💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › rob-sparrow-anarchist-politics-direct-action.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:44:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchist Politics & Direct Action
Author: Rob Sparrow
Date: 1997
Language: en
Topics: direct action, media, reformism, the State
Source: Retrieved on September 19, 2009 from http://www.spunk.org/texts/intro/sp001641.html

Rob Sparrow

Anarchist Politics & Direct Action

This paper discusses Direct Action — the proper method of anarchist

activist action. In it I try to consider some theoretical issues that we

don’t usually get a chance to discuss in the midst of political

campaigns. Some of the issues raised will be, the role of anarchists in

other political movements, the difference between direct action and

symbolic action, the various traditional types of direct action and the

proper attitude of activists towards the police and the media.

“Direct Action” is the distinctive contribution of anarchists in the

realm of political method. While reformists advocate the ballot box,

liberals have their lobbying and their letter writing, bureaucrats have

their work through “the proper channels” and socialists have their

vanguard parties, we anarchists have direct action. Political tendencies

other than anarchism may adopt direct action as a method but its

historical origins and its most vigorous proponents are anarchist.

Because direct action is a political method, before we can properly

understand it and its place in anarchist practice we must first examine

the nature of anarchist political activity.

Ideally, anarchist political activity promotes anarchism and attempts to

create anarchy. It seeks to establish a society without

capitalism,patriarchy or State, where people govern themselves

democratically without domination or hierarchy. As I have argued

elsewhere, this is an activity which is inescapably revolutionary in

nature and which is best carried out collectively in an organisation

dedicated to that purpose. While anarchists remain without a political

organisation of their own, the main avenue for promoting anarchism is to

participate in, contribute to and provide leadership in other political

movements. Our objective in participating in other political movements

and campaigns should be to show that anarchist methods and ways of

organising work. The best advertisement for anarchism is the

intelligence of the contributions of our activists and the success of

our methods. Anarchists should strive to provide living examples of

anarchy in action. As we will see, direct action is one of the best

possible ways of doing this.

Two dangers in Anarchist Political Practice

Before I go on, I want to highlight here two problems which may occur

with anarchist political activity which both stem from a tendency to be

utopian in our political demands. Anarchists are often utopian in their

rejection of any political activity oriented towards the state and in

their failure to establish a realistic connection between their ends and

their means. This sort of utopianism is not a virtue but instead

contributes to anarchism’s continuing political irrelevance to the

majority of Australians.

Anarchism and the State.

In a capitalist economy the activities of “private enterprise” are

rigorously excluded from public scrutiny and control. We have no input

into the decisions about production and investment which determine the

basic conditions of our existence and which are made in corporate board

rooms. In many cases, if we don’t like what we see happening around us,

the only option open to us is to try to change government policy. Thus

most forms of politics today are oriented towards the state. Most

obviously, electoral politics seeks to determine the identity of those

few individuals who supposedly “control” the state. Most forms of

“political protest” also hope to induce, or to force, the state to take

some action to address the protesters’ concerns. Yet anarchism is

largely defined by its rejection of the state as a mode of organising to

meet social needs and anarchists have traditionally — and rightly — been

extremely suspicious of any suggestion that we can succeed in using the

state to serve our ends. It may therefore be tempting for anarchists to

proffer “social revolution” as the solution to all problems.

Anarchists may argue that the problems that people face are the results

of an insane social and economic order and that only a revolution and

consequent creation of anarchy will solve them. But people have problems

and face difficulties here and now which need to be addressed and they

cannot wait for the revolution to solve them. Thus in rejecting attempts

to force the state to address our needs or serve our political ends we

must offer realistic alternative methods of achieving our goals, if we

are to be relevant to the struggles of people today. Sometimes this may

be possible. Sometimes we can organise together, without relying on the

state, to address and solve our problems here and now. As we shall see

below, this is the essence of “direct action”.

Often, however, it won’t be possible to provide genuine solutions to

people’s problems, within the existing order, without recourse to the

state. Whether we like it or not certain social needs are, in current

circumstances, only going to be addressed by the state. Access to

medical resources, secure housing, educational qualifications or income

support are for most people only going to be available as the result of

state action. Relations between the sexes are also another area where

the state seems to be the only plausible existing instrument of social

policy. Domestic violence protection orders and state funded refuges may

not be much of a solution to the problems created by violent or abusive

partners but for some women they are all there is. For many women they

are a necessary step on the road to escaping a cycle of abuse. The

society wide education campaigns which are necessary to challenge sexist

attitudes likewise can only be carried out with state support.

Until anarchists constitute a sizeable portion of the community and are

capable of providing these services — or alternatives — themselves,

activists concerned about these issues will be justified in turning to

the state for help in addressing them.

Furthermore, legislation by the state can represent a real political

victory. This may be because the passing of legislation acknowledges and

gives weight to changes which have already occurred in the political

consciousness of society at large or it may be because the legislation

actually makes a real difference to the living conditions of ordinary

people. Legislation guaranteeing a minimum wage, public health-care,

health and safety standards at work or a decent standard of living for

those excluded from work represents a genuine political victory for the

majority over the ruling class. Not only do such state provided services

make a vast difference in the quality of life of those who otherwise

would have no or little access to them but they also dramatically

increase the possibility of political action. The less time people have

to spend struggling to meet their basic needs, the more time they have

to criticise and challenge the existing order.

The traditional anarchist hostility towards the state then should be

tempered by the recognition that, while it continues to exist, it is an

important site of class struggle. If we reject attempts to exert

pressure on the state we may render ourselves irrelevant to the real

needs of large elements in society. Calling only for revolution is not

going to interest anyone who needs real change now. Anarchists must

provide workable solutions for people here and now. Sometimes this will

involve recourse to the state.

Anarchism and Ends and Means.

One of anarchism’s historical strengths has been its insistence on the

connection between ends and means. Anarchists have insisted that

libertarian outcomes will not result from authoritarian means and, more

generally, have been sensitive towards the ways in which compromises

made in the realm of political methods may corrupt us or infect our

goals. Sometimes, however, this has lead to an over simplistic equation

betweens our means and our ends. Anarchists often fail to address

properly the political question of how our methods relate to our goals.

An example of this is the pacifist claim “If everyone refused to fight

there would be no wars” Now this is clearly true, in fact tautologically

so. But pacifism does not follow from this truism. It does not follow

that the best way to prevent wars is to make an individual commitment to

refuse to fight in them. The connection between our actions and the goal

of peaceful world is a political one. It is political because it

involves the workings of the whole set of power and economic relations

which structure our social and personal decision making. For our

activities to have their intended effect they must be taken up by others

and whether or not this will take place will depend on a whole set of

political and economic factors. It is not at all clear that our refusing

to fight will cause sufficient numbers of others to do so and thus make

war impossible (in fact, this just seems wildly implausible). The best

way to prevent wars may be to address the social systems and the

injustices which cause them. It may even involve fighting.

More generally then, for our means to be suitable to the ends we seek we

must be able to tell a realistic story about exactly how our activities

will bring our ends about. This story will have to take account of the

economic and political realities which affect our lives. It is often not

realistic to believe that everyone else around us will immediately

follow our example.

The best forms of anarchist politics avoid these two forms of dangerous

utopianism and offer people genuine hope and occasional success in their

struggle for a better world. Direct action is a crucial component of

such a politics.

Direct Action.

The distinguishing feature of direct action is that it aims to achieve

our goals through our own activity rather than through the actions of

others. Direct action seeks to exert power directly over affairs and

situations which concern us. Thus it is about people taking power for

themselves. In this it is distinguished from most other forms of

political action such as voting, lobbying, attempting to exert political

pressure though industrial action or through the media. All of these

activities aim to get others to achieve our goals for us. Such forms of

actions operate on a tacit acceptance of our own powerlessness. They

concede that we ourselves have neither the right nor the power to affect

change. Such forms of action are therefore implicitly conservative. They

concede the authority of existing institutions and work to prevent us

from acting ourselves to change the status quo.

Direct action repudiates such acceptance of the existing order and

suggests that we have both the right and the power to change the world.

It demonstrates this by doing it. Examples of direct action include

blockades, pickets, sabotage, squatting, tree spiking, lockouts,

occupations, rolling strikes, slow downs, the revolutionary general

strike. In the community it involves, amongst other things, establishing

our own organisations such as food co-ops and community access radio and

tv to provide for our social needs, blocking the freeway developments

which divide and poison our communities and taking and squatting the

houses that we need to live in. In the forests, direct action interposes

our bodies, our will and our ingenuity between wilderness and those who

would destroy it and acts against the profits of the organisations which

direct the exploitation of nature and against those organisations

themselves. In industry and in the workplace direct action aims either

to extend workers control or to directly attack the profits of the

employers. Sabotage and “go slows” are time-honoured and popular

techniques to deny employers the profits from their exploitation of

their wage-slaves. Rolling and “wildcat” strikes are forms of open

industrial struggle which strike directly at the profits of the

employers. However, industrial action which is undertaken merely as a

tactic as part of negotiations to win wage or other concessions from an

employer is not an example of direct action.

As the examples of direct action in the community above suggest, there

is more to direct action than responding to injustices or threats by the

state. Direct action is not only a method of protest but also a way of

“building the future now”. Any situation where people organise to extend

control over their own circumstances without recourse to capital or

state constitutes direct action. “Doing it ourselves” is the essence of

direct action and it does not matter whether what we are doing is

resisting injustice or attempting to create a better world now by

organising to meet our own social needs. Direct action of this sort,

because it is self-directed rather than a response to the activities of

capital or state, offers far more opportunities for continuing action

and also for success. We can define our own goals and achieve them

through our own efforts.

One of the most important aspects of direct action is the organisation

involved in order for it to be successful. By organising to achieve our

goals ourselves we learn valuable skills and discover that organisation

without hierarchy is possible. Where it succeeds, direct action shows

that people can control their own lives — in effect, that anarchy is

possible. We can see here that direct action and anarchist organisation

are in fact two sides of the same coin. When we demonstrate the success

of one we demonstrate the reality of the other.

Two Important Distinctions

Direct action must be distinguished from symbolic actions. Direct action

is bolting a gate rather than tying a yellow ribbon around it. Its

purpose is to exercise power and control over our own lives rather than

merely portray the semblance of it. This distinguishes it from many

forms of action, for example “banner drops” such as those often engaged

in by Greenpeace, that look militant but, in my opinion, aren’t. These

actions do not directly attack the injustices they highlight, but

instead seek to influence the public and politicians through the media.

Any action directed primarily towards the media concedes that others,

rather than ourselves, have the power to change things.

Direct action must also be distinguished from moral action. It is not

moral protest. By moral protest I mean protest which is justified by

reference to the moral relation to some institution or injustice that it

demonstrates. Moral protest usually takes the form of a boycott of a

product or refusal to participate in some institution. Such actions seek

to avoid our complicity in the evils for which existing institutions are

responsible. No doubt this is morally admirable. But unless these

actions themselves have some perceivable effect on the institutions

which they target, they do not constitute direct action. Direct action

must have some immediate affect to demonstrate that we can exert power.

It should not rely entirely on others taking up our example. Our own

action should have such an affect that we can point it out to others as

an example of how they can change — and not just protest — those things

which concern them. Boycotts, for instance, therefore are not examples

of direct action. If only those who organise a boycott participate in

it, it will almost invariably be ineffective.

Of course, these distinctions are overdrawn. Any action at all involves

some exercise of power. By acting at all, in any way, we overcome our

passivity and deny that we are helpless to affect change. Any action

short of revolution is to some extent both moral and symbolic. Capital,

patriarchy and state have the power to undo all our efforts short of

revolution. Any form of protest can be effectively prevented if the

state is willing to employ the full range of its resources for

authoritarian repression and control. The only form of “direct action”

which cannot be contained by the state is popular revolution. This is

the ultimate direct action that anarchists should aim for, when all

people organise to destroy the existing order and cooperate to run

society without capitalism, patriarchy or authority.

Implications.

So given that any action will be less than ideal, how should we assess

potential direct actions? I would suggest that possible direct actions

should be assessed both as examples of direct action as described here

and against the broader criteria for anarchist actions set out above.

That is, of any action we should ask:

it?

will it build the anarchist movement?

Some further questions we can ask ourselves to help determine the

answers to these are as follows. Firstly, will it draw others in? Is it

the sort of activity which encourages other people to become interested

and involved? Actions which necessitate a high degree of detailed

organisation or secrecy are unlikely to score highly against this

criterion. Will it succeed in achieving its defined objectives? For

instance, will a blockade actually stop work on a site for some period?

Successful actions are the best advertisement for anarchist methods. Are

the politics of the action obvious or at least clearly conveyed to those

who witness it? If the targets of our actions relate only obliquely to

the issue which they are intended to address or the goals of our

activities unclear to those not “in the know” then we are unlikely to

convince others of the relevancy of anarchism. For this reason we must

always be conscious of the messages which our activities convey to other

people and try to ensure that this is the most appropriate possible.

What consequences will result from the action for those involved in it?

Actions which involve a high risk of police beating or of arrest with

consequent heavy fines or imprisonment may reduce the willingness or

capacity of those affected to engage in further political activities, if

any of these things occur. Very few people are radicalised by being hurt

by the police, most are just scared. Often the hours spent dealing with

legal hassles for months after an arrest could have been more

productively spent in other political activity, if the arrest was not

necessary. Finally, how will the action transform the consciousness of

those involved in it? We should aim to engage in activities which

establish within us an increased awareness of radical social and

political possibilities, broaden our base of skills and leave us

confident and empowered. Sometimes actions may have other, less welcome,

effects on the psychology of those involved. Unsuccessful actions may

leave us feeling disempowered and embittered. Actions which involve a

high degree of aggression, confrontation or potential violence may breed

hostility and aggression within us which might hamper our ability to

work productively in other political circumstances.

By assessing our political activities against these criteria and asking

these questions and others like them, I believe that we can ensure that

our actions have the greatest chance of achieving our goals and thus

demonstrate the superiority of anarchist methods of political action.

Some consequences

Anarchists and the police

The relation of activists and demonstrators to the police is a

contentious issue in activist politics in Australia. This is not the

place to give a detailed treatment of the politics of various ways of

relating to the police. But a brief consideration of some of the matters

discussed in this paper can, I believe, aid discussion of the issue by

ruling out a number of possible (bad) answers to the question of how we

should treat the police.

The first implication of the politics of direct action with regards to

our relations with the police is that, wherever possible, we should

disregard the authority of the police. Direct action is action which

acknowledges our own power and right to exercise it. To the same extent

that we recognise the authority of the police and obey their

instructions we are relinquishing our own right and power to act as we

would wish to. So it is actually essential to direct action that we do

not concede the right of the representatives of the state to restrict

our activities. Of course, for tactical reasons, we may have to

acknowledge the consequences that may occur when we ignore the law and

may even have to negotiate with police in the attempt to minimise these.

But it is important that, in doing so, we remember at all times that

although they have the means to do so, they have no right to restrict us

in our liberty.

The discussion of the necessity of a political analysis of the relation

between our ends and our means is also crucial here. Any strategy of

dealing with the police must take account of their role as a political —

and ultimately a class — force. The police force exists to defend the

status quo and the interests of the ruling class. Individual police

officers may occasionally have reservations about doing so but, when

push comes to shove, that is their job. A police officer who doesn’t

follow the orders of the state is no longer a police officer. As

anarchists therefore, the police, not as individuals but as an

institution, are our enemies. They exist to defend all that we wish to

destroy. In their defence of private property and the state, the police

are backed up by the armed force of the state. Behind the police lies

the military who, as numerous historical examples illustrate, are ready

to step in and restore “order” if the civilian population becomes too

unruly.

Once we recognise the police force as a political institution and that

its members therefore necessarily stand in a certain political relation

to us then a number of things become clear.

Firstly, any attempt to “win over” the police, one by one, is doomed. We

can win the cooperation of the police for precisely as long as we fail

to genuinely threaten the existing social order. As soon as our

activities begin to threaten the interests of the state or the profits

of the ruling class the police will move to disperse/arrest/beat us, as

sure as night follows day. Of course, individual police may be moved by

personal convictions. But as I suggested above, this does not change

their political relation to us and the necessity of them acting against

us. It’s their job and if they refuse to do it they will (ultimately)

lose it. A gentle cop does not remain a cop for long. Attempts to win

over the police may succeed in winning over individuals then, but at the

cost of them ceasing to be members of the police force. We will never to

able to win the cooperation of the police as a political force when it

counts.

Secondly, the fact that the police are ultimately backed by the armed

force of the state determines that any attempt to resist or overcome the

police through violence will ultimately fail. While the state and ruling

class are secure politically and can succeed in maintaining the

passivity of the majority of the population, they can defeat any attempt

to threaten them through violent means. The state has more repressive

force at its command than we can ever hope to muster. This is not a

pacifist position. We have every right to employ force in the attempt to

resist the violence of the state. Where a specific act of violence

against the state will achieve a particular tactical objective, without

provoking crippling repression or a disastrous political backlash, then

we would be justified in committing it. But as a political strategy, in

a non-revolutionary period, attempting to overcome the state through

force is doomed.

The beginnings of an anarchist politics with regards to the police

force, then, are to be found in a conscious hostility towards them as an

institution, tempered by an awareness of the tactical realities of

dealing with them. Recognising that the police are our class enemy is

itself an important gain in political consciousness. This is not to

deny, however, that there may be tactical advantages to not antagonising

the police. Indeed, antagonising the police is a sure way to guarantee

extra hassles for protesters. So it should never be done unnecessarily.

But in our care to avoid creating unnecessary trouble for ourselves we

must remember that the source of the confrontation and violence which

sometimes occurs around the police is the police themselves in their

attempts to protect an unjust — and ultimately itself violent — social

order.

Anarchists and the Media

The other important area of politics where my discussion of direct

action has significant practical consequences is in protesters’ relation

to the media. This is an issue which often generates heated discussion

within activist groups and which can have a significant effect on their

politics. Again consideration of the politics of direct action allows us

to go some way towards settling this question.

As I suggested earlier any protest where protester’s are acting entirely

for the sake of media attention or — as actually often occurs — are even

being directed in their activities by the media is not a case of direct

action. Such “media stunts” do not themselves seek to address the

problems which they highlight and are instead directed to getting other

people (usually the government) to solve them. Thus in as far as we are

concerned to be practicing direct action we should shun this sort of

involvement with the media. We should not “perform” for the cameras or

reporters.

Yet, because an important criteria for a successful anarchist action is

its success in reaching other people and convincing them of the efficacy

of anarchist techniques, we can’t really ignore the media. Sadly, the

only contact many people have with political events around them is

through television or the papers.

From these two facts, I believe, the rudiments of an anarchist stance

towards the media emerge. Anarchists should neither ignore the media or

perform for it. Instead we should remain true to our own politics and

seek to achieve our ends through our own efforts. While we do so we

should welcome media attention which might spread news of our activities

and so help build an anarchist movement. When we cooperate with the

media we should do so without compromising the integrity of our own

politics and without distorting either ourselves or our message. Once we

compromise our politics for the sake of media attention then we are no

longer conveying the success of anarchist methods.

Finally the advantages of direct action should encourage us to make

maximum use of our own and community media in attempting to reach out to

others. Rather than relying on the capitalist press to communicate our

message to the people we should do it ourselves. Community papers, radio

and television are themselves examples of direct action in the media.

A final note.

This paper has discussed and advocated the politics of direct action

within the broader context of the purpose of an anarchist politics.

Direct action has many virtues, not least that it is, in essence, itself

anarchy in action. But direct action is not the only form of worthwhile

political action. Anarchists should remain open to the possibilities of

an entire spectrum of political methods. Any form of politics that

involves people and transforms their consciousness in a progressive way

may be useful in the struggle to build an anarchist movement and

ultimately a revolution to create anarchy. Which particular political

movements and methods deserve our support can only been decided within

the framework of a well theorised, consciously anarchist, politics. This

paper is intended as one small contribution to the project of developing

such a framework.