💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › miguel-amoros-capital-technology-and-proletariat.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:24:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Capital, Technology and Proletariat Author: Miguel AmorĂłs Date: April 24, 2010 Language: en Topics: Capitalism, reformism, technology Source: Retrieved on 8th May 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/capital-technology-proletariat-miguel-amor%C3%B3s Notes: Transcript of a speech delivered on April 24, 2010 at the cooperative bookstore, Enclave Libros, Madrid. Translated from the Spanish original: http://praxisdigital.wordpress.com/2011/01/27/capital-tecnologia-y-proletariado-miguel-amoros-2010/
The origins of the proletariat must be sought in the historical period
when feudal society organized itself around the economy and was
transformed into capitalist society. This happened when the rule of
capital, dominant in commodity circulation, invaded the sphere of
production by means of an “industrial revolution”, in which the division
of labor and technology would play leading roles. The commodity, that
is, the product that is exchanged for money, had arisen at various
moments throughout history, always in connection with commerce, but had
never before occupied a central place in society, and its logic had
therefore never previously determined the social order. Not until the
18^(th) century—the century of the Enlightenment—did the moment arrive
when the enormous demand generated by the military needs of the States
give birth to a new system of production, the factory, with its
corresponding one-sided technology based on science and mass production.
The very fact that production became the production of commodities is
fundamental because it implies a special commodity that adds value to
the raw material: that commodity is labor. In short, it required the
creation of a proletariat. Capital created its antagonist, the wage
worker, under conditions that were established by a particular
technology and by a certain course of development pursued by the State.
The industrial proletariat is also the offspring of both of these
factors. Concretely, it is as much the fruit of the steam engine, as it
is of the regimentation of labor in accordance with the
military-industrial model.
The changes ushered in during the modern era were preceded by a slow
evolution of thought, during the course of which reason replaced
religion and disenchanted the world. Secularized man descended from the
heavens to the earth. The world, once it was viewed correctly, could be
explained on its own terms, without spiritual guides. Science came to be
accepted as the highest form of thought, displacing tradition and
authority. A new faith emerged, the faith in progress, the belief that
human betterment would be almost automatically achieved with the
generalization of scientific knowledge and technological innovations.
But progressivist reason was not content with the satisfaction of
knowledge, but wanted to advance under the sign of domination. In
addition to dominating the forces of nature and putting them at the
service of the ruling interests, the doctrine of progress implied a
goal, the complete demolition of the past, which was perceived as
miserable backwardness, as opposed to the future, which was depicted as
almost a paradise. Constant change, an elementary premise of science and
technology, was raised to the status of a moral duty. To oppose change
was to be against progress, to advocate poverty and ignorance. The
balance of forces tilted in favor of the machine and rationalized
organization, because the rule over nature, in other words, progress,
turned into servitude under science and technology. This instrumentalist
mentality paved the way for capitalism and created favorable conditions
for its development. In the new context imposed by the commodity, the
worker was a piece of the industrial mechanism, the source of surplus
value, and a slave of the machine. The production of commodities, and
therefore labor, would be increasingly subordinated to rationalization
and technological innovation. Real capitalist domination is impersonal,
since its directors are always the mere executors, for good or ill, of
rules they do not control. It consists in the power of things over
people, or, more precisely, the power of abstraction over social and
ecological reality, thanks to which the individual appears as the
intermediary between things, as a secondary part of a mechanism, a
plaything of alien laws, regardless of how this power is personified to
its victims. This abstraction assumes a material form through eminently
technical means. It becomes increasingly dependent on technology. Thus,
although domination would be more and more disconnected from the
concrete economic sphere in order to become increasingly technical in
nature, technology itself, having grown up within the economic sphere,
at the heart of the abstraction, would gradually be transformed into a
futuristic fetish situated above classes. Scientific-technological
criteria would be internalized, displacing ideological and political
criteria in the management of private and public affairs. Finally, for
the good of the economy and that of the dominant culture, science and
technology would begin to assume the form of an ideology as guides for
the organization of individual and collective existence.
During its first stage, the basic contradiction of capitalism was the
contradiction between capital and wage labor, between the bourgeois
class and the working class. The real domination of things over
individuals, which is the essence of capitalism, initially assumed the
appearance of personal or class exploitation. There appeared to be an
absolute incompatibility between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat
despite the fact that the class struggle took place within capitalism
and the fact that capital and labor, as two poles of the same relation,
together constitute a special community of interests. Actually, their
radical antagonism was the result of the commodity’s rapid penetration
of society; the growth of capitalism outstripped the development of its
corresponding juridical and political forms—for example, the right to
vote, freedom of association and the right to strike. These forms,
hamstrung by the remnants of the old regime that still affected the
classes, were incapable of mitigating the conflict. This is why the
workers movement began by demanding not just labor reforms, but also
political rights, and faced with the insurmountable obstacles that stood
in its way, it concluded that there was no other way to remove them
except social revolution. As the historical forms that conformed to
bourgeois needs were in the process of being established, the workers
movement was split over the question of methods, and only remained
united with regard to the question of its goals. Reformists and
revolutionaries both claimed to be pursuing the same goals, even if the
means they utilized were different. Nonetheless, the practices of
reformism and Jacobinism led to the creation of the labor bureaucracy
and its clientele, whose existence was made possible by the decline of
skilled trades and their integration into the system. In a subsequent
stage of political-economic development, the workers parties, trade
union collaborationism, Fordism, etc., revealed that the contradiction
between capital and labor was not as absolute as it had previously
appeared to be. Social reforms did not pave the way for the workers’
State or the workers’ community, but gave rise to the development of a
consumer society.
It is true that the revolutionary proletariat created communes, factory
committees, unitary trade unions, workers councils, militias and
collectives, which comprise the undefeated part of its movement and its
legacy to future revolutions. However, the debacle represented by the
construction of a totalitarian State in Russia, the defeat of the
Spanish Revolution and the inter-class anti-fascism of the postwar era
led some to question the historic role of gravedigger of capitalism that
was once attributed to the international working class. Facts such as
massive participation in parliamentary elections, mass consumption and
the entertainment industry revealed a population of wage laborers who
identified with bourgeois morality. Other realities, such as automation
or the expansion of the service sector, highlight the widening gap that
has opened up between production and the proletariat; in all, the
existence of a class society in the process of dissolution, a mass
society. Just as the classes were a creation of immature capitalism, the
masses are a creation of mature capitalism. They are the result of the
decline of the working class in the face of the predominance of
technology in production and managed consumption. Unlike classes, masses
are incapable of emancipating themselves. They are composed of uprooted
individuals, separated from any kind of solidarity or relation that is
not mediated by propaganda or the spectacle. On the social plane, this
means that all life has now become private life, indoctrinated, surveyed
and compelled to consume. In mass society, technology is in command; man
is the raw material of the machine, the instrument by which one social
mechanism constructs another, yet more mechanistic social mechanism. The
dominant values have become directly technical values, because
technology is decisive both with regard to capital formation and the
apparatus of power. The tendency for mass society to become a factory, a
shopping mall, a jail and a laboratory at the same time, or, to put it
another way, the will of the autonomous apparatus of power to become
capable of determining life in accordance with the criteria that
correspond to those four subsystems, reveals the real primary
contradiction of capitalism, the contradiction that is generated by the
clash between the technophile logic of the commodity and the social life
over which it has seized control, including its biological environment.
Exploitation does not cease at the end of the working day. All of life
has been expropriated and, given the impact of this expropriation on the
ecosystem, all of life is directly endangered. The contradiction reaches
its climax by threatening the survival of the species. Capitalism, in
its late stage, brings the era of instrumentalization to an end, the era
when political, economic and moral ideals were supposed to lead to a
technological utopia and, as a result, technology, or “dead labor”,
embraces life in all its aspects, since the latter is unfolding in an
increasingly more artificial environment. Cutting-edge technology is the
human destiny under late capitalism. In such a regime, there is no other
hope besides continuing on the course of technological innovation,
although along the way, due to the demands of the apparatus of
power—whether one calls it the technocratic oligarchy or simply the
megamachine—all human qualities will disappear and the planet will be
destroyed.
The revolts of the sixties and seventies did not fail to point out the
limitations of the old workers movement and to define the revolution as
a subversive transformation of our entire way of life. The situationist
definition, “the proletarian is someone who has no power over his life
and knows it”, transferred the class struggle to the terrain of everyday
life, which to some extent clashed with the SI’s councilist workerism,
as opposed to the more coherent combatant communities or fraternities of
the American radicals. In Europe, however, the industrial proletariat
still occupied the center of production, and the new class consciousness
came into conflict with the old. Young radicals often found themselves
in conflict with the old militants in the factories. The workerist ideal
became entirely obsolete in the midst of the widespread emergence of
lifestyles that demanded freedoms of every kind, free experimentation
and the abolition of all social prejudices and conventions. The last
waves of the workers movement in response to the crisis of the
modernization process were still capable of creating the illusion of a
reprise, or a second offensive, of a kind of “workers autonomy”, but
this was the part of the movement that suffered the most decisive
defeat, while the movement as a whole had the potential to go much
further. As long as the rebellion in the factories went hand in hand
with the rebellion of everyday life, there was a degree of rediscovery
and autonomy, but this conjunction was fleeting. The bitter taste of
defeat during the following years undermined the unrealistic optimism of
the previous years. Institutionalization, subsidies and electoral
mechanisms had transformed the workerist bureaucracy into a reactionary
factor of the first order, which the minor skirmishes mounted by the
radical workers were unable to prevent. With rare exceptions, the latter
remained on the same terrain; the struggles over wages, working hours or
job security, however legitimate they may have been, however violent
they were and however many assemblies arose from their struggles, did
not transgress the limits of capital, and therefore did not undermine
the political-trade union clientelism, nor did they contribute to the
decolonization of everyday life. They did not fight against capitalism,
but against a specific form of capitalism, one that was undergoing a
process of self-liquidation. Furthermore, the subsequent capitalist
offensive of the eighties liberalized customs, generalized consumption
and put an end to the radical outbreaks in the factories. Automation
displaced the mass of wage workers towards construction, distribution
and tourism. The trade union pact restored a model of vertical
negotiation and obscured the class consciousness of revolts. Repression
took care of the rest. The struggle at the workplace was definitively
separated from the struggle for an untrammeled life without capitalist
catastrophes. The idea of revolution was completely discredited and
relegated to the museum of utopias. The persistent residual workerism
was increasingly caught between the contemplation of a consumerist mass
of wage workers, docile and manipulable, and the dream of an abstract
working class, the bearer of universal ideals of emancipation. From then
on, it barricaded itself in its ghetto and survived in the form of
sects, with their dogmas, their symbols and their rituals; it ceased to
be a simple ideology born from an insufficient social analysis and
practice, in order to accommodate itself to the space reserved for it by
the technological era.
The consideration of labor as the element that is common to all of
society, as its organizational principle, as advocated by the supporters
of the proletarian revolution, amounts to presenting socialism as a
regime of workers in pursuit of social reform by evolutionary processes
that have been liberated from the capitalists. Under this
perspective—which is that of progress, or that of the
bourgeoisie—socialism is nothing but a corrected version of capitalism,
and the workers movement is an agent of modernization. This journey does
not require a lot of packing and the workerist bureaucrats chose it with
their eyes open: real capitalism was effectively the only socialism that
was possible, whether it is called the “Welfare State” or the “highly
developed” society. According to this view, the danger is not
integration but exclusion, not having too much capitalism but too
little. If in the past, socialism was often presented as the coherence
of capitalism, now that another more “human” (and more Keynesian)
version is thought to be possible, capitalism has proven to be the
coherence of socialism. Anti-capitalism, if it does not want to be
trapped in a contradiction, must mount a profound response to the forces
of production and the laws of the market. Production and distribution of
commodities will not cease to be production and distribution of
commodities just because production and distribution fall into the hands
of the workers, and should this take place, it will reproduce in one
form or another precisely what it sought to destroy: bosses, private
property, industry, market, the State. Labor, which, once embedded in a
fully developed society of consumption can no longer constitute a
community of the oppressed, is even less capable of serving as the basis
for any kind of free society. Only life can be that basis.
To abolish capitalism without abolishing the proletariat would be
equivalent to reproducing another form of capitalism and, as a
corollary, another ruling class, and another State. To abolish the
proletariat without rejecting the ideology of progress leads to the same
results. If you want to bring the reign of the commodity to an end, you
need to abolish labor as well as the technology associated with its
existence; in short, you must free individuals from the condition of
being workers, you must free them from the objectivized social relation
that transforms them into wage workers, accessories to the machine and
slaves of consumption. The suppression of labor must take place first of
all in production, but not by means of the collective appropriation of
the means of production, or by way of automation, but by the dismantling
of the urban-factory system and the abandonment of the centralizing
machinery. And at the same time, this process must be carried out in
circulation as well, but not only by means of the abolition of money and
the market, but with the elimination of technologized leisure, that new
form of labor. A life emancipated from labor is not a life of leisure;
among other things, it is a life in which productive activity, the
“metabolism with nature”, obeys the satisfaction of needs and does not
determine social functioning, it does not alter “universal fraternity”
in the least way (that is, it does not impede the reproduction of free
social relations). The revolution aspires to nothing but breaking the
chains of labor—especially those of technology—in order to facilitate
the reappropriation of life on the part of individuals, by way of the
free construction of all the moments of their lives. By putting an end
to the constrictions of separate power and autonomous technology, by
putting an end to artificialization, by putting an end to the
manipulation of needs, eroticism, desires and dreams, life will be freed
from barriers and impositions, and will be at its own disposal: it will
escape from the sphere of labor and consumption, that is, of harmful
phenomena and submission. The relations between man and machine, between
humanity and nature, or, more precisely, between individuals and things,
will have to be reinvented, and society will have to be reconstructed
morally and with regard to the requirements of mutual coexistence,
without hierarchies, with the aid of a multifaceted technology based in
agriculture, the arts and the satisfaction of real needs and authentic
desires. To restore equilibrium to the land, to reduce the size of the
cities and to establish new relations with the environment that are not
based on domination. To build free communities. Paradoxically, although
tradition must regulate the rhythms of social life, this does not mean
returning to one or another moment of the past, but making a clean slate
of the present.