlling mechanism. Indeed,
many global theorists nowadays are beginning to contemplate libertarian
social vistas that become possible in an age of computer technology.
Needless to say, if Miller had applied the same criteria by which he so
adversely adjudges anarchismâdistributive justice and social
well-beingâto capitalism and state âcommunismâ then perhaps he would
have declared both these systems unpractical and unrealistic too? But at
least Miller wants to rescue anarchism from the dustbin of historyâto
help us to curb abuses of power, and to keep alive the possibilities of
free social relationships.
Society, we are told, by such authorities as Friedrich Hayek, Margaret
Thatcher, and Marilyn Strathern, either does not exist, or it is a
âconfused categoryâ that ought to be excised from theoretical discourse.
The word derives, of course, from the Latin, Societas, which in turn
derives from Socius, meaning a companion, a friend, a relationship
between people, a shared activity. Anarchists have thus always drawn a
clear distinction between society, in this sense, and the state: between
what the Jewish existentialist scholar Martin Buber called the
âpoliticalâ and the âsocialâ principles. Buber was a close friend of the
anarchist Gustav Landauer, and what Landauer basically arguedâlong
before Foucaultâwas that the state could not be destroyed by revolution:
it could only be underminedâby developing other kinds of relationships,
by actualizing social patterns and forms of organization that involved
mutuality and free co-operation. Such a social domain is always in a
sense present, imminent in contemporary society, co-existing with the
state. For Landauer, as for Colin Ward, anarchy, therefore, is not
something that only existed long ago before the rise of the state, or
exists now only among people like the Nharo or Piaroa living at the
margins of capitalism. Nor is it simply a speculative vision of some
future society: but rather, anarchy is a form of social life which
organizes itself without the resort to coercive authority. It is always
in existenceâalbeit often buried and unrecognized beneath the weight of
capitalism and the state. It is like âa seed beneath the snow,â as Colin
Ward (1973) graphically puts it. Anarchy, then, is simply the idea, to
stay with the same writer, âthat it is possible and desirable for
society to organize itself without government.â
Barclay, H. People without Government (London: Kahn & Averill, 1982).
Bookchin, M. The Ecology of Freedom (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books, 1982).
Re-enchanting Humanity (London: Cassell, 1995).
Bottomore, T. (Ed) A Dictionary ofMarxist Thought (Oxford: Blackwell,
1983).
Clastres, P. Society Against the. State (Oxford: Blackwell, 1977).
Clifford, J. and G. Marcus, (Ed) Writing Culture (Berkeley: Univ.
California Press, 1986).
Ellen, R.F. âWhat Black Elk Left Unsaid,â Anthrop. Today 216; pp.8â12,
1986.
Gledhill, J. Power and its Disguises (London: Pluto, 1994).
Hart, 3 .M. Anarchism and the Mexican Working Class 1860â1931 (Austin:
Univ of Texas, 1978).
Hann, C.M. Socialism (London: Routledge, 1993).
Hindness, B. And Hirst, P.Q. Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1975).
Ingold, T. Evolution and Social Life (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press,
1986).
Miller, D. Anarchism (London: Pent, 1984).
Mintz, J.R. The Anarchists of Casas Viejas (Chicago: Univ. Chicago
Press, 1982).
Pepper, D. Modem Environmentalism (London: Routledge, 1996).
Ward, C. Anarchy in Action (London: Allen & Unwin, 1973).
Zerzan, J. Elements of Refusal (Seattle: Left Bank Books, 1988). Future
Primitive and Other Essays (Brooklyn: Autonomedia/Columbia: Anarchy,
1994).