đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș darren-allen-goodbye-mr-marx.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:58:15. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Goodbye Mr. Marx Author: Darren Allen Date: 5 Oct 2021 Language: en Topics: marxism, post-marxism, technocracy, critique Source: Retrieved on 21st October from www.expressiveegg.org
The great mistake of the Marxists and of the whole of the nineteenth
century was to think that by walking straight on one mounted upward into
the air.
Simone Weil
Marxâs theories are well known enough to need little more than a
summary. He starts by defining the value of commodities as a function of
the work necessary to produce them. This labour, the source of the
workerâs dignity, is the only âcommodityâ which he has to sell. Once the
capitalist has bought sufficient labour to meet his own needs he then
exploits the workerâthrough direct oppression or through indirect
improvements to âefficiencyââfor profit. This profit accumulates, making
capitalists more and more powerful, until the middle-class has been
absorbed into the working-class and the whole miserable, degraded mass
revolts and create socialism. This process is, for Marx, both necessary
and inevitable, which is why he extolled capitalism, and the bourgeois
state, which he believed prepared the conditions for the superior mode
of production of socialism. Itâs also why he worshipped production
itself, the machinery of society, to which he believed that man must
submit until the day it ceases to destroy him. Then, says Marx, all
social antagonisms will magically cease. Marxâs proletariat is,
therefore, a kind of Christ in mass form, âredeeming the collective sin
of alienationâ[1] through its historically necessary suffering. How much
suffering? It doesnât matter. As the proletariat-Christ will bring
heaven down to earth, âending the quarrel between man and manâ and
âsolving the mystery of historyâ, any act which serves this messianic
expectation, no matter how coercive or cruel, is morally justified.
Because the God of History decrees it.
Marx celebrated the dignity of work, he endorsed independent working
class action, he criticised the state and he bitterly opposed unearnt
privilege but, as Camus put it âthe reduction of every value to
historical terms leads to the direst consequencesâ; to precisely the
degradation, dependency, statist oppression and repulsive privilege
which Marx ostensibly opposed. This happens because he located the moral
quality of his prophecy in bare facts; which have no meaning. His
materialism compelled him to banish everything which does not serve the
material needs of perfected society; the objective fact of âlifeâ which
we are forced to preserve. Love, beauty, truth, dignity, independence,
fellow-feeling, all must be sacrificed to this greater good, this
rational, utilitarian âlifeâ.
Marxâs economic and social theories were based on a rationally
apprehensible, law-like universe, a continuation of Western
civilisationâs perennial endeavour to found reality on factual-causal
laws, which began with the Greeks and Jews of the Iron age, and reached
its modern fulfilment in the work of Hegel (the law of history), Darwin
(the law of nature) and Freud (the law of mind). This project is flawed
from its foundation, for the facticity and causality it is founded on
cannot be located in realityâthey are conceptual tools, phenomenally
useful, but no more foundationally real than numbers are. Establishing a
philosophy on a universe of caused facts, or mind-isolated things,
condemns the individual to alienation from the reality of that universe,
that which is âbeyondâ the representations that the mind presents of
it.[2] a mind is incapable of even perceiving what ails itâit is
conditioned by its own activityâlet alone remedying its problems through
fiddling with the rational-material-economic structure of society.
Philosophically speaking, the inherently alienating activity of the
rational mind comes in several varieties, all of which entail gross
fallacies and, to the extent they govern the lives of men and women,
monstrous violence. The âvarietiesâ that Marx held to were rationalism
and materialism which (just like their ostensible opposites, empiricism
and idealism) ignore what the non-rational and the immaterial have to
teach us, forcing the story of humanity into an essentially mechanical
process which can only be explained by artificial, rational laws. Marx,
like all rational managers, had no interest whatsoever in the ineffable,
in the paradoxical, in the ungovernable, in the elusive, or in the
individual which embodies such qualities. He was only interested in the
quantitative, material mass, motivated by entirely mechanical,
utilitarian ends; the satisfying of material needs which must be met
before any other airy-fairy value, like freedom for example, or peace of
mind, is attended to. For Marx âfreedomâ and âpeaceâ must begin with the
rational domination of nature and must find its fulfilment in the
development of industrial technology, the only way, according to Marx,
that the war against âscarcityâ can be won, the unquenchable lack that
all humans are born with.
For Marx, history was a teleological, or purpose-driven, machine, the
purpose being a classless society to which the various antagonisms
within society must inevitably terminate in. Such a paradise is
essentially no different from the standard Judeo-Christian heaven he
rejected; promised, but continually deferred. To this end, Marx
continually praised the development of capitalism â even when it
resulted in the utter degradation of working people. Following the
quasi-fascistic nationalism of Hegel, he praised Englandâs ruin of
India, writing in his essay âThe British Rule in Indiaâ, that the
British empire was âthe unconscious tool of historyâ and that we might
not be happy about the crimes of the British, or the crumbling of an
ancient empire, but that we can console ourselves with the knowledge
this grotesque torture ultimately âbrings us greater pleasureâ. He was
equally sanguine about the European colonisation of the United States.
Such events were ânecessary stagesâ in the linear, law-like process of
history which he was committed to.
For Marx only mechanical, rational processes were of any interest. He
entirely ruled out consciousness (timeless or otherwise) as an agent in
history. Later Marxists attempted to sneak it, or its manifestation in
culture, belief, law and so on, through the back door, or they sought to
understand society as a whole; undermining, in both cases, Marxâs
cast-iron determinative laws and the foundations of Marxism itself. Marx
himself had no interest in exploring non-historical, non-causal and
non-factual realities which is why, beyond his penetrating analysis of
the alienating effects of capitalist economics on the human psyche, he
had almost nothing to say about love, art, death, reality, morality or
anything else of vital interest to human beings. His vision of
revolutionary change, a mechanical, utilitarian process which must
follow the direction of history, was a betrayal of free human nature.
The utilitarian need to meet material needs, for Marx the determinant
factor in human affairs, manifests as the economy, the mechanism by
which such needs were met at scale. For Marx, thought, awareness,
instinct, belief, inspiration are, first of all, subordinate to the need
to eat, sleep and keep warm, and then, as societies grew, to the need to
plant crops, build houses, manufacture trousers and so on. Apparently,
we donât first of all need to be aware, to think, to believe, to have
instincts and to be inspired to hunt, cook, make fire, fire clay, write
books, tile floors or run restaurants. Not that material needs and the
economy donât explain much of the world, or shape manâs attitudes â
obviously they do[3] but positing material-economic facts as the sole or
primitive determining factor in manâs life reduces him to a component in
a material history machine, which isnât just a morally repugnant
conception of humanity, but intuitively false â at least to anyone
conscious enough to experience their own inner reality â logically false
â as all economic relations are founded on an original conception of
property and on a coercively maintained assumption of scarcity â and
empirically false â what actually happens simply doesnât bear out Marxâs
predictions. He was confident, for example, that the immiseration of the
proletariat would compel it to revolt against the bourgeoisie. As we
know, that didnât happen and doesnât happen; man enters the capitalist
world in a submissive state which only gets worse as he is stupefied by
poverty (particularly in the third-world), crippled by professionalism,
domesticated by technology and pacified with the various sops offered to
him by the welfare state â a quasi-socialist mechanism perfectly
consonant with capitalist self-perpetuation.
The so-called âreal basisâ (Engelâs words) on which Marx established his
laws of history led to four disastrous interconnected consequences;
statism, reformism, technophilia and professionalism. Statism â
attempting to create a socialist state (or ânationalist capitalistâ
state) which will then be overthrown by the proletariat â was, according
to Marx, an indispensable step on the road to communism. This is why he
made the almost unbelievable demand that âthe bourgeoisie must first
come to the helmâ. As with many socialists and communists to follow, he
made vague gestures towards the state one day withering away, but like
the constantly deferred freedom of all tyrannous authority, it could
only be effected by first granting power to experts (such as Leninâs
âvanguard partyâ) who will manage the state-mechanism for the âgoodâ of
the people. That this party might (and time and time again did) manage
the state in its own interests didnât seem to occur to Marx, nor that
the technological progress that he demanded as a prerequisite for
meeting the needs of such a state would further bloat it with a
centralised techno-bureaucracy, again with its own interests.
In fact Marx had no intention of bringing down the state, he wished only
to reform it from within. This is why the concrete reforms he called for
in The Communist Manifesto, his âradicalâ programme for revolutionary
change, called for an inheritance tax, graduated income tax and
centralization of credit and communications. Mikhail Bakunin, who, like
all anarchists worth their salt, endeavoured to do away with the state
by actually doing away with it, opposed this feeble, self-serving
gradualism tooth and nail;
Marx is an authoritarian and centralising communist. He wants what we
want, the complete triumph of economic and social equality, but he wants
it⊠through State power, through the dictatorship of a very strong and,
so to say, despotic provisional government, that is by the negation of
liberty. His economic ideal is the State as sole owner of the land and
of all kinds of capital, cultivating the land under the management of
State engineers, and controlling all industrial and commercial
associations with State capital. We want the same triumph of economic
and social equality through the abolition of the State and of all that
passes by the name of law⊠We want the reconstruction of society and the
unification of mankind to be achieved, not from above downwards by any
sort of authority, nor by socialist officials, engineers, and either
accredited men of learningâbut from below upwards, by the free
federation of all kinds of workersâ associations liberated from the yoke
of the State.
In Marxâs âabove-downwardsâ reconstruction of society, nature and
human-nature continue to be dominated, only now in the name of the
people, by technocratic officials and with the deferred aim of doing
away with the authoritarian state. The embarrassing fact that
authoritarian domination persists, and continues to ruin that which it
is supposed to liberate, is pushed out of view by socialists, as is the
fact that, in essence, nothing has changed. âWorkâ, to take one critical
example, was supposed to be liberated in a communist society. The idea
was that by taking over the industrial system of production developed in
a capitalist economy, with all its specialists, and their theories, and
all its technicians, and their machines, something fundamentally
different would thereby result. In the real world this is a ridiculous
ambition. A capitalist machine which, as Marx himself told us, exercises
total control over the working man â over where he works, over how fast
he works and over what tiny specialised manoeuvres he is expected to
make â remains the same machine when governed by a communist state. It
cannot do or be otherwise. How is a furniture-factory for example (the
kind that makes IKEA flat-packs), to hand over autonomy to the
individual worker? How is the individual labourer to take complete
control of the productive apparatus of the shop floor, devised for a
mechanised, rigidly hierarchical system, and designed to mechanically
discipline the workforce? The factory was designed to produce the
maximum number of goods at the lowest cost and the highest speed; this
is what its machines are for. How then are they to be used to produce
high quality handmade goods, at the pace the individual worker chooses,
and with the individual worker able to autonomously exercise his
discriminating intelligence on the whole process of manufacture? How is
the ikea factory to be reformed, under communist governance, into a
small-scale craftsmanâs workshop?
It isnât. It canât be. The factory, as it is, has to be destroyed. And
not just its physical architecture and machinery, but its ideological
and organisational structures; the division of labour activity into a
thousand hyper-specialised tasks, and the division of labour purpose
into the intellectual work of the manager and the submoron machine
servitude of the worker. Somehow, magically, all this can be reformed,
under communist or socialist governance, back into a dignified whole,
although nobody knows how. Marxists and socialists simply hope that all
of the scattered tasks required by, say, the mechanised industrial
cake-making system (one man on the mixing machine, one man on the baking
machine, one man on the cutting machine, one man on the boxing machine)
will somehow, by itself, dissolve into the autonomous activity of a
single baker, and that the management class will, once freed of the
pressures put on it by capitalist owners, freely join hands with the
drones who follow their orders, cheerfully re-skill each other and then
triumphantly march towards a lower-tech society that makes the
specialist skill of the manager, and the power based thereon, obsolete.
We are supposed to imagine that the bureaucratic techno-elite demanded
by a global industrial machine will renounce its power when that machine
is taken from the hands of private business owners and given to the
socialist state, and that nuclear power plants, oil-powered container
ships and injection-moulding factories will be thereby reformed to serve
low-energy, local economies.
This idea is, to anyone able to perceive it without the distorting
ideological filters of leftism, a ludicrous, childish, religious belief.
An immense industrial factory can no more be reformed for the benefit of
man than a tractor can be repurposed to dig over a garden. And just as
the land has to be redesigned to fit the needs of the tractor, so man
has to be redesigned to fit the needs of the factory, which explains why
factory-man (including a management class which may never set foot in a
factory) is so keen on perpetuating the factory system, and resists the
idea that if man is to be in control of the factory the whole factory
has to be destroyed and rebuilt for man â and not just one factory, but
all the interlocking systems which feed into and from it. Factory-man
understands that a radical threat to the industrial system is a radical
threat to his own being, which is why he receives radical critiques of
industrial technology in almost exactly the same way as fundamentalist
believers take radical critiques of their prophets or sacred texts.
Marxâs understanding of what the full âdevelopment of the productive
forcesâ of mankind, through technological progress and expansion,
actually entails, or what it inevitably will entail â the ruin of man
and the absorption of the human psyche into a nightmarish, self-informed
(and, ironically enough, non-material) simulacrum â was nil. He did not
understand, or did not want to understand, that a technocratic system
demands a bourgeois technocratic management elite. His analysis of
productive alienation was second-to-none, and still justly celebrated,
but his obsession with class exploitation blinded him to exploitation by
the democratic mass, by the technocratic system, by professional power
and by the abstracted hyperworld parasitically overwhelming conscious
reality. The alienating effect of having oneâs capacity to freely work,
learn, speak, heal and die completely uploaded into a âweightlessâ
technosphere, or appropriated by a class of technicians (calling
themselves âmanagersâ, âteachersâ, âscientistsâ, âdoctorsâ and
occasionally âbusinessmenâ and âpoliticiansâ) was invisible to Marx, as
it is to all the professionals who, directly or indirectly, have
followed him up the blind alley of technological progress. Bakunin (and,
incidentally, Dostoevsky) saw the writing on the wall;
A scientific body to which had been confided the government of society
would soon end by devoting itself no longer to science at all, but to
quite another affair; and that affair, as in the case of all established
powers, would be its own eternal perpetuation by rendering the society
confided to its care ever more stupid and consequently more in need of
its government and direction.
We now find ourselves in the dead-end that Bakunin predicted and that
Marx and his many followers directed us towards, one where it is no
longer principally kings or capitalists, but professional, technical
experts, and the bewildering supermachine they tend, which oppress us.
The military power and property power of kings and capitalists still
exists, but it has been supplanted by the managerial power of
technicians (who, as their universal acceptance of lockdowns and the
latest bio-fascist phase of the system demonstrated, are just as happy
to see the working classes brutally disciplined as capitalists and kings
ever were) and the reality-absorbing power of virtual unculture and a
world built to serve it.
All of this explains why Marx was contemptuous of that class of society
least affected by industrialisation; namely, the peasantry. Marx (like
Plato) had zero interest in the lessons that wild nature could teach man
and advocated, effectively, the end of small-scale rural production. He
wished to see âmodern methods, such as irrigation, drainage, steam
ploughing, chemical treatment and so forth applied to agricultureâŠâ
along with a âlarge-scaleâ cultivation of the land; what today we would
call a âmonoculturalâ farm. The extermination of bio-diverse nature and
of the conscious lives of those who lived from it didnât, ultimately,
concern him, just as it doesnât those who, despite much high-sounding
âeco-friendlyâ rhetoric, are still engaged in the suppression of
subsistence and of vernacular independence. Such people donât just
include land-owning nobles and information-controlling professionals but
the very proletariat which Marx told us would create a classless
society, but who were and still are engaged, in collusion with the
bourgeoisie and the aristocracy, in the industrialisation of all aspects
of life and culture, imprisoning themselves ever more profoundly in âthe
kingdom of scarcityâ that such activity produces.
David Cayley summarises Ivan Illichâs account of this process;
âThe [working] man found himself in a conspiracy with his employerâ
insofar as âboth were equally concerned with economic expansion and the
suppression of subsistence.â âThis fundamental collusion between capital
and labour,â [Illich] continues, âwas mystified by the ritual of class
struggle.â The breadth of this claim is quite breathtaking. Marx had
asserted that the universal class in which capitalism meets its
comprehensive contradiction and potential abolition is the proletariat.
Not at all, says Illichâthe proletariat is only an accomplice in the war
against subsistence, which is the real site of the contradiction. The
novelty that Marx misses or takes for granted is homo economicus, a
being who must be âdistinguished⊠from all other human beings.â The
class struggle is no more than a ritual, and a ritual, as Illichâs
defines it elsewhere, is âa procedure whose imagined purpose allows the
participants to overlook what they are actually doing.â What the
antagonists/accomplices in the class struggle are âactually doingâ is
making war on subsistence through their joint interest in
industrializing every aspect of culture and every element of
livelihoodâthe project that marks out homo economicus from âall other
human beings.â Marxâs âproletariansâ with âa world to winâ and ânothing
to lose but their chainsâ are, in fact, tightening their fetters by
trying to improve their position in the kingdom of scarcity rather than
fighting for a restoration of the commons. The true universal class is
the shadow workersâall those who toil âunproductivelyâ in the shadow of
production.
Marx had no idea that the working class would become subdued and
domesticated by the âdevelopment of their productive forcesâ, that the
industrialisation of their lives would force them to surrender to the
God of Productivity, and lay waste a natural world in which scarcity
does not exist. Marx was unable to predict that eventually everyone â
meaning the individual psyche of everyone on earth â would inevitably
become a âmeans of productionâ, a virtual capitalist-industry of one,
working in front of, and psychologically welded to, the factory of the
screen. How can you âseize the means of productionâ, as Marx told us to
do, when this means of production is your self? Who or what is to do the
seizing? Marx had no answer to this question. Not because he could not
imagine a world dominated by, say, the internet, but because he did not
â could not â ask any critical questions of the technocratic priesthood
he was part of, and in some senses the founding prophet of.
Marx was the first stagversive, or professional radical; promising
revolution, freedom, equality and other such marvels, but, in his actual
assumptions and actions, supporting the system, and helping to develop
it. He was uncritical of technology or of the techno-bureaucratic class
of functionaries (managers, professionals, politicians, trade-union
leaders) it engendered, he was contemptuous of the power of the rural
poor and the working class (the peasantry and the âinsufficiently
developedâ proletariat, both of which were, for Marx, dispensable before
the almighty laws of history) to manage their own affairs, he was
supportive of colonial wars, provided they worked towards his statist
revolution, and he was committed to a monstrously crude theory of human
life, history and experience with nothing of interest to say about life
beyond it. This is why he was feted by the bourgeois press, by edgy
radicals like John Stuart Mill, by company-men, by progressive
businessmen and by ârevolutionary leadersâ, of whom, several decades
after Marxâs death, Lenin was to be the most notorious, tyrannical
exemplar.
If this were all, we could safely forget about him, but in all these key
respects he is identical to the the countless socialists, communists and
nominal anarchists[4] who followed him, which is why, once we have
extracted the few observations of priceless value he made â along with
those within the indispensable critique of capitalism he initiated (e.g.
those of Braverman, Baran & Sweezy, Mumford, Ellul, Fromm, Berger and
many, many others) â why it is so important to understand and completely
reject his crude, hyper-rational theorising, his brutally insensitive
authoritarianism, his pathetically gradualist reformist â and statist â
politics, his monomaniacal worship of technological, bourgeois-managed
progress, his naked contempt for ordinary people and his celebration of
the civilising machine which makes slaves of us all.
Goodbye Mr. Marx.
An updated version of this essay appears in
, a collection of radical reflections on the system and the self.
[1] The Rebel, Albert Camus
[2] See
.
[3] Or that hunger is caused by belief in food â obviously it is not â
or that coercive propaganda in a hierarchical economic system doesnât
depend on that hierarchy to be accepted â obviously it does.
[4] The social-democrat Chomsky-Bookchin-Graeber-type, and the
nihilistic âagainst everythingâ Sex-Pistol type.