đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș dwight-macdonald-the-root-is-man.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:14:16. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Root Is Man Author: Dwight Macdonald Date: 1946 Language: en Topics: anarchism, individualism, marxism, pacifism, radicalism, Trotskyism Source: Macdonald, Dwight. âThe Root Is Man.â Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia, 1995. Print. Notes: Transcribed from the 1995 Autonomedia republication of the 1953 update of the 1946 original work by âFlighty Dwightyâ Macdonald, by grigor
Marxism is the most profound expression of what has been the dominant
theme in Western culture since the 18^(th) century: the belief that the
advance of science, with the resulting increase of manâs mastery over
nature, is the climax of a historical pattern of Progress. If we have
come to question this pattern, before we can find any new roads, we must
first reject the magnificent system which Marx elaborated on its basis.
A break with a whole cultural tradition is involved, and Marxism looms
up as the last and greatest systematic defense of that tradition.
(âThe Root Is Man,â 1946)
Â
The collapse of the Soviet Union ended a historical epoch that began
with the storming of the Bastille. Today, history no longer absolves
Fidel. The disintegration of the Marxist project has left the Left
exhausted. Like it or not, the breakdown of Marxism, the unraveling of
its scientific and moral claims, is a fact.
Marxismâs demise is not just the extinction of capitalismâs strongest
ideological foe. Marxism was also one of the most profound intellectual
expressions of the High Enlightenment belief in Science, Progress and
Reason. Marxismâs crackup reveals(to those willing to look) gaping fault
lines in the philosophical foundations of the modern age.
In the spring of 1946, Dwight Macdonald published âThe Root Is Manâ in
politics, the journal he and his then-wife Nancy created after breaking
with Partisan Review three years earlier. âThe Root Is Manâ is largely
about the theories of one man: Karl Marx. Macdonald argues that any
serious critique of Marxism must come to terms with Marxismâs origins in
the European Enlightenment. Macdonald shows us the Victorian optimist in
Marx, the would-be Charles Darwin who believed he had finally uncovered
the evolutionary law of human history but whose system unwittingly
articulated, as well as challenged, the desires and values of his own
time. âThe Root Is Man,â however, was not an exercize in armchair
Marxicology or another obituary for a god that failed but a painful
reexamination of views Macdonald had held for over a decade both as a
Communist Party fellow traveller and later as a Trotskyist
revolutionary.
Â
Born in New York City in 1905 and educated at Phillips Exert and Yale,
Dwight Macdonald entered radical politics in the early 1930âs as a
fellow traveller of the American Communist Party. After Stalinâs famous
Moscow trials, Macdonald broke with the CP and became a strong supporter
of Leon Trotsky. In 1939, shortly after the signing of the Hitler-Stalin
Pact, Macdonald joined the Socialist Workers Part (SWP), the American
branch of Trotskyâs Fourth International.
Macdonald made it clear early on that he would be one troublesome Trot.
When submitting his first article to the Trotskyist journal New
International in July 1938, Macdonald enclosed a long letter to the
editor attacking a previous contribution by Trotsky that defended the
crushing of the Kronstadt soviet of sailors and workers in 1921.
Macdonald thought Trotskyâs piece âdisappointing and embarrassing.â In
his letter Macdonald question a Bolshevik Party that âconcentrates power
in the hands of a small group of politicians so well insulated (by a
hierarchical, bureaucratic, party apparatus) against pressure from the
masses that they donât respond to the needs of the masses until too
late.â Despite dangers from the Right, âAre not the dangers of an
airtight dictatorship, insulated against mass pressure, even greater?â
The âOld Manâ (Trotsky) was not amused. âEveryone has a natural right to
be stupid,â Trotsky wrote in reply to Macdonald, âbut beyond a certain
point it becomes an intolerable privilege.â (This was later popularized
into: âEvery mans has a right to be stupid on occasion, but comrade
Macdonald abuses itâ â which was the way Macdonald always â and
frequently â cited it.) James Cannon, Trotskyâs chief American
lieutenant and SWP National Secretary, also knew trouble when he saw it.
Cannon dubbed Macdonald âflighty Dwightyâ and mocked him as the âvery
modelâ of a âpolitical Alice in Wonderland.â In Memoirs of a
Revolutionist, Macdonald mocked back:
Alice is presented in Carrollâs book as a normal and reasonable person
who is constantly being amused, bewildered or distressed by the
fantastic behavior and logic of the inhabitants of Wonderland....[In]
the Trotskyist movement, I must confess I often felt like Alice.
In âThe Root Is Man,â Macdonald was more biter: âAnyone who has been
through the Trotskyist movement...as I have, knows that in respect to
decent personal behavior, truthfulness, and respect for dissident
opinion, the âcomradesâ are generally much inferior to the average
stockbroker.â
At the time Macdonald joined the SWP the situation inside the tiny sect
was particularly savage. The SWP was racked by a series of fierce
internal political debates; debates that would crucially influence âThe
Root Is Man.â Macdonald had been drawn to the Trotskyists precisely
because of his reservations about the nature of Stalinâs Russia. Now the
SWP was fissuring over the same basic question: What was the correct
Marxist view of the Soviet Union?
On August 22, 1939, the foreign ministers of Nazi Germany and the Soviet
Union signed a non-aggression pact that stunned the world. One week
later, Germany successfully invaded Poland. The USSR, in turn, seized
large sections of Eastern Poland with the approval of the Nazis. In late
1939 the Soviet Union also launched its own âdefensiveâ war against
Finland.
The SWP majority argued that the Nazi-Soviet Pact did not change the
Trotskyist view of the USSR as a degenerated workersâ state worthy of
critical support. Trotsky saw Stalinism as a temporary distortion of the
world revolution caused by backward economic and social conditions in
Russia. Yet as long as the Soviet Union maintained a socialist economic
base (the nationalized economy), Trotsky insisted that the USSR remained
true to its revolutionary origins.
Throughout the 1930âs, Trotsky worried that the real threat to socialism
stemmed not from Stalin but from Nicholai Bukharin, another Old
Bolshevik who would be a major defendant at Stalinâs Moscow Trials.
Bukharin strongly opposed Trotskyâs call for the forced
industrialization of the USSR. Bukharin argued that the Soviet Union
should return to some intermediate form of a market economy and not
antagonize the countryâs vast peasant population. Trotsky saw Bukharin
as a stalking horse for a capitalist restoration of the USSR and feared
Bukharinâs ideas would be used by ârightistâ bureaucrats to justify
dismantling the nationalized economy.
For Trotsky, Stalin was a centrist concerned only with the preservation
of personal power. During times of world political stagnation, Stalinism
tilted toward the capitalist-restorationist siren song of Bukharin
inside the USSR and the appeasement of capitalist powers abroad. Yet, in
times of revolutionary upheaval, the same Stalinist machine could either
realign with Trotsky, the leading advocate of âpermanent revolution,â or
risk its own destruction in a new radical upsurge.
Stalinâs adoption of the Trotskyist Left Opposition call for the forced
industrialization of the USSR (a policy that led to countless deaths,
the destruction of agriculture and a virtual civil war in the country
side) was, for Trotsky, objectively progressive because it strengthened
the socialist economic base of the society. Stalinâs failure to advocate
revolutionary class war, however, mirrored the backward nature of the
Stalinist bureaucratic caste. To see Stalinism as a simultaneous
reflection of both the progressive economic base of the USSR as well as
Russiaâs backward economic, cultural and political superstructure was,
Trotsky argued, to think dialectically. Events like the Hitler-Stalin
Pact, far from shaking Trotskyâs faith, only confirmed his view that the
Soviet bureaucracy could make the most radical reversals in policy.
Under the right historical circumstances, Stalin could turn around and
adopt Trotskyâs policies easily as he embraced Hitler.
To the SWP minority, Trotskyâs defense of the USSR (no matter how
brilliantly argued) was radically wrong. Instead of seeing the USSR as a
degenerated workersâ state worthy of critical support, the minority
argued that Stalinâs Russia had become a bureaucratic collectivist
nightmare, a modern despotism of immense proportion drenched in blood.
Trapped in this new, more brutal Ottoman Empire, ordinary workers
enjoyed far less freedom than in the capitalist West. The fact that the
USSR had a nationalized economy only meant that much more power for the
Stalinist elite as it extended its totalitarian rule into all aspects of
civil society.
Â
Dwight Macdonald entered the SWP a firm supporter of the minority. Eager
to join the fray but very much the new kid on the block, Macdonald
complained:
I wrote three long articles for the âInternal Bulletinâ [of the SWP]
but, although I had no trouble getting printed in Fortune, Harperâs, The
Nation, The New Yorker â or for the matter The New International â my
manuscripts were monotonously rejected. The 800 members of the party,
steeped in Marxicology, aged in the Bolshevik-Leninist wood, were a
highly esoteric audience, while I was a highly esoteric writer. They
were professionals, I was an amateur.
(Macdonald, Memoirs of a Revolutionist)
Finally Macdonald did get published and Trotsky again took note.
Macdonaldâs article (which appeared shortly after the minority had
broken from the SWP) included the sentence: âOnly if we meet the stormy
and terrible years ahead with both skepticism and devotion â skepticism
toward all theories, governments and social systems; devotion to the
revolutionary fight of the masses â only then can we justify ourselves
as intellectuals.â Trotsky was enraged. Just a few weeks before he was
murdered, the old lion roared back:
How can we work without a theory?... The whole article is scandalous and
a party which can tolerate such a man is not serious... We can only
develop a revolutionary devotion if we are sure it is rational and
possible, and we cannot have such assurances without a working theory.
He who propagates theoretical skepticism is a traitor.
(Trotsky, âOn the âWorkersâ Partyââ)
For Trotsky, theoretical skepticism was a more dangerous threat to
Marxism than any Stalinist assassin. Marxism was the most advanced
expression of Reason, the High Enlightenmentâs ultimate tribunal for
human action. Trotsky believed Marxismâs scientific method supplied a
foundation for moral and political action far superior to abstract
religious or bourgeois class morality.
Marxism, however, was a peculiar science. In science (at least the
banal, bourgeois kind) anyone using as accepted method can reproduce the
findings of others. Yet Marxismâs own history seemed guaranteed to
encourage theoretical skepticism. For wasnât Bukharin also a Marxist?
(Indeed, Bukharin was considered the leading Bolshevik experts on
Marxist economics.) And Kautsky? And Stalin? And what about the
Mensheviks â werenât they Marxists, too?
The key issue, of course, was not the denial of the usefulness of
Marxist theory in giving profound insight into issues of history,
culture, art and science. Instead, the debate centered on absolutist
claims by various Marxists who wrapped their own subjective political
decisions in the mantle of Marxist orthodoxy.
Like his Stalinist foes, Trotsky used appeals to the class basis of
moral values and the supposed demands of historical necessity to defend
acts otherwise hard to justify. After all, it was Trotsky (not Stalin)
who as the major author of War Communism supported the drafting of
workers into factories and the abolition of independent trade unions. It
was Trotsky who helped create the gulag work camp system and it was
Trotsky who had nothing but praise for the Bolshevik secret police when
Social Revolutionary, Left Menshevik and Anarchist critics of Bolshevism
were being brutally imprisoned, executed or forced into permanent exile.
And it was Trotsky who encouraged Stalinâs disastrous forced
industrialization of the Soviet Union. In his book The Breakdown (Volume
Three of Main Currents of Marxism, Leszek Kolakowski argues that for
Trotsky:
All âabstractâ principles of good and bad, all universal rules of
democracy, freedom, and cultural value were without significance within
themselves: they were to be accepted or rejected as political expediency
might dictate...for Trotsky there was no question of democracy as a form
of government, or of civil liberties as a cultural value... To say that
a thing was good or bad in itself, irrespective of political
consequences, was tantamount to believing in God. It was meaningless to
ask, for instance, whether it was right in itself to murder the children
of oneâs political opponents. It had been right (as Trotsky says
everywhere) to kill the Tsarâs children, because it was politically
justified. Why then was it wrong for Stalin to murder Trotskyâs
children? Because Stalin did not represent the proletariat.
Trotsky defended such twists and turns by repeated appeals to dialectics
and Marxist scientific method. Not surprisingly, the SWP opposition
began to hammer away at Trotskyâs attempt to make himself the chosen
interpreter of Marxâs method. In his essay âScience and Style,â James
Burnham, then an NYU philosophy professor and the SWP minorityâs leading
theorist, challenged Trotsky:
...it is a direct falsehood to say that I, or any other member of the
opposition, reject the Marxian theory of the state. We disagree with
your interpretation and application of the Marxian theory of the
state....Since when have we granted one individual the right of
infallible interpretation?
As for Trotskyâs invocation of science, Burnham asked:
Does science, as you understand it, and the truths it demonstrates, have
a name? What name? âProletarianâ science and âproletarianâ truth?... You
are on treacherous ground, Comrade Trotsky. The doctrine of âclass
truthâ is the road of Platoâs Philosopher-Kings, of prophets and Popes
and Stalins. For all of them, also, a man must be among the anointed in
order to know the truth.
Trotsky immediately grasped the threat. In âAn Open Letter to Comrade
Burnham,â Trotskyâs answer to âScience and Style,â he warned:
The opposition leaders split sociology from dialectic materialism. They
split politics from sociology....History becomes transformed into a
series of exceptional incidents; politics becomes transformed into a
series of improvisations. We have here, in the full sense of the term,
the disintegration of Marxism, the disintegration of theoretical
thought...
(both âScience and Styleâ as well as âAn Open Letter to Comrade Burnhamâ
can be found in Pathfinderâs In Defense of Marxism.)
Trotskyâs argument was specious. The opposition did not deny the
validity of trying to find continuity or development in history. Yet on
a deeper level, Trotskyâs fears were justified. In essence, the
opposition challenged Trotskyâs privileged position as interpreted of
Marxist doxa. But if Marxism was an open method,rather than an exact
science, specific political decisions could no longer be grounded on
appeals to historical necessity since it was not clear that anyone could
honestly claim to know that necessity in the same way science knows the
exact distance between the earth and the moon.
Throughout the history of Marxism, personality cults have arisen both in
tiny sects and vast nations to repress open claims to interpretation. As
soon as such claims are advanced and the scientific mantle surrounding
Marxism deconstructed, so too are the totalitarian structures of
one-party rule, âobjective truthâ and heresy hunting that go
hand-in-hand with them.
The painful truth about Trotsky was that he didnât have the slightest
philosophical (or moral) problem with the suppression of the Mensheviks
or Anarchists. The Objective Demands of History justified all. now the
evil genie of subjectivism and limits to knowledge (themes crucial to
âThe Root Is Manâ) appeared inside the purest of Marxist sects. No
wonder Trotsky feared the âdisintegration of Marxism, the disintegration
of theoretical thought....â Marxism as a system modeled after the
paradigms of 19^(th) century science was becoming unhinged; its truth
claims relativized.
The minority challenge, however, went deeper. The SWP opposition also
called into question orthodox Marxismâs emphasis on the economic base as
the ultimate determinant of the political and cultural superstructure.
by claiming that the base had been so subordinated to the superstructure
that the USSR could no longer be defended as a workersâ state but
opposed as a new, more horrible form of totalitarianism, the SWP
minority denied the most fundamental fixed category of classic Marxist
analysis.
After leaving the SWP in 1940, the minority renamed itself the Workers
Party (best known as the Shachtmanites after their leader, Max
Shachtman, who had been one of Trotskyâs top lieutenants). Besides
Shachtman, the Workers Party had other outstanding members like C.L.R.
James and Hal Draper. But the Workers party had also unwittingly
debunked the very rationale of the vanguard party. James Burnham was one
of the first to realize this. Almost immediately after splitting with
the SWP, Burnham quit the Workers party and announced he had lost faith
in Marxist dialectics.
Unlike Burnham, Macdonald remained a Workers Party supporter although he
resigned from the sect because he was unwilling to follow party
discipline and have his articles vetted by the leadership before
publication. (At the time Macdonald was both a writer and editor of
Partisan Review.) It would take the catastrophe of the second World War
to further awaken the enlightened Marxist Macdonald from the security of
his own dogmatic slumber.
Â
Dwight Macdonald opposed American involvement in the Second World War.
His opposition was rooter in the American Leftâs anti-war tradition and,
in particular, the Socialist Partyâs resistance to U.S. involvement in
World War I. Along with his comrades in the Workers Party, Macdonald
called for a revolutionary uprising of workers both in Germany and the
Allied powers to end the slaughter, a policy that echoed the famous
Zimmerwald line of the Socialist Internationalâs left opposition in
World War I.
Macdonaldâs anti-war stance also grew out of his understanding of the
danger of the State. Sl thought dubbed âBurnhamâs orphanâ by Trotsky,
James Burnham was Dwight Macdonaldâs evil twin. For some time Burnham
(along with a dubious Italian Trotskyist-turned-fascist named Bruno
Rizzi) had been developing the theory that both Germany and Russia
represented new, more advanced âbureaucratic collectivistâ societies
governed not by swashbuckling capitalist tycoons but rational managers;
a new, more scientific elite of power mandarins. (After leaving the
Workers Party, Burnham wrote a best seller called The Managerial
Revolution predicting the rise of such bureaucracies throughout the
world.)
Clearly Macdonaldâs fears were justified. Yet the issue remained: Did
one simply hope for a world revolutionary uprising while Hitler took
over Europe? Macdonald and his fellow editors at Partisan Review
bitterly disagreed. For Phillip Rahv and Sidney Hook the necessity of
stopping Hitler overcame any reservations about joining sides in an
âinter-imperialist war.â
By 1943 the disagreement had become so bitter that Dwight and Nancy
Macdonald quit Partisan Review and launched their own journal, politics,
the first issue of which appeared in February 1944. The Macdonalds
financed politics from their own savings (which included Nancyâs trust
fund), as well as from a gift of a thousand dollars from Margaret De
Silver, the widow of the murdered Italian anarchist Carlo Tresca. Nancy
Macdonald (who had been the business manager of Partisan Review took
over the same job at politics.
Years later Macdonald would call his opposition to World War II a
âcreative mistake.â That âmistakeâ led to a series of brilliant essays
on the war in politics that culminated in Macdonaldâs classic 1945
piece, âThe Responsibility of Peoples,â that opposed the idea of the
collective responsibility of the German people for Nazism. Macdonald
also wrote to save lives. He believed the Allied demand for the
unconditional surrender of Germany, coupled with massive bombing raids
against the German civilian population, only encouraged the Germans to
fight harder by confirming Nazi propaganda about the Carthaginian peace
Germany would be faced with should Hitler lose.
In âThe Responsibility of Peoples,â Macdonald held up a mirror to the
victorious Allies and asked:
If âthey,â the German people, are responsible for the atrocious policies
and actions of âtheirâ...government, then âwe,â the peoples of Russia,
England, and America, must also take on a big load of responsibility....
In the present war, we have carried the saturation bombing of German
cities to a point where âmilitary objectivesâ are secondary to the
incineration of suffocation of great numbers of civilians; we have
betrayed the Polish underground fighters in Warsaw into the hands of the
Nazis, have deported hundreds of thousands of Poles to slow-death camps
in Siberia, and have taken by force a third of Polandâs territory; we
have conducted a civil war against another ally, Greece, in order to
restore a reactionary and unpopular monarch; we have starved those parts
of Europe our armies have âliberatedâ almost as badly as the Nazis
did...we have followed Nazi racist theories in segregating Negro
soldiers in our military forces and in deporting from their homes on the
West Coast to concentration camps in the interior tens of thousands of
citizens who happened to be of Japanese ancestry; we have made ourselves
the accomplice of the Maidanek butchers by refusing to permit more than
a tiny trickle of the Jews of Europe to take refuge inside our borders;
we have rule India brutally, imprisoning the peopleâs leaders, denying
the most elementary of civil liberties, causing a famine last year in
which hundreds of thousands perished; we have â
But this is monstrous, you say? We, the people, didnât do these things.
They were done by a few political leaders and the majority of Americans,
Englishmen and (perhaps â who knows?) Russians deplore them and favor
quite different policies. Or if they donât, then it is because they have
not had a chance to become aware of the real issues and act on them....
Precisely. And the Germans could say the same thing.... It is a terrible
fact, but it is a fact, that few people have the imagination or the
moral sensitivity to get very excited about actions which they donât
participate in themselves (and hence about which they feel no personal
responsibility). The scale and complexity of modern Governmental
organization, and the concentration of political power are excluded from
this participation. How Many votes did Rooseveltâs refugee policy cost
him?... As the French say, to ask such questions is to answer them.
Concluding âThe Responsibility of Peoples,â Macdonald wrote:
The common peoples of the world are coming to have less and less control
over the policies of âtheirâ governments, while at the same time they
are being more and more closely identified with those governments....
not for many centuries have individuals been at once so powerless to
influence what is done by the national collectivities to which they
belong, and at the same time so generally held responsible for what is
done by those collectivities.
With the development of the atomic bomb, Macdonaldâs fear of the descent
of the West into state barbarism and public powerlessness had been fully
realized. One month after the bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki,
Macdonald wrote in politics:
It seems fitting that The Bomb was not developed by any of the
totalitarian powers, where the political atmosphere might at first
glance seem to be more suited to it, but by the two âdemocracies,â the
last major powers to continue to pay at least ideological respect to the
humanitarian-democratic tradition. It also seems fitting that the heads
of these governments, by the time The Bomb exploded, were not Roosevelt
and Churchill, figures of a certain historical and personal stature, but
Attlee and Truman, both colorless mediocrities. Average Men elevated to
their positions by the mechanics of the system.
Some forty-five years before the âwarâ with Iraq, Macdonald noted:
All this emphasizes that perfect automatism, that absolute lack of human
consciousness or aims which our society is rapidly achieving....The more
common-place the personalities and senseless the institutions, the more
grandiose the destruction. It is a GötterdÀm-merung without the gods.
Â
It took Macdonald two years to write âThe Root Is Man.â The scope of the
essay intimidated him. He also had other demands on his time such as
writing, editing, proofreading and publishing politics.
Politics never had more than 5,000 subscribers. They were the first to
read one of the most remarkable American intellectual journals of the
twentieth century. Although this is not the place for a full evaluation
of politics, one can get a sense of its uniqueness by listing some of
its writers: Simone Weil, Albert Camus, Victor Serge, Georges Bataille,
Jean-Paul Satre, Karl Jaspers, George Woodcock, Mary McCarthy, John
Berryman, Robert Duncan, Paul Mattick, Bruno Bettleheim, George Padmore,
Meyer Shapiro, Simone de Beauvoir, Paul Goodman, James Agee, Marshall
McLuhan, Richard Hofstadter, Irving Howe, Nicola Chiaromonte, Lionel
Abel, Andrea Caffi and C. Wright Mills.
There were four remarkable women in the politics circle. Most important
was Nancy Macdonald who managed the journalâs business affairs while at
the same time running various relief efforts to aid veterans of the
Spanish Civil War and victims of Nazism. (The breakup of the Macdonaldsâ
marriage in 1949 would be a major factor in the decision to stop
publishing politics.) Another organizer of politics, Mary McCarthy, was
one of Macdonaldâs closest allies in the libertarian left. (It was
McCarthy who translated Simone Weilâs famous essay on Homerâs Iliad.)
Hannah Arendt (while not writing for politics) became one of Macdonaldâs
most important co-conspirators. In the late 1960âs, Arendt would write
the introduction to a reprint edition of the complete set of politics.
Yet the most powerful intellectual influence on the journal was Simone
Weil, whose critique of violence and essay on Homer had been brought to
Macdonaldâs attention by Nicola Chiaromonte, a Spanish civil war vet,
anti-Fascist exile, and one of Macdonaldâs closest friends. Through
Chiaromonte, the thought of Simone Weil was first introduces to America
in the pages of politics.
Politics also covered such issues as the suppression of the Greek
insurrection, the anti-French insurgency in Indochina, Americaâs refusal
to aid the starving people of Europe, the question of the Soviet Union,
the American civil rights struggle, the need for equal treatment of
homosexuals, the ideas of Wilhelm Reich, attacks on mass culture as
studies on Max Weber, de Tocqueville, Utopian Socialists like Charles
Fourier and anarchists such as Proudhon and Godwin.
One could order from politics Anton Ciligaâs The Russian Enigma (which
has a major impact on Macdonald), Alexander Berkmanâs The ABC of
Anarchism, Camillo Berneriâs Peter Kropotkinâs Federal Ideas, Jomo
Kenyattaâs Kenya, Land of Conflicts, Leo Tolstoyâs The Slavery of our
Times, George Woodcockâs New Life to the Land, Raymond Micheletâs
African Empires and Civilizations, Oscar Wildeâs The Soul of Man Under
Socialism and Rosa Luxemburgâs Letters from Prison.
Politics spoke to radicals who rejected both Stalin and Trotsky but who
were equally intransigent in opposing capitalism. Politics was part of a
larger anti-totalitarian anarchist, pacifist and independent Marxist
milieu that existed in the late 1940âs before the pressures of the Cold
War rigidified political discourse for years to come. Other anarchist
journals like Resistance and Retort in America and George Woodcockâs Now
in England echoed many of politicsâ themes, as did two classic books of
that time: Animal Farm and 1984, by politics fellow traveller George
Orwell. Forums in New York around ideas politics discussed drew
significant audiences. many of politicsâ most active supporters were
leftwing conscientious objectors influenced by Ghandiâs massive civil
disobedience movement in India. It was out of this ferment that âThe
Root Is Manâ emerged, the most famous essay in a series of critical
pieces which appeared under the banner âNew Roads in Politics.â This
essay caused an immediate storm. One lengthy rebuttal by Irving Howe
(then a Workers Party member who worked for Macdonald in the politics
office) called âThe Thirteenth Discipleâ asked:
Where is one to begin in a reply to Macdonald? His forty page article is
a grab-bag of modern confusionism; a pinch of Proudhon; a whiff of
pacifism; a nod to existentialism; a bow to Wilhelm Reich, founder of
the âpsychology of the orgasmâ; a few scrappings from the anarchists; a
touch of philosophical idealism and a large debt to that illustrious
thinker, Paul Goodman.
Years later, in A Margin of Hope, Howe had eased up a bit;
The Root Is Man...(is) in many ways the most poignant and authentic
expression of the plight of those few intellectuals â Nicola
Chiaromonte, Paul Goodman, Macdonald â who wished to disassociate
themselves from the post-war turn to Realpolitik but could not find ways
of transforming sentiments of rectitude and visions of utopia into a
workable politics.
Yet reading âThe Root Is Manâ today is no mere exercise in nostalgia.
Macdonald raised issues that, almost 50 years later, have become even
more critical.
Macdonaldâs assault on the scientific model of thinking echoed Frankfurt
School critiques of instrumental reason. Macdonald, however, located
Marxism itself in the general crisis of Enlightenment thought. For that
alone, âThe Root Is Manâ is extraordinary.
Other crucial issues raised by Macdonald included the question of active
resistance to unfettered growth and the need for economic
decentralization coupled with political democracy. He also took up the
question of reification, citing George LukĂĄcs (not a household name is
1946) to argue that, in the concept of alienation, Marxism made its most
powerful critique of the human condition under capital. The issue of
reification and the damaging effect of mass culture that so concerned
Macdonald would appear again in the mid-60âs Situationist polemic
against the âsociety of the spectacleâ whose roots in dissident Western
Marxism can be found in âThe Root Is Manâ and politics in general.
Above all, Macdonald was most concerned with the way we organize our
daily political action. His insight into how mass socialist and
communist parties reproduce the same deadening effect on the individual
as other forms of bourgeois organization rings true today:
What is not so generally understood is that the traditional progressive
approach, taking history as the starting-point and thinking in terms of
mass political parties, bases itself on this same alienation of man
which it thinks it is combating. It puts the individual in the same
powerless, alienated role vis-Ă -vis the party or trade union as the
manipulators of the modern State do, except that the slogans are
different.... The brutal fact is that the man in the street everywhere
is quite simply bored with socialism, as expounded by the Socialist,
Stalinist, and Trotskyist epigones of Marx... Above all, he feels that
there is no interest in it for him, as an individual human being â that
he is as powerless and manipulated vis-Ă -vis his socialist
mass-organization as he is towards his capitalist employers and their
social and legal institutions.
Â
As soon as âThe Root Is Manâ was published it came under immediate fire
for denying the viability of class struggle. the other major criticism
of âThe Root Is Manâ was its stress on absolute values transcending
history. In fact, only two years after publication of his essay,
Macdonald abandoned one of the absolutes he had endorsed (radical
pacifism) in the wake of what he saw as Stalinâs threat to the West
during the Berlin Crisis.
Along with the 1948 Berlin Crisis and the assassination of Gandhi that
same year, the general threat of a new world war deeply depressed
Macdonald and contributed to his marital breakup. Attempts by the
politics network to organize groups in Europe and communes here also
failed. Politics finally ceased publication in 1949. Macdonaldâs fierce
anti-communist and sense of doom as the radical movement fell apart led
him into the ranks of the Congress for Cultural Freedom (CCF), a group
supported by many leading anti-Stalinist left-intellectuals. Years later
Macdonald would discover the CIAâs role in funding the CCF and its
journals like Encounter.(See Appendix D for a further discussion of
Macdonald and the CCF.)
While Macdonald throughout the 1950âs attacked McCarthyism, he focused
more and more on the need to make a living both as a staff writer for
The new Yorker and freelance journalist. Yet even during the dog days of
the Eisenhower-Nixon era, Macdonald continued to give radical talks on
campuses. One of his favorite themes was the relevance of anarchy. While
Macdonald no longer considered the abolition of private property
necessary, his take on anarchism (in Memoirs of a Revolutionist) is
still striking:
It was odd that anarchism took no root in the thirties, considering (1)
the American temperament, lawless and individualistic, (2) the American
anarchist tradition, from Benjamin Tucker to the Wobblies, and (3) that
anarchism gave a better answer to the real modern problem, the
encroachment of the State, than did Marxism, which was revolutionary
only about bourgeois private property (not a real issue anymore) and was
thoroughly reactionary on the question of the State. But (3) also
explains Marxismâs popularity (though it doesnât justify it): while the
centralized State is the chief danger now to freedom, it is also
necessary to the operation of a mass society based on large-scale
industry. Thus Marxism is âpractical,â since it fits into the status quo
â as in Soviet Russia â while anarchism is âimpracticalâ because it
threatens it. The revolutionary alternative to the status quo today is
not collectivized property administered by a âworkersâ stateâ whatever
that means, but some kind of anarchist decentralization that will break
up mass society into small communities where individuals can live
together as variegated human beings instead of as impersonal units in
the mass sum....Marxism glorifies âthe massesâ and endorses the State.
Anarchism leads back to the individual and the community, which is
âimpracticalâ but necessary â that is to say, it is revolutionary.
In the mid-1950âs the thaw in Russia after Stalinâs death and the
Twentieth Party Congress slowly rejuvenated Macdonald. Although he
always remained a strong anti-communist, Macdonald no longer saw the
USSR as a more advanced version of Hitlerâs Germany. In 1960, Macdonald
became active as a civil libertarian in the cases of Morton Sobell (a
supposed member of the supposed Rosenberg spy ring) and Junius Scales,
another Communist sent to prison under the Smith Act. Macdonald also
became an early member of the New Left and spoke at the closing session
of the first national convention of SDS in 1960. Meanwhile âThe Root Is
Manâ was rediscovered by a new generation of activists. Macdonaldâs
critical support of student radicals culminated in his speaking at the
âCounter Commencementâ held at Columbia during the 1968 strike.
Macdonaldâs activism also led him to participate in a picket line
outside the Waldorf-Astoria to protest the war in Vietnam. The year was
1963, a time when most Americans could not find Vietnam on a map. Later,
in 1967, Macdonald played an important role (with Robert Lowell and
Norman Mailer) in the first big peace march on the Pentagon. Macdonaldâs
radicalism was in striking contrast not just to National Review editor
James Burnham but to Workers Party leader Max Shachtman who by this time
had become a major behind-the-scenes advisor to the AFL-CIO on both
domestic and foreign policy. At various demos, Macdonald would sometimes
bump into young SWP activists who delighted in reminding the old
factionalist that his current views were not so dissimilar to theirs.
âEven a broken watch occasionally tells the right time,â Macdonald would
grumble in response. Dwight Macdonald died in 1982.
Â
Nietzsche defined nihilism as a situation where âeverything is
permitted,â and today we might add âfor the right price.â Our time has
also spawned a series of Jihads against the New World Order. There is
now a frantic search for absolutes, foundational principles, a search
which inspires religious fundamentalists of the Christian, Jewish, Hindu
and Moslem variety as well as those who kill for an inscribed ethnic or
national identity to build their racial Utopias. Contrasted to them are
the efficient, orderly, passionless, non-smoking, technologically
advanced killing machines of the West.
In just such a world it is long past time to rediscover
individualist-centered radical thought from Americaâs rich tradition as
well as thinkers as different as Fourier, Stirner, Kropotkin and
Nietzsche. While the insights of Marxism must continue to inform our
actions, we must also be aware of its glaring weaknesses. It is again
time to take seriously the brilliant battle-cry that concludes Oscar
Wildeâs The Soul of Man Under Socialism: âThe new Individualism is the
new Hellenism.â
Quoting Wilde is especially appropriate in concluding a discussion of
âThe Root Is Manâ because Macdonaldâs essay is also an attempt to
reclaim the spirit of art itself, its values and legislative rights, and
to explore the link between the aesthetic and moral sphere. Macdonald
captures the necessity for a world that imagination, a renewed capacity
to envision the world that makes the very idea of revolt meaningful.
Although T.S. Elliot was a tremendous admirer of politics, Macdonald
does not believe that poets are the unacknowledged legislators of the
world: he does insist that if the oppressed are ever to rule themselves
we must reignite the utopian spark that mass society relentlessly seeks
to subvert, co-opt or destroy.
Of course the terminally hip will scorn any analysis that takes
seriously such Philosophy 101 questions as âHow Do We Live Today?â that
so tortured Macdonald. But for me, âflighty Dwightyâ Macdonald still
speaks and no more brilliantly than in âThe Root Is Man,â one of the
great lost classics of American radicalism.
Â
Kevin Coogan
To be radical is to grasp the matter by to root. Now the root for
mankind is man himself.
â Karl Marx(1844)
Shortly after the second world war began, Trotsky wrote a remarkable
article entitled âThe USSR in Warâ (see The New International, November
1939). It was and attempt to refute the theory that a new form of
society had developed in the Soviet Union, one that was neither
capitalist nor socialist (âdegenerated workersâ stateâ in Trotskyâs
phrase) but something quite distinct from either of the two classic
alternatives. This theory of a âthird alternativeâ had been foreshadowed
in certain passages of Anton Ciligaâs The Russian Enigma (Paris, 1938)
and had been developed in detail by a certain âBruno R.â in La
Bureaucratisation du Monde (Paris, 1939).[1] The proponents of the new
theory called it âbureaucratic collectivism.â
If this theory is correct, the consequences far the Marxist schema are
obviously quite serious; and so Trotsky attempted to demonstrate its
falsity. His article is remarkable because, with a boldness and a sense
of intellectual responsibility not common among present-day Marxists, he
ventured to draw the consequences for Marxism if indeed capitalismâs
heir were to be bureaucratic collectivism. More, he even dared to set a
âdeadlineâ for the long-awaited world revolution.
âThe second world war has begun,â he wrote. âIt attests incontrovertibly
to the fact that society can no longer live on the basis of capitalism.
Thereby it subjects the proletariat to a new and perhaps decisive test.
âIf this war provokes, as we firmly believe it will, a proletarian
revolution, it must inevitably lead to the overthrow of the bureaucracy
in the USSR and the regeneration of Soviet democracy on a far higher
economic and cultural basis than in 1918. In the case, the question as
to whether the Stalinist bureaucracy was a âclassâ or a parasitic growth
on the workersâ state will be automatically solved. To every single
person it will become clear that in the process of this development of
the world revolution, the Soviet bureaucracy was only an episodic
relapse.
âIf, however, it is conceded that the present war will provoke not
revolution but a decline of the proletariat, then there remains another
alternative: the further decay of monopoly capitalism, its further
fusion with the State and the replacement of democracy wherever it still
persists, by a totalitarian regime. The inability of the proletariat to
take into its hands the leadership of society could actually lead to the
growth of a new exploiting class from the Bonapartist fascist
bureaucracy. This would be, according to all indications, a regime of
decline, signalizing the eclipse of civilization....
âHowever onerous the second perspective may be, if the world proletariat
should actually prove incapable of fulfilling the mission placed upon it
by the course of development, nothing else would remain except openly to
recognize that the socialist program based on the internal
contradictions of capitalist society ended as Utopia. It is self-evident
that a new minimum program would be required â for the defense of the
interests of the slaves of the totalitarian bureaucratic society.â
The war is now ended, in unparalleled devastation, hunger, misery in
Asia and Europe, in the shattering of the old class structure of Europe
and the loosening of imperialist bonds in the colonies. Yet no
revolution has succeeded anywhere, or even been attempted; the kind of
defensive battle the EAM put up in Greece, however heroic, cannot be
called a revolution. The ârevolutionary opportunitiesâ which we
socialists expected to occur after this war have indeed materialized;
but the masses have not taken advantage of them. Although the second
world war has been far more destructive of the old order than was the
first, the level both of mass consciousness and of socialist leadership
is far lower that it was in 1917â20. Is it not striking, for example,
that the entire European resistance movement has ebbed away without
producing a single new political tendency, or a single leader of any
stature?[2]
The reasons for this decadence will be considered presently. The fact is
what concerns us now. I think it is time for socialists to face the
situation that actually exists instead of continuing to fix our eyes on
a distant future in which History will bring us at last what we want. It
is strange, by the way, that Marxists, who pride themselves on their
realism, should habitually regard the Present as merely the mean
entrance-hall to the spacious palace of the Future. For the
entrance-hall seems to stretch out interminably; it may or may not lead
to a palace; meanwhile, it is all the palace we have, and we must live
in it. I think we shall live in it better and even find the way to the
palace better (if there is a palace), if we try living in the present
instead of in the Future. To begin with, let us face the fact that
Trotskyâs deadline is here and that his revolution is not.
If, writes Trotsky, the war provokes ânot revolution but a decline of
the proletariatâ and if, consequently, Marxists must recognize that
Bureaucratic Collectivism, not Socialism, is the historical successor to
Capitalism, then: ânothing else would remain except openly to recognize
that the socialist program, based on the internal contradictions of
capitalist society, ended as a Utopia.â
This seems to me as accurate summary of the dilemma Marxists find
themselves in today. For if one bases oneâs socialist program on
capitalist contradictions, and if those contradictions conduct one not
to Socialism but the Bureaucratic Collectivism, then one has no real
basis for socialism. Also, if one assumes that history has only one
possible pattern, predictable in advance if one can discover societyâs
âlaws of motion,â then the triumph of Bureaucratic Collectivism is
Russia and its much greater strength (compared to Socialism) in other
parts of the world today â these developments force one to conclude,
with Trotsky, that totalitarianism is âtheâ future alternative to
Capitalism. In this case, Trotskyâs âminimum program...for the defense
of the interests of the slaves of totalitarianâ society is all that can
be logically attempted. Who is going to take any risks for, or even get
very interested in such an uninspiring â however worthy â program, one
that by definition can never go further than defense? Do not the Russian
and German experiences, in fact, show that such a limited program is
quite impossible under totalitarianism â that one must either go much
farther, or not stir at all?
But why not, after all, base oneâs socialism on what Trotsky
contemptuously calls âUtopianâ aspirations? Why not begin with what we
living human beings want, what we think and feel is good? And then see
how we can come closest to it â instead of looking to historical process
for a justification of our socialism? It is the purpose of this article
to show that a different approach may be made and must be made, one that
denies the existence of any such rigid pattern to history as Marxism
assumes, one that will start off from oneâs own personal interests and
feelings, working from the individual to society rather that the other
way around. Above all, its ethical dynamic come from absolute and
non-historical values, such as Truth and Justice, rather than from the
course of history.
It is only fair to say right now that readers who expect either a new
theoretical system to replace Marxism or some novel program of action
will save themselves disappointment by not reading further. All I
attempt here is to explain, as coherently as possible, why the Marxian
approach to socialism no longer satisfies me, and to indicate the
general direction in which I think a more fruitful approach may be made.
Those looking for either Certainty or Directives will find little to
interest them here.
This essay falls into two main parts.
Part I (âMarxism is Obsoleteâ), which follows immediately, argues that
Marxism is no longer a reliable guide either to radical political action
or to an understanding of modern politics. It proposes that the
traditional distinction between âLeftâ and âRightâ be replaced by a new
âProgressive-Radicalâ division, showing the confusion that comes from
trying to fit recent history into the old âLeft-Rightâ pattern. And it
attempts to show, in some detail, that Marxâs basic concepts, when they
are applied to the contemporary world, are at best beside the point and
at worst positively misleading (since their logic tends to justify the
perfect tyranny of the USSR as against the imperfect democracy of the
West).
Part II (âToward a New Radicalismâ) is an attempt to suggest an
alternative to Marxism as a political approach for those profoundly
dissatisfied with the status quo. It discusses the relationship between
scientific method and value judgments, questions that âIdea of Progressâ
that has been the basis of Left-wing thought for almost two centuries,
and tries to show why the âRadicalâ approach, based on moral feelings,
is more valid today in both ethical and political terms than the
âProgressiveâ approach, based on scientific method, that is still
dominant among American intellectuals. It also suggests certain specific
modes of political behavior and reaction that characterize this kind of
Radicalism.
The first great victory of Bureaucratic Collectivism came in 1928, when
Stalin finally drove Trotsky into exile and prepared, the following
year, to initiate the First Five Year Plan. Between the French
Revolution (1789) and 1928, political tendencies could fairly accurately
be divided into âRightâ and âLeft.â But the terms of the struggle for
human liberation shifted in 1928 â the shift had been in process long
before then, of course, but 1928 may be taken as a convenient watershed.
It was Trotskyâs failure to realize this that gave an increasingly
unreal character to his handling of âthe Russian question,â just as it
is the continued blindness of liberals and socialists to this change
that makes academic, if not worse, their present-day political behavior.
Let me try to define the 1789â1928 âLeftâ and âRight.â
The left comprised those who favored a change in social institutions
which would make the distribution of income more equal (or completely
equal) and would reduce class privileges (or do away with classes
altogether). The central intellectual concept was the validity of the
scientific method; the central moral concept was the dignity of Man and
the individualâs right to liberty and a full personal development.
Society was therefore conceived of as a means to an end: the happiness
of the individual. There were important differences in method (as,
reform v. revolution, liberalism v. class struggle) but on the above
principles the Left was pretty much agreed.
The Right was made up of those who were either satisfied with the status
quo (conservatives) or wanted it to become even more inegalitarian
(reactionaries). In the name of Authority, the Right resisted change,
and in the name of Tradition, it also, logically enough, opposed what
had become the cultural motor of change: that willingness , common alike
to Bentham and Marx, Jefferson and Kropotkin, to follow scientific
inquiry wherever it led and to reshape institutions accordingly. Those
of the Right thought in terms of an âorganicâ society, in which society
is the end and the citizen the means. they justified inequalities of
income and privilege by alleging an intrinsic inequality of individuals,
both as to abilities and human worth.
This great dividing line has become increasingly nebulous with the rise
of Nazism and Stalinism, both of which combine Left and Right elements
in a bewildering way. Or, put differently, both the old Right and the
old left have almost ceased to exist as historical realities, and their
elements have been recombined in the dominant modern tendency: an
inegalitarian and organic society in which the citizen is a means, not
an end, and whose rulers are anti-traditional and scientifically minded.
Change is accepted in principle â indeed, the unpleasant aspects of the
present are justified precisely as the price that must be paid to insure
a desirable future, whether it be Hitlerâs domination of lesser races by
the Nordics, or Stalinâs emancipation of the world working class, or our
own liberalsâ peaceful future world to be achieved through war. The
whole idea of historical process, which a century ago was the badge of
the Left, has become the most persuasive appeal of the apologists for
the status quo.
In this Left-Right hybrid, the notion of Progress is central. A more
accurate terminology might therefore be to reserve the term âRightâ for
such old-fashioned conservatives as Herbert Hoover and Winston Churchill
and to drop the term âLeftâ entirely, replacing it with two words:
âProgressiveâ and âRadical.â
By âProgressiveâ would be understood those who see the Present as an
episode on the road to a better Future; those who think more in terms of
historical process than of moral values; those who believe that the main
trouble with the world is partly lack of scientific knowledge and partly
the failure to apply to human affairs such knowledge as we do have;
those who, above all, regard the increase of manâs mastery over nature
as good is itself and see its use for bad ends, as atomic bombs, as a
perversion. This definition, I think, covers fairly well the great bulk
of what is still called the Left, from Communists (âStalinistsâ)through
reformist groups like our own New Dealers, the British Laborites, and
the European Socialists, to small revolutionary groups like the
Trotskyists.[3]
âRadicalâ would apply to the as yet few individuals â mostly anarchists,
conscientious objectors, and renegade Marxists like myself â who reject
the concept of Progress, who judge things by their present meaning and
effect, who think the ability of science to guide us in human affairs
has been overrated and who therefore redress the balance by emphasizing
the ethical aspect of politics. They, or rather we, think it is an open
question whether the increase of manâs mastery over nature is good or
bad in its actual effects on human life to date, and favor adjusting
technology to man, even if it means â as may be the case â a
technological regression, rather than adjusting man to technology. We do
not, of course, ârejectâ scientific method, as is often charged, but
rather think the scope within which it can yield fruitful results in
narrower than is generally assumed today. And we feel that the firmest
ground from which to struggle for that human liberation which was the
goal of the old Left is the ground not of History but of those
non-historical values (truth, justice, love, etc.) which Marx has made
unfashionable among socialists.
The Progressive makes History the center of his ideology. The Radical
puts Man there. The Progressiveâs attitude is optimistic both about
human nature (which he thinks is basically good, hence all that is
needed is to change institutions so as to give this goodness a chance to
work) and about the possibility of understanding history through
scientific method. The Radical is, if not exactly pessimistic, at least
more sensitive to the dual nature of man; he sees evil as well as good
at the base of human nature; he is sceptical about the ability of
science to explain things beyond a certain point; he is aware of the
tragic element in manâs fate not only today but in any conceivable kind
o society. The Progressive thinks in collective terms (the interests of
Society or the Working Class); the Radical stresses the individual
conscience and sensibility. The Progressive starts off from what
actually is happening; the Radical starts off from what he wants to
happen. The former must have the feeling that History is âon his side.â
The latter goes along the road pointed out by his own individual
conscience; if History is going his way, too, he is pleased; but he is
quite stubborn about following âwhat ought to beâ rather that âwhat is.â
Because its tragic, ethical and non-scientific emphasis corresponds
partly with the old Right attitude, leading to criticisms of Progressive
doctrine that often sound very much like those that used to be made from
the Right, the Radical viewpoint causes a good deal of confusion today.
it is sometimes called âobjectively reactionary.â It would not be hard,
however, to show the peculiar bedfellows, notably the Stalinists, the
Progressives have today. For the fact is that both the Progressive and
the radical attitudes, as here defined, cut across the old Left-Right
dividing line, and in this sense both are confusing and even
âobjectively reactionaryâ if one continues to think in the old terms.
Another frequent allegation of the Progressives, especially those of the
Marxian persuasion, is that the Radical viewpoint which politics
frequently expresses is of necessity a religious one. If by âreligiousâ
is simply meant non-materialistic or non-scientific, then this is true.
But if God and some kind of otherworldly order of reality is meant, then
I donât think it is true. The Radical viewpoint is certainly compatible
with religion, as Progressivism is not; and such radicals as D. S.
Savage and Will Herberg are religious-minded; but I personally see no
necessary connection, nor am I conscious of any particular interest in
religion myself.
I might add that the Radical approach, as I understand it at least, does
not deny the importance and validity of science in its own proper
sphere, or of historical, sociological and economic studies. Nor does it
assert that the only reality is the individual and his conscience. It
rather defines a sphere which is outside the reach of scientific
investigation, and whose value judgment cannot be proved (though they
can be demonstrated in appropriate and completely unscientific terms);
this is the traditional sphere of art and morality. The Radical sees any
movement like socialism which aspires towards an ethically superior kind
of society as rooted in that sphere, however its growth may be shaped by
historical process. This is the sphere of human, personal interests, and
in this sense, the root is man.
The best of the Marxists today see no reason for the dissection of the
old Left that is proposed here. They still hold fast to the classic Left
faith in human liberation through scientific progress, while admitting
that revisions of doctrine and refinements of method are necessary. This
was my opinion until I began publishing politics. In âThe Future of
Democratic Valuesâ (Partisan Review, July-August, 1943), I argued that
Marxism, the heir of 18^(th) century liberalism, was the only reliable
guide to a democratic future; the experience of editing this magazine,
however, and consequently being forced to follow the tragic events of
the last two years in some detail, has slowly changed my mind. The
difficulties lie much deeper, I now think, than is assumed by
Progressives, and the crisis is much more serious. The brutality and
irrationality of Western social institutions have reached a pitch which
would have seemed incredible a short generation ago; our lives have come
to be dominated by warfare of a ferocity and on a scale unprecedented in
history; horrors have been committed by the governments of civilized
nations which could hardly have been improved on by Attila: the
extermination of the Jewish people by the Nazis; the vast forced-labor
camps of the Soviet Union; our own saturation bombing of German cities
and âatomizationâ of the residents of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. It is
against this background that the present article is written; it is all
this which has forced me to question beliefs I have long held.
Let me demonstrate, by reference to recent events in various countries,
how confusing the old categories of âLeftâ and âRightâ have become, and
how inadequate the Marxian schema. As we shall see, it is not just a
matter of the working class revolution failing to materialize. The
situation is far more complex, and far more discouraging. For the full
bitterness of working class defeat is realized only in victory, a
paradox illustrated in the twenties by the Bolsheviks and the German
Social Democracy, and today by the British Labor Party.
the war, where they have not practically disappeared like the Radical
Socialists in France. In Scandinavia, Holland, Belgium, Austria, Italy,
and most of the other lesser European countries, the two great movements
with a Marxian socialist ideology, the Communists and the reformist
Socialists, dominate the political scene.
Communists and the Socialists, with the ambiguous âChristian socialistâ
MRP as the nearest thing left to a bourgeois group. The Bank of France
has been nationalized (remember the â200 familiesâ?) and further
nationalizations are in prospect.
based on the trade unions and explicitly socialist in its program; it
was elected by a landslide majority last summer and has a constitutional
expectation of holding power for the next five years. The Bank of
England has been nationalized, and the party is committed to
nationalizing steel, coal, power, the railroads and other basic
industries.
expropriating the former ruling classes to great degree and breaking
down the industrial structure on which that class rule was based; the
logic of this forces the victors to tolerate the new growth of unions
and left-wing parties which results from this weakening of the big
bourgeois. (Cf. World War I, where the victors left intact Germanyâs big
capitalism, and in fact covertly supported it as a counterweight to
âBolshevism.â)
admitted as a partner with the Kuomintang in a new âliberalizedâ regime;
the Indonesian rebellion seems to be succeeding; the British have been
forced by the gathering intensity of revolt in India to make the mot
definite proposals to date for Indian freedom.
second most powerful nation in the world, and dominates directly all of
Eastern Europe, from the Baltic to the Balkans, a vast area in which its
puppet âpeopleâs governmentsâ have broken the power of the old
bourgeoisie and divided up the big estates among the poor peasants.
more or less intact is the USA. Yet even here we see the unions holding
much more of their wartime gains than was anticipated and strong enough
to force the Federal Government to help them win postwar wage increases.
We also see the State continuing to intervene in the economy, and the
permanent acceptance, by the courts and by public opinion, of such
social measures as the Wagner Act, the Wages & Hours law, Social
Security, and Federal unemployment relief. (Cf. the aftermath of World
War I: the Palmer âRed raids,â industryâs successful âOpen Shopâ
campaign against the unions, the complete control of the government by
big business.)
In short, from the standpoint of the kind of institutional changes
Marxism stresses, the world should be closer to socialism today than
ever before.[4]
Even to the most mechanical Marxist, the above picture will appear
overdrawn. Yet this is the clearly absurd conclusion we reach if we
simply follow the Marxist stress on institutional changes. I say
âclearly absurd,â but the absurdity is apparent only in different
degrees to the various groups on the Left: the Stalinists donât see it
at all, being wholly optimistic now that Russian collectivism is on the
ascendant; the liberal weeklies are more sceptical, but on the whole see
numerous âencouragingâ features in these changes; the Socialists and
Trotskyists are the most critical of all, but find consolation in such
things as the British Labor Party victory and the strength shown by the
CIO in the recent strikes. All of these groups are, in my opinion, too
optimistic about the state of the world; and their optimism stems from
the fact that they all share a common âprogressiveâ viewpoint inherited
mostly from Marx.
Those of us, however, who look at the human content rather that the
historical form, who think in terms of values rather than of process,
believe that socialism today is farther away than ever. War and the
preparation of war has become the normal mode of existence of great
nations. There is a general collapse of the old dreams of international
brotherhood. Nationalism is constantly becoming more virulent, until
even the persecuted minorities like the Negros and Jews are developing,
in their despair, chauvinisms of their own. A sauve-qui-peut philosophy
flourishes everywhere; everyone today is a two-bit realpolitiker. In
this country and abroad, significant sections of the working class stood
out against World War I, but the British and American labor movements
were almost solidly behind World War II. The power of the State has
never been greater the helplessness of the great mass of citizens never
more extreme. All these sinister trends find their intense expression in
the one great non-capitalist nation, the USSR, where science is
worshiped and industrial production is God, where nationalism has
reached a paranoiac pitch, where imperialistic policy is more aggressive
then anywhere else on earth, where 180 million people live in a
combination barracks and munitions plant over which floats the red
banner of Marxian revolution.[5]
If the present tendency of history works out its logic unchecked, then
in the USSR we have the image of the future society. I do not know of a
single party or movement of any size in the world today that is working
to check this tendency in the only way I think it can be checked:
through changing our present social structure in a libertarian socialist
direction.[6]
Nowhere is there visible a party of any size which even aspires â let
alone has the power to do so â to shatter the institutions, beginning
with the nation State, who blind workings are bringing on the next war.
All we ave on the Left is still that banal and hopeless clash of two
unsatisfactory alternatives: the totalitarian heirs of Bolshevism, and
those sapless sons of ineffectual fathers, the liblabs[7] and
socialists.
It will not do to lay the chief blame for this collapse on Stalinist
âbetrayalâ or even on the overwhelming amount of military force in the
hands of the Big Three. What has happened is that the traditional
aspirations which dominate Marxian ideology has implanted in the masses
of Europe have come to coincide to a dangerous degree with the interests
of their rulers, so that the tribunes of the people find themselves in
the absurd and demoralizing position of demanding what will be granted
anyway. They have no vocabulary with which to ask for the things what
are today really in the interests of the oppressed â and which will not
be granted from above.
The social systems of the victorious powers are developing a common
tendency towards a planned, State-controlled economy which considers the
citizen a cell in the social organism and thus at once the ward of the
State, entitled to a job and to average living standards in exchange for
his usefulness in production on the armed forces, and also the Stateâs
docile instrument who could no more rebel than a cell could develop
independently of the total organism. If this latter does happen, modern
political theory agrees with biology in calling the result cancer, which
must be cut out lest the organism die. The Organic State is directed
towards one great end: to assert effectively against other competing
States its own nationalistic interests, which mean preparation for World
War III. All this is a matter of common knowledge in upper-class circles
in the USA, the USSR and other big powers, although, for obvious
reasons, it is not discussed in public.
Now, with such a society developing, what kind of demands do the
tribunes of people put forth today? Do they proclaim a new Rights of
Man? Do they turn pacifist, denounce war as the greatest of evils,
insist on immediate disarmament, beginning with their own country,
expose the fraudulent character if World War II? Do they agitate for
greater freedom of the the press and opinion? Do they push toward
decentralization of industry until its scale becomes human, regardless
of the effects on munitions production? Do they take up arms against the
growing powers of the State? Do they fight against the growth of
nationalism?
These are, of course, rhetorical questions. The reformist movements like
the British Labor Party and our own labor unions are apathetic on such
issues. The Communists are not apathetic; they are intensely hostile.
What kind of aims do both liblabs and Communists actually have? They
want Full Production, Nationalization, Planning, and above all Security,
of both the Social and National varieties. These is nothing in these
demands incompatible with the interests of the ruling class in
organizing a strong nation to compete militarily with other nations.
There are antagonisms, it is true, sharp and sometimes bloody battles.
But these clashes are on secondary issues; they do not affect the trend
towards war and social regimentation. For the struggle is not over a new
kind of society, but over who is to dominate the existing society, the
Old Guard or the Tribunes of the People. It is becoming increasingly
difficult to distinguish the âRightâ from the âLeftâ wing.
The reason for this confusion is basically simple: the historical
process to which the Left has traditionally looked for progress in a
desirable direction has been going on but the result is often not
progress but the reverse. The liberals put their faith is social and
economic reforms; these are being made, but often go hand in hand with
moral barbarism. The Marxists looked to the expropriation of the
bourgeois; this is taking place, but new and in many ways even more
oppressive rulers are replacing the old ones. We are all in the position
of a man going upstairs who thinks there is another step, and finds
there is not. We are off balance. How far may be suggested by some
random examples.
the Tories once it got into power has been described in politics
already. (See the September and November, 1945, issues.) One tiny recent
news item may be added: âLondon, March 7: Britainâs secret service will
cost about $10,000,000 during the coming year, according to government
civil estimates published today. This is five times more than was spent
in 1939.â
19 cabinet ministers are former trade union officials. This government
carries out a âWhite Australiaâ policy, i.e.,complete exclusion of all
immigrants with brown, black, or yellow skins. It also complains that
the reactionary General MacArthur is âtoo softâ on the defeated Japanese
people.
office since 1935, and has put through a great deal of very âadvancedâ
social legislation. It also bans all Asiatic immigrants.
âthe Bolivian Patternâ: the putsch by fascist-minded Army officers which
overthrew the former conservative regime backed by native big business
and the U.S. State Department. The revolutionaries were anti-USA,
anti-capitalist...and anti-Semitic. When they took power, they shot one
of the âbig threeâ tin magnates, passed Boliviaâs first laws favoring
the exploited Indian tin miners...and strengthened the Army. Currently
in Argentina we see the pro-Nazi, dictatorial Army boss, Peron, leading
a working class movement against the bourgeoisie, decreeing enormous
wage advances, trampling on property rights, and getting himself
overwhelmingly elected president in the first honest election in years.
The opposing candidate, Tamborini, was backed by Argentine big business,
the U.S. State Department...and The Nation.
Rights of Man. Last summer the dying act of the French resistance
movement was the fiasco of the âEstates General of the French
Renaissance,â a convention which rashly challenged comparison with the
great Estates General of 1789. Out of it cam a âProclamation and Oathâ
which merely mentioned in passing âequality of rights for all human
beings,â devoting itself to those two great themes of modern
Progressivism: patriotism and production. Quote: âThe independence and
prosperity of the nation, the conditions for its power, depend upon the
unity of all Frenchmen, who must be linked by a common patriotic
aspiration.... The Estates General proclaim: the people may remain
master of their own destiny only if they become mobilized in a patriotic
and enthusiastic spirit, making a determined effort to increase
production. It is the sacred duty of each man and woman to protest
against anything which could impede this effort.â This is not the Comite
des Forges speaking, but the Communists and Socialists. These Leftists
have fulfilled their sacred duty by protesting against...the freedom of
the press. They are the ones who have insisted on making a government
license a prerequisite of publication. If they reply that this is to
prevent big business and former collaborationists from corrupting the
press, one might ask why the Trotskyists and Anarchists have been denied
licenses. When the Constituent Assembly opened debate on the preamble to
the new Constitution, The New York Times reported (March 7, 1946): âThe
discussion appeared confused by reason of the fact that the moderates
and members of the reactionary groups seemed to be defending the
âimmortal principlesâ of the âillustrious ancestorsâ of the 1789, while
the extremists of the Left were demanding restrictions on some of those
liberties championed for generations by the sons of the revolution.â The
rewrite job on the Rights of Man, which eliminated free speech and such
luxuries, was done by a commission composed only of Communists and
Socialists. Copeau, a Resistance leader, âasserted that the rights of
1789 were typically bourgeois whereas the situation today required
social protection and adaptation to a coming Marxist society.â The fight
for a free press was led by old Edouard Herriot, leader of the almost
defunct bourgeois party, the Radical Socialists, who made an eloquent
speech which the Right applauded and the Left heard in a disapproving
silence.[8]
It is revealing to compare Left-Right attitudes in World War I with
those in World War II.
In World War I, these attitudes were consistent in themselves and
cleanly opposed to each other. The Right was chauvinist â after all, as
the ruling class, they felt it was their country â and favored the war
for the simplest, most straightforward economic motives (competition,
âmerchants of deathâ â the complete absence of the latter phrase in
World War II is significant). The bulk of the Left submitted to the
ânecessityâ of the war, since it was unwilling to take a revolutionary
anti-war stand, but its attitude was passive, rather shamefaced. Before
the war, the Right was a militarist and favored a âforwardâ foreign
policy, while the Left was pacifist and anti-imperialist. After the war,
the Right pressed for a Carthaginian peace (or what passed for such in
those innocent days) and emphasized the collective responsibility of the
German people, while the Left tries to lighten reparations and to limit
war guilt to the German ruling classes.
The situation in World War II was much more complex, because in the
interim two phenomena had arisen which cut across the old alignments:
the bureaucratic-collective dictatorships of Hitler and Stalin. The
Franco-Anglo-American bourgeoisie had seen the Kaiserâs Germany as
simply an imperialist competitor, but towards Hitler they had an
ambivalent attitude. Insofar as he was a powerful competitor, they
opposed him, but they supported him insofar as he had created an
âorderlyâ society by liquidating his own Left and insofar as he seemed
to be preparing for war against the USSR. Through Munich, indeed right
up to Hitlerâs attack on Poland and in some cases even later, the Right
saw Hitler mainly as an ally against the Left, specifically against the
USSR. They put up with his aggressions, therefore, and failed to arm
against him. On the other hand, they didnât trust him enough to join him
in a war against Russia, as the Marxists (and Hitler) had supposed they
would. They correctly saw that Nazism was something new (and dangerous
to them), not just an extreme form of monopoly capitalism. So they were
unable to act at all. The Left was also paralyzed by the cross-currents
set up by these new phenomena which didnât fit into the old Left-Right
pattern. On the one hand, it opposed Hitler for the same reasons the
Right favored him, and demanded âcollective securityâ and a firm stand
against Nazi aggression. At the same time, the disillusionment with
World War I was still strong enough to make its general feeling about
war negative; also, its whole tradition was anti-war.
When war came â after Stalinâs pact with Hitler had shown the political
ambiguity of these new societies â it was the traditionally war-hating
Left which was enthusiastic about the war, while the traditionally
bellicose Right went into it with much the same reluctance the Left had
shown in World War I, and for much the same reasons: they could see no
way to avoid it, and yet they felt that their class interests would not
be advanced by it. The Left, furthermore, was able to prosecute the war
more effectively because the high degree of State control a modern war
necessitates fitted in better with its ideology. So in this country, we
see the Left, which in the early thirties had applauded the Nye
Committeeâs exposure of the âmerchants of death,â becoming increasingly
belligerent after Rooseveltâs Chicago speech (1937), while the
Republican Right was almost solidly isolationist. The British Tories
were the architects of Munich; it took the collaboration of the Labor
Party to put real and real vigor and heart into the British war effort.
In France, the contrast was even sharper. âBetween the years 1933 and
1938,â writes Charles Micaud in his recent study, The French Right and
Nazi Germany, âthere took place a complete change in the foreign policy
of the majority of the Right as well as in that of the Left: the
nationalist Right began to preach pacifism, and the pacifist Left to
urge Resistance. âThe reversal of these attitudes,â wrote M. Pierre
Brossolete in LâEurope Nouvelle shortly before Munich, âhas been of a
prodigious suddenness.... And so it is today one can see the most
serious organs of the Right speak of a âLeftist bellicism,â while the
Left returns to the Right their old accusation of being âin the service
of Germany.âââ
The same reversal may be observed in our own postwar policies. The Right
favors a relatively âsoft peace,â partly because it never believed in
the war as an antifascist crusade, and partly because it hopes to make
Germany a barrier to Russian advance; while the Left insists on the
collective responsibility of the German people and presses for
vengeance. The CIO, like the British TUC, has put on record its belief
in the war guilt of the German people. It is Rightists like President
Hutchins, of the University of Chicago, and Senator Wheeler, who
expresses indignation at the extremes to which the victors are going in
Germany; the Rightist Republican Senator Wherry makes speeches about our
policy of starving Europe, especially Germany, which read like
editorials from this magazine. It is the liberal Senator Kilgore who
defends the use of German slave labor, and it is Mrs. Roosevelt who
praises Louis Nizerâs racial tirade against Germans and minimizes the
current starvation in Germany. The actual proposals for postwar Germany
of the reactionary German-baiter, Vansittart, are positively humane
compared with those of the New Dealer, Morgenthau (who recently joined
the committee to feed the General Motors strikers), while the Leftist
paper, P.M., has far outstripped the Hearst press in its
hate-the-Germans-and-Japs campaign.[9] On the other issue of peacetime
conscription, it is the Right Republican Senator Taft who leads the
fight against it, and the Republican floor leader in the House, Martin,
who proposes an international agreement to abolish conscription
everywhere; while the New Dealers, led by first Roosevelt and now
Truman, line up behind the General Staff in favor of conscription.
Both in culture and in politics, Marxism today exercises as
extraordinary influence. In the âsocial sciences,â the
historical-materialist approach first developed by Marx is widely
accepted. (See, for example, my note on âThe Revival of Political
Economyâ in politics for March 1944.) Many workers in these fields who
would be horrified at the idea of being Marxist nonetheless think in the
tradition he established â filtered down (and watered down) through more
ârespectableâ thinkers, as, for example, Weber and Mannheim in
sociology. As for the influence of Marxism in world politics today, I
have already tried to show that in detail.
This strange flickering-up of Marxist concepts, at a time when Marxâs
ethical aims are in ashes, is the afterglow of a great historical period
that is going down in darkness. Marxism is the most profound expression
of what has been the dominant theme in Western culture since the 18^(th)
century: the belief that the advance of science, with the resulting
increase of manâs mastery over nature, is the climax of a historical
pattern of Progress. If we have come to question this pattern, before we
can find any new roads, we must first reject the magnificent system
which Marx elaborated on its basis. A break with a whole cultural
tradition is involved, and Marxism looms up as the last and greatest
systematic defense of that tradition. We who reject Marxism are indebted
to Marx for the very fact that the boldness and intellectual grandeur of
his work make it possible for us to formulate more clearly our own
position in the the process of distinguishing it from his; this is the
service which and great thinker renders to his critics. I know of no
better way to come to the heart of our modern dilemma than by showing
the defects of the Marxian solution.
Marxism is not simply, or even primarily, an interpretation of history.
It is a guide to political action. The worst fate that can befall a
philosophy of action is for it to become ambiguous. This is what has
happened to Marxism. Its ambiguity stems from the fact that Marxâs
ethical aims have not been realized â quite the contrary! â while the
historical process by which he thought they would be realized has to a
large extent worked out as he predicted it would. It is possible to
reach opposite conclusions, on the basis of Marxism, about Soviet
Russia, depending on whether one emphasizes Marxâs ethical values or his
idea of the historical process. Since Marx himself made the process
significant rather than the values, the Stalinists would seem to have a
somewhat better claim to be the ârealâ Marxists than their more
ethically-minded opponents. But the point is not which is âreallyâ the
Marxist view; the point is that each view may be maintained, on the
basis of Marxâs thought, with a good deal of reason. There is an
ambiguity here, fatal to a philosophy conceived as a basis for action,
which was not apparent during Marxâs lifetime, when history seemed to be
going his way, but which is all too clear now that history is going
contrary to socialist values.
Marxâs vision of a good society was essentially the same as that of the
anarchists, the Utopian socialists, and the great 18^(th) century
liberals â also as that of those today whom I call âRadicals.â The same
theme runs through his writings from beginning to end. The Communist
Manifesto (1848): âan association in which the free development of each
is the condition for the free development of all.â Capital, Vol. I
(1867): âa society in which the full and free development of every
individual becomes the ruling principle...production by freely
associated men.â The Critique of the Gotha Program (1875) gives us the
most explicit and famous formulation:
âIn a higher phase of communist society, after the enslaving
subordination of individuals under division of labor, and therewith also
the antithesis between mental and physical labor, has vanished; after
labor, from a means of life, has itself become the prime necessity of
life; after the productive forces have also increased with the all-round
development of the individual, and all the springs of cooperative wealth
flow more abundantly â only then can the narrow horizon of bourgeois
right be fully left behind and society inscribe on its banners: from
each according to his ability, to each according to his needs.â
The political seal of this future society would be the elimination of
all forms of coercion, i.e., the withering away of the State. Some
critics of Marx, in particular certain anarchists whose sectarian
intemperance matches that of certain Marxists, make him out an
ideological apologist for the State. There is indeed a potential towards
Statism in Marxism, but it lies not is Marxâs values, but, as I shall
show presently, in his âhistoricalâ method of thinking about those
values. From the splendid polemic against Hegelâs Philosophy of Law in
1844 to the Gotha Critique thirty years later, Marx consistently
criticized Statism from the standpoint of human liberation. As a
moralist, Marx viewed the individual as the End and society as the
Means.
So much for Marxâs ethical aims. I think it needs no demonstration that
such a society is farther off today than it was in Marxâs time. Now what
about the way Marx conceived the historical process that would realize
these aims? Two passages will give us the grand outlines:
âAt a certain stage of their development, the material forms of
production in society come into conflict with the existing relations of
production or â what is but a legal expression for the same thing â with
the property relations within which they had been at work before. From
forms of development of the forces of production, these relations turn
into their fetter. Then comes the period of social revolution. With the
change of the economic foundation, the entire immense superstructure in
more or less rapidly transformed....In broad outline we can designate
the Asiatic, the ancient, the feudal, and the modern bourgeois methods
of production as so many epochs in the progress of the economics
formation of society. The bourgeois relations of production are the last
antagonistic form of the social process of production â antagonistic not
in the sense of individual antagonism, but of one arising from
conditions surrounding the life of individuals in society. At the same
time, the productive forces developing in the womb of bourgeois society
create the material conditions for the solution of that antagonism. This
social formation constitutes, therefore, the closing chapter of the
prehistoric stage of human society.â (Marxâs Preface to a Contribution
to the Critique of Political Economy.)
âAlong with the constantly diminishing number of magnates of
capital...grows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation,
exploitation; but with this too grows the revolt of the working class, a
class always increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organized
by the very mechanism of the process of capitalist production itself.
The monopoly of capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production....
Centralization of the means of production and socialization of labor at
last reach a point where they become incompatible with their capitalist
integument. This integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist
private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated.... The
transformation of scattered private property, arising from individual
labor, into capitalist private property is, naturally, a process
incomparably more protracted, violent and difficult than the
transformation of capitalistic private property, already practically
resting on socialised production, into socialised property. In the
former case, we had the expropriation of the mass of the people by a few
usurpers; in the latter, we have the expropriation of a few usurpers by
the mass of people.â (Capital, Vol. I.)
Two aspects of the passages concern us here: (1) the assumption that
there is a progressive evolution in history from worse to better; (2)
the description of how the overthrow of capitalism, the final step in
this evolution, would come about.
(1) The belief in Progress is central to Marxâs thought, although his
more sophisticated followers today, for understandable reasons, say as
little as possible about it. As I shall show later on, Marxâs concept of
historical Progress has not only proved to be empirically false, but it
has also been used by the Communists as an ideology to justify the most
atrocious policies. So long as we are bemused by the will-o-the-wisp of
Progress, we can never become truly radical, we can never make man the
root.
(2) Marx predicted that the contradiction between the increasing
productivity of industry and the forms of private property would âburst
asunderâ the capitalist âintegumentâ and lead to âsocialised property.â
The agency that would accomplish this change would be the proletariat,
lashed to the task by increasing misery and historically fitted for it
by the fact that collectivism was to its interest as a class (and, so
far as Marx ever states, to the interest of no other class). The result
of the change would be a nonantagonistic form of social production in
which, for the first time in history, the masses would expropriate âa
few usurpersâ instead of the other way around. As we have seen already
in this article, private capitalism is indeed decaying and the bourgeois
are being expropriated, but the agency is not the proletariat but rather
a new political ruling class which is substituting its rule for the old
ruling class in the time-honored way. The process on which Marx banked
so heavily is being brought about from the top, not the bottom, and is
directed toward nationalism and war. The result is not the liberation of
the masses but their even more complete enslavement, not the coming of
the Kingdom of Freedom but the creation of an even more crushing Kingdom
of Necessity. The external process is working out, but the inner spirit
is the reverse of what Marx expected.
The weakness of Marxism seems to me to be precisely its most distinctive
contribution to socialist thinking: the expectation that external,
materialistic factors (such as changes in class and property
relationships) will bring about certain desired results with âiron
necessity.â Ends, values, cannot safely be treated only as functions of
materialistic factors but must be defined and communicated in their own
terms. Even that concept of change, the essence of his dialectical
method, which Marx thought was intrinsically progressive, has become
ambiguous. One is attracted to his âcritical and revolutionaryâ spirit
which âlets nothing impose on itâ â and yet one cannot but recall that
the Nazis were revolutionaries in their own way, who considered nothing
sacrosanct, who let nothing impose on them, and whose only principle was
a willingness to change anything at any time. This problem of how one
roots oneâs values, which will be treated more extensively later on,
seems to me to be the heart of âthe question of Marxism.â
When Marx concentrated his great intellectual powers on the economic
process of capitalism, he thought he was building on a rock. In the
preface to Capital he quotes approvingly from a Russian review: âThe one
thing which is of moment to Marx is to find the law of phenomena with
whose investigation he is concerned.... This law once discovered, he
investigates in detail the effects in which it manifests itself in
social life. Consequently, Marx only troubles himself about one thing:
to show, by rigid scientific investigation, the necessity of successive
determinate orders of social conditions.... Marx treats the social
movement as a process of natural history, governed by laws not only
independent of human will, consciousness and intelligence, but rather on
the contrary, determining that will, consciousness and intelligence....
The scientific value of such an inquiry lies in the disclosing of the
special laws that regulate the origin, existence, development and death
of a given social organism and its replacement by another and higher
one.â The optimism of the 19^(th) century, both about Progress and about
the possibilities of scientific inquiry, is strikingly expressed here.
Also the influence of Darwinâs evolutionary theory on Marx, with its
reinforcement of the idea of Progress that had arisen in the 18^(th)
century and its emphasis on external environmental factors over human
consciousness. In the same preface, Marx grandiosely writes of âthe
natural laws of capitalist production...working with iron necessity
towards inevitable results.â The necessity has proved to be putty, the
results quite evitable. The rock of Historical Process on which Marx
built his house has turned out to be sand.
It is sometimes said in defense of Marx on this point that he did not
predict the inevitable victory of socialism but rather said that the
choice before mankind was either socialism or barbarism; and that today
we are getting the latter. but what did âbarbarismâ mean to Marx? From
the context of his whole thought, I venture to say it meant
disorganization, chaos, a regression in the scientific-technological
sphere â the sort of thing that took place after the fall of the Roman
Empire. But what we see today is just the opposite: it is the very
triumph of scientific organization of matter (and of men) that is the
root of our trouble; and the greatest triumph of applied science in
generations, the splitting of the atom, may bring us to utter
destruction. Nor is there anything chaotic or disorganized about Soviet
Russia, where ethical barbarism is nonetheless at its height.
How unlikely, furthermore, this alternative of âbarbarismâ appeared to
be to Marx and Engels is evident in the slight attention they gave it.
They threw it in, perhaps from scientific caution, perhaps to heighten
the attractiveness of socialism, but they never bothered to define it,
and it runs counter to the general optimistic spirit of their work. Marx
spent most of his life investigating the âlaws of motionâ of capitalism;
this investment was justified by his assumption that if he could show,
as he did, that these were working to destroy capitalism, he had also
demonstrated the âiron necessityâ of socialism.
In the following three sections, I try to show that (1) the working
class has âcome of ageâ without advancing us towards socialism; (2) a
great shift away from capitalism is taking place without advancing us
towards socialism; (3) modern war, far from offering ârevolutionary
opportunitiesâ for socialism, is creating new conditions which make the
struggle for socialism even more difficult. This failure of history to
take the anticipated course might not be fatal to some systems of
political thought but it is so to Marxism, because that system is built
not on ethical principles but on the historical process itself.
It was to the working class that Marx looked to bring in a better
society. And it is in that direction that his followers today still
look, as a glance at the minute coverage of labor news in almost any
Marxist organ will show. I think it is time for us to recognize that,
although the working class is certainly an element in any reconstitution
of society along more tolerable lines, it is not now, and possibly never
was, the element Marx thought it was. The evidence for this is familiar,
and most Marxists will admit almost every item in detail. They shrink,
however, and understandably enough, from drawing the logical but
unpleasant conclusions that follow. In my opinion, the weight that Marx
attached to the proletariat was excessive economically in that the
organization of the workers into unions has failed to develop into the
broader kind of action Marx expected it to. And it was excessively
politically is that neither the reformist nor the Bolshevik tactic has
led to the hoped-for results.
In the resolution on trade unions he drew up for the Geneva conference
(1866) of the First International, Marx wrote that âwhile the immediate
objectâ of trade unions is âconfined to everyday necessities...to
questions of wages and time of labor,â they must also broaden their
objectives and âconvince the world at large that their efforts, far from
being narrow and selfish, aim at the emancipation of the downtrodden
millions.â For, he continued: âIf the trade unions are required for
guerrilla fights between capital and labor, they are still more
important as organized agencies for superseding the very system of wage
labor.... They must now learn to act deliberately as organizing centers
of the working class in the broad interest of its complete
emancipation.â Engels wrote to Bebel in similar strain (March 18, 1875),
describing the trade union as âthe real organization of the proletariat,
in which it carries on its daily struggles with capital, in which it
trains itself, and which nowadays even amid the worst reaction â as in
Paris at the present â can simply no longer be smashed.â
Engels was partially right: unions can no longer be âsimplyâ smashed;
they tend, indeed, to become ever stronger as capitalism matures. But
this increasing strength has not led in any way to the âemancipation of
the downtrodden millions.â In England the ânew unionismâ which began
with the great dock strikes of 1889 led by socialists like Tim Mann and
John Burns, and which the aged Engels hopefully saluted in the preface
to the 1892 edition of The Condition of the British Working Class in
1844 â this movement towards industrial unionism of the most oppressed
parts of the British proletariat laid the foundations for...the British
Labor Party. In Germany, the debacle of the mighty Social-Democratic
trade union movement, on which Marx and Engels placed their main hope
for socialist leadership, hardly needs underlining here. Nor is it
necessary to elaborate on the evolution â devolution, rather â of our
own CIO, which ten years ago unionized the millions of industrial
workers who form the backbone of the American working class, and which
in that short space of time has recapitulated the history of European
trade unionism, from the rebellious youth to bureaucratic senility.
Instead of broadening their objectives, as Marx expected them to, and
aspiring finally to âthe emancipation of the downtrodden millions,â
unions have usually followed precisely the opposite course. At least, in
the instances cited above, it is striking how in each case the early
struggle to establish unions had an anti-capitalist character which more
and more disappeared as time went on. The evolution has been at first
into simple pressure groups fighting for laborâs interests against the
rest of society (which does not by any means consist only of bankers in
silk hats) and with an attitude of devil take the hindmost so long as
âwe get oursâ; Lewisâ United Mine Workers and the old-line A.F. of L.
unions are still in this stage. There is also a later stage, more
typical of mature capitalism, which indeed involves the assumption of a
broad social responsibility, but as an integral part of capitalism
rather than a force for laborâs emancipation from capitalism.
Industrialists often find it advantageous to have their work force
controlled by a âresponsibleâ union bureaucracy with whom they can deal
on a âreasonableâ basis â in England, for example, the employer himself
often makes union membership a condition of employment. The State also
finds unions of great value as agencies of control, especially in
wartime. In short, the modern union is a bureaucratized
mass-organization which simply extends the conventional patterns of
society into the working class and has little significance as as
expression of a specific working class consciousness. It may be a
narrowminded economic pressure-group, or, more typically, the kind of to
a disintegrating status quo the Social Democracy was in Weimar Germany
and the TUC is today in somewhat similar circumstances in England. In
either case, what it has to do with either socialism or revolution is
obscure.
The most obvious fact about the Proletarian Revolution is that it has
never occurred.[10] Such revolutions as have taken place have not
followed the working class pattern which Marxism anticipates. The Paris
Commune had a very mixed class character and materialized more along the
line of Blanqui or Proudhon than of Marx. The other revolutionary
upheavals have been in the least advanced, not the most advanced,
countries, and have therefore had a mixed peasant-worker character
(Russia, China, Spain). These revolutions in backward lands have either
failed or produced new tyrannies; the Marxist explanation is that the
low level of economic development made socialism impossible. But when
countries are highly developed, their workers donât make revolutions at
all.
The proletarian revolution today is even less of a historical
possibility than it was in 1900. The first world war was the turning
point. The reformist-socialist movements of Europe, by supporting their
capitalist governments in that war, permanently discredited the Second
International. It looked for as time as though the situation had been
saved by the revolutionary wing of Marxism, as represented by the
Bolsheviks. Lenin had at least understood that the working class by
itself could develop no further than trade union consciousness; this
was, as has been pointed out by Max Eastman in his Marx, Lenin and the
Science of Revolution (1925), a basic revision of Marx. The early years
of the Russian revolution were in many ways inspiring. But the
revolution failed to spread to more advanced countries, and the dangers
of bureaucracy and dictatorship which Marxian critics of Leninism like
Rosa Luxemburg and Otto Ruhle had correctly predicted as a consequence
of the ârevolutionary eliteâ theory by which Lenin had tried to repair
the defect in Marxâs idea of the working class â these became more and
more dominant.
In 1928, Stalin signalized his complete victory over Trotsky by exiling
the latter. The failure turned out to have been merely delayed; and when
it came, it was much worse that the reformist failure. The existence of
the Soviet Union is today the worst threat to socialism and the most
confusing factor in any attempts at advance, because Stalinism is not
only a much stronger and more ruthless and determined enemy than the
Second International reformists ever were, but it is also thought by
millions of workers and sincere socialists to be not foe but friend.
This ambiguity is its most dangerous feature.
For the last thirty years, socialism in America has been an âas ifâ
movement; we middle class intellectuals who have comprised its main body
of adherents have generally behaved âas ifâ our movement were a
historical reality. It has not been anything of the sort since 1918;
that is, socialism of any variety has not in that period influenced the
behavior of a historically significant number of Americans; even the
Communists, despite the material and psychological help of their success
in Russian, have never played the role in the trade union movement or in
national politics which the pre-war radical groups played. After the
first world war, American Radicalism lost its mass roots. This fact
should always be kept in mind in evaluating the American leftist
movement; it explains many things.
Between the Civil War and World War I, there arose various mass
movements in America based on the perspective of fundamental social
change: the Knights of Labor, the IWW, the Socialist Party of Debs. In
1910, for example, the Socialist Party had 58,000 dues-paying members,
29 English and 22 foreign-language weeklies, and 3 English and 6
foreign-language dailies. By 1912, the party membership was 126,000;
Debs got almost a million votes that year for President of the USA; such
powerful unions as the United Mine Workers were predominantly socialist,
and at that yearâs A.F. of L. convention the Socialist candidate,
running against Gompers for the presidency, got over one-third of the
votes. (Walter Lippmann is 1913 was not only a Socialist, but a leftwing
Socialist who protested the partyâs expulsion of Big Bill Haywood for
preaching class-war violence.) In the last American presidential
election, the Socialist candidate got less votes than there were
dues-paying party members in 1910. The Wobblies (IWW) have been even
more completely eclipsed: before World War I, they were a major force in
American labor, leading strikes involving hundreds of thousands of
industrial workers, preaching (and practicing) an uncompromising
class-war doctrine based on a libertarian, practically anarchist,
philosophy. Today they are almost extinct. I cannot here go into the
reasons for this depressing evolution â though it is interesting to note
, in connection with the section of this article devoted to the question
of war, that the first world was unquestionably was the greatest factor.
American radicalism was making great strides right up to 1914; the war
was the rock on which it shattered.[11]
The same pattern is found in the history of American trade unionism.
Gompers and all of his associates in founding the A.F. of L. were
Marxists, and many of them were active members of the First
International. In his autobiography, Gompers writes, âIn the early
seventies, New York City looked like Paris during the Commune.â He
describes the seething mass of Garibaldi redshirts, Irish home-rulers,
Germany âforty-eighters,â Russian and Austrian revolutionaries who made
New York âthe cradle of the modern American labor movement.â When
Gompers went to Ferdinand Laurell, the âmental guide through many of my
early strugglesâ to whom he dedicates his book, and asked for âsomething
fundamental, something upon which one could base a constructive
program,â he was given...The Communist Manifesto. âThat document brought
me an interpretation of much that before had been only inarticulate
feeling. This insight into a hidden world of thought aroused me to
master the German language in order that I might read for myself.... I
real all the German economic literature that I could lay my hands on â
Marx, Engels, Lassalle and others....â Marxism was the theoretical base
on which Gompers and his friends founded the A.F. of L. Their main
objection to the Knights of Labor was its amorphous class character and
its lack of a specifically working class program.[12]
The first step towards the A.F. of L. was taken in 1875 when the Gompers
group circulated a call to a conference of trade unionists. This letter
begins: âThroughout the history of the United State, there exist
numerous organized bodies of workingmen who declare that the present
degraded dependence of the workingman upon the capitalist for the means
of livelihood is the cause of the greater part of the intellectual,
moral and economic degradation that afflicts society, that every
political movement must be subordinate to the first great social end,
viz., the economic emancipation of the working class.â And the preamble
to the constitution which the A.F. of L. adopted ten years later â and
which is still its official program â begins with an echo of the thunder
of The Communist Manifesto: âA struggle is going on in all nations of
the civilized world between the oppressors and the oppressed... the
capitalist and the laborer.â
Compare the preamble to the constitution of an exceptionally militant
and progressive present-day union, the United Automobile Workers. This
begins not with an echo of The Communist Manifesto but with a literal
reproduction of...the Declaration of Independence â self-evident truths,
life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness, and all the rest. But even
the 1776 brand of radicalism is too strong for these modern
proletarians: they include the statement about governments âderiving
their just powers from the consent of the governed,â but they omit the
rest of the sentence, which declares that the people have a right to
overthrow a government if they donât like it. The builders of the new
Jefferson Memorial in Washington made precisely the same excision when
they cut this quotation into the marble wall of that pompous edifice.
But the auto workers go them one better: they actually substitute for
Jeffersonâs subversive idea, the following: âWithin the orderly process
of such Government lies the hope of the worker.â The rest of their
preamble is in the same spirit. Far from unions being called on to
change society, the growth of unionism itself is presented as evidence
of such a change already accomplished! (âWe believe the right of the
workers to organize for mutual protection is...evidence...of an economic
and social change in our civilization.â) These proletarians roar gently
as any sucking dove. They have nothing against capitalism or the wage
system; all they want is âa mutually satisfactory and beneficial
employer-employee relationshipâ and âa place at the conference table,
together with management.â And this is in many ways the most
class-conscious union in the country!
âThe grandiose economic crisis, acquiring the character of a social
crisis,â wrote Trotsky in 1931, âwill inevitably become transformed into
the crisis of the political consciousness of the American working
class.â Fifteen years later, some 150,000 American proletarians, each
carrying a union card, labored for many months on an unknown product in
the plants of the âManhattan Districtâ project. When the first atomic
bombing revealed to them what they had been making, they reacted with
patriotic cheers. There may have been other reactions, but I have seen
no reports of them. Furthermore, the petit-bourgeois scientists who
developed The Bomb have expressed the utmost concern over the effects of
their creation â forming associations, issuing statements, proposing
various policies, trying to arouse the public. But I have seen not a
single protest, recommendation, or any other expression from the union
locals that worked on The Bomb.[13]
A form of society has come into being which is not Socialist but rather
an even more oppressive form of class society than Capitalism, and yet
which has resolved those economic contradictions on which Marx based his
expectation of progress to socialism. It is a âthird alternativeâ to
both capitalism and socialism. So far we have had two examples, one in a
backward country (Russia under Stalin), the other in the most advanced
nation of Europe (Nazi Germany after 1936). Tendencies in the same
direction, which may be called âBureaucratic Collectivism,â have been
growing in other nations: the Keynesian economic policies of the New
Deal, the postwar nationalization trend in England and on the continent.
The dominance of war and the preparation for war in the last decade, and
the continuance of this pattern as the tension between the Russian and
the Anglo-American bloc grows â these factors stimulate Bureaucratic
Collectivist tendencies. For if Capitalism was primarily a new method of
producing and distributing the products of industry, Bureaucratic
Collectivism might be regarded as a new method of organizing national
resources â human, cultural, economic â for effective warmaking. Since I
do not see in history the dialectical progressive pattern Marx found
there, and so can see a number of possible alternatives at any given
point in history, Bureaucratic Collectivism does not appear to me (as it
does to Marxists and to Marxists-turned-inside-out like James Burnham)
the sole and inevitable successor to capitalism. Libertarian socialism
may be another alternative at certain times and places under certain
conditions. Therefore, I do not draw the hopeless conclusion Trotsky,
for instance, does as to the future if Bureaucratic Collectivism is
historically âviable.â All that one can say at present, and it is not
precisely cheerful, is that Socialism has not materialized and
Bureaucratic Collectivism has.
Since I have already written at length on Bureaucratic Collectivism, I
shall not recapitulate it all here. My ideas on this subject (at least)
have not changed greatly. The interested reader is referred to âThe End
of Capitalism in Germanyâ (Partisan Review, May-June 1941), âWallace and
the Labor Draftâ (politics, February 1945), and âLabor Imperialismâ
(politics, September 1945). Here I shall take the liberty of drawing
largely on two other old articles of mine which get at the heart of the
question. The first is an analysis of Nazi economics designed to show
the main lines of difference between Bureaucratic Collectivism and
Capitalism (taken from âWhat Is the Fascist State?â; The New
International, February 1941). The second is an application of the
concept to perhaps the most important question confronting socialists
today: the nature of the Soviet Union (taken from âWhy âPolitics?ââ;
politics, February 1944).
The feature which distinguishes capitalism from all other systems of
property relations is production for profit, which mean the regulation
of production by the market. It is the destruction of the capitalist
market that decisively marked Nazism as a new and different system.
In his introduction to the Living thoughts of Karl Marx volume, Trotsky
writes (emphasis mine throughout):
âIn contemporary society, manâs cardinal tie is exchange. Any product of
lobar that enters into the process of exchange becomes a commodity. Marx
began his investigation with the commodity and deduced from that
fundamental cell of capitalist society those social relations that have
objectively shaped themselves on the basis of exchange, independently of
manâs will. Only by pursuing this course is it possible to solve the
fundamental puzzle â how in capitalist society, in which each man thinks
for himself and no one thinks for all, are created the relative
proportions of the various branched of economy indispensable to life.
âThe worker sells his labor power, the farmer takes his produce to
market, the money lender or banker grants loans, the storekeeper offers
an assortment of merchandise, the industrialist builds a plant, the
speculator buys and sells stocks and bonds â each having his own
considerations, his own private plans, his own concern about wages or
profit. Nevertheless, out of this chaos of individual strivings and
actions emerges a certain economic whole, which, true, is not harmonious
but contradictory, yet does give society the possibility not merely to
exist but even to develop. This means that, after all, chaos is not
chaos at all, that in some way it is regulated automatically, if not
consciously.... By accepting and rejecting commodities, the market, as
the arena of exchange, decides whether they do or do not contain within
themselves socially necessary labor, thereby determines the ratios of
various kinds of commodities necessary for society....â
This seems to me a reasonably accurate description of how capitalism
works. There are two main elements: (1) production is regulated by
exchange, that is, by the prospects of the individual and corporate
property owners making a profit by selling their goods on the market;
(2) this market regulates ânot consciouslyâ but as an impersonal,
autonomous mechanism working âindependent of manâs will.â
Now let us apply this definition of capitalism to the Nazi Germany of
1936â1945, an economy I believe to have been essentially Bureaucratic
Collectivist although it had remnants of capitalism. (The same arguments
would apply, of course, even more fully to Soviet Russia.) We may begin
by comparing Trotskyâs description of capitalist economy with the Nazi
press chief, Otto Dietrichâs description of fascist economy as ânot a
mechanism regulating itself automaticallyâ but rather âan organism that
is regulated and directed from one central point.â Under Hitler, the
market continued to exist, but it lost its autonomy: it did not
determine production but was used merely as a means of measuring and
expressing in economic terms the production which was planned and
controlled by the Nazi bureaucracy. The old capitalist forms existed,
but they expressed a new content.[14] After 1936, production in Germany
is determined not by the market but by the needs of Wehrwirstschaft:
guns, tanks, shoes, steel, cement are produced in greater or lesser
quantities not because there is more or less prospect of making profits
on this or that commodity, but because this or that is considered more
or less useful for making war. Economically, this is production for use,
the use being, of course, a highly undesirable one from the social point
of view. Nor is this production controlled by a market mechanism working
âindependent of manâs willâ but by a bureaucratic apparatus which plans
production (as against the well-known âanarchyâ of capitalist
production) and which consciously and willfully works out the best
solution to the particular problem. No individual producer thinks âfor
himselfâ; on the contrary, if not one man, at least a small group of top
bureaucrats, âthink for all.â
The two great riddles which Marx so brilliantly solved â the nature of
commodity production and the process of extracting surplus value â seem
to lose, in a fascist economy, most of the subtle mystery which cloaks
them under capitalism.
âThe wealth of those societies in which the capitalist mode of
production prevails,â begins Capital, âpresents itself as âan immense
accumulation of commodities,â its unit being a single commodity. Our
investigation must therefore begin with the analysis of a commodity.â
What is a commodity? It is, says Marx, âa very queer thing, abounding in
metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties.â The reason for this
mystery is the dual nature of commodities: they are âboth objects of
utility and, at the same time, depositories of value,â that is, they
exist as both âuse valuesâ and âexchange values.â It is the latter which
gives them their capitalist character, and Marx describes how these
âexchange valuesâ are realized through the market (emphasis mine):
âAs a general rule, articles of utility become commodities only because
they are products of the labor of private individuals or groups of
individuals who carry on their work independently of each other. The sum
total of the labor of all these private individuals forms the aggregate
labor of society. Since the producers do not come into social contact
with each other until they exchange their products, the specific social
character of each producerâs labor does not show itself excepts in the
act of exchange.â
When a state bureaucracy displaces the market as the regulator of
production, the individual producers come into social contact with each
other in the sphere of production, that is, they produce according to a
conscious, prearranged plan, so that it would be technically possible â
however politically inadvisable â for each individual producer to know
before he begins to produce just where his own contribution fits into
the general scheme.
A page or two later, Marx writes:
âThe categories of bourgeois economy consist of such like forms. [He had
been describing the forms in which capitalist value is expressed.] They
are forms of thought expressing with social validity the conditions and
relations of a definite, historically determined mode of production,
viz.., the production of commodities. The whole mystery of commodities,
all the magic and necromancy that surrounds the products of labor as
long as they take the form of commodities, vanishes, therefore, as soon
as we come to other forms of production.â
We may see in Nazi Germany what Marx meant: âthe whole mystery of
commoditiesâ had indeed vanished there. Steel was produced there for
use, in guns, in tanks, in ships. Shoes were produced for use, on feet.
The fact that the shortage of shoes (in itself produced by state
planning) would have made the building of a new shoe plants extremely
profitable in the last few years meant nothing to the bureaucracy. The
was a âtheological nicetyâ they disregarded in the interests of
Wehrwirstschaf.
So, too, with the other great mystery of the capitalist mode of
production: the extraction of surplus value. âThe essential difference,â
writes Marx, âbetween the various economic forms of society, between,
for instance, a society based on slave labor and one based on wage
labor, lies only in the mode in which this surplus-labor is in each case
extracted from the actual producer, the laborer.â Under slavery this
surplus-labor (the labor over and above that needed for the maintenance
and reproductions of the laborer himself) is appropriated by the ruling
class in one way, under feudalism in another, and under capitalism in
still another, through the appropriation of âsurplus value.â
Surplus value is realized through the mechanism of the market system.
The worker sells his labor power to the capitalist. Here, as in the case
of the commodity, what seems at first glance a perfectly simple
transaction, Marx was able to demonstrate, is actually very subtle and
complex. In previous forms of economy, the subject class could not
possibly overlook the fact of its subjection, since its surplus-labor
was directly, openly appropriated by the ruling class. But under
capitalism, this relationship is concealed by the market mechanism. âHe
[the worker] and the owner of money meet in the market, and deal with
each other as on the basis of equal rights, with this difference alone,
that one is buyer, the other seller; both, therefore, equal in the eyes
of the law.... He must constantly look upon his labor-power as his own
property, his own commodity, and this he can only do by placing it at
the disposal of the buyer temporarily, for a definite period of time. By
this means alone can he avoid renouncing his rights of ownership over
it.â The result is that the worker conceives of himself as the owner of
a commodity (his labor-power) which he sells to the employer just as any
owner sells any other commodity â free to dispose of his private
property as he thinks best, to sell or not to sell according to the
price offered. Thus he doesnât realize he is contributing surplus labor
to the employer, and it was of course Marxâs great task to make this
clear to him. âThe Roman slave was held by fetters; the wage laborer is
bound to his owner by invisible threads.... His economical bondage is
both brought about and concealed by the periodic sale of himself, by his
change of masters, and by the oscillation in the market price of labor
power.â
In Nazi Germany, the threads again became visible. Since wages were
frozen along with prices by state action, there were no more
âoscillations in the market price of labor power.â Nor was there any
âchange of masters,â since the state was now his master, exercizing all
the functions of the employer: setting of wage rates, conditions of
labor, hiring and firing. It is true that the forms of the old labor
market were still for the most part kept up â though there was a trend
towards direct state conscription of labor power â but these, as in the
case of the capitalist market in general, were purely forms. A strike
for higher wages or shorter hours would have had to be directed against
the state power which decided wages and hours; it would have become at
once a political act, to be dealt with directly by the Gestapo. The
private âemployerâ was little more than a straw boss, enforcing orders
handed down to him by the state bureaucracy. This change in some ways
greatly intensified the sharpness of the struggle between exploited and
exploiter. But this struggle took place in terms quite different from
those which Marx described as characteristic of the capitalist system of
society.
I do not consider the Soviet Union to be any sort of socialist or
âworkersâ State, whether âdegeneratedâ or not, but rather a new form of
class society based on collective ownership of the means of production
by the ruling bureaucracy. It is not only not socialism, but it is a
form of society profoundly repugnant to the ideals of Liberty, Equality
and Fraternity which have been shared by most radicals, bourgeois or
socialist, since 1789. That it is based on collectivised property, and
that it is the heir of the first successful proletarian revolution â
these facts call for a revision of traditional Marxist conceptions.
The most important attempt to apply Marxist theories to the development
of Soviet Russia was, of course, Trotskyâs. His analysis seems to me
wrong in two major respects: (1) he expected the counter-revolution to
some in the form of a restoration of capitalist property relations; (2)
he saw a basic antagonism between the collectivised economy and the
totalitarian political regime. These judgments flowed from his Marxist
belief that capitalism and socialism are the only historical
alternatives today. In the turning-point year 1928, Trotsky therefore
considered the chief threat to the revolution to come from the kulaks
and nepmen, with Bukharin as their spokesman. Stalin he actually termed
a âcentristâ who would soon be brushed aside once the renascent
bourgeoisie had consolidated their position â or, given a more favorable
turn, after the workers had rallied to Trotskyâs own socialist platform.
When the next year Stalin crushed Bukharin, began to liquidate the
kulaks, and instituted the First Five Year Plan, Trotsky was compelled
by the logic of his theories to salute all this as a âleftwardâ step.
Actually, I think Anton Ciliga is right, in his remarkable book, The
Russian Enigma, when he presents the First Five Year Plan as the
foundation of the totalitarian society Stalin has built. The key passage
(pp. 103â4) is worth quoting â it should be remembered Ciliga is
describing the conclusions he came to in 1930 after several years of
life in Russia:
âDid not the captains of the Five Year Plan bear a resemblance to the
shipsâ captains of Cortes? Was there not the same thirst for pillage and
conquest under a guise that was sometimes ingenuous and sometimes had
the cynicism of Christian â or Communist â missionary activity? Both
ancient and modern conquistadors brought not only guns and blood but
also a new order, more oppressive but on a higher level than the old.
The conquerors did not bring happiness to the people; they brought them
civilization.
âThese reflections, this interpretation of the Five Year Plan, were in
direct contradiction to the official theories of Stalinism, as well as
to those of the Trotskyist Opposition. Trotskyism as well as Stalinism
saw in these events only a struggle between two social orders:
proletariat versus bourgeois, the latter embracing the kulaks and the
relics of the former ruling classes. As for me, I had come to the
conclusion that three social systems were taking part in the struggle:
State capitalism,[15] private capitalism and socialism, and that these
three systems represented three classes: the bureaucracy, the bourgeois
(including the kulaks) and the proletariat.... The difference between
Trotsky and Stalin lay in the fact that...Stalin saw the triumph of pure
socialism, pure dictatorship of the proletariat, whereas Trotsky
perceived and stressed the gaps and bureaucratic deformations of the
system.... The experience of subsequent years showed me the strength of
the organic bonds that united the Trotskyist Opposition withe the
bureaucratic regime of the Soviets.â
Because he saw a fictitious antagonism between collectivism and
dictatorship, Trotsky insisted that the Stalinist bureaucracy were
Bonapartist usurpers, a gang of bandits who had grabbed control of the
collectivised economy but who were forced, in order to maintain their
political power, to take actions which clashed with the needs of this
economy. But it would now appear that there is no such conflict, that
economic collectivisation and total dictatorship can exist peacefully
side by side, their gears meshing in smoothly together. The very thing
which today is to many people an indication of the progressive nature of
the Soviet Union, namely the successful resistance to German invasion,
seems to me to show something quite different: that the decisive
contradictions Trotsky saw between collectivism and dictatorship do
exist. Trotsky always predicted that this alleged contradiction would
cause great internal political difficulties for Stalin in the event of
war, especially if the war began with big defeats. The strain of war
would widen the alleged fissure between the masses and the bureaucracy,
he thought. But the actual course of events has been quite different:
although the war began with the most catastrophic large-scale defeats,
not even a rumor has reached us of any political opposition to the
regime at any time.[16] This does not mean Stalinâs regime is therefore
progressive; Hitler also had wide popular support. Modern
totalitarianism can integrate the masses so completely into the
political structure, through terror and propaganda, that they become the
architects of their own enslavement. This does not make the slavery
less, but on the contrary more â a paradox there is no space to unravel
here. Bureaucratic collectivism, not capitalism, is the most dangerous
future enemy of socialism.[17]
In the century after Waterloo (1815â1914), there was only one war in
Europe between first-class powers: the Franco-Prussian War. The the
first half of the 20^(th) century, there have already occurred two world
wars which involved not only all the great European powers but also the
USA, Russia and Japan; and a third world war is generally anticipated.
Furthermore, World War II was much more destructive of lives, property
and culture than World War I, and the atomic bomb promises to make World
War III devastating beyond any historical parallel.
These are commonplaces, but it is easy (and pleasant) to forget them. It
is also easy to forget that the whole body of socialist theory, from the
Utopians through Marx, Engels, Proudhon and Kropotkin to Luxemburg,
Lenin and Trotsky (after whom it ceased to develop significantly) was
built up during the âHundred Years Peaceâ after Waterloo.
From these facts, two conclusions emerge. (1) The preparation and waging
of war is now the normal mode of existence of every great nation; the
creation of military force is no longer one among other means of
advancing the national interest but rather, it is now the national
interest (cf. Simone Weilâs âWords and Warâ in the May, 1946, politics).
(2) Since the chronic world warfare of our day was unknown to them, the
theoreticians of socialism devoted their attention mainly to the
internal class struggle and failed to work out an adequate theory of the
political significance of war; this gap will remains to be filled; until
it is, modern socialism will continue to have a somewhat academic
flavor.[18]
Marxism regards war as a means to an end, a method of advancing certain
definite class interests; as a means, it is subordinated to its end, so
that if the destruction it causes seems likely to exceed the gains to
those groups using this means, they will presumably not use it; there is
implied in this whole view a certain rationality, even moderation and
limit, to warfare, so that one can say that a given war may offer a
ârevolutionary opportunityâ or that the victory of one side may be more
advantageous to the cause of socialism than the victory of the other.
There was some truth in these ideas in Marxâs time, but they are now
obsolete. War has become an end in itself; instead of advancing certain
class or national interests at the expense of others, war tends more and
more to make the situation of the âvictorsâ indistinguishable from that
of the âdefeated,â as in Europe today; the effects of the technical
measures that must be taken to fight a modern war have become more
important than any political effect of the warâs outcome. In a word, was
seems to have lost its rationality, so that one might say there will
probably be a third world war because there has been a second world war;
that is, the existence of powerful warmaking apparatuses, with economies
and social institutions deformed to support them, and the quite
justified fears of every nation of attack from every other nation â
these factors are the key to the problem, rather than the expansive
needs of capitalist imperialism (which the new State-capitalist economic
techniques have largely obviated) or the âcontradictionâ between Soviet
collectivism and American private capitalism (which exists but is not so
automatic in its effects as Marxists think). The machine is out of
control and is grinding away according to its own logic. Here is another
example of âreificationâ (âthing-ificationâ): human creations developing
their own dynamic and imposing their own laws on their creators.
Although Marx was the first to analyze this tendency in capitalism (âthe
fetishism of commoditiesâ), he had no such insight about warmaking. One
is struck by the superficiality of Marxâs ideas about war, in contrast
to his understanding of capitalism. âHowever the war may end,â he wrote
during the Franco-Prussian war, âit has given the French proletariat
practice in arms, and that is the best guarantee of the future.â
(Letters to Kugelmann, p. 116) The proletariat has by now had plenty of
such practice; our problem is to get less of it. This simplistic notion
of Marxâs (whose very simplicity shows what a perfunctory interest he
took in the question of war, for his mind was not a simple one) was
understandable in his day, but what would we think of a modern socialist
who would advance it?
So, too, with the related expectation that out of the chaos of war would
come revolutionary opportunities. âMarx and Engels hailed the Crimean
War,â writes a biographer, âfor, after all, the war did mean that the
three major powers which had been the mainstay of counter-revolution had
fallen out, and when thieves fall out, honest folks are likely to
benefit by it.â And Engels, after a remarkably accurate prediction of
the nature and even the line-up of World War I, added â...only one
result absolutely certain: general exhaustion and the establishment of
the conditions for the ultimate victory of the working class.... This,
my lords, princes and statesmen, is where in your wisdom you have
brought old Europe. And when nothing more remains to you but to open the
last great war dance â that will suit us all right. The war may perhaps
temporarily push us into the background , may wrench from us many a
position already conquered. But when you have set free forces which you
will be unable to control, things may go as they will: at the end of the
tragedy, you will be ruined and the victory of the proletariat will
either be already achieved or at any rate inevitable.â
The quotation from Trotsky at the head of this article shows the
persistence of this approach to war among Marxists even today. Now we
see that even after two world wars, the victory Engels expected has
turned out to be all too evitable. It is true that capitalism (and
bureaucratic collectivism) has âset free forcesâ it is âunable to
control,â but the socialists are equally unable to control these forces.
The âgeneral exhaustionâ Engels rightly foresaw as an aftermath of world
war includes also the proletariat. Modern warfare is so insanely
destructive that the seeds of a new order are wiped out along with the
old order. The failure of anything to come out of the European
resistance movement shows that the masses are at the moment incapable of
political effort. Nerves twisted by saturation bombing raids, feelings
numbed by massacre and suffering, vigor sapped by too little food for
too many years â out of these thistles we must not expect figs.
A related Marxian illusion is that the victory of one or the other side
in a modern war may advance the cause of socialism. Marx and Engels took
sides, on this basis, in the American Civil War and the Franco-Prussian
War. I think it may be questioned now whether the beneficial results
they expected from these conflicts (abolition of slavery, unification of
Germany) have turned out to be quite so important to âprogressâ as they
expected. The hardboiled pragmatic attitude of Marxism show up at its
worst in this now crucial matter of taking a stand in war. See, for
example, the extraordinary letters Engels wrote to Bebel in 1891 on the
proper line to take in the war he saw materializing between Germany and
France-Russia. He reasoned that because âwe [i.e., the German
Social-Democracy] have the almost absolute certainty of coming to power
within ten years,â a German victory was essential. âThe victory of
Germany is therefore the victory of the revolution, and if it comes to
war we must not only desire victory but further it by every means.... We
must demand the general arming of the people.â (My emphasis â D.M.) In
sketching out the military strategy of such a war, Engels sounds like a
member of the Imperial General Staff. And all this, of course, in the
name of revolution. (See Selected Correspondence of Marx and Engels, pp.
488â493.) This superficial view of war â I had almost said âfrivolousâ â
is perhaps excusable in a 19^(th) century thinker, but it cannot be
forgiven after World Wars I and II. Yet the great bulk of the Second
International took it in both these wars, with the addition of the
Stalinist in this war; and already we hear the same kind of reasoning
advanced in lining up sides in World War III.[19]
Such small Marxist groups as the Trotskyists and the British I.L.P. do
not share this illusion, which is good, but they hold to an explanation
of the origin of modern war which is also based on a Marxist analysis
and which blinds them to the primary nature of the problem. Namely, that
the expansive needs of capitalism and the resulting competition for
colonies, foreign markets, and overseas outlets for investment is the
cause of wars. This theory cannot explain the warlike tendencies of
bureaucratic collectivisms like the Soviet Union or post-1936 Germany,
the most militarily aggressive powers of our times. And even
capitalistic power, as Weil pointed out, go to war now rather to gain or
defend the means of making war (oil fields, strategic bases, friendly
smaller nations) than for the classic Marxian reasons. The capitalist,
motivated by rationalistic profit and loss considerations, fears the
risk of war much more than the military man, the bureaucrat, or even the
idealistic liblab. In Japan, the big-business Zaibatsu were the peace
party; it was the militarists, basing themselves on the peasant
conscripts and playing a demagogically âpopularâ game against the
big-business politicians, who pushed Japan along its imperialist path
after 1932. Perhaps the strongest argument against the Marxist
interpretation is the failure of American imperialism to dominate
Europe, as Trotsky predicted it would, after World War I, and the even
more striking weakness of American foreign policy today. In the case of
the Big Three, the degree of imperialist aggressiveness seems to be in
inverse proportion to the strength of capitalist institutions.
Not only has it become impossible to fit modern war into the Marxian
framework, but a reverse action has also taken place: war has had a
shattering effect on that framework.
Marx and Engels regarded the periodic economic crises which they
predicted would occur under capitalism as the immediate causes of
revolutions. âWe can almost calculate the moment,â wrote the latter is
his preface to the first volume of Capital, âwhen the unemployed, losing
patience, will take their own fate into their hands.â And Marx, in The
Class Struggles in France, noted that âa real revolution is only
possible in the periods when these two factors, the modern productive
forces and the bourgeois production forms, come into collision with each
other.... A new revolution is only possible in consequence of a new
crisis. It is, however, just as certain as this.â How do these crises
arise? Marx sums it up in Capital (V. III, p. 568): âThe last cause of
all real crises always remains the poverty and restricted consumption of
the masses as compared to the tendency of capitalist production to
develop productive forces such a way that only the absolute power of
consumption of the entire society would be the limit.â
In a fully-developed Bureaucratic Collectivist society like that of
Russia, none of the above applies: crises may occur, but they have a
political character and cannot be shown â or at least have not been
shown â to arise from the kind of periodic and automatic economic
imbalance described by Marx. The forms of production still conflict with
the productive forces â but along new lines. In societies like our own
and England, which are still capitalist but in which Bureaucratic
Collectivism is spreading, techniques of State spending, economic
control, and deficit financing have been developed which in practice
have avoided crises and in theory should be able to do so. These new
economic forms are closely related to preparation for warfare. As
Stalinâs recent election speech emphasized, the Five Year Plans were
primarily armament-building programs. Hitlerâs rearming of Germany was
made possible by the brilliant adaptation Dr. Schacht made of Keynesâ
theories, which he carried so far as to produce by 1936 (and quite
without intending to do so) an economy that was more Bureaucratic
Collectivist than it was capitalist. As for the military implications of
New Deal economics, note that in 1933, after four years of Hooverâs
laisser-faire capitalism, there were 16 million unemployed, or one out
of every three workers. The New Dealâs Keynesian approach did reduce
employment to manageable proportions â from 7 to 10 millions. But it was
war that really solved the problem: by 1943, unemployment had
practically vanished (1 million), nor has it to date â since the hot war
has been followed by the cold â again risen to significant heights.
The modern war-making State, even if it is still mainly capitalist, thus
avoids Marxâs âinevitableâ economic crises. Through deficit spending, it
enlarges the purchasing power of the masses. And it brings to bear âthe
power of consumption of the entire societyâ through vast orders of
munitions (a form of buying which has the further advantage of removing
the goods entirely outside the market sphere so that they donât compete
for a share of the public spending power: the ultimate consumer of
munitions â and the adjective is most fitting â is the Enemy soldier).
There is also largely eliminated another one of the factors to which
Marx looked for the self-disintegration of capitalism: the âindustrial
reserve army of the unemployed.â In wartime, this becomes a real army.
In peacetime, it gets employment through the measures just noted. For,
while Marx was able to demonstrate how essential âan industrial reserve
armyâ was to the bourgeoisie to keep down the price of labor, such an
army is of no advantage to the rulers of a warmaking society, which
needs two things above all: ânational unityâ and full production.
Unemployment, with its idle and discontented millions, from this
standpoint has only disadvantages.
Finally, nothing improves the economic position of the working class and
strengthens its trade unions more than a really good war. This
phenomenon, which was uneasily noted by Marxists in World War I, has
become positively absurd in World War II. In this country, there was a
considerable increase in union membership during the war, and
âmaintenance-of-membershipâ clauses, which give the union a certain
degree of stability, became standard procedure in War Labor Board
awards. Manufacturing wages went up 71% (from $26 to $45 a week average)
between 1940 and 1943. This is all common knowledge, but it puts an odd
twist on the idea that the improvement of the class position of the
workers is necessarily connected with progress. And it makes it very
difficult to convince the workers as workers that war is a curse.
JĂ©sus Espinosa, a Mexican gardener of the city of San Antonio, Texas,
was asked last week to venture an opinion on an important subject. What
did he think of the atomic bomb?
JĂ©sus stared, then shrugged his shoulders eloquently.
Should the U.S. give it to other nations?
âWhy not?â said JĂ©sus.
But what if the other nations started a war with it?
JĂ©sus brightened, âMore work, better pay,â he said.
Did he and his friends discuss the possibilities of atomic energy?
JĂ©sus gave his interviewer a long, pitying look and went back to
shoveling dirt.
(Time, March 18, 1945.)
It is true that Mussolini was demagogic when he transposed the
class-struggle theme by speaking of âproletarian nationsâ like Italy
whose hope lay in rebellion against âbourgeois nationsâ like England
(stifling at the same time his own working class movement the better to
fight what might be â demagogically â called âthe international class
struggleâ). But the point is he was not just being demagogic. Nor was
Hitler when he joined those hitherto warring concepts ânationalâ and
âsocialism.â Everywhere today we see the class struggle inside nations
yielding to struggle between nations, so that the main conflict nowadays
is between peoples and not between exploiters and exploited. If history
has indeed a motor â which I doubt, just as I doubt the existence of
History with a capital âHâ â the motor is war, not revolution.
Everywhere ânational unityâ is weakening the class struggle:
politically, it moderates class conflicts by emphasizing the common
national enemy; economically, it makes concessions to the masses in
return for their support is warmaking. In Russia, where Hitlerâs
ânational socialismâ has been realized far more completely than it ever
was in Germany, the political control of the rulers over the ruled is so
complete that the economic concessions are the most trifling, the gap
between the living standards of the masses and their exploiters is the
widest.
Marxists will retort that revolutionary class struggle inside each
nation is the way to weaken the present supernationalism that is leading
us to a third world war. I would agree that it is certainly and
important method, but this simply raises the question of WHY there is so
little class struggle today, WHY the masses follow their leaders to war
with such docility. It is one purpose of this article to suggest that
the Marxist answers to this question of WHY are superficial and in large
measure obsolete. And certainly, until we can answer the question WHY
the condition exists, we cannot do much effectively about changing it.
The more war becomes dominant, the more the ruling classes can
monopolize continually â not just in time of actual hostilities â the
most powerful ideological weapon they have ever grasped: the appeal for
âunityâ of the whole nation against a threat from the outside. This
weapon is powerful psychologically, because it plays on very deep fears
and in-group loyalties. It is also powerful in rational terms, because
it is perfectly true that national defeat is catastrophic for all
classes, not just for the ruling class. Thus the strongest appeal of the
Nazis in the terrible final year of the war was their picture of what
the consequences of defeat would be for the German people; and now we
see â and doubtless the Germans see even better â that the Nazis were
quite right in all their predictions.
One striking confirmation of the way war rather than class struggle has
become the center of our world is the importance that foreign policy now
assumes. The disagreements between âLeftâ and âRightâ on domestic
policy, unsubstantial enough precisely because of the needs of ânational
unityâ in order to present a strong front to competing nations, vanish
completely when the really vital question of foreign policy arises. Thus
at the 1943 United Auto Workersâ convention in Buffalo, the biggest sign
in the hall read: âTHE UAW-CIO STAND UNITED WITH OUR COMMANDER-IN-CHIEF,
FRANKLIN D. REOOSEVELT.â Thus the British Labor Party Foreign Minister
Bevin takes pride in the âcontinuityâ of his policies with those of his
Tory predecessor, Eden. Not enough attention, by the way, was paid to a
speech Bevin made last April during the election campaign in which he
proposed that âforeign policy should henceforth be treated as an
all-party matter.â It is true that the French Socialists favored a
smaller army than DeGaulle, but that was because they had a more sober
appreciation of what is economically possible now than the romantic
general had, not because of any principled difference. Thus when Foreign
Minister Bidault, speaking in the National Assembly, defended Franceâs
colonial record and defied the rest of the world to try to dispossess
France of her sovereignty over certain territories, Time (April 9, 1945)
reported: âFor once, no cries of dissent welled from the Assembly. For
Right, Center and Left alike, empire was above politics.â This too, was
âcontinuity of policy,â for on February 3, 1939, the French Chamber of
Deputies unanimously resolved âthat all parts of the Empire are placed
under the protection of the nation to the same extent as continental
France, that the sovereignty of France is indivisible and cannot be
transmitted, delegated or shared.â
Now that the national State has become the great menace, and war and
foreign policy the great issues, the ârealisticâ attitude that has
always distinguished Marx and his followers on these matters has become
quite unrealistic (if oneâs aim is not effective warmaking or the
furtherance of nationalistic ambitions). The Anarchistsâ uncompromising
rejection of the State, the subject of Marxian sneers for its
âabsolutistâ and âUtopianâ character, makes much better sense in the
present era than the Marxian relativist and historical approach.[20] The
pacifists also seem to be more realistic than the Marxists both in their
understanding of modern war and also in their attempts to do something
about it. A very interesting essay could be written today about the
unrealism of Realism and the metaphysical nature of Materialism.
This part of my argument I undertake reluctantly, for I have no
philosophical training and donât feel at home in this field. Those more
at home may perhaps dismiss what follows with Sheridanâs criticism of a
young politicianâs first speech: âThe honorable member has said much
that is sound and much that is new; but what is sound is not new and
what is new is not sound.â I have long thought, however, that our
over-specialized culture would profit if amateurs were more daring in
treating matters usually left to experts, and have acted often on that
assumption. In any case, the course which our society is taking is so
catastrophic that one is forced to rethink for himself all sorts of
basic theoretical questions which in a happier age could have been taken
for granted. Questions which formerly seemed to me either closed or
meaningless are now beginning to appear open and significant. Such
questions are those of Determinism v. Free Will, Materialism v.
Idealism, the concept of Progress, the basis for making value judgments,
the precise usefulness of science to human ends, and the nature of man
himself. (In this I am not particularly original, of course: a similar
shift of interest may be observed among most Western intellectuals, the
most recent example being the vogue of existentialism.) I do not propose
to try to settle any of these vast questions here â indeed I am coming
to suspect that most of them cannot ever be settled in the definite way
I once assumed they could be. But it will be necessary to go into them
somewhat in order to make clear the necessity, for those who still
believe in the ethical aims of socialism, of adopting a âRadicalâ
attitude.
By âscientific methodâ I mean the process of gathering measurable data,
setting up hypotheses to explain the past behavior of whatever is being
investigated, and testing these hypotheses by finding out if they enable
one to predict correctly future behavior. The essence is the ability to
accept or reject a scientific conclusion by means of objective â and
ultimately quantitative â tests whose outcome is unambiguous: that is,
there is recognized to be a universal standard independent of the
individual observer which forces everyone to assent to a given
conclusion if it can be shown to meet the requirements of this standard.
As Karl Pearson puts it: âThe scientific man has above all things to
strive at self-elimination in his judgments, to provide an argument
which is true for each individual mind as for his own. The
classification of facts, the recognition of their sequence and relative
significance is the function of science, and the habit of forming a
judgment upon these facts unbiased by personal feeling is characteristic
of the scientific frame of mind.â (The Grammar of Science; Everyman
edition, p. 11; my emphasis.)
By âvalue judgmentâ I mean a statement that involves the notion of
âGoodâ and âBadâ in either an ethical or an esthetic sense. Such a
judgment is always ambiguous because it involves a qualitative
discrimination about something which is by its very nature not reducible
to uniform and hence measurable units; the âpersonal feelingâ of the
observer not only enters into the judgment but is the chief determinant
of the judgment. It is impossible, therefore, ever to solve a moral or
esthetic problem in the definite way that a scientific problem can be
solved, which is why one age can build on the scientific achievements of
all past ages, whereas it is notorious that in art and ethics no such
progress may be observable. It is also impossible to prove an ethical or
esthetic judgment in such a way as to compel everybody else, or indeed
anybody else, to assent to it. This is not to say that communication,
persuasion, and demonstration are not possible in this realm. It is, but
along unscientific lines. In a word, there seems to be something
intrinsically unknowable about values, in a scientific sense, although
artists and moral teachers have shown us for several thousand years that
knowledge is attainable by other methods.[21]
An example may bring out the contrast. The modern detective story and
the novels of Henry James share a common structural pattern: a mystery,
a problem is proposed, and the dramatic interest lies in the readerâs
sense of coming to the solution of the mystery. With not too much
straining, it might also be said that the problem is the same in each
case: what kind of people are these âreally,â as James would say, which
are the Good ones, which are the Bad? The difference is that a
detective-story writer reduces this to a question that is scientifically
manageable: who pulled the trigger, who poisoned the medicine? So we
always at the end get a solution of the mystery; we find that so-and-so
is the criminal, and hence that, since the committing or not committing
of a physical act is our only criterion, so-and-so is quite definitely
the Bad character. But in James, despite the most subtle and laborious
analysis and despite a whole series of dramatic revelations, we find
that the clearing-up of one ambiguity simply opens up several others,
which in turn suggest other mysteries undreamed of before the process of
elucidation began, so that the onion is never, so to speak, completely
stripped. For the heart of Jamesâ onion, unlike that of the detective
writer, is unattainable, since the problem he sets himself is ethical
and esthetic rather that scientific, a problem of values which by its
very nature can never be âsolvedâ but only demonstrated. The Golden Bowl
is an inquiry into the moral behavior of four people; at the end we are
no farther along towards a final judgment as to who is Good and who is
Bad than we were at the beginning â we have even lost ground, in fact â
and yet we have learned a great deal about both the people and their
ethics. The greater the artist, the more we feel this about his work,
which is one reason Henry James is more interesting than Agatha
Christie.
A thoroughgoing scientific approach, such as Marxâs was in intention,
sees the world as of one piece, all of it by its nature able to be
understood scientifically; to the extent that it is not so understood,
the imperfection of our present knowledge is to blame. This view sees
judgments as illusory in their own terms (since with sufficient
scientific knowledge it is assumed they could be shown to be simply
reflections of some deeper scientifically-graspable reality â historical
according to Marx, psychological according to Freud) although of course
values are conceded to be real enough as phenomena.
My own view is that value judgments are real in both the above senses,
that they as in fact our ultimate basis for action whether we realize it
or not, and that they belong to an order of reality permanently outside
the reach of scientific method. There are two worlds, not one. I suppose
I am, philosophically, a dualist; there is precedent for such a
position, but the contemporary trend on the Left has been along Marxian
or Deweyan lines so that one feels quite uncomfortable in it. At any
rate, the crucial question seems to me to be not how we arrive at our
values, or what consequences their realization will have, but rather
what values we should hold. How may we tell Good from Evil? In Tolstoyâs
great phrase: What Should a Man Live By?
The question of what we base our value judgments on, how we know what is
Good and what is Evil, may seem remote and academic in an age which has
witnessed Maidanek and Hiroshima. Confronted by such gross violations of
the most modest ethical code, may we not take it for granted that there
is general agreement that such things are Evil, and instead of splitting
hairs about metaphysical questions like the nature of values, devote
ourselves rather to the practical implementation of this universal
agreement? In a word, when Evil is so patent, is our problem not a
scientific one (devising Means to an agreed-on End) rather than an
ethical one (deciding what Ends we want)?
This is âjust common senseâ â which means it will not stand close
examination. That extreme Evils are committed today, with no large-scale
opposition, by the agents of great nations â this leads me to conclude
not, with the liberals and the Marxists, that the peoples of those
nations are horrified by these Evils, groaning under the bondage of a
system which permits such things to happen, and waiting expectantly for
a practical program to be put forward which will eliminate them; but
rather that, on the contrary, these Evils are rejected only on a
superficial, conventional, public-oration and copy-book-maxim plane,
while they are accepted or at least temporized with on more fundamental,
private levels. How deeply does modern modern man experience the moral
code he professes in public? One recalls the encounter of two liblab
American journalists with a Labor member of the British cabinet during
the war. They asked him for âsome sort of idea about what Britain was
fighting for.â The Laborite was puzzled. âThen he smiles and said that
Britain, of course, could state the sort of aims we seemed to demand, of
course, Britain could get out a list of points. But he asked us what
they would mean â they would be mere platitudes. He was intensely
sincere and he could not understand why we should be shocked...â (P.M.,
January 30, 1941.)
The fact that âeverybodyâ agrees that war, torture, and the massacre of
helpless people are Evil in not reassuring to me. It seems to show that
our ethical code is no longer experienced, but is simply assumed, so
that it becomes a collection of âmere platitudes.â One does not take any
ricks for a platitude. Ask a dozen passersby, picked at random, whether
they believe it is right to kill helpless people; they will reply of
course not (the âof courseâ is ominous) and will probably denounce the
inquirer as a monster for even suggesting there could be two answers to
the question. But they will all âgo alongâ with their government in
World War III and kill as many helpless enemy people as possible. (While
the monstrous questioner may well become a C.O.) Good and Evil can only
have reality for us if we do not take them for granted, if they are not
regarded as platitudes but as agonizing problems. Thus the easy,
universal agreement that war is Evil is a matter for suspicion, not
congratulation.[22]
Scientific method cannot answer Tolstoyâs question. It can tell us
everything about a work of art or a way of life â its psychological and
economic motivation, its historical significance, its effects on the
beholder or the participant â everything except the one essential thing:
is it Good? Scientific method can tell us how to reach a given End: the
chances of success by one method against another, the past experience of
other people, the favorable and unfavorable factors. It can tell us what
the consequences of reaching a given End will be. It can even tell us a
good deal about why we in fact choose one set of values (i.e., on End)
rather than another; that is, it can tell us all about the historical,
economic, glandular, psychological and other objective actors involved
in value choices. All this information is important and useful. But
science is mute on what is, after all, the central question: what values
should we choose, what End ought we to want? Science comes into play
only after the values have been chosen, the End selected. For it, the
End must always be âgiven,â that is, assumed as a fact, a datum which
scientific method cannot and should not âjustifyâ any more than it can
tell why coal âought to beâ coal. [23]
Many, perhaps most, scientists will agree with this limitation of the
scope of scientific method â and with the more general proposition it
rests on, that the world of value judgment is intrinsically unknowable
through science. So, too, will those at the other extreme: the
religiously minded. It is the Progressives who deny this limitation; in
this they follow their masters, Marx and Dewey, each of whom has made a
Promethean effort to unify the two worlds by deducing values from
scientific inquiry.
I have discussed this problem of values with Marxists and Deweyans a
good deal of late. They generally begin by assuming a âself-evidentâ
that Man ought to want Life rather than Death, or Plenty rather than
Poverty; once some such assumption is made, then of course that have no
difficulty showing how science can help us reach this End. But if the
assumption is questioned, it soon becomes clear that it is based on
other assumptions: that âManâ means âmost people of the time and place
we are talking about,â and that the ânormalâ or ânaturalâ as defined in
this statistical way is what one ought to want. It is understandable
that their answer should take a quantitative form, since science deals
only in measurable quantities. But if what most people want is oneâs
criterion of value, then there is no problem involved beyond
ascertaining what in fact people do want â a question that can indeed be
answered by science, but not the one we started out with. For this
answer simply raises the original question in a different form: why
should one want what most people want? The very contrary would seem to
be the case: those who have taught us what we know about ethics, from
Socrates and Christ to Tolstoy, Thoreau, and Gandhi, have usually wanted
precisely what most people of their time did not want, and have often
met violent death for that reason.
But, it will be objected, surely it is possible to base an ethical
system on human needs by investigating âhuman natureâ through such
sciences as psychology, anthropology and sociology. âIdeals need not be
idealist,â writes Helen Constas (politics, January 1946). âThe ethical
standards of socialism can be and are derived directly from the physical
and psychological needs of human beings, and are therefore quite real
and materialist. This is the only scientific base for socialism.â This
is a plausible and attractive idea; it is the approach of the main
theoreticians of both anarchism and Utopian socialism (see below under
âAncestral Voices Prophesying Progressâ). What could be more direct and
satisfying a solution than to discover, by scientific inquiry, what
human needs are and then to construct an ethical system that will give
the maximum satisfaction to those needs? But how is one to tell the
ârealâ or ânormalâ or âgoodâ human needs from the âpervertedâ or âbadâ
ones? As one extends the scope of oneâs investigation over large masses
of people, the variety and mutual exclusiveness of human needs becomes
ever more confusing; and as one intensifies oneâs vision into any single
individual â oneâs self, for example, it becomes more and more difficult
to tell which needs are âreal and materialistâ and which are not. One
can only solve this question by constructing a metaphysical and
scientifically unverifiable model of ârealâ or âtrueâ human nature â
i.e., what oneâs heart tells one men should be like â and applying this
as a standard to the vast mass of contradictory data oneâs scientific
labors have amassed. The only possible scientific model of human nature
is, we have seen above, the one arrived at by ascertaining what in fact
most people have wanted most of the time. But an ethics based on this
would not be an attractive one. Most people in the past and today have
been conditioned by exploitative social institutions to want such things
as to be fed in return for submission to authority, or to play god in
their own family circle, or to despise the weak and honor the strong. if
these unpleasant traits are held to be perversions of human nature, then
one must ask on what scientific basis this finding is made; it is an odd
conception of normality which expresses itself only in a few individuals
and cultures throughout mankindâs long history. Scientifically, the
Machiavellians would seem to have the better of this argument.
Marx and Dewey are at least bothered by the problem of values, even
though unable to reconcile it with their scientific monism. The more
consistent scientific-monists, however, simply deny the reality of the
whole problem. They argue that one has merely the illusion of
value-choice: in âreality,â one reacts to stimuli of which one may not
be conscious but which there is no reason to suppose are intrinsically
incapable of being understood through science. They maintain that, just
as the advance of science has shown us that many phenomena can now be
explained scientifically, so in the future those areas of human
motivation which now seem to us out side the sphere of science will be
likewise brought safely under control.
This takes us to the philosophical problem of Free Will, which I donât
feel competent to discuss beyond saying that either thoroughgoing answer
to it seems to me absurd. If there is no Free Will, then there must be a
cause for every result; but how does one arrive at First Cause â what
causes that? (Religion answers this with God, but this seems to me more
an evasion than an answer.) But if there is Free Will, complete and
unforced, then how can one explain the influence of scientifically
determinable factors (glandular, sexual, climatic, historical, etc.) on
every choice that one makes? One must conclude, and I do conclude, that
although vast areas if human motivation are determined, there is a
certain area â a vital core, so to speak â where we have a free choice.
(A determined choice is a contradiction is terms.) So far as action
goes, this core is the âpoint,â since the rest is determined â i.e., we
react rather than act. Whether Free Will exists or not, it thus seems
necessary to behave as though it did; just as whether or not values
exist independent of scientifically explainable causes, it also seems
necessary to behave as though they did. Necessary, that is, if we aspire
â as all socialists, whether of the Radical or the Marxian-Progressive
variety, do aspire at least in theory â not to perpetuate the status quo
(to react) but on the contrary to revolutionize it (to act).
Once we have divorced value judgments from scientific method, we are
embarked on a slope which can easily lead if not to Hell at least to
Heaven. For if we assume that men decide what is Good, True, Just and
Beautiful by a partially free choice, then the blank question confronts
us: if our value-choices are not wholly determined by the scientifically
understandable ârealâ world (I put ârealâ in quotes because what the
scientificians call the âunrealâ world seems to me equally real), then
where in the world or out of it, DO they come from? The easiest answer
is the religious one: that there is some kind of divine pattern, of
otherworldly origin, to which our choices conform. This I reject for
three reasons. The most important is that, even in adolescence, religion
has never interested or attracted me.[24] Here I stand with the young
Marx, who wrote in his doctoral thesis: âPhilosophy makes no secret of
the fact: her creed is the creed of Prometheus: âIn a word, I detest all
the gods.ââ Secondly, the religious answer seems to me another form of
determinism, and hence is alien to Man ans degrades him to a parasite of
a superior power. Why should we recognize the overlordship of God
anymore than that of History or Science or the Unconscious? Thirdly, the
very fact that the religious hypothesis, for the same reason, is
suspect: the âtrickâ in living seems to me precisely to reject all
complete and well-rounded solutions and to live in a continual state of
tension and contradiction, which reflects the real nature of manâs
existence. Not the object at rest but the gyroscope, which harmonizes
without destroying the contradictory forces of motion and inertia,
should be our model. Perhaps the most serious objection to Marxism is
that, in this sense, it is not dialectical enough.
The attempt to give values either a religious or a scientific basis
seems to me an attempt to objectify what is a subjective, personal, even
arbitrary process. I think each manâs values come from intuitions which
are peculiar to himself and yet â if he is talented as a moralist â also
strike common chords that vibrate respondingly in other peopleâs
consciences. This is what ethical teachers have always done; it is the
only way we have ever learned anything essential about ethics or
communicated our discoveries to others; that is should appear such a
mysterious business today, if not downright childish, is one of the many
signs of the disproportionate place scientific method has come to occupy
in our consciousness. For the fact that there is no scientific base for
ethics does not mean there is no base at all (or only a religious one),
any more than the fact that, as I do believe, it is impossible to decide
scientifically whether a poem is any good or not means that there is no
way to tell (or proves the existence of God). It simply meant that there
are two worlds and that we in practice live on two levels all the time.
Tolstoy gives three characteristics of a prophecy: âFirst, it is
entirely opposed to the general ideas people in the midst of whom it is
uttered; second, all who hear it feel its truth; and thirdly, above all,
it urges men to realize what it foretells.â Here we see the paradox: the
great ethical teachers have always put forward ideas which the majority
of men of their time think nonsense or worse â and yet which these same
men also feel are true. The prophecy strike through to something in
common the prophet and the very people who stone him to death, something
deep down, far below the level accessible to scientific study (Gallup
polls) or to rational argument.
This âsomething is commonâ cannot be the mores of the historical period
in question, for it is just his own time which rejects most violently
the prophetâs teachings, while for thousands of years after his death
people in widely different social conditions continue to be deeply moved
by them. How can one, for example, on historical-materialist grounds,
explain the attraction of Tolstoy in 19^(th) century Russia or some of
us today in this country feel towards the ideas of Lao-Tse, who lived in
China in the seventh century B.C.? In this sense, we may say that Truth,
Love, Justice, and other values are absolute: that, in addition to the
variations in these conceptions which appear under different historical
circumstances, there is also an unchanging residue which is not
historically relative. The similarities between menâs values in widely
different historical periods seem to me at least as striking as the
differences which, following Marx, it has been customary to emphasize.
The âsomething in commonâ seems to be related to the nature of the human
beings who have inhabited this earth during the last five or six
thousand years. (I am willing to concede that this âsomething is commonâ
is historically relative to this extent: that an inhabitant of Saturn,
who may well have six legs, no head and a body the size of a cockroach,
probably would not understand Platoâs notions of Justice.)
To sum up:
feelings of the individual, not in Marxâs History, Deweyâs Science, or
Tolstoyâs God.
action, is the only one worth talking about since the rest is by
definition determined.
themselves; if Truth is a value for one, then a lie is not justified
even if it is in the class interests of the proletariat.[25] (2) They
have an element which is not historically relative, except in the sense
of relating to human beings on this earth and not to Saturnians or
Martians.
Science is competent to help us behave more wisely, once we have chosen
our Ends, but it cannot help us choose them. Or, put differently: it can
improve our technique of action, but it cannot supply the initial
impetus for action, which is a value-choice: I want this, not that. At
that crucial initial moment in any action, the moment of choice, I
maintain that science is incompetent, and that there is some intuition
or whatever involved which we simply do not understand. It is not the
validity of scientific method, but rather its proper scope. An Attempt
is made to deflate the over-emphasis on science in Western culture of
the past two centuries, to reduce scientific method to its proper role
of means to ends that are outside its province. In short, a dualistic
approach is suggested. But a dualist appears to a materialist to be
merely a disguised idealist, whence the outcries about ârejecting
science.â I donât expect this explanation to still them. Since the great
experiment at Hiroshima, I have discussed with many people the above
question, and I have observed how deeply âscientisedâ our culture has
become, so that otherwise coolheaded and rational persons react to the
slightest questioning of scientific progress the way a Tennessee
fundamentalist reacts to Darwinâs theories. Any suggestion, for example,
that maybe we know more about nature by now than is good for us, that a
moratorium on atomic research might lose us cheaper power but gain us
the inhabited globe â the slightest speculative hint of such an idea is
greeted with anger, contempt, ridicule. And why not? A god is being
profaned.
At the politics meetings last winter [i.e., 1946], most of the audience
showed this cultural reflex. If a speaker said he doubted the value of
scientific method in certain relations, he was at once attacked from the
floor: âWhat! You want to junk science and go back to stone axes?â Many
listeners could not distinguish between the statement âScientific method
has its limitations,â and the statement, âScientific method is
worthless.â When I said, âScience cannot tell us what values to choose,â
someone rose to object: âMacdonald says science leads us to choose bad
values.â
It is, of course, not enough to just assert values; unless they are
acted on, values arenât meaningful at all, and the concrete way they are
acted on in a given specific situation is their reality. Put
differently: it is true that is Truth, Love and Justice are not closely
defined, both rationally and in actual situations, they are so vague
that almost any evil may be committed, and has been committed, under
their cover; ethical teaching and speculation is an attempt to define
them partly by analysis, partly by appealing to people to realize them
here and now in their everyday lives. To say that Marxâs demonstration
of the historical shifts that take place in values, of Deweyâs concept
of experience are misleading when made the only approach to values in
not to say that they should be âjunked.â In my opinion, they are great
advances in our understanding (as is also Freudâs exploration of
unconscious motivation) which it would be a real cultural regression to
abandon. What should be rejected is what seemed to these thinkers the
main point: the reduction of all experience to their terms.
Truth, the cognition of which is the business of philosophy, became in
the hands of Hegel no longer an aggregate of finished dogmatic
statements which, once discovered, had merely to be learned by heart.
Truth lay now in the process of cognition itself, in the long historical
development of science, which mounts from lower to ever higher levels of
knowledge without ever reaching, by discovering so-called
âabsolute-truth,â a point at which it can proceed no further... Just as
knowledge is unable to reach a perfected termination in a perfect, ideal
condition of humanity, so is history unable to do so; a perfect society,
a perfect state are things which can only exist in the imagination. On
the contrary, all successive historical situations are only transitory
stages in the endless course of development of human society from the
lower to the higher.
(Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach, p. 21)
I agree that absolute truth is unattainable, that a perfect society can
exist âonly in the imagination,â and that Hegel and after him Marx made
a great intellectual advance in emphasizing the historical-relative
aspect of truth. But I donât see why one must accept Engelsâ conclusion
that there is no absolute truth outside the historical process. Engels
thinks that because such truth can exist âonly in the imaginationâ â the
âonlyâ in revealing, by the way â it must therefore be unreal. But why?
The imagination is part of life, too, and absolute, unchanging truth may
be quite real even if one grants the imperfection of humanity and the
consequent impossibility of absolute truth ever being realized outside
the imagination. If there is a contradiction here, it is because human
life is contradictory. And Engels himself is caught in the
contradiction, for how can he speak of historical evolution from the
âlowerâ to the âhigherâ without some criterion that is outside
historical development, i.e., is an absolute existing âonly in the
imagination?â How can we test this alleged progression if we have no
definition of âhigherâ that is independent of the process itself?
The passage from Engels, by the way, strikingly anticipates Deweyâs
concepts of âexperienceâ and âknowledge as a process,â to which the same
objections apply. On this whole question, Dewey is close to Marx.
To know what is useful for a dog, one must study dog nature. This nature
itself is not to be deduced from the principle of utility. Applying this
to man, he that would criticize all human acts, movements, relations,
etc., by the principle of utility, must first deal with human nature in
general, and then with human nature as modified in each historical
epoch. Bentham makes short work of it. With the driest naiveté he takes
the modern shopkeeper, especially the English shopkeeper, as the normal
man.
(Marx, Capital, V. I p. 668, footnote.)
But where does Marx himself consider âhuman nature in general?â Does he
not, on the contrary, constantly deny there is any such thing and
constantly assert that human nature only exists âas modified in each
historical epoch?â Does he not also arbitrarily take as âthe normal manâ
not, true enough, the British shopkeeper, but at least the kind of man
whose needs the French Enlightenment has assumed, for all sorts of
historical reasons, it was the proper aim of social institutions to
satisfy? (Iâm not saying it wasnât perhaps as good a model as was then
available; Iâm simply pointing out that Marx, like Bentham, naively took
as an example of human nature in general, without any critical
examination, a historically limited human type.) Marx can see very well
the fallacy in Benthamâs making utility his value-principle without
asking âuseful for what?â But he is blind to his own similar failing.
âUndoubtedly,â it will be said, âreligious, moral, philosophical and
juridical ideas have been modified in the course of historical
development. But religion, morality, philosophy, political science and
law constantly survive this change. There are, besides, eternal truths,
such as Freedom, Justice, etc., that are common to all states of
society. But Communism abolishes eternal truths, it abolishes all
religion and all morality, instead of constituting them on a new basis;
it therefore acts in contradiction to all past historical experience.â
What does this accusation reduce itself to? The history of all past
society has consisted in the development of class antagonisms... One
fact is common to all past ages, viz., the exploitation of one part of
society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social consciousness of
past ages, despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays, moves
within certain common forms, or general ideas, which cannot completely
vanish except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms.
The Communist revolution is the most radical rupture with the
traditional property relations; no wonder its development involves the
most radical rupture with the traditional ideas of all of the
bourgeoisie. But let us have done with the bourgeois objections to
Communism!
(The Communist Manifesto, Part II.)
The Argument that the author put into the mouth of their bourgeois
critic seems to me sound, and perhaps the impatient interjection, âBut
let us have done...,â with which they break off their reply shows that
they themselves were vaguely aware they had failed to meet it. Their
reply is that what seem to be âeternalâ truths are really truths that
have been common to all past societies, and that the common character of
these truths reflects the common nature of these societies, which have
all been based on class exploitation. Since the future communist society
will be classless, its concepts of Justice, Freedom, etc., will be
different from and superior to those of past class societies. This would
imply that the authors have a concrete idea of what this new communist
morality looks like (else how do they know it will be either different
or superior?). But of course they donât. Quite the contrary. The above
passage is preceded by the famous section in which the authors meet the
various charges that communism will ruin family life, abolish property,
destroy culture, etc., by showing quite convincingly that only bourgeois
minority actually enjoy these blessings and that capitalism has already
taken them away from the mass of people. They state repeatedly that it
is only the bourgeois form of these things that communism proposes to
abolish; in the communist future, men will for the first time experience
real Freedom, real Justice, real morality â as against the past, in
which such concepts have been perverted into ideological coverings for
exploitation. This is indeed an important difference, but it is not the
one we began discussing here. For what can possibly be the content of
this future real morality if it is not he persisting core of past
morality stripped of all class-exploitative perversions? If Marx and
Engels are not simply projecting into the communist future those
âeternal truthsâ they make such fun of, smuggling them in disguised as
âthe real thing,â then what is their conception of that future communist
morality which will be so much better than what we have known up to now
that they devoted their whole lives to trying to realize it, and called
on the workers of the world to ceaselessly rebel until it is achieved?
How do we know the struggle is worth it unless we get some idea of what
these fine new values are? To have âinventedâ a brand-new morality would
have indeed been writing ârecipes for the cook-shops of the future,â and
Marx wisely, and in line with his own historical approach, refrained
from doing this. But the only other way to get any idea of what this
future morality would look like was to project the ârealâ (read
âsupra-historicalâ) core of past morality into the future, which is what
Marx did without admitting it.
But why is it important that Marx assumed his ethics instead of stating
them explicitly, so long as he did have values and admirable ones (as I
agree he did)? Thus Sidney Hook, defending Marxism against the
criticisms made recently in these pages, describes it as âa huge
scientific judgment of valueâ (New Leader, Feb. 23, 1946). He means,
presumably, that Marxâs values are implicit in his whole work, that, as
Marxists have put it to me, Marx constantly demonstrates in his analysis
of capitalism what he means by Justice and Freedom, even if he does not
formally define these concepts and work out their implications. This is
even alleged to be a superior way to approach these questions. I deny
this. Marxâs failure to state clearly what his ethical assumptions were,
and to devote as much thought o this kind of problem as the anarchist
theoreticians, for example, did, has given his doctrine an ambiguity
which anarchism has never had. Because he concentrated so ferociously on
capitalism as the Enemy and denied so vigorously the validity of any
general moral values, it is possible for the most inhumane and
authoritarian class society in the world to make his doctrines the basis
of its official ideology. No doubt some Stalinist pundit has already
demonstrated that Freedom and justice have a historical content in the
Soviet union which Marx was naturally unable to foresee, that they are
indubitably very different from the bourgeois ideas of these things
which Marx attacked (the most cynical apologist for the English factory
system of 1830 could hardly have imagined anything so horrible as a
Soviet forced-labor camp), and hence that â lacking any general
principles on the subject from Marx â non-Freedom in Russia today is
actually a historically higher form of Freedom and would have been so
recognized by Marx were he alive today. That Marx would not so react to
the Soviet Union I think may be taken for granted; but he certainly went
out of his way to make it easy for such an interpretation to be made.
The Gotha Program episode suggests the dangers of Marxâs practice of
assuming his basic principles, and therefore neglecting to define them
clearly. In 1875, the Marxists and Lassalleans united to form the German
Workers Party, the parent of the Social Democratic Party. Although the
Marxists were led by Bebel and Liebknecht, with whom Marx and Engels had
been in close personal touch for years, they agreed to a programmatic
statement which was decidedly unMarxian. Marxâs criticism is just and
penetrating; it exposes the philistinism, the lack of revolutionary
insight, the narrow nationalism and above all the State-idolatry of the
program. But why did he have to make it? How could his closest followers
mistake so grievously his teachings? The answer is that up to then Marx
had not put down on paper with any concreteness what he meant by
âCommunismâ or what were the long-range aims of socialism, as he saw
them. These disjointed notes on a long-forgotten program are still the
closet approach we have to a discussion by Marx of these principles. No
wonder Bebel and Liebknecht blundered, no wonder Marxists still disagree
as to just what Marx âreallyâ meant to say about many basic questions.
It is also significant that Marx and Engels, for tactical reasons, did
not make public their disagreement with the basic program of their
German followers. Engels explains why in a letter to Bebel (Oct. 12,
1875): âThe asses of the bourgeois papers have taken this program quite
seriously, have read into it what is not there and interpreted it in a
communist sense. The workers appear to do the same. It is this
circumstance alone which has made it possible for Marx and myself not to
dissociate ourselves publicly from such a program. So long as our
opponents and the workers likewise insert our views into this program,
it is possible for us to keep silent about it.â (What could be a more
striking example of the pragmatic approach to communication: that the
meaning of a statement lies in the effect it produces on the audience?
Again, Dewey and Marx come close...) So it was not until 16 years later
that Marxâs Critique was first published.
Instead of the teacher who enlightens, the revolutionary who inspires by
telling the truth however awkward the moment, Marx here as too often
elsewhere appears as the realpolitiker, willing to engage in chicanery
for an apparent political advantage. I write âapparentâ because, as is
often the case, this kind of pragmatic manipulation of the truth turned
out to be most unrealistic. For we know how the German Social Democracy
developed, how timidly respectable it was, how grotesquely unfitted to
make any kind of revolution. These tendencies were clear in the Gotha
Program, and Marx saw them, yet he refrained from saying anything in
public about them because the bourgeois âassesâ could not see them. But
the working class were also asses, since they âdo the sameâ; and one
might have expected Marx to want to enlighten them at least. How much
difference it would have made is a question. If Marx had been bolder and
more responsible in his handling of the Gotha Program, if the clear
definition of principles had appeared to him to be as important as the
elaboration of scientific investigation, at least the bureaucrats who
led the German Social Democracy to shameful defeat would have had more
difficulty in appropriating Marxism as an ideology â just as would also
the Stalinists today.
The modern faith in Science is closely related to another great modern
faith: the belief in Progress. This conception resolves the
contradiction between scientific method and value judgments by asserting
that there are not two worlds â but rather only one world, a world that
is in theory completely understandable through the scientific method. If
there is only one world, then there is no problem of values â indeed,
values exist only as reflections of more basic factors. To the believer
in Progress, however, this conclusion appears to mean that, in the
working-out of science, good values are implicit. (The
self-contradictions of this position have been examined in the preceding
section.) For it can easily be shown that there has been enormous
progress in science, and if scientific method can be applied to all of
mankindâs problems, then there is justification, almost a necessity, for
seeing a progressive pattern in manâs history. Not much progress can be
shown, it is true, in precisely the spheres which some of us think are
outside the scope of scientific method â ethics and art â though there
have been brave attempts to demonstrate even this, as when Engels writes
in the Anti-Duhring: âThat...there has on the whole been progress in
morality, as in all other branches of human knowledge, cannot be
doubted.â But if we assume, as does Marx, the most thoroughgoing of the
prophets of Science and Progress, that art and morality are projections
of some underlying reality which is accessible to science, then the
problem solves itself easily enough.[26] Especially if we adopt Marxâs
particular underlying reality: the development of the instruments of
production. For it is just in this field that science is most competent,
so that we can console ourselves for present unpleasantnesses by a
vision of a future in which science will have created for us the
splendid âmaterialistic baseâ for a glorious superstructure. The awkward
thing, of course, is that science has more than done its part and has
presented us by now with a materialistic base even grander than Marx
ever hoped for, culminating in atomic fission; while the results are
not, to say the least, glorious. But of that, more later.
It is important to recognize that, although Marx carried the notion of
scientific progress so far that he was able to monopolize the magic
term, âscientific socialism,â for his own system, this approach was by
no means peculiar to him but was rather that of Left political thinkers,
bourgeois and socialist alike, in the 19^(th) century. The only
important exception that occurs to me in Alexander Herzen.
Practically all our ideological ancestors were agreed on the notion of
scientific progress. The French Encyclopedists established this concept
in the 18^(th) century, and Condorcetâs Historical Outline of the
Progress of the Human Spirit (1795) was its first great statement. The
19^(th) century socialists â Utopian, Marxian and anarchist â who were
the historical heirs of the Encyclopedists, all tried to justify their
political systems in scientific terms. In this, they were the children
of their time. The only sceptical or hostile voices were those of
political conservatives like Burkhardt and De Tocqueville, of religious
spokesmen like Kierkegaard â and of the poets and novelists. That
something was lacking in the 18^(th) century ideology of scientific
progress could be deduced from the fact that it is hard to find a
literary man of the first rank whose values were either bourgeois or
socialist. Even Tolstoy, whose novels are perhaps the most successful
examples of naturalism in art we have, came to reject in the most
thoroughgoing way, the scientific and materialistic assumptions on which
naturalism is based.
This is such a crucial point, and the claims of Marxism to be the one
and only form of âscientific socialismâ are today so generally accepted
by both its friends and enemies, that it seems worth documenting it a
little. Let us hear what the three great Utopians and the two most
important anarchist theoreticians have to say on the question of science
and progress:
ROBERT OWEN: ...for the first time, I explained the science of
constructing a rational system of society for forming the character and
governing human nature beneficially for all our race...knowledge of this
scientific development of society was forced upon me by thirty years of
extensive practice through various departments of the business of real
life, and by much study to overcome the many obstacles which stood in
the way of combining a scientific arrangement of society to prevent the
innumerable evils inflicted by error on the human race...the first
publication ever given to the world which explained, even in its
outline, the circle of the practical science of society to form a good
and superior character for all, to produce abundance of superior wealth
for all, to unite all as members of a superior enlightened family. (The
Life of Robert Owen, by Himself; New York, 1920, p. 322.)
FOURIER: Our destiny is to advance; every social period must progress
toward the one above; it is Natureâs wish that barbarism should tend
toward civilization and attain to it by degrees... It is in vain, then,
Philosophers, that you accumulate libraries to search for happiness,
while the root of all social ills has not been eradicated: industrial
parcelling, or incoherent labor, which is the antipodes of Godâs
designs. You complain that Nature refuses you the knowledge of her laws:
well! if you have, up to the present, been unable to discover them, why
do you hesitate to recognize the insufficiency of your methods, and to
seek new ones? ... Do you see her refractory to the efforts of the
physicists as she is to yours? no, for they study her laws instead of
dictating laws to her...What a contrast between your blunderings and the
achievements of the exact sciences! Each day you add new errors to the
old ones, while each day sees the physical sciences advancing upon the
road of truth...(Selections from the Works of Fourier, edited by Charles
Gide; London, 1901; pp. 51â54.)
SAINT-SIMON: A new science, a science as positive as any that deserves
the name, has been conceived by Saint-Simon: the science of man. Its
method is the same as that of astronomy or physics... From our first
meeting we have repeated that Saint-Simonâs conception was provable by
history. Do not expect from us either the discussion of isolated facts â
laws as simple and constant as those of biology... Saint-Simon;s mission
was to discover these laws...Mankind, he said, is a collective being
which grows from one generation to the next as a single man grows
throughout his lifetime. This being has grown in obedience to its own
physiological law; and this law is that of progressive development...
Cast away your fears, then, gentlemen, and struggle no more against the
tide that bears you along with us toward a happy future; put an end to
the doubt that withers your heart and strikes you impotent. Lovingly
embrace the altar of reconciliation, for the time is come and the hour
will soon sounds when all will be called and all will be chose.
(Doctrine de Saint-Simon â a series of lectures by Bazard, Enfantin and
other disciples of Saint-Simon; originally published 1829; republished
Paris, 1924; pp. 92â3, 158, 161, 178.)
Proudhon: With the revolution, it is another matter... The idea of
Progress replaces that of the Absolute in philosophy...Reason, aided by
Experience, shows man the laws of nature and of society, and says to
him: âThese are the laws of necessity itself. No man has made them;
Nobody forces them upon you. They have little by little been discovered,
and I exist only to bear witness to them. If you observe them, you will
be just and righteous. If you violate them, you will be unjust and
wicked. I propose no other sanction for you.â (General Idea of the
Revolution in the 19^(th) Century, London, 1923, pp. 294â295.)
There is a quantitative science which compels agreement, excludes the
arbitrary, rejects all Utopian fancies; a science of physical phenomena
which grounds itself only on the observation of data... There ought to
be also a science of society â a science which is not to be invented but
rather discovered. (De la Celebration du Dimanche; quoted in La Pensée
Vivante de Proudhon, edited by Lucien Maury; Paris, 1942, p. 7.)
Kropotkin: Anarchism is a world-concept based upon a mechanical
explanation of all phenomena, embracing the whole of nature â that is,
including in it the life of human societies and their economic,
political and moral problems. Its method of investigation is that of the
exact natural sciences... Its aim is to construct a synthetic philosophy
comprehending in one generalization all the phenomena of nature â and
therefore also the life of societies... Whether or not anarchism is
right in its conclusions will be shown by a scientific criticism of its
bases and by the practical life of the future. But in one thing it is
absolutely right: in that it has included the study of social
institutions in the sphere of natural-scientific investigations; has
forever parted company with metaphysics; and makes use of the method by
which modern natural science and modern materialist philosophy were
developed. (âModern Science and Anarchismâ; in Kropotkinâs Revolutionary
Pamphlets, New York, 1927, pp. 150 and 193.)
There are two striking similarities between the above quotations and
Marxist doctrine: (1) the rejection of philosophical idealism and the
attempt to put socialism on a scientific and materialistic basis; (2) a
related optimism about history, in the sense that it is assumed that the
more contradictory, irrational and humanly destructive social
institutions are, the more surely will they be superseded by socialism.
The first similarity is interesting in the light of the Marxistsâ
successful appropriation â shall we say âexpropriation?â â of the
once-magic term âscientific socialism.â As the above quotations show,
the anarchists and Utopians were just as concerned as Marx was to put
socialism on a scientific basis. The difference is simply that where he,
following Hegel, looked to history for this, they, following rather the
French Encyclopedists, looked to biology, psychology, and anthropology.
If Marxism is historical materialism, their theories might be called
natural-science materialism. Engels, who vulgarized and distorted so
much of Marxâs thought, is responsible for the confusion here too: his
famous pamphlet, Socialism â Utopian and Scientific, draws the line
between Marx and the âUtopiansâ entirely in terms of historical theory;
it was such a brilliantly effective piece of special-pleading that to
this day the friends and enemies of Marxism alike agree (wrongly) that
it is indeed the sole form of âscientific socialism.â
The second similarity â the optimism about the ultimate rationality of
history â is interesting, too. It may be that one of the reasons for the
lack in our time of any socialist theoreticians that measure up to the
giants of the 19^(th) century is that society has become too irrational
and humanly destructive. A minimum degree of human rationality is
perhaps necessary in a social system for its opponents to criticize it
effectively, just as disagreement is not possible unless the disputants
have something in common; parallel lines do not conflict. Marxâs exposĂ©
of capitalist economics, or Proudhonâs of representative government â
such achievements were possible only because there was a certain minimum
rationality in the institutions criticized, so that their defenders were
compelled to stand on certain general principles. The difficulty in
evolving a theoretical criticism of Bureaucratic Collectivism today may
partly lie in the completely destructive, opportunistic and nihilistic
character of the phenomenon, so that there is nothing to get a hold of,
so to speak, On the one hand, the fraudulent pretensions of The Enemy to
rationality and human decency can easily be refuted â all too easily.
But on the other hand, the power of The Enemy to maintain this fraud is
far greater than it was in the last century. Thus we have social
institutions which are more easily shown to be bad than were those in
Marxâs and Proudhonâs time, and yet which show a survival power quite
unexpected by those great but far too confident thinkers. The process of
history, in a word, appears now to be a more complex and tragic matter
than it appeared to the socialist and anarchist thinkers, who were,
after all, children of their age, not ours. The area of of the
unpredictably, perhaps even unknowable, appears far greater now than it
did then. At least it does if we think in their rational and scientific
terms â and we have not yet worked out satisfactory alternative terms.
One things is, finally, notable: since 1914, it has not been the
Marxists who have made important contributions to historical thinking
(although theirs is par-excellence a historical discipline) but rather
non-materialistic and anti-socialist historians like Toynbee and
Spengler.
As D.S. Savage has pointed out (âSocialism in Extremis,â politics,
January 1945), those who build their political philosophy on the idea of
progress tend to justify the Means by the End, the Present by the
Future, the Here by the There. the Progressive can swallow war as a
Means to the End, peace; he can overlook the unsatisfactory Present by
fixing his eyes on a distant and perfect Future, as in the case of the
USSR; he can justify the loss of individualâs freedom Here as necessary
to a workable organization of society There. He is able to perform these
considerable feats of abstract thinking because he, who makes so free
with the charge of âmetaphysicianâ and âUtopian,â is actually the
arch-metaphysician of our time, quite prepared to sacrifice indefinitely
and on the most grandiose scale the real, material, concrete interests
of living human beings on the altar of a metaphysical concept of
Progress which he assumes (again metaphysically) is the âreal essenceâ
of history.
And what an assumption this idea is based on: nothing less than the
daring hypothesis â which the Progressive advances as if it were the
most elementary common sense â that the ârealâ nature of scientific
advance is to benefit humanity. There are, it is admitted, certain
regrettable by-products of this advance. The atomic bomb is one, and
another is the new âgerm sprayâ developed by our own scientists which
promises to make The Bomb look positively benevolent. An unidentified
member of Congress gives a lyrical account of its possibilities:
âThey have developed a weapon that can wipe out all forms of life in a
large city. It is a germ proposition and is sprayed from airplanes... It
is quick and certain death. You would not have to drop a germ on every
person in a city. One operation would be sufficient, for the effects
would spread rapidly.â(New York Times, May 25, 1946.)
According to the scientific metaphysician, this sort of things is a
regrettable by-product of Progress, a perversion, in fact. He will point
out that this lethal germ spray has also been developed, in the form of
DDT, to rid mankind of those insect pests which cause $5,678,945,001
worth of damage in this country alone every year (or fill in your own
figures). And he will conclude that the problem is to use it for Good
instead of Evil, or more specifically, to spray it on insects but not on
people. The solution of this problem is for us to become even more
scientifically-minded than we are now, to extend the sway of scientific
method over ethics; if he is a Marxist, he will call this approach
âdialectical.â if one suggests that perhaps there may be more Evil than
Good in scientific progress, not in the sense that there is anything
intrinsically (i.e. metaphysically) good or bad about such progress, but
in the historical sense that up to now the Bad results of every
technological advance seem to outweigh the Good ones, and that what with
The Bomb and our new DDT-for-People this promises to be even more
strikingly the case in the future â if one ventures such a wild notion,
his reaction is violent. One is told â and I speak from experience â
that one is (1) an ascetic who rejects this-worldly, human satisfaction
in favor of some kind of mortification of the flesh; (2) a Utopian
dreamer whose value judgment, regardless of its ethical merits, has not
the slightest practical significance or chance of historical
realization.
I think it can be argued, in both cases, that the shoe is on the other
foot.
(1) Personally, I am not particularly ascetic. It is, indeed, just
because I do value human, this-worldly satisfactions that I am skeptical
about Scientific Progress. The real materialists today are those who
reject Historical Materialism. For manâs mastery of nature has led to
natureâs mastering man. The ever more efficient organization of
technology in the form of large, disciplined aggregations of producers
implies the modern mass-society which implies authoritarian controls and
the kind of irrational â subrational, rather â nationalist ideology we
have seen developed to its highest pitch in Germany and Russia. The one
great power today whose culture is most materialistic, whose leaders
proclaim themselves Marxists, where the crudest optimism of progress is
rampant, is also the one where the alienation of man from his own
products has gone the farthest, the one whose citizens lead the lives of
bees or of ants but not of men, the one whose soldiers, fresh from the
land of materialistic progress and Five Year Plans, are astounded at the
ease, luxury and comfort of life in Bulgaria and will commit any crime
to possess themselves of a bicycle. So we, too, may perish in the next
war because atomic fission is the latest stage of scientific discovery,
and Progress depends on the advancement of science. But a simple-minded
person might see in such modern truisms as that you must reach socialism
through dictatorship (âSure, the Soviet Union isnât democratic, but
thatâs the only way a backward country can be raised to an industrial
level that will support democratic institutions later on â just wait
fifty years!â) or that atomic fission holds ultimate promise of the
Abundant Life â such a simple person might see in these propositions a
similarity to that promise of a better life in Heaven on which the
Catholic Church banks so heavily.
(2) It may be that the fact that Western intellectuals are showing more
and more signs of what Sidney Hook has called âthe new failure of nerveâ
â i.e., skepticism about scientific progress â is of some historical
significance, for intellectuals often sense now what most people will
believe later on. Is it fantastic to imagine that large masses of people
may become, as life grows increasingly unbearable in our
scientifically-planned jungle, what might be called Human materialists
(as against the Historical and Progressive variety)? That they may
conclude that they donât want electric iceboxes if the industrial system
required to produce them also produces World War III, or that they would
prefer fewer and worse or even no automobiles if the price for more and
better is the regimentation of people on a scale which precludes their
behaving humanly toward each other?
I would draw the readerâs attention to the word âifâ in the preceding
sentence. I am not saying that it is impossible to produce automobiles
without also producing war and bureaucracy; I am merely proposing a line
of action if this turns out to be the case. It is a complex question
what is the maximum scale on which institutions can be good, and also of
how scientific inquiry may be utilized for good ends. The answer will
depend, first, on our value judgment and to what is good; and second on
the results of scientific inquiry into the ways, in a certain time and
place, science and technology may be used to bring about this good. I
suspect there is a point of technological development beyond which the
bad human results must outweigh the good ones under any conceivable
social system. But I am not at all sure this is true; and Paul and
Percival Goodman, for example, have come to the opposite conclusion:
that a conflict between technological efficiency and human good is
theoretically impossible, and that where one seems to exist it is
because our faulty culture leads us to a false conception of efficiency.
They would argue, for example, that the saving in producing automobiles
in huge plants like River Rouge is more than offset by the waste
involved in the workers travelling long distances to the job, the huge
distributive network necessary, etc. Their book, Communitas, demonstrate
this thesis. It may be true; I hope it is. But my point here is that the
harmony of industrial efficiency and human good is still an open
question, not a closed one, as the Progressives assume.
The bomb that vaporized Hiroshima less than a year ago also levelled â
though some of us donât seem yet aware of it â the whole structure of
Progressive assumptions on which liberal and socialist theory has been
built up for two centuries. For now, for the first time in history,
humanity faces the possibility that its own activity may result in the
destruction not of some people of some part of the world, but of all
people and the whole world for all time. The end may come through
radioactive substances which will poison the atmosphere, or through a
chain reaction riping apart the earthâs crust, releasing the molten rock
in the interior. Most scientists say that at the present stage of
development of atomic energy, that it not possible (though others say it
is). But no one can say definitely what will happen in another decade or
two of Atomic Progress. Scientific progress has reached its âend,â and
the end is turning out to be the end (without quotes) of man
himself.[27]
What becomes of the chief argument of Progressives â that out of present
evil will come future good â if we now confront the possibility that
there may not be a future? In that once popular expression of the
Progressive ideology of the last century, Winwood Readeâs The Martyrdom
of Man, the author writes: âI give to universal history a strange but
true title: âThe Martyrdom of Man.â In each generation, the human race
has been tortured that their children might profit by their woes. Our
own prosperity is founded on the agonies of the past. Is it therefore
unjust that we should also suffer for the benefit of those who are to
come?â And what a future Reade saw rising out of the agonies of the
present! He expected scientific progress to enable man to travel among
the stars, to manufacture his own suns and solar systems, to conquer
death itself. The progress has not failed, but it has brought universal
death; instead of manufacturing new solar systems, man seems more likely
to destroy his own little globe. And our sufferings, far from being for
the benefit of those who are to come, are more likely to remove the
first condition of their coming: the existence of an inhabited earth.
It is the materialistic Reade who today appears grotesquely metaphysical
in his assumptions. So, too, Engels: âThe process of replacing some
500,000 Russian landowners and some 80 million peasants by a new class
of bourgeois landed proprietors cannot be carried out except under the
most fearful sufferings and convulsions. But history is about the most
cruel of goddesses, and she drives her triumphal car over heaps of
corpses, not only in war but also in âpeacefulâ economic development.
And we men and women are unfortunately so stupid that we can never pluck
up courage to a real progress unless urged to it by sufferings almost
out of proportion... There is no great historical evil without a
compensating historical progress.â (Letters to Danielson, Feb. 24 and
Oct. 17, 1893.) So long as there was an indefinite future before us,
this kind of Progressive metaphysics had at least the appearance of
reasonability. No one could prove, after all, that after several
centuries or even several millennia of sufferings, detours, and
âtemporary regressions,â history would not finally lead humanity to the
promised kingdom. It was thus logical â how sensible is another matter â
to view the present in terms of the future. But now that we confront the
actual, scientific possibility of The End being written to human history
and at a not so distant date, the concept of the future, so powerful an
element in traditional socialist thought, loses for us its validity.
This bitter enlightenment, if from it we can learn to live in the here
and now, may offer us the one possible escape from our fate.
To the Progressive, art is as awkward a subject as ethics. Esthetic
values cannot be scientifically grounded any more than morals can. Nor
can art be fitted into the pattern of historical progress; the Greeks
were technologically as primitive as they were esthetically civilized;
we have outstripped Archimedes but not Sophocles. Finally, if values are
taken to be historically relative, why do we enjoy art created thousands
of years ago and expressing a way of life alien to ours in most ways?
These questions bothered Marx, who was personally sensitive to
literature ant to that of the Greeks especially. He tries to answer them
at the end of the Critique of Political Economy:
âIt is well known that certain periods of highest development of art
stand in no direct connection with the general development of society,
nor with the material basis and the skeleton structure of its
organization. Witness the example of the Greeks as compared with the
modern nations... The difficulty lies only in the general formulation of
these contradictions. No sooner are they specified than they are
explained. Let us take for instance the relation of Greek art... to our
own... Is the view of nature and of social relations which shaped Greek
imagination and Greek art possible in the age of automatic machinery and
railways and locomotives and electric telegraphs? Where does Vulcan come
in as against Roberts & Co.; Jupiter as against the lightning rod; and
Hermes as against the Credit Mobilizer? All mythology, i.e., that nature
and even the form of society are wrought up in popular fancy in an
unconsciously artistic fashion... Is Achilles possible side by side with
powder and lead? Or is The Iliad at all compatible with the printing
press and the steam press? Do not singing and reciting and the muses
necessarily go out of existence with the appearance of the printerâs
bar, and do not, therefore, disappear the requisites of epic poetry?â
Two things are striking about this passage: (1) the way Marx goes to the
heart of a question; (2) the fact that it is not the question he started
to answer. Instead of showing, in historical-materialist terms, how the
existence of a high art may be reconciled with its low material base
(the âhighâ and âlow,â as Marx uses them, are value terms, please note),
he slides over into a demonstration of quite another matter: that Greek
art presupposes mythology, which is no longer possible once man has
mastered nature. From a value problem which his system cannot deal with,
Marx slips into a historical problem it can handle admirably.
But one of the signs that Marx was a great thinker is that his thought
is often more profound than his system, which is why he bothered by all
sorts of things it never occurred to his epigones to see as problems at
all. A Kautsky would have let it go at the above passage, quite
satisfied (not that he could lave written it in the first place; he
would have taken twenty pages and would have muffled the point in the
end). But Marx was evidently still uneasy, vaguely aware that he had
evaded the real problem. So he returns to it: âBut the difficultly is
not in grasping the idea that Greek art and epos are bound up with
certain forms of social development. It rather lies in understanding why
they still constitute with us a source of esthetic enjoyment and in
certain respects prevail as the standard and model beyond attainment.â
Here at least Marx puts the question unequivocally. His answer is less
satisfactory: âA man cannot become a child again unless he becomes
childish. But does he not enjoy the artless ways of the child and must
he not strive to reproduce its truth on a higher plane?... Why should
the social childhood of mankind, where it had obtained its most
beautiful development, not exert an eternal charm as an age that will
never return? There are ill-bred children and precocious children... The
Greeks were normal children... The charm their art does for us does not
conflict with the primitive character of the social order from which it
had sprung. It is rather the product of the latter, and is rather due to
the fact that the unripe social conditions under which the art arose and
under which it alone could appear can never return.â
This seems to me an appalling judgment. In the typical
philistine-sentimental manner, Marx affects to see Greek art as a
charming object from a vanished past, something which the modern stands
apart from and appreciates, which an indulgent smile, as the adult looks
at the little joys and sorrows of children. To the philistine, indeed,
it is precisely the apartness, the definitely long-done-with-ness of
Greek art that is its most fascinating characteristic; since thus he may
accept it without letting it disturb his complacency about the Progress
made since then (âunripe social conditionsâ). Marx was not a philistine,
which is why I said he âaffectedâ to view Homer in this light. I think
that his esthetic sensibility was too lively, his imagination too
profound, for him to make such a judgment spontaneously. He was coerced
to it by the necessities of his historical-materialist system, in which
he was imprisoned, alienated from values as surely as the proletarian is
alienated from the products of his labor; there was no other way for him
to escape acknowledging that there are suprahistorical values in art.
As it chances, Simone Weilâs âThe Iliad, or the Poem of Forceâ
(politics, November 1945), puts forward the opposite thesis to Marxâs.
She shows that the Homeric Greeks had a more adult conception of warfare
and suffering than we have â it is we who are children, and ill-bred
children at that â and that, far from being able to stand apart and view
The Iliad as an expression of a primitive, long-past world, we are so
close to its mood today that we can view our own deepest fears and
emotions in its terms. Without a single direct reference to the present
â the essay was written in the months following the fall of Paris â Weil
is able to communicate our modern tragedy through a scrupulous analysis
of the ethical content of The Iliad. Except for a few Marxists, who
could not understand why a political magazine should feature a
âliteraryâ article, everyone who read the article seemed to grasp the
point at once: that by writing about a poem written three thousand years
ago, Simone Weil has somehow been able to come closer to contemporary
reality that the journalists who comment on current events. She had, of
course, the immense advantage over Marx of living in a time when the
19^(th) century dream of progress has collapsed in brutality, cruel and
helpless suffering so that our kinship with Homerâs dark times emerge
clearly. Thus the historical method may be used to show its own
limitations. For we can now see, from our own present experience, that
during the last century, for certain historical reasons, the grim visage
of History was overlaid for a time by illusions which were powerful
enough to deceive even so profound a sensibility as Marxâs â and one of
such a naturally tragic cast, too.
My purpose in writing this article is to find a basis for political
action.[28] This may seem an odd statement, since the article deals with
only the most general kind of theoretical questions while its proposals
for actions, as will shortly appear, are of the most modest nature. But
it is because the traditional assumptions of the Left about political
action no longer seem valid that it is necessary, if we are to act, to
begin by criticising them in broad terms. I am enough of a Marxist to
agree that creative political action must be based on theory, and enough
of a Christian to agree that we cannot act for good ends until we have
clarified the nature of Good. So another of the paradoxes among which we
uncomfortably exist is that we can find a road to action only through
philosophical speculations.
If this article has a âpoint,â I should say it is that it criticises the
Progressive notion of what is ârealâ and what is âunrealâ in political
action. It seems to me that the view of this crucial question which Marx
put forward as his major contribution to socialist thought has by now
become generally accepted among Progressives of all shades, from
Trotskyists to New Dealers. This is that consciousness (and conscience)
are less ârealâ than the material environment, and that the individual
is less ârealâ than society; that is, that the former of these two pairs
depend on the latter, are determined by the latter.[29] From this
follows the assumption that the only ârealâ political action is on a
mass scale, one involving trade unions, parties, the movements of
classes. This means that, politically, one thinks of people in terms of
classes or parties instead of in terms of individual human beings; and
also that oneâs own motivation for action springs from identification
with a class or a historical process rather than from oneâs personal
sense of what is right and true. In short, the historical, rather than
the personal level of action, is thought to be the Real level, and the
criterion of Reality in judging a political proposal is how many people
it sets in motion. This quantitative standard is typical of our
scientized culture.
It is to Marx above all that we owe the present general acceptance of
this criterion of Reality. The difficulty today, as I showed in Part I
of this article, is that the Marxian notion of historical Reality and
the Marxian revolutionary values have come into conflict: i.e., that the
course of Marxâs History seems to be leading us away from socialism as
Marx conceived of it. This split puts Marxians into one of two untenable
positions: either their programs command mass support but donât lead
towards socialism (Stalinists, French and Italian Socialists, British
labor Party); or else their programs remain faithful to socialist
principles but command no significant following (U.S. Socialists,
Trotskyists, Britainâs Independent Labor Party). In a word, political
activity along Marxian lines today is either Real but not Socialist, or
Socialist but not Real.
What, then, Is To Be Done? In a 1946 issue of Pacifica Views, a reader
describes a meeting of the Philadelphia branch of the Committee for
Non-Violent Revolution:
â...we proceeded to get down to the business at hand, the first item of
which was an evaluation of the two recent CO demonstrations in
Washington and at Byberry. All agreed that they were damn good
demonstrations... The group displayed the greatest interest in a
discussion of Dwight Macdonaldâs recent article, âThe Root Is Man.â
Everyone agreed it is a damn good article and that the world is in a
helluva shape. At 9:45 some intemperate person slipped in a question
about âwhat can we DO?â There was a momentary silence, someone mentioned
cooperatives and there was a general agreement that cooperatives were
very valuable. This it was 9:50 and time for the meeting to break up. A
half hour later, as I leaned against the bar and fondled my glass of
beer, the thought occurred to me that the eveningâs discussions had
ended at the same place all the articles I could recall having read in
Pacifica Views or politics had ended.â
This is a perfectly natural reaction, and a widespread one. When I first
began politics, readers used to ask me all the time what they could DO ?
(They donât ask so much now...) All I could ever think of to suggest was
reading, thinking, and writing; but, as several were rude enough to
point out, even if these pursuits were granted the honorable status of
Action, the answer was helpful only to scholars, journalists â and to
the editors. Since then, I must admit that such halfhearted additional
suggestions as I made about working in the trade unions or in some group
like the Socialist Party or the Michigan Commonwealth Federation (it
seems incredible, but I once wrote a lead article about the MCF as a
potential mass-socialist party), that even these appear less and less
worth investing time and hope in. On the other hand, some of us late
seem to be getting some dim notion at least of the kind of political
activity worth engaging in. the specific forms of action, and the
organizations to carry them out, are yet to be created. We seem to be in
early stages of a new concept of revolutionary and socialist politics,
where we can hope for the present only to clear the ground, to criticise
in a new direction. Anarchism and pacifism provide the best leads for
this direction, but only leads; something quite different from either of
them, as they have traditionally developed, will probably have to be
evolved.
The trouble with mass action today is that the institutions (parties,
trade unions) and even the very media of communication one must use for
it have become so perverted away from sensible human aims that any
attempt to work along that line corrupts oneâs purposes â or else, if
one resists corruption in the sense of sticking by oneâs principles, one
becomes corrupt in a subtler way: one pretends to be speaking to and for
millions of workers when one is not even speaking to and for thousands;
we are familiar with the revolutionary rodomontade of tiny Marxist
parties which address themselves to an âinternational proletariatâ which
never pays the slightest attention to them; this is a species of
self-deception, at best, and at worst a kind of bluffing game. It is
time we called that bluff.
As socialists, our central problem today is what George LukĂĄcs calls
âreificationâ (âthingificationâ), that process which Marx prophetically
described in his theory of âalienationâ: the estrangement of man from
his own nature by the social forces he himself generates.
âThis crystallization of social activity,â write the young Marx and
Engels in The German Ideology, âthis consolidation of what we ourselves
produce into an objective power above us, growing out of our control,
thwarting our expectations, bringing to naught our calculations, is one
of the chief factors in historical development up to now. And out of
this very contradiction between the interest of the individual and that
of the community, the latter takes and independent form as THE STATE,
divorced from the real interests of individual and community... The
social power, i.e., the multiplied productive forces... appears to these
individuals, since their cooperation is not voluntary but coerced, not
as their own united power but as an alien force existing outside them,
of the origin and end of which they are ignorant, which on the contrary
passes through a peculiar series of phases and stages independent of the
will and action of men â nay, even the prime governor of these!...
âHow does it come about that the personal interests continually grow,
despite the persons, into class-interests, into common interests which
win an independent existence over against the individual persons...? How
does it come about that, within this process of the self-assertion of
personal interests as class-interests, the personal behavior of the
individual must become hard and personal behavior of the individual must
become hard and remote, estranged from itself...?â[30]
It is not difficult to sketch out the kind of society we need to rescue
modern man from his present alienation. It would be one whose only aim,
justification and principle would be the full development of each
individual, and the removal of all social bars to his complete and
immediate satisfaction in his work, his leisure, his sex life and all
other aspects of his nature. (To remove all social bars does not, of
course, mean to remove all bars; complete happiness and satisfaction is
probably impossible in any society, and would be dull even if possible;
regardless of the excellence of social institutions, there will always
be, for example, persons who are in love with other who arenât in love
with them.) This can only be done if each individual understands what he
is doing and has the power, within the limitations of his own
personality and of our common human imperfection, to act exactly as he
thinks best for himself. This in turn depends on people entering into
direct personal relationships with each other, which in turn mean that
the political and economic units of society (workshops, exchange of
goods, political institutions) are small enough to allow the participant
to understand them and to make their individual influence felt. It
effective wars cannot be fought by groups the size of New England town
meetings, and I take it them cannot, this is one more reason for giving
up war (rather than the town meeting). If automobiles cannot be made
efficiently by small factories, then let us make them inefficiently. If
scientific research would be hampered in a small-unit society, then let
us by all means hamper it. Said the young Marx: âFor Hegel, the
starting-point is the State. In a democracy, the starting-point is
man... Man in not made for the law, but the law is made for man.â
This is all clear enough. What is not so generally understood is that
the traditional Progressive approach, taking History as the
starting-point and thinking in terms of mass political parties, bases
itself on the same alienation of man which it thinks it is combating. It
puts the individual into the same powerless, alienated role vis-Ă -vis
the party or the trade union as the manipulators of the modern State do,
except that the slogans are different. The current failure of the
European masses to get excited about socialist slogans and programs
indicates that the masses are, as Rosa Luxemburg constantly and rightly
insisted, much smarter and more âadvancedâ than their intellectual
leaders. The brutal fact is that the man in the street everywhere is
quite simply bored with socialism, as expounded by the Socialist,
Stalinist, and Trotskyist epigones of Marx, that he suspects it is just
a lot of stale platitudes which either have no particular meaning
(Socialists, Trotskyists, British labor Party), or else a sinister one
(Stalinists). Above all, he feels that there is no interest in it for
him, as an individual human being â that he is as powerless and
manipulated vis-Ă -vis his socialist mass-organization as he is towards
his capitalistic employers and their social and legal institutions.
Here is observable a curious and unexpected (to Progressives) link
between the masses and those dissident intellectuals here and there who
are beginning to show a distrust of the old Marxian-Deweyan-Progressive
verities and to cast about for some firmer ground. Each party, in its
own way, has come to find the old slogans and axioms either treacherous
or boring â mostly the latter. boring because they give no promise of
leading to that which they proclaim, and meanwhile still further
alienate man from his true and spontaneous nature.
From all this one thing seems to follow: we must reduce political action
to a modest, unpretentious, personal level â one that is real in the
sense that it satisfies, here and now, the psychological needs, and the
ethical values of the particular persons taking part in it. We must
begin way at the bottom again, with small groups of individuals in
various countries, grouped around certain principles and feelings they
have in common, These should probably not be physically isolated
communities as was the case in the 19^(th) century since this shuts one
off from the common experience of oneâs fellowmen. They should probably
consist of individuals â families, rather â who love and make their
living in the everyday world but who come together often enough to form
a psychological (as against a geographical) community. The purpose of
such groups would be twofold. Within itself, the group would exist so
that its members could come to know each other as fully as possible as
human beings (the difficulty of such knowledge of others in modern
society is a chief source of evil), to exchange ideas and discuss as
fully as possible what is âon their mindsâ (not only the atomic bomb but
also the perils of child-rearing), and in general to learn the difficult
art of living with other people. The groupâs purpose toward the outside
world would be to take certain actions together (as, against Jim Crow in
this country, or to further pacifism), to support individuals whether
members of the group or not who stand up for the common ideals, and to
preach those ideals â or, if you prefer, make propaganda â by word and
by deed, in the varied everyday contacts of the group members with their
fellow men (as, trade union meetings, parent-teacher associations,
committees for âworthy causes,â cocktail partied, etc.).[31]
The ideas which these groups would advance, by word and deed, would
probably run along something like the following lines:
all past imagination make pacifism, in my opinion, a sine-qua-non of any
Radical movement. The first great principle would, therefore, be the
killing and hurting others is wrong, always and absolutely, and that no
member of the group will use such methods or let himself be drafter to
do so.[32]
party, is also wrong in principle, and will be opposed with sabotage,
ridicule, evasion, argument, or simple refusal to submit to authority â
as circumstances may require. Our model here would be the old I.W.W.
rather than then Marxist Internationals.[33]
the future will be looked on with suspicion. People should be happy and
should satisfy their spontaneous needs here and now.[34] If people donât
enjoy what they are doing, they shouldnât do it. (this includes the
activities of the group.) This point is a leaning, a prejudice rather
than a principle; that is, the extent to which it is acted on would be
relative to other things.
want it at any given moment has nothing to do with its validity for the
individual who makes it his value. What he does, furthermore, is
considered to be just as ârealâ as what History does.
Progressive frame of mind, of acting here and now, on however tiny a
scale, for their beliefs. They would do as the handful of British and
American scientists did who just refused, as individuals and without any
general support, to make atomic bombs; not as Albert Einstein and other
eminent scientists are now doing â raising money for an educational
campaign to show the public how horrible The Bomb is, while they
continue to cooperate with General Groves in making more and bigger
bombs.
themselves from the Marxian fetishism of the masses, preferring to be
able to speak modest meaningful truths to a small audience rather than
grandiose empty formulae to a big one. This also means, for the moment,
turning to the intelligentsia as oneâs main supporters, collaborators
and audience, on the assumption that what we are looking for represents
so drastic a break with past traditions of thinking and behaving that at
this early stage only a few crackpots and eccentrics (i.e.,
intellectuals) will understand what weâre talking about, or care about
it at all. We may console ourselves that all new social movements,
including Marxism, have begun this way: with a few intellectuals rather
than at the mass level.
While it is still too soon to be definite about what a Radical does
(beyond the vague suggestions just indicated), it is possible to
conclude with a more concrete idea of what he is. What are his attitudes
toward politics? They may be summed up under five heads:
The first two adjectives which occur to a Progressive when confronted
with a Radical attitude are: ânegativisticâ and âunrealistic.â In this
section, let us consider the former.
During the late war, those of us who opposed it were told by
Progressives who supported it that our position was absurd because we
couldnât âdo anythingâ about it; that is, we couldnât stop the war. They
felt that they were at least acting in accordance with their
convictions; that is, they were helping bring about an Allied victory.
This criticism, however, reveals as incomprehension of the nature of
modern social organization: there is no place in the orderly,
bureaucratized workings of a first-class power today for individual
emotion, will, choice, or action. As the late Dr. Goebbels well
expressed it: âMoods and emotions, the so-called âmoraleâ of the
population, matters little. What matters is that they should preserve
their bearing (Haltung)... Expressions such a patriotism and enthusiasm
are quite out of place. The German people simply do their duty, thatâs
all.â (Das Reich, April 9, 1943.) The Progressive is the victim of an
illusion which he could puncture for himself in a moment if, instead of
doing what his Draft Board told him to do, he had tried to volunteer for
the work he thought he could do best. He would have been told by some
harassed bureaucrat: âFor Godâs sake, go home and wait till we call you.
Donât some around upsetting our Selective Service system, which is a
delicate and complex affair geared to process so many of you patriots in
such and such a time for such and such kinds of service.â Thus the only
difference between those who submit to the draft because they are afraid
not to and those who welcome it because they want their country to win
the war, is in the ethical value attached to an identical action. But
the Progressive, as a good Deweyan or Marxian, does not believe in
values apart from action. The Radical, however, does not submit to the
draft; he refuses to do what the State wants him to do; by not acting,
he is thus acting â and in the Deweyan sense that what he does (or
rather doesnât) distinguishes him from those with different values. The
only way to be positive vis-Ă -vis the modern State is to be negative,
i.e., refuse to do what it wants one to do. The situation might be
compared to a group of people being driven in a high-powered automobile
along a road that ends in a precipice. They see the Radicals sitting by
the side of the road â just sitting. âYaahh, negativists!â they cry.
âLook at us! Weâre really doing something!â (There is no space here to
develop the relevance of Lao-Tseâs principle of ânon-actingâ â and
perhaps it is not necessary.)
The Progressive insists that one has a duty in every situation to choose
between what he calls ârealâ alternatives, and that it is irresponsible
to refuse to make such a choice. By ârealâ he means an alternative which
has a reasonably good chance of success. Thus in World War II, he saw
two real alternatives: to support the Allies or to support Hitler. He
naturally chose the former. The trouble with his ârealâ alternatives is
that each of them is part of the whole system of war and exploitation,
to put an end to which is the very justification of his choice. The
Radical believes â and I think logic is on his side â that only an
alternative which is antithetical to the existing system can lead one to
the abolition of the system. For him, it is unrealistic to hope to
secure a peaceful world through war, to hope to defeat the brutality and
oppression of Hitler by the brutality and oppression of the American and
Russian political systems. Consider the Radical approach to the present
situation of France, for example. Today that country lies between two
mighty imperialisms: Russian and Anglo-American. The French Progressive
wants to create a decent socialist society in France and to avoid the
destruction of France in a future war between the two blocs. But in his
terms of ârealâ alternatives, he can only think of aligning France with
one or the other of the two powerblocs (with Russia if he is a
Communist, with Anglo-America if he is a Socialist) and making France as
strong a power as possible. It is not hard to show that a weak power
which allies itself to a stronger one does not thereby avert war and
does not even escape being sacrificed as a pawn in that coming war; and
that, as the examples of Nazi Germany and Stalinist Russia show us, to
build a strong army and munitions industry means to enslave and oppress
the people, regardless of the literary charm of the slogans under which
the dirty work is done. The Radical Frenchman would begin by himself,
personally, refusing cooperation in the above policy, sabotaging it at
every chance, and trying to persuade by argument and emotional appeal
his fellow men and women to do likewise. The final perspective would be
a pacifist-socialist revolution; this would have at least a chance of
striking fire in the hearts of other peoples, spurring them to similar
action against their oppressors. Success would be problematic, but at
least (1) it would not be logically and historically inconceivable ( as
is the case with the Progressiveâs armament-and-alliance program), and
(2) his end would be congruent with his means, so that he could view the
situation with clear eyes and a whole heart, free from the befuddling
and stultifying evasions and compromises which the Progressive must
resort to in such a situation.[35]
the greatest living theorist of Progressivism, as defined in this
article, is John Dewey. It seems not irrelevant to recall that Dewey
gave active support to both World War I and II. The contrast between the
Progressive and the Radical notions of ârealisticâ and âpositiveâ action
comes out in the contrasting behavior in World War I of Dewey and his
brilliant young disciple, Randolph Bourne.
âIn 1916,â we read in Louis Fillerâs life of Bourne, âBourne broke with
John Dewey, and a rift opened that was to become wider as both men
formulated their stands on the war. The differences between them were to
culminate in a statement of principles by Bourne which was to stand as
perhaps his supreme literary achievement. Dewey had slowly come around
to the conviction that war represented a state of affairs which had to
be faced and mastered by men who wished to be effective social agents...
The justice of the Allied cause was the assumption behind the articles
which Dewey contributed to The New Republic and The Dial in the interim
between American isolation and Americaâs entrance into the war. Deweyâs
role was to provide the theoretical base for armed preparedness.
âDeweyâs conclusions followed logically from his philosophy because the
essence of pragmatism was action. âOur culture,â he wrote, âmust be
consonant with realistic science and machine industry, instead of a
refuge from them.â (âAmerican Education and Cultureâ, New Republic, July
1,1916.) If the task of the day was war, then our culture must be
âconsonantâ with war. Dewey, therefore, called for army training as a
form of contemporary education. (New Republic, April 22, 1916.)
âThe very thought of military regimentation aroused in Bourne the
keenest agitation, and out of his desperate denial of the idea came one
of his most brilliant essays: âA Moral Equivalent for Universal Military
Serviceâ (New Republic, July 1, 1916.)... It was persuasive but was it
practical> It demonstrated how essentially the poet Bourne was, that the
relative value of education and war, and not the question of how he or
anyone else could most effectively influence American affairs for the
better, seemed to him the immediate question demanding solution...
Bourne was fighting for a doomed cause.â
That Filler shares, on its most Philistine level, Deweyâs pragmatic
approach only adds to the weight of the above contrast; he evidently
considers Bourne and idiot(âpoetâ is the polite term in this country)
for being so âimpracticalâ about war. (Who could improve on Fillerâs
incautious formulation of the Deweyan approach: âIf the task of the day
was war, then our culture must be consonant with war?â) Yet Deweyâs role
in World War I is now an embarrassing episode to be glossed over
lightly; while Bourneâs development From Deweyan pragmatism to a Radical
viewpoint, with anarchist and pacifist overtones, enable him to write
during the war his finest articles and to see with a ârealismâ denied to
Dewey the political meaning of the catastrophe: the end of the 19^(th)
Century Progressive dream. Bourneâs cause was doomed; Dewey got his war;
yet whose was the triumph?
Writing of Homerâs constant demonstration of the evanescence of power,
Simone Weil observes:
âThis retribution... was the main subject of Greek thought. It is the
soul of the epic. Under the name of Nemesis, it functions as the
mainspring of Aeschylusâ tragedies. To the Pythagoreans, to Socrates and
Plato, it was the jumping-off point of speculation upon the nature of
man and the universe. Wherever Hellenism has penetrated, we find the
idea of it familiar. In Oriental countries, which are steeped in
Buddhism, it is perhaps the Greek idea that has lived on under the name
of Kharma. The Occident, however, has lost it, and no longer even has a
word to express it in any of its languages: conceptions of limit,
measure, equilibrium, which ought to determine the conduct of life are,
in the West, restricted to a servile function in the vocabulary of
technics. We are only geometricians of matter; the Greeks were, first of
all, geometricians in their apprenticeship to virtue.â
The best approach, intellectually, to the whole problem of socialism
might be, simply, to remember always that man is mortal and imperfect
(as Hopkinson Smith put it: âThe claw of the sea-puss get us all in the
end.â) and so we should not push things too far. The moderation of the
Greeks, as clearsighted and truly scientifically minded a race as this
earth has ever seen, showed in their attitude toward scientific
knowledge should become our guide again. Despite their clearsightedness
(really because of it), the Greeks were surpassed by the intellectually
inferior Romans in such âpracticalâ matters as the building of sewers
and the articulation of legal systems, much as the ancient Chinese,
another scientifically-minded and technologically backward people,
discovered printing and gunpowder long before the West did, but had the
good sense to use them only for printing love poems and shooting off
firecrackers. âPracticalâ is put in quotes because to the Greeks it
seemed much more practical to discuss the nature of the good life than
to build better sewers. To the Romans and to our age, the opposite is
the case â the British Marxist, John Strachey, is said to have once
defined communism as âa movement for better plumbing.â The Greeks were
wise enough to treat scientific knowledge as a means, not an end; they
never developed a concept of Progress. This wisdom may have been due to
their flair for the human scale; better than any other people we know
of, they were able to create art and a politics scaled to human size.
They could do this because they never forgot the tragic limitations of
human existence, the Nemesis which turns victory into defeat overnight,
the impossibility of perfect knowledge about anything. Contrast, for
example, the moderation of Socrates, who constantly proclaimed his
ignorance, with the pretentions of a 19^(th) century system-builder like
Marx. The Greeks would have seen in Marxâs assumption that existence can
be reduced to scientifically knowable terms, and the bold and confident
all-embracing system he evolved on the basis of this assumption â they
would have set this down to âhubris,â the pride that goeth before a
fall. And they would have been right, as we are now painfully
discovering. Nor is it just Marx; as the quotations from the other
19^(th) century socialist and anarchist theoreticians show, this
scientific âhubrisâ was dominant in the whole culture of that Age of
Progress. But it just won;t do for us. We must learn to live with
contradictions, to have faith in scepticism, to advance toward the
solution of a problem by admitting as a possibility that it may be
insoluble. The religious and the scientific views of the world are both
extreme views, advancing total, complete solutions. We should reject
both (as the Greeks, by the way, did; they were a notably irreligious
people, putting their faith neither in the Kingdom of Heaven nor the
Cloaca Maxima). Kierkegaard advises us to âkeep the wound of the
negative open.â So it is better to admit ignorance and leave questions
open rather than to close them up with some all-answering system which
stimulates infection beneath the surface.
To Marxâs âfetishism of commoditiesâ I would counterpoise our modern
fetishism â that of the masses. The more Progressive oneâs thinking, the
more one assumes that the test of the goodness of a political program is
how wide a popular appeal it makes. I venture to assert, for the present
time at least, the contrary: that, as in art and letters,
communicability to a large audience is in inverse ratio to the
excellence of a political approach. This is not a good thing: as in art,
it is a deforming, crippling factor. Nor is it an eternal rule: in the
past, the ideas of a tiny minority, sometimes almost reduced to the
vanishing point of one individual, have slowly come to take hold on more
and more of their fellow men; and we may hope that our own ideas may do
likewise. But such, it seems to me, is our situation today, whether we
like it or not. To attempt to propagate political ideas on a mass scale
today results in either corrupting them or draining them of all
emotional force and intellectual meaning. The very media by which one
must communicate with a large audience â the radio the popular press,
the movies â are infected; the language and symbols of mass
communication are infected; if one tries to use these media, one gets
something like the newspaper PM, and something like the political
writings of Max Lerner. Albert Camus, for example, edited the
underground Resistance paper, Combat, during the German occupation of
France. After the liberation, Combat quickly won a large audience, and
Camus became one of the most widely read and influential political
journalists in France. Yet, as he told me, he found that writing about
politics in terms of the great parties and for a mass audience made it
impossible for him to deal with reality, or to tell the truth. And so he
has withdrawn from Combat, giving up what in traditional terms would
seem to be a supremely fortunate chance for a socially-minded
intellectual to propagate his ideas among the masses, in order to be
cast about for some better way of communicating. This will be found, I
suspect, in talking to fewer people more precisely about âsmallerâ
subjects.
As it is with communication, so it is with political organization. The
two traditional Marxian approaches to organization are those of the
Second and the Third International. The former puts its faith in mass
parties, tied in with great trade unions; the latter, in a disciplined,
centralized, closely organized corps of âprofessional revolutionariesâ
which will lead the masses in revolutionary situations. Superficially,
it would seem that the vast scale of modern society calls for mass
parties to master it, while the centralized power of the modern State
can be countered only by an equally centralized and closely organized
revolutionary party. But the fact seems to be just the contrary: the
State can crush such groups, whether organized as mas parties or as
Bolshevik elite corps, the moment they show signs of becoming serious
threats, precisely because they fight the State on its own grounds, they
compete with the State. The totalization of State power today means that
only something on a different plane can cope with it, something which
fights the State from a vantage point which the Stateâs weapons can
reach only with difficulty. Perhaps the most effective means of
countering violence, for example, is non-violence, which throws the
enemy off balance (âmoral jiujitsuâ someone has called it) and confuses
his human agents, all the more so because it appeals to traitorous
elements in their own hearts.[36]
All this means that individual actions, based on moral convictions, have
greater force today than they had two generations ago. As an English
correspondent wrote me recently: âThe main reason for Conscientious
Objection is undoubtedly that it does make a personal feeling have
weight. In the present world, the slightest sign of individual revolt
assumes a weight out of all proportion to its real value.â Thus in
drafting men into that totalitarian society, the U.S. Army, the
examiners often reject anyone who stated openly that he did not want to
enter the Army and felt he would be unhappy there. We may assume this
action was not due to sympathy, but rather to the fact that, as
practical men, the examiners knew that such a one would âmake troubleâ
and that the smooth running of the vast mechanism could be thrown out by
the presence of such a gritty particle precisely because of the
machineâs delicately-geared hugeness.
Another conclusion is that group action against The Enemy is most
effective when it is most spontaneous and loosest in organization. The
opposition of the romantic clubs of German youth (âEdelweiss,â âBlack
Piratesâ) was perhaps more damaging to the Nazis than that of the old
parties and unions. So, too, World-over Press reports that a recently
discovered secret list of British leaders to be liquidated by the Nazis
after the invasion of England gave top priority not to trade unionists
nor to leftwing political leaders but to well-known pacifists.
What seems necessary is thus to encourage attitudes of disrespect,
scepticism, ridicule towards the State and all authority, rather than to
build up a competing authority. It is the difference between a frontal
attack all along the line and swift flanking jabs at points where the
Enemy is weakest, between large-scale organized warfare and guerrilla
operations. Marxists go in for the former: the Bolsheviks emphasis
discipline and unity in order to match that of The Enemy; the reformists
try to outweigh The Enemyâs power by shepherding great masses of voters
and trade unionists into the scales. But the status quo is too powerful
to be overthrown by such tactics; and, even worse, they show a
disturbing tendency to lead one over to the side of The Enemy.
Granted that individual actions can never overthrow he status quo, and
also that even spontaneous mass rebellion will be fruitless unless
certain elementary steps of coordination and organization are taken. But
today we confront this situation: the masses just do not act towards
what most of the readers of this magazine would recognize as some
fundamental betterment of society. The only way, at present, of so
acting (as against just âmaking the recordâ for the muse of Marxian
history by resolutions and manifestos âagainst imperialist war,â âfor
the international proletarian revolution,â etc.) seems to be through
symbolic individual actions, based on one personâs insistence on his own
values, and through the creation of small fraternal groups which will
support such actions, keep alive a sense of our ultimate goals, and both
act as a leavening in the dough of mass society and attract more and
more of the alienated and frustrated members of that society. These
individual stands have two advantages over the activities of those who
pretend that mass action is now possible:
(1) They make a dramatic appeal to people, the appeal of the individual
who is bold enough and serious enough to stand alone, if necessary,
against the enormous power of The State; this encourages others to
resist a little more that they would otherwise in their everyday life,
and also preserves the living seeds of protest and rebellion from which
later on bigger things may grow.
(2) They at least preserve the revolutionary vitality and principles of
the few individuals who make such stands, while the mass-actionists
become, if they stick by their principles, deadened and corrupted
personally by their constant submission in their own personal behavior
to the standards of The Enemy â and much more corrupted than the simple
bourgeois who feels himself at one with those standards (anyone who has
been through the Trotskyist movement, for example, as I have, knows that
in respect to decent personal behavior, truthfulness, and respect for
dissident opinion, the âcomradesâ are generally much inferior to the
average stockbroker). On the other hand, if they compromise with
principles in order to establish contact with the masses, they simply
become part of The Enemyâs forces, as is the case with the British Labor
Party and the French Socialists. Marxists always sneer at the idea of
individual action and individual responsibility on the grounds that we
are simply interested in âsaving our own souls.â But what is so terrible
about that? Isnât it better to save oneâs soul than to lose it? (And NOT
to âgain the whole world,â either!)
The first step towards a new concept of political action (and political
morality) is for each person to decide what he thinks is right, what
satisfies him, what he wants. And then to examine with scientific method
the environment to figure out how to get it â or, if he canât get it, to
see how much he can get without compromising his personal values.
Self-ishness must be restored to respectability in our scheme of
political values. Not that the individual exists apart from his fellow
men, in Max Stirnerâs sense. I agree with Marx and Proudhon that the
individual must define himself partly in his social relations. But the
point is to make these real human relations and not abstract concepts of
class or history. It has often been observed that nations â and, I might
add, classes, even the proletariat â have a lower standard of ethical
behavior than individuals do. Even if all legal constraints were
removed, I take it we can assume that few people would devote themselves
exclusively to murder or would constantly lie to their friends and
families; yet the most respected leaders of present societies, the
military men and the political chieftains, in their public capacities
become specialists in lying and murder. Always, of course, with the
largest aims, âfor the good of humanity.â[37]
A friend put it well in a letter I received several months ago: âSo long
as morality is all in public places â politics, Utopia, revolutions
(nonviolent included), progress â our private mores continue to be a
queasy mixture of chivalry and cynicism: all in terms of angles, either
for or against. Weâre all against political sin, we all love humanity,
but individuals are sort of tough to love, even tougher to hate.
Goldenhaired dreams, humanitarian dreams â whatâs the difference so long
as they smell good? Meanwhile, patronize any whore, fight any war, but
donât marry the girl and donât fight the boss â too dangerous... No.
Damn, our only chance is to try to get as small, private, honest,
selfish as we can. Donât you agree that one canât have a moral attitude
toward Humanity? Too big.â
Or to put it more generally. Technological progress, the organization
from the top of human life (what Max Weber calls ârationalizationâ), the
overconfidence of the past two centuries in scientific method â these
have led us, literally, into a dead end. Their trend is now clear:
atomic warfare, bureaucratic collectivism, âthe crystallization of
social activity into an objective power above us, growing out of our
control, thwarting our expectations, bringing to naught our
calculations...â To try to fight this trend, as the Progressives of all
shade do, with the same forces that have brought it about appears absurd
to me. We must emphasize the emotions, the imagination, the moral
feelings, the primacy of the individual human being , must restore the
balance that has been broken by the hypertrophy of science in the last
two centuries. The root is man, here and not there, now and not then.
The validity of Marxism as a political doctrine stands or falls on its
assertion that the proletariat is the historical force which will bring
about socialism. The reason political Marxism today is of little
interest, save to a few romantic or pedantic sectarians (and of course
to the Communists, but in a form so debased and distorted as to bear
about the same relation to Marxâs teachings as the âChristianityâ of the
Catholic Church in Francoâs Spain bears to the teachings of Christ), the
reason is that the proletariat has not been the motive force in either
of the two great revolutions of our century, the Bolshevik and the Nazi,
but has been as much the passive victim or, at best, accomplice of the
organized elites which have made those revolutions, as the bourgeoisie
themselves.
The Marxist idea was that just as the bourgeoisie developed inside the
feudal system for centuries and finally became strong enough to replace
it with capitalism, so the workers are developing their power within
capitalism and will finally âburst asunderâ the bourgeois integument.
Writing a half-century ago, in his crabbed, doctrinaire, original and
prophetic Two Pages from Roman History, Daniel De Leon put his finger on
the peculiar weakness of the proletariat: âThe working class, the
subject class upon whom depends the overthrow of capitalism and the
raising of socialism, differs from all previous subject classes called
upon by History to throw down an old and set up a new social system.â
The difference is that other classes first gained âthe material means
essential to its own economic systemâ and then made the revolution. But
the proletariat, by definition, is propertyless. âHolding the economic
power, capital, on which the feudal lords had become dependent, the
bourgeois was safe under fire.... Differently with the proletariat. It
is a force every atom of which has a stomach to fill, with wives and
children with stomachs to fill, and, withal, precarious ability to
attend to such needs. Cato the Elder said in his usual blunt way: âThe
belly has no ears.â At times this circumstance may be a force, but it is
only a fitful force. Poverty breeds lack of self-reliance. Material
insecurity suggests temporary devices. Sops and lures become captivating
baits. And the one and the other are in the power of the present
ruling-class to maneuver with.â
If the American working class were ever going to make a revolution, it
would have done so, or at least tried to do so, during the 1929â1933
depression. Instead, it voted in Roosevelt, who proceeded to captivate
it with âsops and luresâ of reform. One of the most tragi-comic
documents in our social history is the pamphlet, Culture and the Crisis,
which the League of Professional Groups for Foster and Ford put out in
the fall of 1932. It was signed by and extraordinarily wide range of
intellectuals, among them Sherwood Anderson, Newton Arvin, Erskine
Caldwell, Lewis Corey, Malcolm Cowley, John Dos Passos, Theodor Dreiser,
Waldo Frank, Granville Hicks, Sidney Hook, Sidney Howard, Alfred
Kreymborg, James Rorty, Frederick L. Schuman, Lincoln Steffens, and
Edmund Wilson. âAs responsible intellectual workers,â they proclaimed,
âwe have aligned ourselves with the frankly revolutionary Communist
Party, the party of the workers.â They rejected Roosevelt because his
election would result in nothing more than âchanges here and there in
the machine of governmentâ; They rejected Norman Thomas because the
Socialists âdo not believe in the overthrow of capitalismâ and hence
âare the third party of capitalism.â Nothing less than the real thing
would satisfy these incipient Robes-pierres, nothing less than âthe
revolutionary struggle against capitalism under the leadership of the
Communist Party,â which is alleged to stand for âa socialism of deed not
words.â But when these deeds are named, the heady wine of revolution
turns into very small beer indeed. âThere is only one issue in the
present election â call it hard times, unemployment, the farm problem,
the world crisis, or simply hunger.â This issue is to be met by the
Communist Partyâs program of âimmediate demands,â viz: (1)
State-financed unemployment and social insurance; (2) no more wage-cuts;
(3) emergency farm relief and a debt and mortgage moratorium for
farmers; (4) equal rights for Negros; (5) defense of workersâ rights
against capitalist terror; (6) âa united front against imperialist war;
for the defense of the Chinese people and the Soviet Union.â Except for
(4), on which little progress was made until the Truman Administration,
Rooseveltâs New Deal put into effect this entire program (if his
recognition of the Soviet Union and his âcollective securityâ crusade
against Nazi Germany may be taken as implementing the rather vague sixth
point) as well as adding several dozen other similar measures such as
TVA, the SEC, and the Federal housing program. What price revolution?
Or compare the aftermath of the Great French Revolution and the 1917
Russian Revolution. Both degenerated from their initial promise of
democracy and liberation into the one-man dictatorships of Napoleon and
Stalin. This political regression, however, did not mean that the old
ruling class regained its economic power. Napoleon did not restore their
estates to the nobles but, on the contrary, laid the legal and
governmental foundations for the 19^(th) century French capitalism.
Stalin did not call in foreign capital or restore private property and
the capitalist market, as Trotsky expected him to do, but on the
contrary pushed Trotskyâs own policy of state-owned industrialization
and of farm collectivization ahead at a brutally fast tempo. There is,
however, one significant difference: Napoleon did not turn against those
in whose name the 1789 revolution had been made, the bourgeoisie, but
rather acted as their representative. But Stalin smashed the working
class and reduced them to subjection. Napoleon and his generals and
officials ruled without disturbing the economic power of the
bourgeoisie, but under Stalin the workers lost such slight economic
power as they had had, including even the protection of their trade
unions, for not they, but the Stalin bureaucracy was the new ruling
class put into power by the 1917 Revolution. They were all the more
easily subdued since Lenin and Trotsky, in the early years of that
revolution, had broken the workersâ own instruments of political and
economic power: the Soviets and the workersâ committees which for a
brief time ran the factories. The workers were easily dispossessed by
Lenin and Stalin because they had never possessed in the first place.
This chronic impotence of the working class has forced latter-day
Marxists into apologetics whose metaphysical nature contrasts amusingly
with Marxismâs claim to being a materialistic doctrine. When one is
indelicate enough to refer to the great mass of evidence by now
available on the subject, one is met with indulgent smiles. First of
all, the Marxists explain, the trade union bureaucrats and/or the
Communists are traitors, misleaders of labor, their policies are
anti-working class, and they maintain their control through force and
fraud. If one presses the matter and asks why, if the workers have been
successfully pulled and coerced for a century, they will be able to
assert themselves in the future, one discovers that when a Marxist talks
about âworking class aimsâ and âworking class consciousness,â he means
nothing so vulgar as the actual here-and-now behavior of workers but
rather what the workers would want and would do if they knew what their
ârealâ interests were. Since the proletarian rarely does know his ârealâ
interests and constantly tends to identify his interests with those of
his exploiters, the result is that his ârealâ behavior, Marxistically
speaking, is usually in conflict with his really real behavior, so that
socialism becomes an ideal which the workers are assumed to cherish in
their hearts but which they rarely profane by putting into action. (As
Alfred Braunthal has put it: âthe mystic cult of The Masses, who always
feel the right way but always act the wrong way.â) A metaphysical
distinction between two kinds of reality is involved here. Thus a
Marxist exults over the rise of the British Labor Party because it is a
labor party (metaphysical reality) and at the same time denounces its
entire leadership as traitors to the working class (materialistic
reality). This produces a position as theoretically impregnable as it is
practically sterile. The rank-and-file â suppressed, passive, coerced â
is always judged on the basis not of what it does but of what it is
assumed to want to do, while the leadership, which is seen as the
active, coercive party, is always judged by what it does. That perhaps
the leadership is a true expression of the needs and desires of the
ranks, if we look at the matter only from a historical-materialistic
standpoint â this idea is much too simple for a Marxist.
I have no objection to basing oneâs politics on a metaphysical,
unprovable value judgment that people should want certain things â in
fact, that is just what I think one ought to do. But I object to
metaphysical assumptions being smuggled into a doctrine which affects to
be materialistic. This is confusing both intellectually and practically,
and is simply a way of avoiding the unpleasant reality. The real
reality, that is.
When Karl Liebknecht, the German socialist who, with Rosa Luxemburg,
heroically opposed his own government in World War I, exclaimed âThe
main enemy is at home!â, he gave a watch-word to a generation of
revolutionists. We radicals in the thirties continued to repeat it. The
appearance of Nazism as the enemy in World War II, however, caused some
of us to doubt its validity. And now that Soviet totalitarianism has
succeeded Nazism as the enemy, Liebknechtâs noble and idealistic slogan
seems to me false, and those who still believe it I must regard as
either uninformed, sentimental, or the dupes of Soviet propaganda (or,
of course, all three together). This is because I believe Soviet
Communism to be both far more inhumane and barbarous as a social system
than our own, and also to offer a greater threat to the peace and
well-being of the world today. I have no doubt that almost everyone who
will read this pamphlet will agree with this, but, reader, before you
skip what follows, ask yourself whether (1) your agreement is perhaps no
a little too quick, as one agrees with someone who states some
unpleasant idea precisely so he cannot force you to really confront it,
really absorb it into oneâs consciousness (always a painful process),
and (2) whether this âfact of life,â to which you so readily â perhaps
even a little hastily? â assent, whether it has made a real difference
in your actions (a sentiment or conclusion which leaves oneâs behavior
unchanged cannot be taken seriously). I say this because in discussing
with pacifists and radicals this agonizing problem of war and Soviet
Communism, I have often observed that they will grant, much too easily,
the political evaluation made above and yet will continue to advocate
policies which are inconsistent with this evaluation (but consistent
with their general approach). Their agreement, in short, is Platonic and
Pickwickian. (I know how one performs such mental gymnastics under the
influence of an ideology because I have done it myself â see âTen
Propositions on the War,â Partisan Review, July-August, 1941.)
Coming back to the question â where is the main enemy? â let me offer in
evidence excerpts from two things I wrote after The Root Is Man. This
first is from the Spring, 1948, issue of politics:
USA v. USSR.
Let us admit at once â let us, indeed, insist on the point â that all
the criticisms made of the USSR here and in the following articles could
also be made of the USA. Ours, like theirs, is an unjust society, where
the few have too much and the many too little. Ours is an imperialist
State, like theirs, whose leaders lie like troopers and equivocate like
lawyers; a militarist State, like theirs, busily preparing for World War
II; a repressive State, like theirs, which is about to draft its youth
against their will. The American common people, like their Russian
brothers, are kicked around from cradle to grace by their Betters, and
are inhibited from leading satisfying lives by a massive structure of
ingenious and irrational institutions. Our culture, too, is a debased
mass-culture, ruled by commerce as theirs is by the Central Committee.
Et cetera, et cetera.
The difference is partly one of degree: in USSR all the above
unpleasantnesses are carried a great deal further than they are in USA.
The rich are richer and the poor, poorer. Imperialism is more vicious:
USA bribes nations with massive capital exports (Marshall Plan), but
USSR either absorbs them by force (the Baltic nations) or subjugates
them by installing a Communist police state (the rest of Eastern
Europe). Militarism more blatantly: USSR spends more of its national
income on war preparation than USA, has four or five times as man of its
citizens under arms, indoctrinates children more systematically with
militarist ideas, and dolls up its generals more resplendently.
Repression is much more severe: the American common people have too few
civil liberties, the Russians have none at all. Social institutions are
not more massively impenetrable to popular pressures: the American
school system is run by locally elected bodies, the Russian directed by
the State. Political institutions are less democratic: Congress and the
President do not truly represent the people, but at least they can be
thrown out every two or four years, and at least they exercise power
within the limits of written rules and after public debate; the 15 or 17
members of the Central Committee rule so far beyond public knowledge and
legal control that they could tomorrow order all red-heads to be
âresettledâ in Kamchatka â and they would be obeyed. Culture is more
totally debased: in USA, artists writers, and intellectuals with the
determination or the cash can ignore the commercial market and produce
decent work; in the USSR, there are no loopholes â the artist cannot
create independently of the Central Committeeâs directives since the
State controls the art galleries, the orchestras and concert halls, the
theatres, and the book and periodical publishers.
There are, further, certain ways in which the USSR is not comparable,
even in degree, to USA or to any other civilized country today. Is there
any other major nation where slave labor exists on a massive scale?
Where all strikes are forbidden by law? Where over half the state budget
is raised by the most regressive form of taxation: sales taxes which
fall most heavily on those least able to pay? Where colonels get thirty
times the pay of privates? Where no figures on national income have been
published since 1938 and no price indices since 1931? Whose soldiers, in
foreign lands, go crazy at the sight of such luxuries as bicycles,
watches, and leather shoes? Whose DPâs open their veins rather than
return to the motherland? Whose secret police have their own secret
courts, which try and sentence without appeal? Where children are
officially applauded as patriots for denouncing their parents to the
authorities? Where the political authorities instruct writers on prose
style, movie directors on montage, and composers on the proper use of
polyphony and dissonance? Where citizens may be imprisoned for talking
to foreigners? Where emigration is forbidden, and the families of
illegal emigrés are punished whether or not they had knowledge of the
attempt?
But the differences go deeper. Not only is Reaction, as it was called in
the simple old days, carried much further in USSR than in USA. But this
is not done there, as here, furtively and apologetically, but rather as
a matter of principle, in the name of Socialism, Peopleâs Democracy and
other high notions. the powerful workings of ideology transmute these
ugly realities into their opposite: they become the principles of a New
Order which is asserted to be the glorious reverse of the undoubtedly
wicked Old Order.
This is the Big Lie which Hitler once amateurishly peddled, but which
the Communists are really putting over. It is not just the absence of
truth; it is the very reverse of truth. Black is not called Blue or Dark
Brown, but White. The political system which has gone far beyond
Bismarck or Louis Napoleon in authoritarian repression is proclaimed as
the realization of the program laid down in The Communist Manifesto. The
society in which strikes are outlawed and workers are legally tied to
their jobs is presented as the workersâ fatherland. The worldâs most
chauvinist and militarist government is sincerely believed by millions
of Americans to be striving for world peace against the evil
machinations of the State Department and the British Foreign Office. The
empire that has added vast new satrapies since 1945, while its two chief
rivals have either confined themselves to Pacific atolls or
(reluctantly) freed their richest subject domains, is gilded by ideology
with the moral splendor of anti-imperialism. Most striking of all, a
double standard of international morality has been insinuated into the
minds of millions of non-Communist workers and intellectuals. Truman is
denounced for his Doctrine, but the more far-reaching interference of
the Communists in other nationsâ affairs is passed over in silence. The
American Legion is properly excoriated for its flagwaving jingoism, but
the same things in USSR becomes transmuted into Peopleâs Patriotism in
Defense of the Socialist Fatherland. Much is said, again properly, about
the moral infamy of the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, but
not a word about the American proposals for international control of
atomic energy, accepted by all the other great powers, and recently,
after years of dispute, abandoned because of the opposition of the one
nation in the world which cannot afford to permit international
inspection of its domestic arrangements: the USSR.
The list could be extended. The point would remain the same: the most
militarist, imperialist, anti-democratic, and reactionary nation in the
world is precisely the one which millions of Americans and Europeans
have fixed their aspirations for world peace, national independence,
democracy and human progress. this is a Fact of Life today, and one that
must be faced, whether one is a liberal, a Marxian socialist, a
conservative, or, as in the case of the present writer, an anarchist and
pacifist. The way to face it, in my opinion, is to tell the truth about
USSR, without suppression and without compromise. If there is a chance
of avoiding World War III, it must be based on truth and not on lies.
And certainly not on The Big Lie.
âI Choose the Westâ
In the winter of 1952, I debated Norman Mailer at Mt. Holyoke College;
my position was summed up in the above title, his was âI Cannot Chose.â
This is what I said (excising repetitious material):
I choose the West â the U.S. and its allies â and reject the East â the
Soviet Union and its ally, China, and its colonial provinces, the
nations of Eastern Europe. By âchoosingâ I mean that I support the
political, economic, and military struggle of the West against the East.
I support it critically â Iâm against the Smith and McCarran Acts,
French policy in Indo-China, etc. â but in general I do choose, I
support Western policies.
During the last war, I did not choose, at first because I was a
revolutionary socialist of Trotskyist coloration, later because I was
becoming, especially after the atom bomb, a pacifist. Neither of these
positions now appear valid to me.
The revolutionary socialist position assumes there is a reasonable
chance that some kind of popular revolution, a Third Camp independent of
the warring sides and hostile to both, will arise during or after the
war, as was the case in Russia in March, 1917. Nothing of the sort
happened in the last war, despite even greater destruction and chaos
than in 1917â19, because the power vacuum was filled at once by either
Soviet or American imperialism. The Third Camp of the masses just
doesnât exist anymore, and so Leninâs ârevolutionary defeatismâ now
becomes simply defeatism: it helps the enemy win and thatâs all.
As for pacifism, it assumes some degree of ethical similarity in the
enemy, something in his heart that can be appealed to â or at least
something in his traditions. Gandhi found this in the British, so his
passive resistance movement could succeed, since there were certain
repressive measures, such as executing him and his chief co-workers,
which the British were inhibited from using by their traditional moral
code, which is that of Western civilization in general. But the Soviet
Communists are not so inhibited, nor were the Nazis. So I conclude that
pacifism does not have a reasonable chance of being effective against a
totalitarian enemy. Pacifism as a matter on individual conscience, as a
moral rather than a political question, is another thing, and I respect
it.
I choose the West because I see the present conflict not as another
struggle between basically similar imperialisms as was World War I but
as a fight between radically different cultures. In the West, since the
Renaissance and the Reformation, we have created a civilization which
puts a high value on the individual, which has to some extent replaced
dogmatic authority with scientific knowledge, which since the 18^(th)
century has progressed from slavery and serfdom to some degree of
political liberty, and which has produced a culture which, while not as
advanced as that of the ancient Greeks, still has some appealing
features. I think Soviet Communism breaks sharply with this evolution,
that it is a throwback not to the relatively human Middle Ages but to
the great slave societies of Egypt and the Orient.
Nor are the Communists content, or indeed able, to confine this
20^(th)-century slave system to Russia or even to the vast new provinces
in Asia and Eastern Europe added since 1945. Like Nazism, Soviet
Communism is a young, aggressive, expansive imperialism (as against, for
instance, the elderly British imperialism, which since 1945 has
permitted India, Egypt, and Iran to escape from its grip). Also like
Nazism, it represses its own population so brutally that it must always
be âdefendingâ itself against alleged foreign enemies â else its
subjects would ask why such enormous sacrifices are needed. The rulers
of Soviet Russia will consider they are encircled by threatening
invaders so long as a single country in the world is left that is
independent of them. A reader asked the Moscow Bolshevik recently: âNow
that we control a third of the world, can we still speak of capitalist
encirclement?â The editors replied: âCapitalist encirclement is a
political term. Comrade Stalin has stated that capitalist encirclement
cannot be considered a geographic notion.â (Thus the existence of a UN
army on the Korean peninsula constitutes a political encirclement of
Communist China.) Furthermore, precisely because the bourgeois West is
so obviously superior, in most of the spiritual and material things that
people value, to the Communized East, the mere existence of a
non-Communist country is a danger to Communism. This was shown in 1945â6
when the Red Army troops returned from their contact with Europe
âinfected with bourgeois ideologyâ â i.e., they had seen how much more
free the masses outside Russia are and how much higher their standard of
living is â and had to be quarantined in remote districts for a
while.[38]
In choosing the West, I must admit that already the effects on our own
society of the anti-Communist struggle are bad: Senator McCarthy and his
imitators are using lies to create hysteria and moral confusion in the
best Nazi-Communist pattern; building a great military machine cannot
but extend the power of the Sate and so encroach on freedom. In short,
we are becoming to some extent like the totalitarian enemy we are
fighting. But (1) being on the road is not the same thing as being there
already (though one might think it was from certain Marxist and pacifist
statements), and (20 this malign trend can be to some extent resisted.
After all, here and in Western Europe there still exist different
political parties, free trade unions and other social groupings
independent of the State; varied and competing intellectual and artistic
tendencies; and the protection, by law and by tradition, of those
individual civil rights on which all the rest depend. Ours is still a
living, developing society, open to change and growth, at least compared
to its opposite number beyond the Elbe.
When Ulysses made his journey to the Elysian Fields, he saw among the
shades his old comrade-in-arms, Achilles, and asked him how are things?
Achillesâ answer was: âI would rather be the slave of a landless man in
the country of the living than the ruler of the kingdom of the dead.â
This is my feeling. I prefer an imperfectly living, open society to a
perfectly dead, closed society. We may become like Russia, but we may
not â the issue is not settled so long as we are independent of Moscow.
If Moscow wins, the door is slammed shut, and to open it again would be
a more difficult and brutal business than is now required by the
measures to keep it open.
I think the point at which I began to stop believing in pacifism as a
political doctrine was the Russian blockade of Berlin. In the Summer,
1948, issue of politics I asked, and answered, some questions as to my
crumbling convictions:
Should the Western powers withdraw their troops from Berlin?
To do this as part of a general pacifist program would be good. But if
it is done, it will not be a symbol of a pacifist-socialist revolution
but simply a tactical move by militarist-capitalist governments. It
would mean just what Munich meant: not peace-in-our-time but
appeasement, and would thus strengthen, not weaken, the Stalin regime.
Furthermore, such a move would not awaken any reaction in the Russian
army or people, and would hand over to the Russians for punishment
thousands of Berliners who have so courageously indicated their
preference for the Westâs imperfect democracy against the Eastâs perfect
tyranny. This betrayal, aside from its moral aspects, would hardly
encourage the rest of Europe to resist the spread of Communism.[39]
Assuming a pacifist revolution in the West, would this not merely insure
the world triumph of Russian totalitarianism?
First, let me say to my correspondents above that pacifism to me means
to resist Stalinism, not to submit to it. The resistance is non-violent
because I think it is immoral to kill or injure others, and because, on
the political level, warfare means killing precisely our best allies
against Stalinism, namely the people of Russia, who are the chief
victims of Stalinâs system, but whom the fires of war would wed closer
to the Kremlin.
Pacifism does assume that not in the leaders but in the ranks of the
enemy there is something similar to itself to which it can appeal,
whether innate human feelings or an ethical-cultural tradition. that is,
love and reason and respect for truth and justice working for us behind
the enemy lines. And that this fifth column can be stirred into action
if we reveal unmistakably that it has already conquered in our own minds
and hearts. Does this fifth column exist in the Russians today? That is
a very speculative question.
Let us dismiss, first, the illusion of some of the more innocent
pacifists that it exists in comrades Stalin, Molotov, Vishinsky, et al.
These gentlemen would interpret any showing of brotherly love by the
West as simply a weakness, and would take advantage of a pacifist
revolution to occupy Europe and the USA preliminary to instituting a
Peopleâs Progressive Order. But would the Red Army march/ And, if it
would, what prospects are there that its soldiers, and the population
back home in Russia, would be won over to our side by pacifist tactics?
Human beings do not respond to love; they do have a feeling for truth
and justice; they do dislike authority and repression; they do have
prejudices against murder. They also have the reverse of these
instincts, of course, but at least both tendencies exist, and one can
choose which to appeal to. the Stalin regime has done its best to bring
out in the Russians the reverse of the feelings listed above. How
successful has it been? On the one hand, there is the barbarous behavior
of the Red Army in Germany and Eastern Europe; the absence of rebellion
inside Russia; the cynicism and apathy shown in the documents on Russian
life printed in the last issue. On the other, there is the fact of
large-scale desertions from the Red Army, of episodes like the Kosenkina
case, of the distaste for the regime also shown in the documents printed
last issue. The current defiance of Russian totalitarianism by large
numbers of Berliners â quite unexpected by the Western authorities and
newspapermen there â may be a sign that twelve years of Nazism have not
too profoundly reshaped the German people. But Stalin has been in power
for twenty years, and has enjoyed a much more complete and intimate
control than Hitler did. The very completeness of his control makes it
hard to evaluate its effects on the Russian people, since they are
deprived of all possible outlets of self-expression. Except the jokes.
Perhaps here is a sign of the existence of our fifth column!
In any case, we can say that the political leaders of USA have made no
effort to see whether this fifth column exists or not. Their policy is
static, unimaginative, niggardly, unfeeling. As their âunconditional
surrenderâ policy plus the saturation bombings forced the German people
to stick to Hitler to the end, so they are now solidifying the Russians
behind Stalin. Except for the happy inspiration of the Marshall Plan â
and even that is no in danger of being superseded by military
expenditures â the US Congress and State Department have made no appeal
to the imagination of the peoples of Europe and USSR. A nation which
refuses to permit more than a token immigration of DPâs, and that only
under the most humiliating conditions, offers little encouragement to
such dissident potentialities as there may be inside USSR today.
What about the chances of the American people adopting, in the face of
the Soviet threat, an attitude of non-violent resistance?
Slight. The practice of loving, non-violent resistance towards oneâs
enemies is a difficult discipline which even Gandhi, despite his
leadership of a great mass movement, proved to ave been unable to
implant in the Indian masses. As he himself â unlike our own pacifist
sectarians â recognized in the last year of his life, the communal
massacres showed that his life work had been a failure in this respect.
The American temperament would seem to be less receptive to non-violence
than the Indian, certainly there is no such popular tradition of it as
in India. Also, the British authorities were themselves bound by a moral
code which had some similarity to that of Gandhiâs, whereas the Soviet
authorities are not so bound.
If your chief political objective today is the overthrow of Stalinism,
and if you do not think either pacifism or socialism can give answers to
the specific political issues â such as whether the US army should get
out of Berlin or not â which arise in the course of the fight, and if
war seems the most likely final upshot of the kind of resistance the
West, as now constituted (and you see little hope of a basic change
before World War III), offers; then will you not support World War III
when and if it comes?
No.
Why not?
Because I agree with Simone Weil that the methods that must be used in
fighting a modern war are so atrocious and clash so fundamentally with
the ends I favor as to make impossible the achieving of those ends.
Specifically, the mass slaughter of the enemy population by atomic
bombing and bacteriological warfare, and the destruction of the fabric
of Western civilization if not the globe itself.
The usual argument for supporting war today is that if someone comes to
burn down your house and kill your family, you have a right to kill him
in order to prevent this. But this analogy, so persuasive to the popular
mind, is misleading because it leaves out of account the chief
difference between such a situation and the wars of our time. If you
kill someone to prevent him burning your house and killing your
children, the result is that your house is not burned and your children
are not killed. But war today seems to bring about just what it is
allegedly fought to prevent. After Hitler is defeated, the same evils
reappear with the hammer and sickle on their caps instead of the
swastika. And the moral and physical destruction employed to defeat
Hitler has mounted to a total comparable to the hypothetical damage
which the war was fought in order to avoid. A better analogy would be:
The proprietor of a china shop battles a gang intent on breaking his
china. But the encounter is so furious that most of the china is broken
anyway; in fact, the proprietor himself seizes some of the most precious
items in his stock to smash over the heads of the attackers.
Then if both violence and non-violence, for different reasons, seem
impractical today, you are in a dilemma?
Yes.
So much for my 1948 thinking on the dilemma posed by the Soviet threat
on the one hand and the horrors of modern warfare on the other. i would
still go along with most of the above, with the important exception that
if it comes to war with the Soviet Union, Iâll probably support this
country, critically, with misgiving, and with the deepest respect for
those whose consciences forbid them to do so â but still shall do so in
all likelihood. Yet what does âsupportâ mean here, really? Can one use
such a term of oneâs relationship to something so beyond his control as
a modern war? Itâs like taking a position toward an earthquake. One
thinks of Margaret Fullerâs âI accept the universe!â and Carlyleâs
comment, âGad, sheâd better!â
Besides this general historical dilemma, there were certain curious
ethical results of holding pacifist views today which came to bother me
more and more as I observed them cropping up in discussions with
fellow-pacifists. To summarize them very roughly:
ignorance of the Facts of Life about Communist totalitarianism or else
to gloss them over. An example was the absurd and shameful Peace
Proposals which the Quakers put forward several years ago, in which, for
example, the latter-day descendants of the most intransigent fighters
against Negro slavery forgot to say anything about the vast slave-labor
camps in the Soviet Union.
who asked, âAm I my brotherâs keeper?â Yet pacifists often show
indifference to the fate of peoples threatened with incorporation into
the Soviet empire; some of my friends in the movement werenât especially
disturbed by the fact that, if the U.S. Army were to pull out of Berlin
in 1948, some two million Berliners would have been rewarded by us for
their heroic resistance to totalitarianism by being abandoned to our
mutual enemy. If you feel you are your brotherâs keeper, then at the
very least a painful dilemma is created when, say, Hitlerâs armies
invade Poland to replace its imperfect republican institutions with the
more perfect tyranny of Nazism.
speakers from the floor expressed amazement that I, as a pacifist,
should consider the consequences of an action. If the act is god in
itself, they argued, then it should be done, regardless of consequences.
But it seems to me that it is almost entirely by its consequences,
whether immediate or long-range, that we evaluate an action. I think
Tolstoy was sophistical when he reasoned that, since we can know our own
intentions but cannot know completely what will be the consequences of
an act, the only guide to action is âthe inner state of the mind and
heart.â We donât in fact know our own hearts so well as he assume, nor
are the consequences of most actions so difficult to predict.
Having now stated why I am no longer a pacifist and why I will probably
support this country if it comes to war with Soviet Russia, just as I
approved of Trumanâs action in resisting the invasion of South Korea
with force, let me now edge back against, not toward pacifism, but
toward scepticism and indecision. If it comes to a world war, I think we
are done for, all of us. In supporting measures of opposition, including
military ones as in Korea, against the Communists, I reason that the
best chance of postponing war and perhaps avoiding it altogether is for
the West to keep up its military strength and to be prepared to counter
force with force. Appeasement didnât work with the Nazis and it wonât
work with the Communists. I admit that the results of the Korean have
been disastrous, especially for the Korean people; if I were a South
Korean, Iâm not sure I should have not preferred to have just let the
North Koreans take over peacefully. Yet perhaps, in terms of world
politics, the results of not making a fight to defend the Korean
Republic would have been even more disastrous, like the results of
letting Hitler absorb the Rhineland, Austria and Czechoslovakia without
a fight.
Perhaps there is no solution any longer to these agonizing problems.
Certainly the actual workings of history today yield an increasing
number of situations in which all the real alternatives (as against the
theoretically possible ones) seem hopeless. The reason such historical
problems are insoluble now is that there have been so many crimes,
mistakes, and failures since 1914, and each one making the solution of
the next problem that much more difficult, that by now there are no
uncorrupted, unshattered forces for good left with which to work. A
decent social order in Europe after the first world war, for instance,
would have made Hitlerâs rise impossible; even after he took power, a
Loyalist victory in the Spanish Civil War or some radical reforms in
France by Leon Blumâs Front Populaire would have made his position very
difficult. But none of these things happened, and when the Reichswehr
marched into Poland, what solution was possible? Some of us felt it was
our duty as socialists to âoppose the war,â i.e., to refuse to fight the
Nazis under the flags of existing governments; we also had illusions
about the historical possibility of a âthird campâ of the common people
arising and making it possible to fight the Nazis with clean hands, so
to speak. But this alternative, it is now clear, existed only on the
ethical and ideological plane; it had no existence on the historical
level. The only historically real alternatives in 1939 were to back
Hitlerâs armies, the back the Alliesâ armies, or to do nothing. But none
of these alternatives promised any great benefit for mankind, and the
one that finally triumphed has led simply to the replacing of the Nazi
threat by the Communist threat, with the whole ghastly newsreel
flickering through once more in a second showing.
This is one reason I am less interested in politics than I used to be.
Dwight Macdonaldâs turn from active political opposition to both the
West and the USSR unwittingly led him into the orbit of the CIA and the
Congress for Cultural Freedom (CCF), a group of Western intellectuals,
many from the Left, opposed to Soviet totalitarianism. In order to
understand Macdonaldâs encounter with the CIA it is helpful to begin by
examining his complex intellectual relationship with James Burnham,
whose writing helped shape Macdonaldâs own analysis of both fascism and
creeping forms of totalitarianism in the West.
In 1938 Dwight Macdonald helped finance an American edition of Daniel
Guerinâs Fascism and Big Business. in his introduction to Guerinâs book,
Macdonald argued that fascism was the logical outcome of capitalism in
decline, not some aberration. by 1940, however, Macdonald no longer saw
fascism simply as a puppet of big capital. Macdonald now believed that
fascism was more a merger of the worst aspects of socialism as well as
capitalism into a new form of society rather than the final stage of
capital in decline. In Stalinâs Soviet Union, Macdonald saw this new
society in a more perfected form than in pre-Holocaust Nazi Germany.
Macdonaldâs contention that Nazi Germany was a form of âblack socialismâ
deeply upset the Workers Party. Macdonaldâs article in the New
International stating his thesis was heavily edited, a fact that enraged
him and contributed to his leaving the sect.
Macdonaldâs view of Nazi Germany echoed the thinking of James Burnham
who believed that both the USSR and Nazi Germany had developed forms of
social organization superior to the anarchic laissez-faire chaos of the
West. Although little thought of today, James Burnham has the strange
distinction of being both one of the first exposers of the national
security state as well as one of its first advocates. No full history of
the American intelligence establishment can be written without some
examination of Burnhamâs role.
Burnhamâs theories also helped shape the outlook of the post-war Right
in favor of global interventionism and away from isolationism. In The
Conservative Intellectual Movement in America, George Nash says: âMore
than any other single person, Burnham supplied the conservative
intellectual movement with the theoretical formulation for victory in
the cold war.â Best remembered today as an editor at National Review, it
was James Burnham who recruited William F. Buckley into the CIA.
Burnhamâs own ties to the American intelligence community, however,
began shortly after he left the Trotskyist movement. By the mid-1940s
Burnham was a consultant to the Office of Strategic Services (OSS), the
predecessor organization to the CIA.
After breaking with Trotskyism, Burnham carried on his war with
Stalinism by becoming what he had condemned in his Soviet foe, a
theorist of the all-powerful state run by a powerful elite whose
decisions would be governed not by Nazi or Bolshevik moonshine but by
pragmatic evaluation of the realities of geopolitics. Burnhamâs theories
helped shape the CIA.
Kevin Smantâs biography of Burnham (How Great the Triumph: James
Burnham, Anticommunist and the Conservative Movement) reports that in
1947, âBurnham was recruited into the fledgling United States Central
Intelligence Agency by Office of Strategic Servicesâ veteran Kermit
Roosevelt. He would serve mainly as a part-time consultant attached to
the Office of Policy Coordination (the CIAâs covert action wing).â
The OPC was heavily involved in trying to organize anticommunist
underground groups in Eastern Europe. Many of their recruits were either
ex-Nazis or Nazi collaborators. (Unknown to the OPC, Soviet spy Kim
Philby was regularly informing Moscow about its plans.) Burnham became
involved in the exile movement and while at National Review Burnham
regularly reported on meetings of various East Bloc
âgovernments-in-exileâ tied to the CIA-backed World Anti-Communist
League (WACL). The dependence on pragmatic Realpolitik to justify the
hiring of ex-Nazis by the CIA mirrored the tortured rationale used by
Communists to justify the Hitler-Stalin Pact.
The tensions between Macdonald and Burnham can be seen in the Congress
for Cultural Freedom that both men supported in the mid-1950âs. Burnham,
for example, wanted to declare the American Communist Party illegal and
hoped the CCF would back such a policy.. he also testified for the
government in an unsuccessful attempt to get his old comrades in Max
Shachtmanâs Workers Party (now called the Independent Socialist League)
listed as a subversive organization by the U.S. Department of Justice.
Macdonald, however, believed McCarthyism only destroyed what appeal the
United States had against the USSR throughout the world. While the USSR
took tiny steps in the 1950âs to expose Stalinism, it was the James
Burnhams of America who wanted to create their own Stalinist state free
from internal dissent. Such disputes racked the CCF and the revelation
of covert CIA funding to the CCF in the 1960âs convinced Macdonald that
the debate inside the CCF was secretly manipulated by the CIA for its
own objectives. Macdonald also believed the CIA directly blocked his own
chance to become editor of the CCFâs magazine Encounterbecause of his
opposition to McCarthyism. The CIAâs covert attempt to rig the CCF was a
textbook example of the kind of disguised totalitarianism that Macdonald
so feared.
K.C.
Â
A Note on the Text
The text if The Root Is Man used in this edition comes from its 1953
republication by Cunningham Press and differs slightly from the original
version which appeared in politics is 1946. When Cunningham Press
proposed reprinting The Root Is Man, Macdonald agreed, âon condition
that I might add new material commenting on events since 1946 and,
especially, indicating the considerable changes in my own thinking since
then. I have cut a few passages that now seem to me superfluous or
intolerably long-winded (as against tolerably so), perhaps two or three
pages in all, but have otherwise not altered the original text. Where I
now disagree or think some later event to the point, I have added
numerous footnotes. (The footnotes depending from asterisks were in the
original version.) I have also added some appendices dealing with
matters too lengthy for footnotes.â In this edition we have merged the
footnotes as endnotes and have deleted an article by politics
contributor Andrea Caffi called âMass Politics and the Pax Americana,â
which Macdonald included in the 1953 edition because it was submitted
too late to be printed in the last issue of politics.
[1] In 1941, James Burnham gave popular currency to the idea in The
Managerial Revolution. Unfortunately, he vulgarized it so
enthusiastically as to make it a source of confusion rather than
enlightenment. (See the reviews by H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills in
Ethics, Jan. 1942, and by myself in Partisan Review, Jan.-Feb. 1942.)
[2] It did indeed produce Tito and DeGaulle, but they led away from
democratic socialism and towards nationalist authoritarianism.
[3] It is not intended to suggest there are not important differences
between these tendencies. The Stalinists, in particular, should be most
definitely set off from the rest. Their Progressivism is a complete
abandonment to the historical process, so that absolutely anything goes,
so long as it is in the interests of Russia, a âhigherâ form of society.
The other groups, although they put more emphasis on the historical
process than is compatible with the values they profess, do stand by
certain general principles and do recognize certain ethical boundaries.
[4] True, this âleftistâ tide has somewhat ebbed in the last few years:
the Right, especially DeGaulle, has gained in France at the expense of
the Left, and still more in Italy; the Tories have come to power in
Britain and the Republicans here. (On the other hand, India is free and
China has gone Communist.) But these political changes havenât gone deep
enough to alter the big picture: the Tories have not gone in for
denationalizing, nor is their foreign policy very different from
Laborâs; the Republicans have accepted the New Deal social reforms and
the strong position of the unions, although in political civil-rights,
their tolerance of McCarthy is ominous (but political tolerance was not
very noticeable in the Roosevelt-Truman regimes either, as cf. the early
Smith Act prosecutions, the loyalty purge, the Attorney-Generalâs black
list of subversive groups, and the âresettlementâ â i.e., forced
deportation to camps in the interior â of the entire Japanese-American
population of the West Coast after Pearl Harbor). No, to date at least,
the Rightist current looks to me not like a flood sweeping away the
Leftist postwar gains but simply a tide that will ebb in its turn â part
of the systole and diastole of the heartbeat of the status quo.
[5] As of 1953, amen!
[6] By âsocialismâ I mean a classless society in which the State has
disappeared, production is cooperative, and no man has political or
economic power over another. The touchstone would be the extent to which
each individual could develop his own talents and personality.
[7] I.e., liberal-labor, a Britishism I like because it expresses the
flipflop, wishywashy nature of the beast and because it does not confuse
our modern âliberalsâ with their individualistic 19^(th) century
forbears. The old liberals were liberal â they believed in free trade
and free speech for everybody and they detested the State as a
collective restraint on the individual â but the modern âliberalsâ limit
freedom to those who are âprogressive,â i.e., on the side of âthe
peopleâ and âthe workersâ; as for the State; they love it, if itâs on
their side.
[8] A few recent curiosa may be added: Since he broke with the workersâ
fatherland and came under the influence of the hyenas of decadent
Western capitalism, Tito has instituted a long series of democratic
reforms in Yugoslavia, including curbing the powers of the secret police
and abolishing forced labor.... At the opening of a recent session of
the French National Assembly, there was a seating crisis because,
according to The New York Times of July 2, 1951, âNobody wishes to be
seated on the right.â ...During the 1951 trial of the Rosenburgs and the
other atomic spies, one Max Elitcher testified: âHe inquired if I knew
of any engineering students or graduates who were âprogressive,â who
would be safe to approach on espionage.â... In 1948, Peron added labor
attachés to the staffs of all Argentine embassies.... Also cf. the
amusing chapter on âBabbitt Revisitedâ in Peter Viereckâs new book, The
Shame and Glory of the Intellectuals, in which George F. Babbittâs son
is depicted as an orthodox liblab just as conventional and naively
philistine as his father only in an opposite political direction.
[9] âThe German people have let Max Lerner down,â I wrote in the April,
1945, politics. âThey have failed him and damn near busted his big
progressive heart. It seems that Lerner was scooting along behind the
advancing Ninth Army in his jeep when he came across a group of German
civilians. âIt was a drizzly afternoon and they were clustered under a
cement shed open at one end. There was a woman with a several-weeks old
baby, and there was an old man of 87. Most were men and women in their
early forties, with a scattering of children. They were almost all
farmers.â They had been hiding in cellars for three days while American
guns destroyed their village in the course of âthe war that they
themselves had brought on.â (How âthey themselves had brought it onâ is
not specified.)
âDescending from his jeep, Lerner asked them: Are You Guilty? He records
no reply from the baby, but the others answered that they never trusted
or liked Hitler, that they had always considered the Nazis criminals and
that they were Catholics and hence opposed for religious reasons to
Hitlerâs policies. Why then, asks Lerner, did you allow the Nazis to do
these things? âWith one accord, they answered that they had yielded to
force, and to force alone.â But this doesnât go down with Lerner, he
points out to the shivering, bomb-dazed farmers that the people of
France, Belgium, Poland, and Russia didnât yield to Nazi force, so why
did they? (According to reliable sources, the above countries were at
war with Germany.) This was a blockbuster: âThey were silent.â
(Different interpretations might be put on this silence.)
ââI came away heartsick and discouraged,â writes Lerner. âThe crime of
these people was cowardice and moral callousness rather than active
criminality. [Heâs trying to be fair, after all.] Nowhere did I find the
moral strength to face the fact of guilt. Only protests that they were
not responsible for what had happened.â Even the baby, judging by its
silence, lacked a sense of responsibility for Hitler, which shows how
deeply ingrained moral callousness is in the German national character.â
[10] And probably never will occur. See Appendix A for a discussion of
the peculiar metaphysics of Marxism re. the working class, and also the
special weakness of the proletariat as an aspiring ruling class.
[11] For an excellent history and analysis of the political rise and
decline of American socialism, see Daniel Bellâs chapter in Socialism
and American Life (Princeton, 1952, 2 vols.).
[12] Considering the later development of Gompers and the labor movement
he founded, this original Marxism has a double meaning to the modern
observer: it suggests not only the radicalism of the youthful Gompers
but also the ambiguity of Marxism as a guide towards socialism; for
although Gompers discarded the socialist aims of Marxism, he never gave
up what Marx himself always emphasized as the road to those aims: the
struggle for the specific class interests of labor. His dedicating his
life-story to the Marxist, Laurrell, and the way he describes his early
Marxist leanings show that Gompers himself was unaware of any basic
change in his philosophy.
[13] When, in the summer of 1946, some pacifist members of the Workers
Defense League planned to picket the Oak Ridge atom bomb plant to
protest against atomic warfare, the League was pressured to prevent them
by the local CIO leadership, which feared the picketing would do
âirreparable harm to our current organizing drive among the Oak Ridge
workers.â The director of the CIOâs Tennessee Regional Office wrote that
if the pickets persisted âWe will be forced to take drastic measures to
denounce your program, which we would not like to do.â Confronted by
this unexpected opposition, the would-be pickets, who were mostly
socialists and so starry-eyed about labor unions, called off the
demonstration. (See politics, Aug. 1946, for the text of the letters in
this episode, with my own comment thereon.)
[14] Those Marxists who insist that the persistence of these forms â
profits, wages, prices, etc. â proves that the Nazi economy is still
capitalist should remember that in the Soviet Union these forms also
largely exist. The Soviet state trusts keep books in capitalist style
and if they donât show profits, the managers are liquidated; the workers
are paid wages in rubles and spend them in shops on food, clothing,
etc.; there is even a budding rentier class, living on the proceeds of
investments in 6% government bonds. But most of us would agree that this
is not a capitalist economy, that its contradictions are not those of
capitalism but of quite another kind.
[15] This is what I call âBureaucratic Collectivism.â Since the market
seems to me the distinguishing mark of capitalism, the term âState
capitalismâ has always appeared a contradiction in terms.
[16] It now appears that there was, in the first year of the war, not
political opposition but at least widespread though unorganized
disaffection, and that the dizzy speed of the German advance â the
panzer divisions smashed through to within fifty miles of Moscow in the
first months â was due partly to mass surrenders of Russian soldiers.
But the Nazis speedily cemented up again this split between the people
and the Kremlin by the brutality with which they treated occupied
Russia, much as Rooseveltâs Unconditional Surrender policy plus the
terror bombings gave the Germans no alternative except to support the
Nazis to the bitter end. (Cf. Weilâs description of modern warfare as a
joint conspiracy of the opposing general staffs and governments against
the peoples on both sides of the battle line.)
[17] See Appendix B for elaboration of this point.
[18] For some non-academic thinking on modern war and politics, see
Simone Weilâs âReflections on Warâ (politics, Feb. 1946) and âWords and
Warâ (politics, March 1946); also two remarkable and
not-enough-noticed-at-the-time pieces by âEuropeanâ in politics: âIs a
Revolutionary War a Contradiction in Terms?â (April 1946) and âViolence
and Sociabilityâ (Jan. 1947); also, of course, that little classic from
the first World War, Randolph Bourneâs The State, with its sombre
refrain: âWar is the Health of the State!â
[19] I must confess that I myself now line up with the West in the cold
war and probably will continue to do so when and if it becomes hot, but
for, I hope, more sober reasons than Engelsâ â out of disillusion and
despair rather than illusion and hope. But see Appendix C for why I have
felt forced to come, reluctantly and still a bit tentatively, to this
bleak conclusion.
[20] âBakunin has a peculiar theory,â Engels wrote to Cuno in 1872, âthe
chief point of which is that he does not regard capital, and therefore
the class contradiction between capitalists and wage-earners...as the
main evil to be abolished. Instead, he regards the State as the main
evil.... Therefore, it is above all the State which must be done away
with, and then capitalism will go to hell itself. We, on the contrary,
say: do away with capital, the appropriation of the whole means of
production in the hands of the few, and the State will fall away itself.
The difference is an essential one.â It is indeed.
[21] âWhat is the wisdom that world literature has accumulated or the
virtue it has taught? Poetry and philosophy look as confusing and as
contradictory as life itself. Can any one summarize what he has learned
from Shakespeare and Cervantes? ...What then, in all seriousness, does
one learn about wisdom and virtue from the poet? The answer is simple.
One learns that they exist. And if that seems very little, perhaps it
will seem not unimportant nevertheless when one realizes that nowhere
else can one learn that fact either so well or, perhaps, even at all.
All the sciences and techniques, from politics to plumbing, are
concerned primarily with ways and means. So too is the day-to-day living
of most men. All are methods for getting what one wants without must
question concerning why one wants it or whether one ought to want it at
all. But that why and that whether are the real subject of literature;
it reminds us continuously that they ought to be inquired into.â
âProbably the very men who were ready to give up âthe humanitiesâ as a
bad job [he refers to the trustees of a foundation who had decided to
give only to scientific research because they felt that the humanities
failed to provide any clear guidance to human betterment] are well
enough aware that what the world needs most is a sense of values.
Probably they have some faint hope that sociology will define them in
some formula or science discover them in some test tube. But in neither
such way will or can the thing ever come about. Nothing can be made to
seem good or bad merely by doing it, only by contemplating it. And
literature is concerned, not with doing things, but with contemplating
things that have been done. From it only one consensus of opinion can be
deduced, but that one is unanimous. It is not merely that this or that
is wise or good but merely that things are either wise or foolish, good
or bad in themselves, and that a good deal depends on our decision which
is which....
âIn any event, the world of humanities is simply that vision of the
world in which the question of values is assumed to be the most
important question of all. Anyone who has ever read much literature has
almost inevitably formed the habit of making that fundamental
assumption. And if he has not âgot anywhere,â he has at least stayed
somewhere that it is very important that man should stay. In fact, it is
the only place he can stay and remain Man.â (Joseph Wood Krutch:
âThinking Makes It Soâ; The Nation, Aug. 13, 1949.)
[22] Since Iâm no longer a pacifist, I could no longer write this
eloquent paragraph. Again, see Appendix C.
[23] Nor can science (or knowledge or scholarship) tell us what to value
esthetically. The ethical and the esthetic spheres are oddly linked in
being two great areas impenetrable to scientific method, because in both
cases the question is not how or why something occurs but rather a
judgment as to what value one puts on it. âI donât know anything about
art but I know what I likeâ is a bromidic but also a perfectly sensible
statement. (A New Yorker cartoon showed two people in an art gallery
discussing a bespectacled, bearded intellectual peering anxiously at a
picture: âHe knows all about art but he doesnât know what he likes.â)
Apropos all this: a University of California sociologist wrote me a
friendly but rather contemptuous letter after this article appeared in
politics dismissing as ânonsenseâ the statement that âthere seems to be
something intrinsically unknowable about values, in a scientific sense,â
saying I reminded him of a colleague who âtells his classes that men are
born with a sense of right and wrong,â and predicting: âYou are faced
with these possible courses: (a) suicide, (b) religion, of the Friends
variety, (c) ethical hedonism. At your present stage, (b) seems most
likely.â None of these predictions have yet materialized. But his future
turned out quite interesting â in fact, he seems to have chosen
alternative (c): a year or so ago, he was convicted of burglary, which,
it appeared, he had been practicing for some time as a means of
supplementing his academic salary. (In all fairness, I must admit that I
know of no other critic of my article who has been convicted of any
serious crime.)
[24] Those who are curious as to why I am not religious â and so many
seem to think it odd, given the rest of my attitudes, that Iâm beginning
to think maybe itâs odd myself â should consult my answer in Partisan
Reviewâs symposium, âReligion and the Intellectualsâ (May-June 1950, pp.
476â480).
[25] I now think I was wrong here. Some kinds of lies are justified. If
a refugee from a lynch mob, or from the Soviet secret police, were
hiding in my house, I should certainly tell the mob or the police that
he was not. To tell the truth in such circumstances would be to
sacrifice the greater moral obligation for the lesser. So, too, with
violence: even if one believes it wrong in principle, as I do, I think
non-violence at times could also result in greater wrong than violence,
as if one refused to defend a child against violence or allowed an armed
man to kill someone rather than use force to disarm him. My one-sided
insistence on absolute truth in this passage was a reaction to the
relativism of the Marxian approach to ethics, which in the case of the
Bolsheviks shaded off into cynicism. I was trying to build some barrier
against the sort of corruption described in the following anecdote
related by Ignazio Silone: âThey were discussing one day, in a special
commission of the Comintern Executive [in Moscow], the ultimatum issued
by the central committee of the British trade unions ordering its local
branches not to support the Communist-led minority movement on pain of
expulsion.... The Russian delegate, Piatnitsky, put forward a suggestion
which seemed to him as obvious as Columbusâ egg: âThe branches should
declare that they submit to the discipline demanded, and then should do
exactly the contrary.â The English representative interrupted: âBut that
would be a lie.â Loud laughter greeted his ingenuous objection â frank,
cordial, interminable laughter, the like of which the gloomy offices of
the International had perhaps never heard before. The joke quickly
spread all over Moscow.â (The God That Failed; R. Gossman, ed.; Harper,
1949.)
[26] With what exultation do the young Marx and Engels announce this
reductive idea â the joy of system-builders who have dug down to the
bedrock on which their system can be firmly constructed: âIn direct
contrast to German philosophy which descends from heaven to earth, here
we ascend from earth to heaven. That is to say, we do not set out from
what men say, imagine, conceive, nor from men as narrated, thought of,
imagined, conceived , in order to arrive at men in the flesh. We set out
from real, active men, and on the basis of their real life-process we
demonstrate the development of the ideological reflexes and echoes of
this life-process. The phantoms formed in the human brain are also,
necessarily, sublimates of their material premises. Morality, religion,
metaphysics, all the rest of ideology and their corresponding forms of
consciousness, thus no longer retain the semblance of independence.â
(The German Ideology; my emphasis.)
[27] There is now (1953) another delightful vista looming up ahead on
the March of Scientific Progress: the possibility that the new hydrogen
bomb, if used in quantity in a war, may set up radioactivity which will
affect the human genes so that future generations of âmutantsâ â i.e.,
Charles Addams monstrosities â will appear. A more optimistic forecast
is that it will render everybody sterile.
[28] I didnât find it and I canât say Iâm still looking very hard for
it. Too discouraging. And my own personal life too absorbing â this
being both a cause and effect of my diminished interest in politics. But
Iâm sure these pages wonât do any harm to those who are still carrying
the banner of radical revolution, or should I say carrying to torch for
it? Maybe my age (47) has something to do with it. Maybe people become
conservative as they age because a young man thinks of the future as
infinite, since the end (death) is not imaginable to him, and so he
lives in it. But a middle-aged man feels that This Offer Is Good For A
Limited Time Only, that the future is all too finite, the end all too
conceivable. So, in time, he looks to the present, and in space, his
interests contract closer to his personal life. The young man, feeling
he has âall the time in the world,â plans his house on a noble scale and
starts to build it of the best Utopian materials. But the middle-aged
man, his house still far from finished, just wants to get a tarpaper
roof on before winter sets in.
[29] I am aware that Marx constantly denied the direct relationship
between the economic base and the ideological superstructure which his
followers constantly attributed to him. But insofar as his theories have
a specific content, they do tend to reduce consciousness and conscience
to functions of the economic base; and his disclaimers were vague and
weasel-worded, usually employing the expressions âultimatelyâ or âin the
long runâ without defining what is the long, as against the short, run.
[30] English translation, International Publishers, 1939, pp. 22, 23,
24, and 203. I have put âcoercedâ instead of this editionâs ânatural,â a
change I think justified by its own Note 12, p. 202. These formulations
are so wonderfully precise and imaginative as to make one regret all the
more that Marx, instead of making his theory of alienation the
cornerstone of his intellectual effort, chose to waste years on economic
analysis which today has only historical interest. Now was it just a
matter of a lost opportunity. The remedy for this alienation of man by
his own creations which Marx evolved, misled by his
historical-materialist concepts â that is, the class struggle conducted
by parties and trade unions directed towards replacing capitalism with
collectivism â this has turned out to be simply the 20^(th) century
aspect of that alienation which the above passage so admirably
describes.
[31] This remark about cocktail parties produced more scornful criticism
than anything else in the whole article, and perhaps with reason, since
I must confess I have been more assiduous in attending cocktail parties
than in making radical propaganda at them. But I donât think what I had
in mind in the paragraph as a whole was silly. What I was getting at is
well put in the Early Christian âLetter to Diognetusâ (quoted by Time
from The Apostolic Fathers): âChristians are not different from the rest
of men in nationality, speech or customs; they do not live in states of
their own, nor do they use a special language, nor adopt a peculiar way
of life. Their teaching is not the kind of things that could be
discovered by the wisdom or reflection of mere active-minded men....
They live each in his native land, but as though they were not really at
home there. They share in all duties like citizens and suffer all
hardships like strangers. Every foreign land is for them a fatherland,
and every fatherland a foreign land... They dwell on earth, but they are
citizens of heaven. They obey the laws that men make, but their lives
are better than the laws. They love all men, but are persecuted by
all.... In a word, what the soul is to the body, Christians are to the
world.â
[32] Again, I am now more moderate in my absolutism. Under certain
extreme circumstance, I would use force, personally and even as a
soldier.
[33] Though I still hold to the tendency expressed here, the actual
formulation now seems to me absurdly overstated. Even the Wobblies,
after all since they lived in a world of cops and judges, must have
submitted to authority far more often than they rebelled against it or
evaded it â or else, they would have spent all their time in jail (where
again, if they consistently flouted authority, they would have spent all
their time in solitary confinement if not worse). Also, certain kinds of
social authority â as, traffic laws, sanitary regulations â are far from
even the purest anarchist viewpoint not objectionable and indeed useful.
Proudhon drew the line sensibly: he was willing to submit to the State
in matters which did not seem to him to importantly affect his interests
adversely.
[34] âTo make such a statement,â a friend wrote me, âamounts to saying
in so many words that one doesnât give a damn about moral ideals.
Morality, in fact, is nothing at all if it is not giving up something in
the present in favor of something not only of the future but even of the
purely âideal.â And it isnât even a question of morality: no intelligent
activity of any kind would be possible if your statement, and your
demand for immediate satisfaction, had to be taken seriously.â Even
though I qualify this statement as âa leaning rather than a principle,â
I still must admit it is onesided as put here, and that acting out an
ethical ideal may often involve some sacrifice of the present to the
future and perhaps also of oneâs spontaneous, or at least immediate,
needs. But the prevailing morality, Christian or Marxian, I think
involves far too much of that kind of thing, going to the extremes of
the Puritan and of the Communist fanatic. I think pleasure and virtue
ought to be re-introduced to each other, and that if thereâs too much of
the sacrificial and not enough of the enjoyable about oneâs political or
ethical behavior, itâs a bad sign. Those who have a real vocation for
saintliness, like Gandhi, generally strike one as happy to the point of
positive gaiety. But too many of us are self-alienated drudges of virtue
or work, like Poseidon in Kafkaâs sketch: âPoseidon sat at his desk,
doing figures. The administration of all the waters gave him endless
work.... It cannot be said that he enjoyed his work; he did it only
because it had been assigned to him; in fact, he had already filed
frequent petitions for â as he put it â more cheerful work, but every
time the offer of something different was made to him, it would turn out
that nothing suited him quite so well as his present position....
Actually, a shift of posts was unthinkable for Poseidon â he had been
appointed God of the sea in the beginning and that he had to remain.
What irritated him most â and it was this that was chiefly responsible
for his dissatisfaction with his job â was to hear of the conceptions
formed about him: how he was always riding about through the waves with
his trident. When all the while he sat here in the depths of the
world-ocean, doing figures uninterruptedly, with now and then a trip to
Jupiter as the only break in the monotony â a trip, moreover, from which
he usually returned in a rage. Thus he had hardly seen the sea... and he
had never actually travelled around it. He was in the habit of saying
that what he was waiting for was the fall of the world. Then, probably,
a quiet moment would be granter in which, just before the end and after
having checked the last row of figures, he would be able to make a quick
little tour.â
[35] This paragraph now seems nonsensical to me.
[36] As of 1953, I admire the ingenuity of this argument almost as much
as I deplore its insubstantiality. I fear that I overestimated the
fermenting power of the yeast and underestimated the doughiness of the
dough.
[37] âFor Godâs sake, do not drag me into another war! I am worn down
and worn out with crusading and defending Europe and protecting mankind;
I must think a little of myself. I am sorry for the Spaniards â I am
sorry for the Greeks â I deplore the fate of the Jews â the people of
the Sandwich Islands are groaning under the most detestable tyranny â
Bagdad is oppressed â I do not like the present state of the Delta â
Tibet is not comfortable. Am I to fight for all these people? The world
is bursting with sin and sorrow. Am I to be champion of the Decalogue
and to be eternally raising fleets and armies to make all men good and
happy? We have just done saving Europe, and I am afraid the consequence
will be that we shall cut each otherâs throats. No war dear Lady Grey;
no eloquence; but apathy, selfishness, common sense, arithmetic.â So,
Sydney Smith, shortly after the Napoleonic wars.
[38] It is too early to tell how much difference Stalinâs death has
made. Certainly there has been a remarkable âsofteningâ of Soviet policy
â above all, in the reversal of the conviction of the doctors framed up
as the poisoners of Zhdanov and in the public admission their
confessions had been extorted by force, the first time such an admission
has been made in Soviet history. This may be merely a maneuver by one
faction among Stalinâs would-be heirs against another, or it may be a
recognition by the whole top leadership, which they only dare now that
the dreaded Stalin is dead, of widespread resentment at and disgust with
the brutality of Stalinâs policies. If the former, then this âsofteningâ
will be followed by another purge and another âhardeningâ once the
factional struggle ends in decisive victory. If the latter, then its
significance is obviously much greater. But even in that case, it will
be a long and crooked path that Soviet society will follow in inching
back from the extremism of 1929â1953 policies.
[39] This reply is not very satisfactory, from a pacifist standpoint.
The fact is that there is no pacifist (or socialist) answer to the
question of Berlin, just as there wasnât to Munich. As a pacifist, I
cannot say, Donât Yield, since the consequences might be war â though I
think they would not be â and it is irresponsible to support an action
without being willing to support its possible consequences. On the other
hand, a pacifist for the reasons given above cannot recommend getting
out of Berlin either (any more than he could have recommended, though
many pacifists mistakenly did, giving Czechoslovakia to Hitler as a step
towards either peace or justice). Such situations, and they are
increasing, are dilemmas for the pacifists or socialists. They call into
doubt, in my mind at least, the political validity of a âUtopian,â or
ultimatist, position today.