đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș mason-herson-hord-wither-the-state.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:43:20. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Wither the State Author: Mason Herson Hord Date: Winter 2019 Language: en Topics: the state, social ecology, Marxism, post-Marxism Source: *Harbinger: A Journal of Social Ecology*, Issue 1, Winter 2019. https://harbinger-journal.com/issue-1/wither-the-state/
The proletariat seizes political power and turns the means of production
in the first instance into state property. But, in doing this, it
abolishes itself as proletariat, abolishes all class distinctions and
class antagonisms, abolishes also the state as a state. Society thus
far, based upon class antagonisms, had need of the state, that is, of an
organisation of the particular class, which was pro tempore the
exploiting class, for the maintenance of its external conditions of
production, and, therefore, especially, for the purpose of forcibly
keeping the exploited classes in the condition of oppression⊠When at
last it becomes the real representative of the whole of society, it
renders itself unnecessary. As soon as there is no longer any social
class to be held in subjection; as soon as class rule, and the
individual struggle for existence based upon our present anarchy in
production, with the collisions and excesses arising from these, are
removed, nothing more remains to be repressed, and a special repressive
force, a state, is no longer necessary. The first act by virtue of which
the state really constitutes itself the representative of the whole of
society â the taking possession of the means of production in the name
of society â this is, at the same time, its last independent act as a
state. State interference in social relations becomes, in one domain
after another, superfluous, and then dies out of itself; the government
of persons is replaced by the administration of things, and by the
conduct of processes of production. The state is not âabolished.â It
withers away.
âFriedrich Engels, Anti-DĂŒhring (1878)
Recent years have seen a burgeoning convergence among revolutionaries
from the Marxist and anarchist traditions, especially around the nuts
and bolts of working-class movement-building. Most excitingly, this has
meant a shared, renewed emphasis on base-building and dual power to
guide our organizing. We often work together on shared political
projects and read each otherâs literature. In many cases, we share the
same goal of a stateless, classless society free of all domination. Yet
serious theoretical and strategic differences remain, especially in
regard to how power should be wielded to transition between capitalism
and that liberated future. This question remains essential; in the words
of the British Marxist Ralph Milliband, âthe exercise of socialist power
remains the Achillesâ heel of Marxism.â[1] With a focus on the
âdictatorship of the proletariat,â this essay will attempt to think
through this question by bringing the Marxist idea of the âwithering
awayâ of the state into conversation with the political theory of social
ecology. I will attempt to recenter a matter often skirted by Marxists
and anarchists alike: the role of direct democracy in the governance of
a revolutionary society.
Though not myself a Marxist (nor for that matter an anarchist), I have
worked to engage with the core Marxist literature on the âdictatorship
of the proletariatâ in a manner which, while critical, I intend to be
comradely and in good faith. I have little patience for polemic and do
not wish to reproduce the variety of hostility that has characterized
almost all writing by social ecologists on Marxism. I do not believe it
has been effective at connecting with the democratic spirit that many
Marxists hold close at heart. With that in mind, I will rely on extended
quotes from Marx, Engels, and Lenin to allow them to speak for
themselves, with the aim that any necessary paraphrasing be
light-handed.
Most of all, however, this exchange between Marxism and the radical
democratic tradition is intended to be constructive, a contribution I
hope might be genuinely useful for Marxists and libertarian socialists
alike in thinking through the problems of our politics. There are thorny
questions to be unpacked, answers to which do not spring cleanly from
the revolutionary socialist canon. The stakes of such dialogues and
debates are high, and if we take our politics seriously, we need to be
willing to look these theoretical problems squarely in the face. I look
forward to a thoughtful and impassioned dialogue about them.
Friedrich Engels, chief intellectual partner to Karl Marx, articulates
across his written work an elegant hypothesis for how a workersâ state
brings about the stateless society of communism: âSociety thus far,
based upon class antagonisms, had need of the stateâŠfor the purpose of
forcibly keeping the exploited classes in the condition of
oppression.âThus for Engels, the state exists to manage class conflict
while upholding the power of the ruling class. But when the state,
through the overwhelming power of the working class, âtakes possession
of the means of production in the name of society,â it âconstitutes
itself the representative of the whole of society.â Through this act of
expropriation, classes and their resulting antagonisms cease to exist.
With âno longer any social class to be held in subjection,â the state
thereby ârender[s] itself unnecessary.â Having no purpose to repression
and no one to repress, the state necessarily fades and disappears. It
âis not âabolished,â it withers away.â[2]
This ideaâs persuasive power comes from the simplicity and directness of
its internal logic. The conclusionâthat the expansion of the state sets
it on a course of self-abolitionâis counterintuitive, but flows clearly
from one step to another from its premises. It has a formulaic quality
that is predictive without speculation: what many Marxists might call
âscientific.â Committed readers of the Marxist canon may simply leave it
at that, concluding that this is therefore the road to communism. But
the heart of science is testing such ideas up against what we can
observe in the worldâand unlike Marx, Engels, and Lenin, we have now a
full century of dozens of socialist or communist states ruled by
workersâ parties that have sought to put this into practice, in one form
or another. The unfortunate fact we must grapple with is that this
simple prediction, that state ownership of the economy leads the state
to wither away, has never once occurred. Socialists have put forward a
number of attempted explanations for this.
Chief among them is the problem of imperialism. In addition to
controlling an exploited subject class, the other classical function of
a state is to defend against external threats, which for socialist
states have been abundant. By this line of thinking, one would expect
that socialist states would, pending international revolution, maintain
strong militaries and border controls but absent the class conflict that
necessitates state repression, foster free and open societies within.
Yet this has not been a feature of actually-existing socialism either,
where the stateâs repressive apparatus has continued apace. Indeed, in
some cases that domestic repressive apparatus instead aggressively
expanded under self-identified socialist states.
Another possibility is one anticipated by Marx: the need for socialist
states to first develop the productive forces of society so that the
material conditions of real social freedomâfulfillment of basic needs,
freedom from toil, the leisure to participate in the collective
decision-making of societyâare first in place.[3] For instance, the
Soviet Union was established in an essentially feudal agrarian society,
and carried out a program of breakneck industrialization at incalculable
human and ecological cost, becoming in only a few decades the first
country in history to send a person into space. Yet, despite reaching a
degree of industrial development comparable to the West in which meeting
the needs of all while reducing working hours was possible, this never
resulted in free democratic participation by the whole working class,
nor through this deeper democratization a withering of the state.[4]
A rather more disturbing rationalization suggests that, despite
successful expropriation of the capitalist class, âbourgeois elementsâ
were not yet sufficiently suppressed. What this argument sets in motion
is the specter of the eternal but poorly defined enemy within, a fifth
column whose extermination must come before the working class may
actually take the reins through free democratic deliberation. During
Stalinâs rule in the Soviet Union, the bugbear that could explain any
failure and justify any repression was the âTrotskyite wreckerâ who
exploited the trust of faithful comrades to sabotage the revolution; in
China under Mao, it was the âcapitalist roaderâ who secretly sought the
restoration of capitalism.[5] In his March 1937 report to the Central
Committee of the Communist Party, Stalin wrote,
Present-day Trotskyism is not a political trend in the working class but
a gang without principle, without ideas, of wreckers, diversionists,
intelligence service agents, spies, murderers, a gang of sworn enemies
of the working class, working in the pay of the intelligence services of
foreign states⊠We must bring about a situation where there is not a
single Trotskyite wrecker left in our ranks.[6]
Similarly, the Central Committee of the Communist Party of China kicked
off the Cultural Revolution with the following communiqué:
Those representatives of the bourgeoisie who have sneaked into the
party, the government, the army, and various cultural circles are a
bunch of counter-revolutionary revisionists. Once conditions are ripe,
they will seize political power and turn the dictatorship of the
proletariat into a dictatorship of the bourgeoisie. Some of them we have
already seen through, others we have not. Some are still trusted by us
and are being trained as our successors, persons like Khrushchev, for
example, who are still nestling beside us.[7]
The defense that dissent within the ranks is grounds for setting
democracy aside becomes, in effect, an admission that communism can
never be achieved, as dissent in one form or another is
inextinguishable. Such a politics renders âcommunismâ a horizon where
every step in its direction requires greater political repressionâa
horizon which only retreats a step in turn. As with Robespierreâs
ârepublic of virtueâ and the mountain of severed heads that rose
ever-higher behind him, one cannot purge, repress, or exterminate their
way to a stateless and classless society.[8] Better explanationsâand
better politicsâare needed.
I would like to suggest a different approach to this problem. Rather
than only seeking out forces that inhibit this expected withering of the
state under socialism, i.e., taking the âwither awayâ formula as a
given, I believe we also need to interrogate the formula itself, to
dissect it and reexamine its assumptions. By bringing some of the
critical insights of social ecology about direct democracy and the state
into this discussion, I think we can zero in on just what is wrong with
the Marxist prediction about the withering of the state and place
ourselves on firmer theoretical footing for achieving a democratic
communist future.
The origins and nature of the state in Marxist theory are interwoven
with the origins of class. The stateâs development and basis for
existence is understood as a consequence of class society. In The Origin
of the Family, Private Property, and the State, Engels writes:
[The state] is the product of a society at a certain stage of
development; it is the admission that this society has become entangled
in an insoluble contradiction with itself, that it is cleft into
irreconcilable antagonisms which it is powerless to dispel. But in order
that these antagonisms, classes with conflicting economic interests,
might not consume themselves and society in sterile struggle, a power
seemingly standing above society became necessary for the purpose of
moderating the conflict, of keeping it within the bounds of âorderâ; and
this power, arisen out of society, but placing itself above it, and
increasingly alienating itself from it, is the state.[9]
Despite its appearance as standing above society and its internal
conflicts, in Marxist theory the state is rather an implement of the
ruling class to preserve its power. Marx and Engels therefore see the
exercise of state power as an extension of class conflict and broadly
reducible to such. This leads to a view of the state as passive, lacking
any internal dynamics independent of the interests or goals of the class
that wields it.
Between each past successive class society, upheavals or political
revolutions transformed the structure of the state, which cleared the
remnants of the previous social order and ushered into being the new.
Marx imagined that the transition out of capitalism would be similar.
The workersâ struggles would necessarily escalate towards their winning
political power as a class, in the form of the dictatorship of the
proletariat.
First-time readers of Marx may be confused or shocked (or worse,
excited) by the use of the word dictatorship, a term whose meaning took
on new dimensions through the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
Marx deploys âdictatorshipâ as a more neutral term, referring to
political power and the exercise thereof. Before adopting the
terminology of âdictatorship of the proletariatâ (not his own coinage),
he variously referred to this idea as ârule of the proletariat,â
âpolitical power of the working class,â and other such phrases that ring
more democratically to twenty-first century ears. In The âDictatorship
of the Proletariatâ from Marx to Lenin, Hal Draper argues that Marxâs
meaning was nothing like the Blanquist idea of dictatorship; not rule by
a tyrannical elite but collective governance by the masses of working
people directly.[10] Draper writes:
To understand this, the reader must put aside the modern aura that makes
âdictatorshipâ a dirty word for us; for this aura did not yet exist. How
do you counteract the primitive notion of dictatorship that was so
common precisely among the people who wanted to be good revolutionaries?
You tell them: Dictatorship? That means rule. Yes, we want the rule of
the proletariat; but that does not mean the rule of a man or a clique or
a band or a party; it means the rule of a class. Class rule means class
dictatorship.[11]
It must also be kept in mind that Marx was convinced that capitalism
would soon convert the vast majority of humanity into wage laborers,
such that rule by the working class to his mind meant something rather
like âpolitical power to the 99%.â Working-class rule was therefore
understood as both radically democratic and embodying the true general
social interest, echoing core goals of social ecology.
While Marx and Engelsâs perspectives on the specifics of how the working
class were to achieve political power shifted over the course of their
lifetimesâat some points favoring an insurrection to overthrow the
capitalist state, at others for winning the âbattle of democracyâ via
working-class parties absorbing the majority of the voting
populationâthe idea that the road to communism runs only through the
dictatorship of the proletariat was constant throughout their political
lives. Marx did have some specific ideas about what this political
supremacy of the working class would accomplish. If a constitutional
democratic republic did not yet exist, the workers would establish one.
They would nationalize industry, and with state control over the
economy, they would begin to plan production to be more efficient while
pushing forward rapid technological advances. These would allow the
workersâ state to shorten the workday, freeing more time for ordinary
working men and women to participate in governing the socialist society.
They would abolish the standing army and redistribute their weapons to
militias of the working class. Armed to defend their new society and
expropriate the expropriators, the people themselves would replace any
âspecial forceâ for repression in the form of a professionalized army
and police force. This dictatorship of the proletariat marks the
disappearance of the state as a âpower, arisen out of society,
butâŠplac[ed] above itâŠalienat[ed] from it.â[12] The people armed and
assembled, in this view, are the state.
Commune
In the spring of 1871, Parisians who were resisting the disarmament of
their citizen militias cast out the national government of France. The
new system these ordinary men and women devised to replace it was a
government of participatory democracy and worker control, with decisions
made through popular assemblies and recallable delegates. The working
class was in the saddle, guiding the transformation of a city of nearly
two million people. This was in many ways dramatically different from
Marxâs political vision of nationalized industry, universal national
programs, and state-driven technological development. As the Commune was
embraced by the First International, Marx came to accept that the
reality of emerging revolutionary movements was even more transformative
than he had previously envisioned, calling it âthe political form at
last discoveredâ for the emancipation of the working class.[13] The
Commune became the living example of socialist revolution that many
communists, Marx and Engels included, would continually refer to, long
after its defeat. As Engels wrote twenty years later, âWell and good,
gentlemen, do you want to know what this dictatorship looks like? Look
at the Paris Commune. That was the Dictatorship of the Proletariat.â[14]
Lenin too looked to the Paris Commune as the model of the dictatorship
of the proletariat. In his most important work, The State and
Revolution, Lenin makes his case for why the working class cannot take
hold of the state as it exists, but must instead overthrow it and erect
in its place a fundamentally different sort of government. To that end,
he quotes at length from Marxâs pamphlet on the Commune, The Civil War
in France. Detailing the many ways the Paris Commune fully democratized
public life, Lenin writes:
Thus the Commune appears to have substituted âonlyâ fuller democracy for
the smashed state machine: abolition of the standing army; all officials
to be elected and subject to recall. But as a matter of fact this âonlyâ
signifies the very important substitution of one type of institution for
others of a fundamentally different order. This is a case of âquantity
becoming transformed into qualityâ: democracy, introduced as fully and
consistently as is generally conceivable, is transformed from bourgeois
democracy into proletarian democracy; from the state (i.e., a special
force for the suppression of a particular class) into something which is
no longer really a state.[15]
He argues that these changes in the functioning of democracy amount to
not a difference in degree, but in kind. The matter of direct recall
upends the relationship of power between public officials and the
people, turning those officials from representatives handed independent
decision-making power into mere delegates who may only carry forward the
decisions of ongoing popular assemblies. The abolition of the standing
army and the armament of popular militias in their stead reflects and
upholds this reversal. The qualitative transformations wrought by the
Paris Commune were so total that Lenin regarded the new system as âno
longer really a state.â
In 1875, in a letter to August Bebel criticizing the Gotha Program,
Engels likewise wrote that the Paris Commune âhad ceased to be a state
in the true sense of the term.â[16] Lenin, responding to this some
decades later, regards this claim as Engelsâs âmost important
theoretical statementâ![17] If the Paris Communeâthe shining example of
the dictatorship of the proletariatâwas not really a state, then what
was it?[18] Is the dictatorship of the proletariat also then not a
state? And if this is so unclear, what is a state?
In their many debates with anarchists over the years, Marxists argued
vigorously that the state should be abolished, but not overnight. They
offered instead a political program of abolishing privileged rule in
favor of the direct governance of society by the vast majority. Leninâs
central argument in The State and Revolution is that the proletariat
cannot lay its hands on the ready-made machinery of the state, but
instead must destroy the state and build something else in its place
that is not a state. To anarchist ears, that is doing away with the
state overnight.[19]
Mikhail Bakunin, Pyotr Kropotkin, Murray Bookchin, and others in the
libertarian socialist tradition have advocated the replacement of states
by federations of free communes, governed directly by ordinary people
without mediation through ruling elitesâin short, the Paris Commune to
scale.[20] What then distinguishes this from the dictatorship of the
proletariat which is âno longer really a stateâ wherein the âfunctions
of state power devolve upon the people generallyâ?[21] What are we to
make of the fact that the desired political system of those who do not
want a state, transitional or otherwise, aligns closely with the Marxist
vision of a âworkersâ stateâ? Are these merely definitional challenges,
or something more fundamental?[22] I do not mean to suggest the
differences between Marxism and anarchism are merely semantic, but
clearly we must think through the word âstateâ with more precision.
On this topic, Marx, Engels, and Lenin are all guilty of category
muddling. Much of the theoretical verbiage in their relevant passages
masks, rather than clarifies, the underlying ideas. The fundamental
problem underlying Engels and Leninâs ambiguityâthe dictatorship of the
proletariat being not quite a stateâis that there are two core
characteristics that make something a state, and as a result they are
struggling to describe a social order in which one but not the other is
present.
The first characteristic is the control over the means of organized
violence, to defend or repress. It is in terms of this characteristic
that Marx and Lenin define the state. Lenin writes, âThe state is a
special organization of force; it is an organization of violence for the
suppression of some class.â[23] Both Marx and Lenin denounce the foolish
intent of anarchists to abolish the state as âlaying down their arms,â
leaving the revolution exposed to bourgeois reaction.[24] Contemporary
political scientists also tend to define the state as the institution
with a monopoly on the legitimate use of violence.
The second characteristic, which Engels and Lenin recognize (sometimes
implicitly, other times explicitly) as a key feature of states is that
they are structures of elite rule. States are organized according to
command and control, through which a small group of rulers can impose
its authority upon the rest. The state, as Engels notes, is above
society, being inherently a form of minority rule. Lenin writes that
âThe Commune ceased to be a stateâ in so far as it no longer repressed
the majority of the population.[25]
These two defining characteristics are closely related, of course, as
the function of the first (the monopoly on âlegitimateâ violence) is to
preserve and enforce the second (minority rule). But they are not the
same thing. In a generous interpretation of Marx and Engels, the
dictatorship of the proletariat is a new sort of governance in which the
second characteristic has been overthrown and no longer applies, with
the powers of decision-making and the means of violence to enforce them
having been devolved to the whole society of working people. This, it
seems, is what Engels means in saying that the Paris Communeâand by
extension the dictatorship of the proletariatâis âno longer a state in
the proper sense of the word,â as one of the defining features of the
state has been abolished.[26]
Even as these two aspects of states are connected, distinguishing them
as distinct features is the only way to gain theoretical clarity on the
state and the problem before us. Some of the insights of Bookchin and
social ecology more broadly are particularly helpful here. In his essay
âAnarchism, Power, and Government,â he writes:
[J]ust as elsewhere I have distinguished between politics and
statecraft, I must now also point out the distinction between
governments and states⊠All states are governments, but not all
governments are states. A government is a set of organized and
responsible institutions that are minimally an active system of social
and economic administration. They handle the problems of living in an
orderly fashion. A government may be a dictatorship; it may be a
monarchy or a republican state; but it may also be a libertarian
formation of some kindâŠ
What kinds of governments, then, are not states? Tribal councils, town
meetings, workersâ committees, soviets (in the original sense of the
word), popular assemblies and the like are governments, and no amount of
juggling with words can conceal that factâŠ
A state, by contrast, is a government that is organized to serve the
interests of a privileged and often propertied class at the expense of
the majority. This historic rise of the state transformed governance
into a malignant force for social development. When a government becomes
a stateâthat is, a coercive mechanism for perpetuating class rule for
exploitative purposesâit invariably acquires different institutional
characteristics. First, its members are professionalized to one degree
or another, in order to separate them from the mass of the population
and thereby impart to them an extraordinary status, which in turn
renders them the full-time protectors of a ruling class. Second, the
state, aided by military and police functionaries, enjoys a monopoly
over the means of violence.[27]
Bookchin argues that a government only becomes a state when it
structures itself as an institution of elite rule to assert their power
over the rest of the population. His vision of a stateless society is
one where power lies with the people as a whole instead of a small group
of governing officialsânot one lacking the organized use of force. In
fact, in Urbanization Without Cities, he writes, âA true civicism that
tries to create an authentic politics, an empowered citizenry, and a
municipalized economy would be a vulnerable project indeed if it failed
to replace the police, the professional army⊠with an authentic militiaâŠ
for dealing with external dangers to freedom.â[28]
When it comes to the necessity of force in overthrowing the present
system and defending the new socialist government, Bookchin is on the
same page as the Marxists. So too are the classical anarchists like
Bakunin, Kropotkin, and Malatesta. The question of force is not what
separates them. It ought not be where we draw the lines of debate about
the state.
If we are to adopt Bookchinâs distinction between states and
governments, then an institution or set of institutions is therefore
only a state if it meets both of our criteria. If it meets the first
(organized violence) but not the second (elite rule), it is some popular
system of government that is not a state. If it meets the second but not
the first, it cannot last (or exist at all), as elite rule relies on
force and coercion. We may also imagine into the future forms of
communal government that meet neither requirement, where hierarchy and
force have both been banished; this is what Marx would term the higher
stage of communism.
David Harvey, one of the few Marxists to genuinely engage with
Bookchinâs work, lays out a somewhat different perspective in âListen,
Anarchist!,â a playful reference to Bookchinâs own 1969 pamphlet
âListen, Marxist!â Harvey frames the issue as a matter of serious
anarchists coming to recognize the necessity of state-building in some
fashion, but acknowledges that much of this comes down to defining
terminology:
The odd thing here is that the more autonomistas and anarchists grapple
with the necessity to build organizations that have the capacity to ward
off bourgeois power and to build the requisite large-scale
infrastructures for revolutionary transformation, the more they end up
constructing something that looks like some kind of state⊠Bookchinâs
position on all of this is interesting⊠Opposition to the state must not
carry over to opposition to government⊠Consensus decision making, he
says, âthreatens to abolish society as such.â Simple majority voting
suffices. There must also be a âserious commitmentâ to a âformal
constitution and appropriate by-lawsâ because âwithout a democratically
formulated and approved institutional framework whose members and
leaders can be held accountable, clearly articulated standards of
responsibility cease to exist⊠Freedom from authoritarianism can best be
assured only by the clear, concise and detailed allocation of powerââŠAll
of this looks to me like a reconstruction of a certain kind of state
(but this may be nothing more than semantics).[29]
In essence, if it looks like a state and quacks like a state, shouldnât
we call it a state? I do not particularly want to push back on Harvey
here to argue about what is and is not a state; the meaning of the word
is not a fact of the universe floating in the world outside language or
theory. What does matter is that whatever categories we use encompass
and reflect real distinctions in our social world. This may mean we take
âstateâ to mean the same thing as âgovernment,â as Harvey suggests,
while clearly distinguishing between governments where decisions come
from on high (the political order we as revolutionaries aim to
overthrow) and those where decisions flow from below (the system of
radically democratic popular self-rule that we strive to establish). Or
it could mean we distinguish the broader, arguably neutral categories of
government and governance from âthe state,â a more particular form of
government organized around elite domination through the implements of
violence, as Bookchin does. I believe the second option results in
considerably more clarity, but it is inessential to my argument.
Crucially, as thinkers and organizers we must recognize that this
consensus of meaning within a shared leftist discourse has not yet been
achieved. This is a source of dispute and confusion that must be
consciously navigated while communicating these ideas both within and
beyond our movements. Sloganeering will not suffice; simply asking
âabolish the state, yes or no?â is not good enough either. Yet we
nevertheless require firmer answers than âWell, sort of.â Semantics
undergird this problem, but it is not merely semantic. The confused way
we talk about states also garbles our thinking about essential questions
for revolutionaries.
Prevailing Marxist notions of what is and is not a state consider the
Paris Commune and a Marxist-Leninist one-party dictatorship to be the
same sort of political order, both dictatorships of the proletariat, but
also consider the Paris Commune to be categorically different from
anarchist polities like the Ukrainian Free Territory or the Shinmin
Prefecture despite their clear similarities in form.[30] The lines of
this debate about abolishing the state are drawn artificially, with a
certain sectarian shallowness. This serves to confuse and obscure the
deeper debate between those who advocate a socialism from below through
the direct popular self-governance of the working class and those who
merely desire another form of elite rule. In short, the manner and the
terms in which both anarchists and Marxists have discussed these
questions have actively impeded the revolutionary leftâs ability to
think about them clearly.
This confusion creates fertile ground for polemical distortion and
misrepresentation. More dangerously, it opens space for groups to co-opt
the moral force of âall power to the peopleâ even as they do not value
democracy and undermine it as it suits them. Lenin himself was guilty of
all the above, both in his writings and political life. He straddled the
imprecision that we need now to overcome, riding soviet democracy into
power while preparing justifications for its replacement by the party
apparatus. As he writes in The State and Revolution, âDemocracy is of
great importance for the working class in its struggle for freedom
against the capitalists. But democracy is by no means a boundary that
must not be overstepped; it is only one of the stages in the process of
development from feudalism to capitalism, and from capitalism to
communism.â[31] But democracy is not a stage, nor a boundary; it is the
masses in power. To âoverstepâ democracy can only mean to roll back that
popular power.
The question we must always ask is this: does the working class as a
whole govern the socialist society, or does a segment of society govern
the working class? Lenin cannot, or will not, provide a consistent
answer. Mere paragraphs away from the most radically democratic
assertions of his entire corpus, he dismisses the notion that workers
can function without being under the control of state managers as
âanarchist dreams.â[32]
Here, the state-as-elite-rule makes a hasty return. Leninism has quietly
snuck undemocratic governance into the back door of the dictatorship of
the proletariat, unseen because he defines the new regime in terms of
whether the workers hold gunsânot who commands them. Even if the people
are armed, who directs their activity? Are they participants in
collective decision-making or recipients of orders? Weapons or no
weapons, it was never the legionaries, conscripts, or knights who ruled
the states of class societies present and past, but the senators,
ministers, and kings. There may be rule by the whole working class, or
there may be rule by a special stratum of decision-makers, but not both.
And once Lenin is firmly in power, these ambiguities immediately give
way. In a practical essay written in 1918 for the purpose of orienting
his new government, he writes, the ârevolution demandsâprecisely in the
interests of its development and consolidation, precisely in the
interests of socialismâthat the people unquestioningly obey the single
will of the leaders of labour.â[33] In the same passage Lenin states,
âGiven ideal class-consciousness and discipline on the part of those
participating in the common work, this subordination would be something
like the mild leadership of a conductor of an orchestra.â Yet he goes on
to add, âIt may assume the sharp forms of a dictatorship if ideal
discipline and class-consciousness are lacking.â Lenin, of course,
leaves it up to his own discretion how âmildâ his one-man rule is going
to be, saying it depends upon whether or not the people are sufficiently
âdisciplined.â[34] Weâve moved a long way from the rule of all over
all.[35]
So, let us take up again the initial question: why have we not seen the
state wither away? Reconsider Engelsâs formula: The state exists to
control class conflict. If by the power of the workers the state seizes
all property, then all is held in common and classes cease to existâand
therefore the stateâs architecture of coercion no longer serves any
purpose.
Here is the flaw in the formulaâthe bug in the dialectic. If by the
power of workers, the state seizes all property, then all is held in
common and classes cease to exist. Unless the structure of the state is
fundamentally transformed, such that the people rule directly through a
system of radical democracy, with no special strata to make decisions on
their behalf, state ownership of the entire economy isnât common
ownership of the economy. It is just ownership by those who control the
state. Then all is held in common simply does not follow from a program
of nationalizing industry. If the state does not cease to be a state,
there remains an elite class who command the labor power of others, and
class conflict proceeds apace.[36]
âClass,â after all, means the existence of different and opposing
relationships to the means of production. State ownership of the means
of production is not the abolition of class, because most people work
for the state while a smaller group commands their labor by wielding
state authority. Even if they call themselves workers, these new elites
are set apart with their own particular class interests: the privileges
of their status, their vantage point removed from the experience of the
workers they command, and most fundamentally their authority over the
labor of others.
This managerial class not only has distinct interests in direct conflict
with a transition to communism, which would require them to relinquish
their special status; they also hold the power to defend those interests
against agitation from below. When conflicts between workers and party
leaders arise, the latter can simply rely on state repression to uphold
their decisions and their social position. As this is not a classless
society, neither is it to be a stateless one.
No less a Leninist than Leon Trotsky, long beholden to the idea that
ânationalized property equals socialism,â later warned in The Revolution
Betrayed of this tension between state ownership and the people:
The new constitution â wholly founded, as we shall see, upon an
identification of the bureaucracy with the state, and the state with the
people â says: â⊠the state property â that is, the possessions of the
whole people.â This identification⊠becomes the source of crude
mistakes, and of downright deceit, when applied to the first and still
unassured stages of the development of a new societyâŠ
State property becomes the property of âthe whole peopleâ only to the
degree that social privilege and differentiation disappear, and
therewith the necessity of the state. In other words: state property is
converted into socialist property in proportion as it ceases to be state
property. And the contrary is true: the higher the Soviet state rises
above the people, and the more fiercely it opposes itself as the
guardian of property to the people as its squanderer, the more obviously
does it testify against the socialist character of this state
property.[37]
If only Trotskyâthe butcher of Kronstadt himselfâhad internalized this
lesson sooner.
These problems are, at least in part, a consequence of the fact that
Marxism lacks a clear political theory. The state is seen as but an
empty stage, upon which the agents of the class struggle may speak their
lines and advance the plot. As a result, what many Marxists call
dialectical materialism is instead a variety of idealismâa belief that
so long as they have the correct ideas, the leaders of a dictatorship
will take the correct path. But what of the interests and antagonisms
built into the state form, structured by who commands whose labor and
who benefits from it? The stage is no empty vessel; its shape shapes the
story. Like the feudal manor, slave plantation, private firm, or any
other institution of hierarchy, the state has a logic unto itself.
No structure of minority rule can be a container for rule by the whole
of society; this circle cannot be squared. Too often Marxist discourse
shrouds this dilemma of the âworkersâ stateâ with tenuously stacked
layers of political representation: the class speaks for the whole of
society, the party speaks for the class, the central committee speaks
for the party, and the party leader speaks for the central committee.
Each degree of separation is held together by dubious democratic
accountability, or in most cases by rhetoric alone. Such farcical
ârepresentationâ serves only to disempower working people.
The arrival of socialists to power, even those with the most noble
democratic intentions, does not ensure that the working class will
govern society, for the working class is not itself in power. To return
to Hal Draper, âYes, we want the rule of the proletariat; but that does
not mean the rule of a man or a clique or a band or a party; it means
the rule of a class.â[38]It is of course the central thrust of the
politics of social ecology that this quandary cannot be overcome without
revolutionizing the structures of public governance, abolishing
representative rule itself in favor of confederal direct democracy.
Without direct democracy, these contradictions can never be
unraveled.[39]
The question of nationalizing industryâas opposed to municipalizing,
cooperatizing, or other forms of democratic social controlâis a debate
to be had within the movement. But it must be recognized that state
ownership and central planning are not in themselves socialism; they are
not the road to communism. It is direct democracy that is the
fundamental ingredient, the âform of freedomâ that opens the door to a
classless future. There can be no revolutionary dictatorship of the
proletariat without power being vested in forms of deliberation and
decision-making resting with the people themselves. Direct democracy is
what separates the stagnation of proclaimed workersâ states, whether
Marxist-Leninist or social-democratic, from a transition to
communism.[40]
In part, we can attribute this theoretical weakness on the part of Marx
and Engels to their scientism and consequent love affair with necessity.
Newtonian physics shows us that objects in motion have no say in the
matter: the outcomes of their paths are determined by necessity. Marx
and Engels too thought in terms of laws of motion, and believed they had
discovered those of history. The following century, Hannah Arendt noted
that the very language of ârevolutionâ itself is of mechanistic,
astronomical origin, and chastised viewing societyâs progression through
this ânotion of irresistibility, the fact that the revolving motion of
the stars follows a preordained path and is removed from all influence
of human power.â[41] It was never enough for Marx and Engels to project
forward what weâas revolutionaries, as the working class, as human
beingsâshould do, to bring about this better future. The earnest moral
outrage of the young Marx aside, the lasting framework of Marxâs
philosophy of history casts all in terms of what will, what must come to
pass. Thus in the Marxist story of the future, the state is not
abolished, it withers away.
But replacing the state with radical democracy is not an assured,
necessary outgrowth of the development of capitalism. It is what
Bookchin terms a potentiality, the seeds of which are planted in the
human soil, in need of protection and nurturing. It will require
deliberate, conscious action on the part of organized masses, which may
be redirected into mistakes of the past or into dead ends not yet
encountered. Lenin stated that when âthe majority of the people itselfâ
is armed, a âspecial force for suppressionâ becomes unnecessary. But
this is not what occurred in Paris in 1871, nor in similar popular
revolutions since. Standing armies werenât suddenly superfluous; they
had to be actively disarmed. The organized power of ordinary people,
cradling dreams of a freer tomorrow, dissolved the authority of the
state into their own organs of radical democracy. Whether such a
democratization is the cumulation of an extended, steady struggle to
wrest power from elites or a dramatic clash that at last boils over
between the people and their rulers, it must be the work of our own
hands. There is, simply put, no mechanism nor precedent for the state to
just wither awayâit is we who must wither the state.
---
Mason Herson-Hord is an organizer and writer in Detroit, MI. He is on
the coordinating committee of Symbiosis and lead organizer for the Motor
City Freedom Riders, a metro Detroit organization of bus riders
organizing for transit justice. He is also a board member of the
Institute for Social Ecology. His work, focusing primarily on
movement-building and ecological philosophy, has been published in In
These Times, The Ecologist, Perspectives on Anarchist Theory , Socialist
Forum, and the Journal of World-Systems Research.
[1] Ralph Milliband, âLeninâs The State and Revolutionâ (The Socialist
Register, 1970).
https://jacobinmag.com/2018/08/lenin-state-and-revolution-miliband.
[2] Friedrich Engels, Anti-DĂŒhring/Herr Eugen DĂŒhringâs Revolution in
Science (New York, International, 1939), 306â307. All quoted words in
this paragraph are pulled from the epigraph fromabove.
[3] In his Critique of the Gotha Programme (1875), Marx distinguished
between the first, or âlower,â stage of communism, in which the working
class has full command of the economy but where access to what is
produced is still conditional on how much one works, and the second, or
âhigher,â stage of communism, in which all inequality and injustice has
been fully eradicated and society is at last organized around the
principle of âfrom each according to their ability, to each according to
their need.â In the transition from the lower stage to the higher stage,
the workersâ state brings societyâs productive forces to maturity and
steadily sheds the lingering elements of capitalism. It is here that we
may note an inkling of doubt in Engelsâs formula, with suggestion that
transition to statelessness might not be so immediate after all, that a
state may persist under âlower stage communismâ for an indefinite
period. It should also be noted that in the industrialized world and
arguably in most âdevelopingâ countries as well, we are now currently
technologically capable of providing for the needs of all while working
far less. Reducing working hours indeed appears to be an urgent
ecological necessity.
[4] It is also unclear why technological development is presumed to be
only a capitalist- or state-driven possibility, such that this could
never be carried out by the association of free producers. See, for
example, how self-directed collectivization of enterprise during the
Spanish Civil War increased output by 20% in a six-month period (Ronald
Fraser, The Blood of Spain, London, Pimlico, 370). But that is a
discussion for another time.
[5] During the Stalin era, âwreckingâ was a specific criminal charge for
any acts serving to undermine the Soviet economy, including complaining
about oneâs working conditions (which allegedly damaged workersâ
morale). The label of âwreckerâ was used to enforce labor discipline and
absolute obedience to Party directives, while casting a wide net for
repression of political opponents. âCapitalist roaders,â according to
Mao, were those of the capitalist class who sought the restoration of
capitalism from within the Communist Party itself. Mao condemned
Stalinâs successor, Nikita Khrushchev, as a capitalist roader.
[6] Joseph Stalin, Mastering Bolshevism, Marxist Pamphlets No. 1(New
York, New Century Publishers, 1937), 12, 27.
http://collections.mun.ca/PDFs/radical/MasteringBolshevism.pdf.
[7] âCircular of the Central Committee of the Communist Party of China
on the Great Proletarian Political Revolutionâ (1966).
https://www.marxists.org/subject/china/documents/cpc/cc_gpcr.htm.
[8] One may note that the Communards of Paris, the architects of that
first dictatorship of the proletariat, in fact smashed the guillotine
into pieces and burned that symbol of state terror before an enormous
cheering crowd. Such should be all revolutionariesâ feelings towards the
terror.
[9] Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and
the State (1884),280.
[10] Louis Auguste Blanqui was a French revolutionary socialist and
contemporary of Marxâs (1805â1881). Unlike most socialists, Blanqui did
not believe in the importance of mass movements, but rather thought the
revolution should be carried out by a small band of conspirators, who
would establish a temporary, autocratic dictatorship (in the common
contemporary sense of the term) to redistribute societyâs wealth.
[11] Hal Draper, The âDictatorship of the Proletariatâ from Marx to
Lenin (New York, Monthly Review Press, 1987).
https://www.marxists.org/subject/marxmyths/hal-draper/article2.htm.
[12] Engels, The Origin of the Family, 280.
[13] Karl Marx, The Civil War in France (1871), 26.
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/download/pdf/civil_war_france.pdf.
[14] Friedrich Engels, 1891 Introduction to The Civil War in France by
Karl Marx (1871).
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1871/civil-war-france/postscript.htm.
In addition to The Civil War in France, other important sources on the
Paris Commune are Kristin Ross, Communal Luxury: The Political Imaginary
of the Paris Commune (London and New York, Verso Books, 2015), Murray
Bookchin, The Third Revolution: Popular Movements in the Revolutionary
Era, Volume 2 (London and New York, Cassell, 1998), and Carolyn J.
Eichner, Surmounting the Barricades: Women in the Paris Commune
(Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press, 2004).
[15] Vladimir Lenin, The State and Revolution (1917) in Essential Works
of Lenin: âWhat Is to Be Done?â and Other Writings, ed. Henry M.
Christman (New York, Dover Publications, 1987), 301.
[16] Letter from Engels to Bebel (March 18â25, 1875), first published by
Bebel in Volume II of his memoirs (Aus miner Leben) in 1911.
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/letters/75_03_18.htm.
[17] Lenin, The State and Revolution, 320.
[18] The Russian anarchist Mikhail Bakunin similarly described the Paris
Commune as âa bold and outspoken negation of the Stateâ (âThe Paris
Commune and the Idea of the State,â 1871).
[19] Indeed, according to Nicolai Sukhanovâs eyewitness account (The
Russian Revolution, 1917: A Personal Record, trans. Joel Carmicael, New
York, Harper and Brothers, 1984, 269â285), Leninâs first stop after
getting off the train at the Finland Station was Bolshevik headquarters,
to give a two-hour speech to Party leaders laying out the ideas of The
State and Revolution, shocking the orthodox Marxists with his heretical
âpurely anarchist schemaâ (Sukhanov, The Russian Revolution, 282). As a
result, a significant number of Russian anarchists (most famously Victor
Serge) actually joined the Bolshevik Party, with the rationale that the
most radical Bolsheviks were by that point effectively anarchists. In
âListen, Marxist!,â (1969,
https://www.marxists.org/archive/bookchin/1969/listen-marxist.htm),
Murray Bookchin writes, âIndeed, much that passes for âMarxismâ in State
and Revolution is pure anarchismâfor example, the substitution of
revolutionary militias for professional armed bodies and the
substitution of organs of self-management for parliamentary bodies. What
is authentically Marxist in Leninâs pamphlet is the demand for âstrict
centralism,â the acceptance of a ânewâ bureaucracy, and the
identification of soviets with a state.â
[20] So central was the Commune to Bookchinâs political thought that he
dubbed his mature politics âCommunalism.â
[21] Lenin, The State and Revolution, 301. Lenin also writes that âwe
[the workers as a whole] shall reduce the role of state officials to
that of simply carrying out our instructionsâ (ibid 307). This is
functionally identical to Bookchinâs views on the distinction between
policy-making (the deciding authority of the assembly) and
administration (which may be delegated to select recallable
individuals).
[22] In fact, in that previously cited letter to Bebel (footnote 16),
Engels suggested banishing the word âstateâ altogether, as a term whose
usage sowed more confusion than it illuminated, to be replaced with
Gemeinwesen, a German word that can mean âcommunity,â âcommonality,â or
âcommune.â It seems that my frustrations about antagonistic discourses
talking past each other may have been shared.
[23] Lenin, The State and Revolution, 287.
[24] Anarchist pacifists notwithstanding, this is of course not at all
what anarchists take âabolish the stateâ to mean. As Bookchin responds
in âListen, Marxist!,â âNor did the anarchists of the last century
believe that the abolition of the state involved âlaying down armsâ
immediately after the revolution, to use Marxâs obscurantist words,
thoughtlessly repeated by Lenin in State and Revolution.â An unfortunate
quality of Marxist critiques of anarchism is persistent
misrepresentation. Despite its brilliance in other ways, The State and
Revolution is frequently quite shameless in this regard. By way of
illustrative example, Lenin spends paragraphs battling the âfederalism
of Proudhonâ as a political form inferior to Marxismâs centralism. Some
pages later, as if to pretend that his extended discussion of the
political forms put forward by anarchists never took place, Lenin
claims, âThe utopians busied themselves with âdiscoveringâ political
forms under which the socialist transformation of society was to take
place. The anarchists dismissed the question of political forms
altogetherâ (The State and Revolution, 312). These displays of
intellectual dishonesty only muddy our theoretical waters still further.
[25] Lenin, The State and Revolution, 320.
[26] We should keep in mind that the means of violence have also been
fundamentally transformed. The abolition of standing armies and the
redistribution of arms to democratic militias is a category shift, a
change in kind; it may not be quite correct to say that one aspect of
state-ness is abolished in the dictatorship of the proletariat while the
other endures intact. And indeed, according to Lenin, the supersession
of elite rule by direct self-governance of the working class sets
society on the path to abolishing organized violence as such. As a
directly democratic society dissolves class distinctions, the means of
violence, such as they are, become increasingly obsolete and may
eventually be set aside.
[27] Murray Bookchin, âAnarchism, Power, and Government.â
http://new-compass.net/articles/anarchism-power-and-government.
[28] Murray Bookchin, Urbanization Without Cities (Montreal and New
York, Black Rose Books, 1992), 285.
[29] David Harvey, âListen, Anarchist!: A personal response to Simon
Springerâs âWhy a radical geography must be anarchistââ (2015).
http://davidharvey.org/2015/06/listen-anarchist-by-david-harvey/. Harvey
here quotes from Bookchinâs essay âThe Communalist Project,â published
in The Next Revolution: Popular Assemblies and the Promise of Direct
Democracy (London and New York, Verso, 2015).
[30] I should note that with closer examination this distinction falls
apart on its own terms, at least for the case of the Free Territory
(also known as Makhnovia), which was defended through organized violence
by the Revolutionary Insurrectionary Army of Ukraine.
[31] Lenin, The State and Revolution, 346.
[32] ibid, 307.
[33] Lenin, âThe Immediate Tasks of the Soviet Government,â April 28,
1918. https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1918/mar/x03.htm.
Here, Lenin invokes Engels, from his short essay âOn Authorityâ (1872).
Engels wrote, âBut the necessity of authority, and of imperious
authority at that, will nowhere be found more evident than on board a
ship on the high seas. There, in time of danger, the lives of all depend
on the instantaneous and absolute obedience of all to the will of one.â
[34] ibid.
[35] It should furthermore be noted that despite the enduring legacy of
Leninism as being for the destruction of the bourgeois stateâs
bureaucracy, it is not actually clear that anything resembling this took
place in Russia. In Leninâs Government: Sovnarkom 1917â1922 (Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1979, 51), T.H. Rigby argues that there was
âhigh level of continuity in the central administrative machine of the
Russian stateâ such that administrative changes brought by the
Bolsheviks âwere scarcely greater than those sometimes accompanying
changes of government in Western parliamentary systems.â The
commissariats of the new state were in almost all cases simply renamed
ministries from the Tsarist regime, staffed by the same bureaucrats but
now headed by Bolshevik Party leaders. In practice, this was in fact a
matter of (to use Marxâs phrase) âlay[ing] hold of the ready-made state
machinery.â
[36] There is an extensive literature on the class society of the Soviet
Union and other regimes led by Communist Parties. See, for instance,
Michael Albertâs discussion of the âcoordinator classâ who rule over
workers in a centrally planned economy (Albert, âBeyond Class Rule Is
Parecon,â 2012); Paul Mattickâs introduction to Anti-Bolshevik Communism
(1978), which argues that state ownership under Communist rule
constituted a âmodified capitalist systemâ (â[S]tate-control of the
economyâŠexercised by a privileged social layer as a newly emerging
ruling class, has perpetuated for theâŠlabouring classes the conditions
of exploitation and oppressionâ); and the broader literature of the
International Left Opposition, the Johnson-Forest Tendency, et. al.,
which broke from Trotsky to diagnose the Soviet Union as âstate
capitalism.â
[37] Leon Trotsky, The Revolution Betrayed: What Is the Soviet Union and
Where Is It Going, trans. Max Eastman, 1936.
https://www.marxists.org/archive/trotsky/1936/revbet/ch09.htm.
[38] Draper, The âDictatorship of the Proletariat.â
[39] There is a vast literature on competing visions of how specifically
the principles of direct democracy are to be institutionalized in (and
on the way to) a liberated society, which are beyond the scope of this
essay to discuss in any detail. The traditions of anarcho-syndicalism
and council communism both maintain that all economic decisions should
be made by the workers of those industries, coordinated through
cooperative federations. Little emphasis is placed on the political
sphere outside of production. Murray Bookchin and others have instead
advocated for bringing production into politics, placing economic
decisions under the control of the community as a whole. Hybrids of
these two basic models abound. For an overview of anarcho-syndicalism,
see Rudolf Rocker, Anarcho-Syndicalism: Theory and Practice (London,
Secker and Warburg, 1938). For reflections on council communism, see
Paul Mattick, âCouncil Communismâ (1939),
http://libcom.org/library/council-communism-mattick, and Anton
Pannekoek, Workersâ Councils (Oakland, AK Press, 2002). For an in-depth
discussion of worker control versus community control, see Howard
Hawkins, âCommunity Control, Workersâ Control, and the Cooperative
Commonwealthâ (Society and Nature, 1993). Existing models of direct
democracy to scale should also be considered, which include (among
others) democratic confederalismâs council system in the Autonomous
Administration of North and East Syria, the caracoles and juntas de buen
gobierno in Zapatista-controlled territory in Chiapas, and the grama
sabha in Keralaâs system of Peopleâs Planning.
[40] In The State and Revolution, Lenin notes, âThe more complete
democracy becomesâŠthe more rapidly does the state begin to wither awayâ
(349).
[41] Hannah Arendt, On Revolution, 1963, p. 47. Penguin Books, London
and New York.