đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș roi-ferreiro-beyond-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:36:37. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Beyond Democracy
Author: Roi Ferreiro
Date: 2009
Language: en
Topics: democracy, history, populism
Source: Retrieved on 10th December 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/beyond-democracy-roi-ferreiro
Notes: Written between March 18 and May 23, 2009. Translated from the Spanish original at: http://cai.xtreemhost.com/cica/indice.htm

Roi Ferreiro

Beyond Democracy

Introduction

Modernity looks back upon Greece and Rome as the primal references for

its political culture. They were the first class societies in the modern

sense, characterized by the rise of the State and of commerce—to the

detriment of pre-political forms that were still based on religion,

where political power and the priesthood were closely linked. It is on

the basis of these two fundamental characteristics that the rise and

development of democratic political forms in Athenian Greece and the

Roman Republic can be explained.

If the supporters of modern democracy have refreshed themselves from

these two springs, they have done so without critically examining their

socio-historical roots, despite the fact that the latter have been

understood since antiquity. As we shall see below, the reason for this

is obvious. Without an understanding of these socio-historical roots it

is not possible to grasp precisely the immanent limits of democratic

forms which, from an abstract form in principle, have led to the modern

formulation of the concept of anarchy as the dissolution or suppression

of political power.

Following the historian Arthur Rosenberg, we could say that democracy

“in itself”, as an abstract form, does not exist. It always assumes the

form of a particular socio-political movement, with a corresponding

class composition. But even this is not completely correct. In my

opinion there is indeed a generic relation between the democratic

political form “in itself” and society’s class composition, beyond the

variations of the political composition due to class struggles and the

impetus of social development, and even beyond variations in the forms

of production. This is essentially due to the fact that the social basis

and prototype of democratic forms is commodity exchange, which has been

historically developed by way of diverse forms of production. By making

this claim I do not intend to overlook or disregard the major

differences between political regimes or, to put it another way, the

major differences with regard to the degree of effective democracy that

can be realized on the basis of particular forms of production.

The idea of political equality, which is the functional basis of

democracy, is thus historically derived from the praxis of civil

equality. But it is derived from a civil equality within class

societies, in which such an equality only exists empirically on the

basis of property. And property is the origin of law, and particularly

of the status of the citizenry. Equal rights, consequently, although

only existing as a formal reality, develops on the basis of a society of

owners who freely carry out their economic activity, and whose products

are exchanged as a function of value. In political regimes this social

composition and its degree of development are expressed in the

distribution of power. A distribution in proportion to economic wealth

represents the interests of the big property-owners. An egalitarian

distribution represents the general interests of the smaller

property-owners and traders and, up to a certain point, of the

proletariat.

Greece and the Degeneration of Democracy

The military defeat of Athens by Sparta in the Peloponnesian War meant

that the Athenian democratic regime was discredited and the Spartan

oligarchy enjoyed greater prestige. For Plato, this was combined with

the fact that it was the Athenian regime that had condemned his teacher

Socrates to death. Thus, first Plato, and then to a lesser extent his

disciple Aristotle, adopted a critical attitude towards democracy,

favoring an aristocratic form of government and a more restricted

democracy that would overcome the problem of demagogy, respectively.

For Plato, democracy was a degenerate form of the Republican form of

government. For Aristotle, democracy was a good form of government, but

one that had to be protected from demagogy by aristocratic formulas. The

Roman historian Polybius called this degenerated form of democracy

“ochlocracy”.

“A fifth form of democracy, in other respects the same, is that in

which, not the law, but the multitude, have the supreme power, and

supersede the law by their decrees. This is a state of affairs brought

about by the demagogues. For in democracies which are subject to the law

the best citizens hold the first place, and there are no demagogues; but

where the laws are not supreme, there demagogues spring up. For the

people becomes a monarch, and is many in one; and the many have the

power in their hands, not as individuals, but collectively. Homer says

that ‘it is not good to have a rule of many,’ but whether he means this

corporate rule, or the rule of many individuals, is uncertain. At all

events this sort of democracy, which is now a monarch, and no longer

under the control of law, seeks to exercise monarchical sway, and grows

into a despot; the flatterer is held in honor; this sort of democracy

being relatively to other democracies what tyranny is to other forms of

monarchy. The spirit of both is the same, and they alike exercise a

despotic rule over the better citizens. The decrees of the demos

correspond to the edicts of the tyrant; and the demagogue is to the one

what the flatterer is to the other. Both have great power; the flatterer

with the tyrant, the demagogue with democracies of the kind which we are

describing. The demagogues make the decrees of the people override the

laws, by referring all things to the popular assembly. And therefore

they grow great, because the people have an things in their hands, and

they hold in their hands the votes of the people, who are too ready to

listen to them. Further, those who have any complaint to bring against

the magistrates say, ‘Let the people be judges’; the people are too

happy to accept the invitation; and so the authority of every office is

undermined. Such a democracy is fairly open to the objection that it is

not a constitution at all; for where the laws have no authority, there

is no constitution. The law ought to be supreme over all, and the

magistracies should judge of particulars, and only this should be

considered a constitution. So that if democracy be a real form of

government, the sort of system in which all things are regulated by

decrees is clearly not even a democracy in the true sense of the word,

for decrees relate only to particulars.” (Aristotle, Politics, Book 4,

Part 4.) (See:

classics.mit.edu

)

The annalists and thinkers like Plato and Aristotle insisted upon

contrasting the most centralized political forms with the most

decentralized forms, where the distribution of power is more

egalitarian. This even applies to the case of democracy, as can be seen

in the passage quoted above. This is a result, as we shall see below, of

the fact that democracy originally had a very restricted meaning, which

has slipped into the background in our time.

In my view, this kind of position reflected the growth of ideological

mystification with respect to the historical process involving the

increasing autonomy of political power separate from the social mass

that went hand in hand with the expansion and concentration of

accumulated mercantile wealth. For a class regime, it is logical that

anything that destroys its very constitution would be considered to be

degeneration. Thus, in Plato, Aristotle or Polybius, degeneration is

also discussed in the opposite sense. That is, not with reference to a

relative regression of the centralization of political power, in favor

of the masses, but rather with reference to an excess of centralization,

or an arbitrary shift in the distribution of power within the ruling

class, one that could very well imply a distribution of power that does

not correspond with the distribution of wealth (the degeneration of

monarchy into tyranny, or aristocracy into oligarchy).

It seems obvious that these ideological views from antiquity play a

significant role in the configuration of modern democracy. Thus, the

modern model of representative democracy was originally inspired by the

limited forms whose theoretical dimension was based on Aristotle and

whose example had much more to do with the Roman Republic than with

Athenian democracy. A partial exception that went beyond this concept,

the French Revolution, was inspired more by the Athenian ideal. But by

adopting in practice a representative form that contradicted that ideal,

it created favorable conditions for the counterrevolutionary reversal of

Thermidor. The French Revolution was therefore the practical

manifestation on a grand scale of the fundamental contradiction of

modern democracy, between the sovereignty of the citizenry and the

representative system. As is also true of capital, however, this

contradiction is inherent to and functional for the modern democratic

system, it is its source of vitality and, as long as one operates within

its categories, it cannot be transcended.

The political milestone of the French Revolution boils down to the fact

that it nonetheless presupposed the establishment of Athenian democracy

as an ideal model, as the most coherent formulation of the democratic

regime. With the development of capitalism, and the regulation of the

latter by means of an institutionally moderated class struggle,

democracy would be provided with a relatively stable and coherent

socio-economic and cultural basis, which assumed the representative form

was an unavoidable necessity; it was a simple matter to use the Athenian

example to legitimate and perfect the modern, Roman-style democracies.

Modern democracy thus became a form of government specially adapted to

the contemporary class struggle, while its own effective foundation—the

freedom of property and exchange—was progressively eliminated by the

historical development of the concentration and centralization of

capital.

Democracy and Ochlocracy in Greece

Now we shall take a closer look at the deeper meaning of the polemics of

antiquity, which requires that we first study the etymology of democracy

and ochlocracy.

The famous prefix “demo” of the word democracy [1] did not originally

mean, and did not figure in the practice of Greek democracy in this

sense, “the people”, as it is often interpreted today. The “demos” was a

small-scale territorial political form, similar to the commune. It is

true that it presupposed an assembly (the agora) in which the citizenry

directly participated; but the majority of the population—women, slaves,

metics (foreign merchants and craftsmen), debtors of the city and those

whose rights had been revoked, and of course children—were practically

excluded from the enjoyment of the rights of citizenship. This may seem

merely anecdotal if Greek society is viewed from the perspective of its

formal similarities with its modern counterpart so as to emphasize its

functional virtues.

From the historical materialist point of view, however, we must

acknowledge the fact that the economic foundation characteristic of

Hellenistic and Roman grandeur was composed of slavery and war. It was

this foundation that made Athenian democracy possible. This is why I do

not think it was by chance that direct citizens’ democracy grew in

tandem with the expansion of slavery. I think this can be understood as

a form of class collaboration, with imperialist expansion as an

additional source of wealth, which would obviously have the effect of

reducing the friction between the various layers or classes of Athenian

democracy. This also allows us to trace the outlines of another kind of

parallel with modern democracy.

From the formal point of view, what stands out is the fact that the

individual is only recognized politically as a citizen. Thus, his

participation is a vehicle for the ruling interests in the polis. By way

of the category of citizenship, the individual was subjected to an

institutional system and a constitution that were functions of a

particular form of the distribution of wealth. The individual as such

was only a political subject under these conditions, as is also the case

in today’s democracies. Immigrants, for example, did not have the status

of citizens and were therefore not political subjects.

It is therefore clear that democracy, from its very beginnings, never

had anything to do with the everyday notion of “popular sovereignty”:

“Most of those whose object it has been to instruct us methodically

concerning such matters, distinguish three kinds of constitutions, which

they call kingship, aristocracy, and democracy. Now we should, I think,

be quite justified in asking them to enlighten us as to whether they

represent these three to be the sole varieties or rather to be the best;

for in either case my opinion is that they are wrong. For it is evident

that we must regard as the best constitution a combination of all these

three varieties, since we have had proof of this not only theoretically

but by actual experience, Lycurgus having been the first to draw up a

constitution — that of Sparta — on this principle. Nor on the other hand

can we admit that these are the only three varieties; for we have

witnessed monarchical and tyrannical governments, which while they

differ very widely from kingship, yet bear a certain resemblance to it,

this being the reason why monarchs in general falsely assume and use, as

far as they can, the regal title. There have also been several

oligarchical constitutions which seem to bear some likeness to

aristocratic ones, though the divergence is, generally, as wide as

possible. The same holds good about democracies. The truth of what I say

is evident from the following considerations. It is by no means every

monarchy which we can call straight off a kingship, but only that which

is voluntarily accepted by the subjects and where they are governed

rather by an appeal to their reason than by fear and force. Nor again

can we style every oligarchy an aristocracy, but only that where the

government is in the hands of a selected body of the justest and wisest

men. Similarly that is no true democracy in which the whole crowd of

citizens is free to do whatever they wish or purpose, but when, in a

community where it is traditional and customary to reverence the gods,

to honour our parents, to respect our elders, and to obey the laws, the

will of the greater number prevails, this is to be called a democracy.

We should therefore assert that there are six kinds of governments, the

three above mentioned which are in everyone’s mouth and the three which

are naturally allied to them, I mean monarchy, oligarchy, and mob-rule.

Now the first of these to come into being is monarchy, its growth being

natural and unaided; and next arises kingship derived from monarchy by

the aid of art and by the correction of defects. Monarchy first changes

into its vicious allied form, tyranny; and next, the abolishment of both

gives birth to aristocracy. Aristocracy by its very nature degenerates

into oligarchy; and when the commons inflamed by anger take vengeance on

this government for its unjust rule, democracy comes into being; and in

due course the licence and lawlessness of this form of government

produces mob-rule to complete the series. The truth of what I have just

said will be quite clear to anyone who pays due attention to such

beginnings, origins, and changes as are in each case natural. For he

alone who has seen how each form naturally arises and develops, will be

able to see when, how, and where the growth, perfection, change, and end

of each are likely to occur again.” (Polybius, The Histories, Book 6,

Chapter 2.) (See:

penelope.uchicago.edu

)

The word ochlocracy [2] is derived from “ochlos”, which means crowd or

mass of people. That is, it conveys the sense, as is evident in

Polybius, of the assumption of power by the masses as a whole, or of the

conversion of the disorganized masses into an effective political power.

This is why the intellectuals of the ruling class mystify the term

ochlocracy, defining it as the result of demagogic influence over the

masses and politically proscribing it, with the argument that the

pressure of the masses distorted true or ideal democracy, so that the

“general will” was destroyed by the particular wills imposed from below.

This association of the term ochlocracy with demagogy and manipulation

in the sense of populism can only constitute a particular historical

case, which in reality contradicts the very concept of ochlocracy. If

the masses are effectively sovereign then demagogy is not possible.

Thus, we see that the concept of ochlocracy in classical literature

presents two contradictions:

1) masses without the capacity for self-organization and, consequently,

without the capacity for self-constitution as a political subject,

cannot exercise power;

2) masses that are manipulated, that exercise their power on behalf of a

minority, do not themselves exercise power.

In the first case what we have is a projection of the ruling class. The

“disorganized masses”, the mob (or, in Rome, the plebs) in the

pejorative sense of the word as it is used by the ruling classes, is

“disorganized” only with respect to the prevailing standards of

organization or to the existing legal norms. This assumes, then as well

as now, that spontaneous autonomous organization does not or cannot

exist; therefore, all action on the part of the “disorganized masses” is

dangerous in and of itself and is incapable of leading to anything good,

or it is even incapable of developing a clear awareness of its goals and

of consistent action to achieve said goals. [3]

“When a state has weathered many great perils and subsequently attains

to supremacy and uncontested sovereignty, it is evident that under the

influence of long established prosperity, life will become more

extravagant and the citizens more fierce in their rivalry regarding

office and other objects than they ought to be. As these defects go on

increasing, the beginning of the change for the worse will be due to

love of office and the disgrace entailed by obscurity, as well as to

extravagance and purse-proud display; and for this change the populace

will be responsible when on the one hand they think they have a

grievance against certain people who have shown themselves grasping, and

when, on the other hand, they are puffed up by the flattery of others

who aspire to office. For now, stirred to fury and swayed by passion in

all their counsels, they will no longer consent to obey or even to be

the equals of the ruling caste, but will demand the lion’s share for

themselves. When this happens, the state will change its name to the

finest sounding of all, freedom and democracy, but will change its

nature to the worst thing of all, mob-rule.” (Polybius, The Histories,

Book 6, Chapter 57.) (Ibid.)

In the second case, what we have is a veiled form of tyranny. For the

purposes of the democrats, however, who represent class society, the

tyranny of the “uneducated” majority and the tyranny of an educated

minority are the same, because both abolish their allocation of

political power. Thus, from the democratic point of view in the

strictest sense of the term, and if we want to speak accurately, all

mass revolutionary processes in their political dimension constitute a

form of ochlocracy. If this concept is so unknown or sounds so strange

today, this should not cause us to reject its use but to discover to

what extent we are ourselves still completely immersed in class culture

and particularly bourgeois class culture.

Rome: Power and Virtue

The Roman political regime also presents etymological parallels with the

Greek case. The plebs was distinguished from the people (populus), with

regard to the rights of citizenship as well. The term that can be

translated as rabble (vulgus) was also used, which meant common people,

to refer to the plebs. Plebs therefore has the same meaning as the Greek

ochlos: the masses in general, disorganized, lacking rights or outside

the system of the ruling hierarchy.

The context of the struggle between plebians and patricians in Rome was

also that of an expanding slave society. The plebians comprised a

heterogeneous class, since, although it was initially defined by its

difference from the patricians, it included both landowners (adsidui) as

well as the landless (proletarii), among those who were free men. Their

struggle for equal rights was therefore a mixture of interests and this

category cannot be defined as a social class determined by landownership

or propertylessness, but by antiquated political rights which entered

into conflict with the new mercantilist economic base. The patricians,

as the name indicates, were defined by their membership in large family

units under a pater familiae, who initially possessed enormous power.

These family units were based upon a common and inalienable patrimony of

land (terra patria) and slaves. They thus constituted a concentrated

economic and political power, which governed the whole society through

its representatives.

At first, plebians were exempt from military service and taxation. But

this changed with Roman territorial expansion, which obliged the State

to resort to the plebians for revenue and soldiers. The plebians began

to fight for their rights, thereby threatening the Republic’s defensive

capabilities. As a result, first civil equality was obtained, then

political equality. This led to the basic formulation of Roman law,

which was previously limited to the customary interpretations of the

patricians, and the official institution of the tribunate as a form of

egalitarian representation for the plebs. With the passage of time,

however, as the wealthy plebians participated in the military assembly,

this favored the formation of a patrician-plebian aristocracy

(nobilitas) set against the urban proletariat, because service in

political office was not remunerated. Political rule thus remained, even

during times of instability, in the hands of the wealthy class.

The Roman Republic never became a direct democracy, or even a

representative democracy, so that the problem of demagogy as the source

of a turn towards ochlocracy was not so great a threat there as it was

in Greece. But this had another aspect: if popular rebellion was held in

check by a more consistently autonomous power structure, at the same

time it was necessary to curb its autonomy from society, by way of

society itself. The reasons for this were expressed quite well by

Polybius in the passage quoted above, where he says:

“When a state has weathered many great perils and subsequently attains

to supremacy and uncontested sovereignty, it is evident that under the

influence of long established prosperity, life will become more

extravagant and the citizens more fierce in their rivalry regarding

office and other objects than they ought to be. As these defects go on

increasing, the beginning of the change for the worse....” (Polybius,

The Histories, Book 6, Chapter 57.)

But before we continue to examine the problem of political forms, we

must pause for another etymological investigation.

According to Mariano Grondona [4] there are two concepts of power among

the Greeks. The first is arkhein, which means to “initiate” and to

“dispatch”—whence are derived arkhĂ© (origin) and arkhos (chief). Thus,

the original power is that of the chief, which leads Grondona to posit a

despotic genesis of power. On the other hand, the actual word power is

derived from the Indo-European poti (chief), whence the Greek posis

(husband) and despotes (owner) are derived. According to Grondona, it

was from this original meaning that the meaning of the word power was

extended to signify “the generic capacity for doing something”.

This etymological origin in arkhein thus assumes archaic forms of

society, where power is transmitted from chief to chief in obedience to

an ancestral custom or tradition. This characteristic, and not its

alleged character as “despotic command” as Grondona argues, is in my

opinion what explains the fact that concepts like “monarchy” (the power

of one) or “oligarchy” (the power of a few) have retained the root word

arkhos (chief), while in other concepts the latter was replaced by

kratos, which means a power that is voluntarily established—which is

also translated as “government”.

We thus arrive at the other part of the word democracy. The latter

should therefore be translated, literally, as “government by the demos”

or more generally “government by the citizenry”. But the most important

thing is that, as we have seen, the original meaning of democracy refers

to a type of political system in which power is separated from its

traditional bonds to custom, religion, etc. The concept of democracy

therefore had nothing to do with that of “sovereignty”—a power that is

“above all” the others.

The concept of sovereignty as such emerges after the classical era.

According to Georg Jellinek, it first arose during the Middle Ages, as a

result of the struggle between the Church, the Imperial power and the

great lords and municipal guilds:

“The Church, which wanted to place the State in its service; the Roman

empire which did not want to concede to the various States any more

importance than that of provinces; and the powerful nobles and municipal

guilds, which felt that they were powers that were independent of the

State and opposed to it.” (The General Theory of the State, 1900.)

The idea of sovereignty thus arose in order to express “the opposition

of State power to the other powers” and attained maturity with the

process of the centralization of political power that led us to the

modern era. [5] It was not by chance that this process was driven

forward by the primitive accumulation of capital, which was so carefully

examined by Marx. This is why the bourgeois idea of sovereignty refers

to the State, postulating the citizenry as sovereign only through the

State. The “people” is sovereign only insofar as it constitutes the

State and by means of the latter, even though, in theory, the former is

the source of political power and, on the other hand, the established

power is supposed to be its emanation or the alienation of the immanent

power of the “people” (Rousseau). Bourgeois political theories thus came

to justify the subordination of centralized state power, formed under

the old regime, to the new rising class, the bourgeoisie, which also

needed the support of the popular masses to rise to power (and therefore

needed the support of democracy). Sovereignty as the effective power of

the people is a different concept, which is clearly connected with the

struggles directed against bourgeois state power. As we have seen,

however, the use of the concept of sovereignty to refer to the power of

the masses in general is inadequate, since it is still inscribed within

the limits of democracy.

We shall now continue with our etymological investigation.

The development towards democracy, in the Athenian case, began according

to Grondona with the emergence of a distinction between natural laws and

the laws of the city (nomos). This means that power was no longer only

commanded, but also legislated. This assumes the government is based on

norms that can be changed at will and, at the same time, are inscribed

in a definite framework: the politeia. The possibility thus arises that

the subject of this political will can also be voluntarily determined.

This created the context appropriate for the formation of the deme or

demos, those constituencies where individuals resided, which thus became

polites (political).

In another vein, I cannot agree with Grondona when he interprets the

evolution of the notion of “power” so that it means “the generic

capacity for doing something”.

From what we discussed above it follows that traditional power or

arkhos, and institutional power or kratos, have quite specific

denotations. As for poti, the source of the Latin word potere, it

connotes the sense of possession which is accentuated in the Greek posis

and, at the same time, also in the sense of command in despotes, which

is similar to the Greek kratos. But all these terms equally share the

reference to social or collective forms of power, so that they do not

just define power as an individual generic capacity. This underlying

duality can be explained by the development of the alienation of social

power from individual power, between the political organization of

society and the capacity of the individual for action, which is

manifested by way of group struggles and yields to distinct forms of

government.

We can understand this problem better through a consideration of the

case of Rome.

The word designating the capacity of the individual for action in Latin

was virtus and in Greek andreia—whose meaning was identical. [6] Both

derived from an Indo-European root word (vir/aner) that means man (the

masculine) and which was also the source for the word virile. [7] There

is, however, a similar Indo-European root word, vis, which means force.

Which is why it can be said that in antiquity these root words vir and

vis were indistinguishable. Vis means vital force, which includes

violence. Thus, both root words appear to be complementary and allow us

to arrive at a basic shared meaning: man defined by his immanent force,

which is externalized by his vital activity in society. This basic

shared meaning is also shown by its evolution into virtus, vita (life)

or vitium (defect or vice).

Virtus, for its part, is composed of the suffix -tut, which means

condition or quality. But virtus does not refer to an external condition

or quality, but to an internal one. In this respect one can clearly

discern its relation to life or vital force. But this is even more

explicit in its primary Latin meaning, worth or courage.

What is of interest here is that the term virtus underwent a complex

evolution until it came to possess the full meaning of the word virtue.

By this I mean to say that this evolution had to result from complex

socio-historical transformations (among which, as late as the modern

era, we must include the general tendency towards the abstraction of the

human and the latter’s subordination to technics, which is quite visible

in the term’s current state of disuse, or in its use as an

adjective—“virtuoso”—to refer to particular technical abilities).

In Roman society, where the basic values were masculinity, militarism

and morality, the concept of virtus was practically indispensable in

judging individual behavior. Thus, Lucilius said that: “Virtus ... is to

be able to pay in full a true price for things in which we participate,

and in which we live ... it is to know what is right, what is useful,

and what is honorable for a man, what is good and likewise, what is bad,

what is useless, shameful ... to put the interest of fatherland first,

of parents next, and third and last, our own.” (Lucilius, Satires. See:

Myles Anthony McDonnell, Roman Manliness: Virtus and the Roman Republic,

Cambridge University Press, New York, 2006, pp. 124–125.) Unlike the

Greeks, the Romans had a pragmatic mentality, which implicitly

presupposed an emphasis on virtus as a practical quality, distinct from

mere intellectual knowledge, whose separation from practice they

considered to be one of the defects of the Greeks. Thus the idea of the

virtutes came to include all the “good qualities”.

Virtus was associated with a worldly or divine reward, especially with

military glory, which was also understood as something hereditary, for

which reason one had to compete in order to equal or surpass the virtus

of one’s predecessors. This also posed the problem, however, of

competition for worldly glory in the form of dignitas—political power

and wealth. Particular interests were opposed to general interests,

which is why Cicero proclaimed that politics should be understood as a

way of life and conduct. At the same time, socio-historical conditions

caused virtus to be an ideal that was initially linked to nobilitas. But

with the expansion of the Republic, the ostentatious wealth of that

upper class produced a generalized deviation of the concept’s meaning,

which was detached from the traditions of the forefathers in order to

establish the social ethos as its true axis. With this development the

individual’s capabilities and conduct were emphasized as the roots of

virtus. In this way, these two factors, political and economic

respectively, determined the promotion of virtus to an ethical quality

which, as an individual responsibility, was simultaneously objectively

social and allowed one to refer individual actions to the collective

interest. We thus arrive at a definition of the Roman ideal of the

social individual.

Virtue as Psycho-Social Self-Power

As a preliminary conclusion to our etymological and historical study, I

believe that the generalization of the concept of power as the “generic

capacity to do something” can be explained by a phenomenon of alienating

transposition, in which one term becomes assimilated to its opposite.

But since nothing, alienation included, is absolute, the concept of

virtue has not been completely assimilated to that of power.

Power always retains the meaning of an instrumental capacity, while

virtue retains the meaning of a vital or immanent capacity. “To live

well” is virtuous. “To do something well” refers us to a mode of

technical activity, to the manipulation of objects. Even when we say, “I

can move”, we are unconsciously referring to our bodies as objects, upon

which we can exercise our will power, which is in this instance

conceived as an autonomized force of the body or imagined as external to

its organic function.

The separation between potere and virtus, considering the alienation of

the latter in the former, must therefore be considered as the symbolic

expression of a particular socio-historical reality, not as an

accidental contrast or superimposition. Linguistic differences are

always cognitive representations of practical differences, and the

preservation of terms whose meaning has been assimilated by without

being completely identified with other terms (thus becoming partial

synonyms) presupposes that said practical differentiations have an

enduring and antagonistic socio-historical basis.

What I said above is not meant to bypass the problem of everyday usage,

which also has a practical basis in today’s society. In my view the key

is to reclaim the concept of virtue and reinvest it with its full

meaning, in order to provide a foundation and complement for power as

the instrumental capacity for action.

When it opposes established power, virtue is the self-power of the

individual in the face of the autonomized power of institutions. Thus,

if in the concept of ochlocracy we discover the arkhé (the beginning or

original source) of collective self-power, in the concept of virtus we

discover the arkhé of individual self-power. The complementary and

harmonious development of ochlocracy and virtus would only be possible

if there were to be no distinction between community power and

government power, or between everyday life and political life. It would

mean, in short, the achievement of anarchy, for which we are now capable

of providing a more profound definition: the suppression of all forms of

autonomized power that opposes individuals, whether of law or tradition,

and their replacement with a new form of power that, as the term itself

says, “lacks a beginning” or “lacks command”, because its source is

timeless and immanent to human beings. This power is the direct

expression of their humanity via cooperation. But anarchy as a political

regime requires a humanity that has developed the quality of

self-government: its social virtue. This characteristic only started to

become a concrete possibility for humanity thanks to the development of

psychological and social self-consciousness on the one hand, and the

development of human cooperation towards increasingly complex forms, on

the other.

We may also note the contrast between power and virtue on the

psychological plane.

Power is the instrumental use of vital force, in order to set in motion

or to direct. It constitutes the essential quality of ego psychology, as

the ego is the autonomized self-concept as opposed to the complete

psycho-physical being. The activity of the ego presupposes an

instrumental relation to psychical energies and drives, whose

objectification it determines by means of the fixation of goals—which

requires the previous abstraction of functional data from the sensory

world, on the basis of which it builds representations with which the

being’s needs are identified, and finally on this basis it establishes

relations of hierarchy or priority internally among the drives and

externally among the forms of action, some of which remain fixed as

habits of behavior or thought, and some of which are more ephemeral. In

this way, the ego relates to reality as a whole only in the form of an

instrumental object, and thus the meaning of power (appropriation,

possession, control) is an essential aspect of all of the ego’s

behavior, including its intellectual behavior. [8]

Virtue, meanwhile, is the use of vital force in order to do something

that corresponds to our nature, which means self-realization—the

fullness, the good and the beautiful for humans. It therefore

presupposes a psychological and psychosomatic integration in general,

and an overcoming of the ego’s autonomization in particular. To the

extent that this is achieved, the interior state ceases to shift between

continuous conflicts and the self-organizational capacity immanent to

the psyche, it becomes conscious, it allows a self-determination without

all the mechanical mediations that characterize the ego, but without

leading to a blind, spontaneous mode of activity.

As I have said, however, the historical preconditions for anarchy are

not yet fully developed. They must nonetheless be fully developed on the

basis of, and in a radical and integral break with, life today in its

entirety. This is why the above reflections do not imply that an

immediate supersession of democracy is possible, which leads us to the

problem of transitional political forms.

Beyond Democracy

Despite all the differences between democracy and ochlocracy as systems

of political organization, ochlocracy may nonetheless still be

understood as a form of direct democracy, although it is actually more

than that. It is a “democracy” with regard to its internal functioning,

but not with regard to its constitution:

Focusing on the concept of ochlocracy is of particular interest today

because, in the search for new concepts to describe political forms,

such terms as “holocracy”, “plurarchy”, and “demarchy” have arisen ...

Holocracy is a term used to describe a world government as a solution

for all the problems afflicting today’s society. It is not necessary to

point out that, with regard to its real effects, holocracy would

essentially change nothing in social relations, and by itself is not a

necessary factor for bringing about such change. Plurarchy is defined as

a system in which decision-making is not binary (yes/no); those who

support one side or another may act on their own account without

external sanction and the common will is established only by consensus.

The first aspect does not necessarily conflict with either democracy or

ochlocracy. But the second aspect, in reality, poses a risk, because it

assumes that the will of the various factions cannot be limited by the

will of all, which is a projection of bourgeois individualism. The

factions can only exist as formations of the whole, although the latter

does not present itself in that way in the stage of the constituent

emergence of movements or communities, when it divides from the

dispersion. Even so, these factions are emanations of the social whole

and can only emerge simultaneously thanks the relative homogeneity of

the whole. Demarchy is an intermediate concept between democracy and

ochlocracy. It means that the organized people is the basis of political

power, that the people is the “beginning” of that power, but in this

sense it is only another form of direct democracy and preserves the

formal characteristics of democracy.

By way of conclusion, we may say that democracy exists wherever it is

not the community which directly self-organizes it, but where a formal

structure exists which mediates the effective constitution of the social

community as political community and conditions it. This occurs in all

permanent organizations, which presuppose a structure, rules, program,

habits, etc. At the same time, these organizations, within capitalism,

presuppose the general separation between political power and everyday

life, units of life and organizational units of power—one cannot leap

over the global structure of capitalist society. Participation in them

and therefore the power of the individuals who are its members, is

delimited by adherence to these patterns and divisions. The external

individuals have no direct power over these stable organizations.

For these three reasons, permanent proletarian organizations within

capitalism are always democratic in form, in the strict sense that we

have outlined above. The ochlocracy of the proletariat can only arise as

the political expression of the revolutionary process in such a way that

it will be the appropriate name for the unlimited democracy that the

radical revolutionaries want as the form of the revolutionary power of

the masses, and whose structure in the past was exemplified by the model

of the soviet or council system. Acracy would be one more step forward,

since it presupposes the complete disappearance of political power with

the suppression of the remnants of inequality produced by class society,

together with their corresponding forms of subjectivity.

The Problem of Decentralization

Recent discussions concerning political forms have shifted towards more

concrete forms.

For example, the concept of “distributive networks” has been proposed in

opposition to the typical concept of networks as decentralized entities,

but in which in practice some nodes are dominant or central. All

decentralization is always relative and, therefore, the key question is

never formal decentralization, but effective decentralization. Real

decentralization of power must mean that power is “distributed”, in our

case equally, among the nodes (which in the cyberpunk movement are the

individuals themselves; the blogger movement on the internet, for

example).

Direct democracy always implies formal decentralization, of course, but

it usually does not address the problem of effective decentralization.

In this context what we mean by formal decentralization is the

decentralization of decision-making. The effective participation of

individuals in the preparation, development and implementation of the

political will remains on a secondary plane, as a derivative rather than

an organic element. There is no effective connection between decision

and implementation, because the decision-making body is not identical

with the executive body. The individual who has the right to participate

in decision-making does not thereby also acquire the duty to implement

the decisions. In this way, in a few words, it is taken for granted that

direct democracy in the decision-making process is equivalent to the

establishment of a regime of freedom. The content is assimilated to the

form.

The political form we need must start from a totally different approach.

What in the political form does not have to be organic, what has to be

instrumental, is not effective participation, considered in its quantity

and quality (space) as well as in continuity and endurance (time). The

instrumental [9] must be the purely political moment, deliberation and

decision-making, with its modalities. One thing is that this moment has

to adopt a form that corresponds to the kind of participation that is

sought. This is obvious: means and ends have to be coordinated. But it

is entirely another matter to think that the form of decision-making can

produce, in itself, a corresponding type of participation. It is a

purely practical matter: most collective activity does not consist in

decision-making, but in preparing for decision-making or implementing

the decisions, which is why the dynamic of execution is what determines

the dynamic of collective life.

In this sense, the very concept of democracy is insufficient, however it

is qualified. Instead, the concept of ochlocracy fills the breach

completely. Because it refers to the fact that the political subject is

not a formal structure (demos) or a mass of individuals connected to

that structure: it is the collectivity as such, for itself. That is,

ochlocracy implies a type of participation that is not determined—or, is

neither driven by nor limited—by a formal structure or by an individual

connection with such a structure, but by subjectivity itself and the

form of activity that characterizes the masses. In other words, it is a

mass of people that consciously transforms its individual self-powers

into a social power, which permanently acts as both constituent and

institutional power at the same time. Without this vital premise,

ochlocracy is impossible, but so is what is commonly called direct

workers democracy, since then the latter would be vacated of the

participation or the content that it needs to be a living form (or else

that participation or content will simply not last). Only the privilege

of the decision-making and deliberative moments, by granting them

permanent forms (assemblies, etc.), allows the preservation of the

illusion that direct democracy can possess some value in itself, or that

it can exist at the margins of the effective and concrete participation

of individuals.

We now enter the more functional concrete plane. That the decisions are

made following procedures that are crafted to conform to a compensated

collective will—or put another way, procedures designed to avoid

attacking or scorning the freedom of minorities, but which do not

elevate them above the majorities, either—is not the most important

issue. What matters is that decisions are made through the conscious

participation of all the individuals involved in their preparation and

implementation. On this plane, democracy only has to exist as a

procedural form, not as a rigid institutional system. The error of the

traditional anarchist view is its fixation above all on the form of the

procedure and its losing sight of what we discussed above: the problem

of effective participation.

The procedural problem is not what is most important: whether decisions

are made by consensus or by majority vote, for example. What is

important is whether the individual who participates in the

decision-making process must acquire, together with this right, the duty

of participating in the preparation and implementation of these

decisions, in accordance with the motto of the statutes of the first

IWA: “no rights without duties, no duties without rights.”

In practice, the subordination of majorities to consensus with

minorities is no less authoritarian than majority decision. The

“voluntary” submission to consensus does not abolish authoritarianism,

but internalizes it. In this way a reification of the collective power

is created in the form of a dominant abstract entity—the assembly as

political community. Each individual or group is obliged to submit to

this institution if it wants to continue to participate in the real

community. As a result, they do not possess real autonomy, but an

autonomy that is alienated and crystallized as the property of the

assembly as a formal structure.

It is the presence of rigidities of this kind that has made democracy,

even direct democracy, a political system. Therefore, we must reduce

them as much as possible, as insurrectionalist anarchism has correctly

advocated—which is a step in the right direction, although I think that

its solutions are inadequate.

The solution to the problem of bureaucracy is not to turn the committees

into structures subordinated to the assemblies. The solution is to

create, following the approach of Marx and Engels, conditions where the

committees cannot become autonomous, [10] for the purposes of which the

formal convoking of assemblies is insufficient—even if they are convened

on their own impulse.

Similarly, the solution to the problem of authoritarianism is not to

prevent one person from imposing his will upon another. The solution is

to bring about conditions where anyone can fight effectively against the

authority that he or she rejects. Since the problem of authoritarianism

is rooted in the direct relations between individuals, it cannot be

overcome by way of “anti-authoritarian” rules, which do not go to the

root, but only ameliorate the problem. And as I have explained above, by

themselves formal measures favor a mystifying democratic formalism,

which becomes an obstacle to the understanding of the problem of the

development of individual autonomy and its indispensability for the full

development of collective autonomy.

Democracy reduced to a procedural form, in order to develop a permanent

debate and total participation of individuals, besides being for the

purpose of deciding their concrete actions, overcomes the formalist

rigidity without falling into its opposite—an informalist rigidity—and

concentrates its attention on the most important thing: the development

of free and equal cooperation and its extension. This means that

democracy is no longer stable as such, that it is in the process of

transition towards ochlocracy. Perhaps the concept of “demarchy” could

be applicable to describe this transitional form, in which democratic

forms persist in the matter of procedure, but have become subordinated

as an instrumental element to the direct will of the self-aware and

self-motivated individuals—“it begins” (arkhĂ©) in them and returns to

them—which is the basis of ochlocracy.

Populism and Right Wing Rhetoric

The ruling class definition of ochlocracy attributes to this term a

character that is perverse in itself, while it considers democracy and

other forms of government as “pure”. This has resulted in the fact that

even today the concept is utilized to criticize, for example, the

populist governments in Latin America, especially when they use mass

mobilization to their advantage. In some cases the concept is explicitly

used, but for the most part the old refrain of demagogy is repeated,

which has come to be used as a synonym.

The association between demagogy—and more generally the absence of

self-aware popular action—and political programs that are supposedly

“socialist”-oriented is therefore reinforced: an obviously right wing

approach, which is nothing but the obverse of the leftist populism to

which it is opposed.

The argument’s plausibility is based principally on the image of

populist leaders or parties, which, whether or not they use the explicit

lie to manipulate the masses, provide plenty of examples of how they

accentuate the discretional use of information in order to bring about a

reaction on the part of the masses that is favorable for their interests

or programs. This is an inherent feature of all populist bourgeois

politics—or all bourgeois politics that includes the active search for

mass support—and does not especially depend on which party or leaders

hold State power. In any case, their political position can either

enhance or reduce their propensity to demagogy and their influence over

the masses.

It so happens that, generally, in capitalist society to speak the truth

is not politically profitable. This is not necessarily because there are

interests that must be concealed. It is rather because the masses

themselves do not want to know the truth. They only endure and accept

their alienating existence by clinging to expectations associated with

capitalist progress, and their very existence causes them to feel

powerless before the general trend of historical development, incapable

of establishing another social system. This is why they are predisposed

to pay more attention to the discourse that they want to hear than to

the one that appeals to and seeks to provide a true explanation of the

facts. They prefer the discourse that nourishes their illusions to the

one that refutes them.

Given this vicious circle, the very existence of the masses is

encapsulated in a lie. And it is this lie itself that makes their

existence endurable. All the social lies in the era of capitalism are

based on the axiom that the social development of commerce, guided

correctly, will resolve today’s sufferings and limitations, or at least

gradually reduce them. It cannot be denied that this axiom has a very

precise subjective foundation, which is the source of the powerful

resistance of the masses to all revolutionary discourse or action. It is

a form of subjectivity that projects its needs into the appropriation of

objects; which is ready to convert its being, its life, into a means for

having and therefore it is completely functional for the development of

commodity production. This is true even when, to achieve this goal, it

finds itself in opposition to the bourgeoisie. In fact, the masses only

rebel against capitalism because the latter has disappointed this kind

of expectation to what they thought was their due, not because they have

overcome their spiritual self-alienation. In other words, it represents

the interests of variable capital rather than the interests of the

liberation of humanity. If in order to achieve this kind of goal the

proletariat constitutes itself as a class, and acts as a class, it

nonetheless only attains this objective on the formal level; it does not

effectively become a class-for-itself in the Marxian sense, but in fact

remains a class-for-capital. And then the class rebellions or struggles

are transformed into a spur for the further development or improvement

of capitalism.

Typical forms of social behavior continue to prevail, which can be

simply differentiated by degrees of passivity/activity with relation to

capitalist development: some sit back and wait, others put their

shoulders to the wheel. But all share the same expectations, they

project the same goals into their praxis, which brings some meaning into

their miserable lives. More precisely, the belief inherent to the

dominant form of subjectivity, according to which the complex psychic

dynamic that characterizes human life can be gradually expanded and

realized in the future, so that capitalism provides a form of

realization for all impulses.

But this conformist expectation is not fulfilled. Neither by the

development of consumer society, which clashes with the limits of

capital, nor by access to a higher level and greater diversity of this

consumption. Thus, by definition, the psychic or vital human dynamic can

only be satisfactorily realized by way of an unlimited self-activity,

through the free unfolding of all its needs and capacities. And this is

impossible in today’s society not only because of the limits of

capitalist production, but because all material production is

economically, technologically and ecologically finite. If this were not

enough, it is becoming increasingly obvious that the growth of the level

of consumption does not in and of itself contribute to either happiness

or the development of the human faculties. This phenomenon has very deep

roots. Existence is activity. Human nature is essentially self-directed

activity and thus it is only in self-directed activity that one can find

self-realization. Possessing, having, is a form of retention or

reduction of self-directed activity as such, besides restricting or

subordinating self-directed activity in general to this particular

modality. This is why it can never produce a happy life or favor the

development of the human faculties. To the contrary, it produces a

feeling of emptiness and impotence, because possession is an alienated

form, instead of being just another function, of self-directed activity

as such. One lives to possess, instead of possessing in order to live,

and existence is sacrificed to possession. In this way, material

production instead of serving to enrich and amplify self-directed

activity, life, impoverishes it in alienated consumption as much as in

alienated labor. And one cannot just stop doing this, because that form

of labor is its effective basis and, in itself, already contains the

principle of the subordination of life to possession: in the general

form of the subordination of living labor to accumulated labor, and in

the particular form of the transformation of the life of the worker into

a mere means to earn a wage.

On this psycho-social basis, capitalism has come to completely subsume

subjectivity as desire and as creation, perfecting the cycle of capital.

This achievement completes the subjection of the entire dynamic of

society, both in the material and the spiritual senses, as a function of

the cycle of capital. Proletarians can no longer live except as elements

of this all-embracing process of capital, which includes production,

circulation and consumption and reconfigures the fabric of everyday

social relations as a functional whole to serve its needs.

But let us now return to the problem of populism.

It is evident that, upon the above-described social foundation, all

populism almost inevitably acquires a certain flavor of the political

strongman. This may be more pronounced in some cases than in others. If

we consider this from the point of view of classical antiquity, this

kind of authoritarian politics based on populist demagogy is, from the

perspective of the forms of government or political systems, an activity

characteristic of tyranny. [11] In these cases popular support, however

active it may be, is instrumental and alienated. It is therefore not a

question here of a democracy that has degenerated, but of a democracy

that has been violated in such a manner that it has allowed an

illegitimate ruling class to obtain power. What is presented to a sector

of the ruling class as a degeneration of democracy, is in reality merely

a transformation from oligarchy to tyranny.

This shows how, in general, bourgeois politics is profoundly demagogic

when it refers to history to back up its arguments. The concept of

democracy itself is used demagogically: good democracy is always

formally constituted in accordance with the class-based structure of

society and its development; the democracy that the “mob” believes in is

always a perverted democracy. When examples arise showing how this is

not necessarily true, where the masses demonstrate a revolutionary

self-organizational capacity and are not just conservative, then resort

is had to the false identity <popular rule=mob rule>, and to the

following syllogism: given A (popular rule is mob rule), and B (mob rule

is perverse, irrational, dominated by falsehoods, etc.), then C (popular

rule is perverse—and its origin lies in the power of the people, as is

implicit in A). This fulfills a dual function: on the one hand, as an

argument of the bourgeois factions against popular rule, but above all

as a mystifying argument regarding this capacity of the masses. In the

case of Venezuela this can be clearly seen. The faction of the

bourgeoisie opposed to Chavism knows perfectly well that the latter’s

power depends more on the self-directed activity of the proletarian

masses, as limited as this may be, than on the bourgeois sectors that

support Chavez.

The Populist Degeneration of Proletarian Politics

The syllogism referred to above is, however, tremendously “popular”,

precisely in the pejorative sense that the classical thinkers conferred

upon the “rabble”, the “plebs” or the “mob” as political subjects. The

conclusion of the syllogism, “C”, has become a more or less unconscious

premise of all variety of prisoners of the democratic-liberal mentality,

including many anarchists who criticize these governments for being

authoritarian and do not go beyond this. The most important result is

that the populist governments are questioned in terms of bourgeois

politics, as agents contrary to individual freedom, to legitimate

interests, etc. Even when they engage in socialist demagogy, they are

condemned for their incoherence, rather than being denounced for their

capitalist character from the very beginning.

It is not too hard to see that the real question concerns the interests

to which populist politics respond, and which normally comprise their

consistent contents, despite variations in the concrete governmental

policies. This aspect does not interest, of course, bourgeois political

forces. Because it brings to the forefront concrete class interests and,

where there is a combination of distinct class interests, or even

contradictory ones, it logically leads us to evaluate their respective

influences on the determination of government policies.

On the other hand, these same bourgeois forces are interested in merging

the heterogeneous mass mobilization with the autonomous actions of the

masses. For if one takes “popular power” for granted, then the latter is

only confirmed to the extent that it effectively directs social

development and determines concrete governmental policies, which is

almost never the case. The right wing forces are very careful to bring

this contradiction of populism to the attention of the masses in these

terms. But it is otherwise with regard to the left wing of capital, in

so far as it participates in the development of populism (for example,

many Leninist parties). In this case they cannot attack the

mystification of the power of the masses without also attacking their

own positions, and this is why any support for populism ultimately leads

to capitulation, first programmatically and then theoretically.

The case of Bolshevism is paradigmatic in this regard. It very well

illustrates how populist logic is capable of integrating the opposition

and thus establishing a mystified history of the revolutionary actions

of the masses. On the assumption that the government supported by the

people is equivalent to the real political hegemony of the people, all

opposition to this government is illegitimate. On the assumption that

this government represents progress, all opposition is also reactionary.

On the other hand, the actions of the masses who support this government

are legitimate and progressive, while the actions of those who rebel

against it are the fruit of manipulations. Thus, even today a large part

of the “Marxist” left believes in the mystified history that the

epigones of Leninism have propagated for ninety years, especially in its

“critical” anti-Stalinist version. They do not acknowledge the

counterrevolutionary character of Bolshevism with respect to proletarian

actions since its origins, nor do they admit the mystification of the

Bolshevik government as an expression of the proletariat, or its

politics and ideology as a mystification of Marxian thought. And, as I

pointed out above, there are those among this leftist majority who, on

the basis of anarchism, have reduced the problem of Bolshevism to the

problem of authoritarianism—understood as a problem of subjectivity, of

a perversion for and through power—and have consistently considered the

origins of the Bolshevik government to be legitimate, since the latter

was endorsed by the masses during the first few years of the

revolution—origins that were perverted by the application of

authoritarian ideas, of course. [12]

Unqualified antiauthoritarianism is always based on a fetishism of

formal organization, and for this reason shares with populism an

abstract view of the activity of the masses. For both, a popular or

proletarian action is an action carried out by the masses of the people

or of the proletariat. Thus, if this action should result in some form

of despotism, this is attributed to the will (conscious or manipulated)

of these same masses. For some, this will is directly attributed to the

authoritarian mentality of the masses. For others, it is attributed to

the influence of the authoritarian mentality of their leaders. From the

historical-materialist point of view, however, a popular or proletarian

action is one that, besides being carried out by the corresponding

subject, tends to lead to the type of social interests that the material

organization of society and the overall historical conditions determine

for these subjects. In other words, “action by the proletarians” (form)

and “action with a proletarian character” (content) are not the same nor

do they necessarily imply one another. [13] At the cutting edge of the

concrete, the action of the proletarians is only consistent with its

socio-historical determinations insofar as it leads to a movement of

self-liberation, of disalienation. But where it expresses an acceptance

of their existence in self-alienation and only attempts to formally

modify it, by the restriction of its struggle, for example, to raising

wages or supporting social welfare policies, the proletariat is only

acting as a class-for-capital.

[1]

es.wikipedia.org

(Greece). (Spanish-language Wikipedia reference. The corresponding

English language Wikipedia entry’s section on etymology does not refer

to the original territorial meaning of the term “Demos”, as of July

2011.)

[2]

en.wikipedia.org

[3] Polybius himself, however, left some indications of another kind of

mob: “The mob, enraged by this action, was no longer content to complain

in private and in secret, but some went abroad by night and posted

placards in the public places, while others congregated in small groups

during the day and publicly vented their hatred for the chiefs.”

[4] Mariano Grondona, Historia de la democracia, September 2000. See:

www.ucema.edu.ar

[5] See:

www.soberania.es

/

[6] Catalina Balmaceda, Virtus romana en el siglo I a.C., 2007. From

this point forward I will take use this work as a source for information

regarding the development of the concept of virtus, although I will

focus on different aspects of this development. (For an English-language

treatment of the same topic, see: Myles Anthony McDonnell, Roman

Manliness: Virtus and the Roman Republic, Cambridge University Press,

New York, 2006 (Translator’s note).)

[7] But not the word “varón” [a Spanish word that means “male”], which

appears to have resulted from a variant spelling of the word “barón” [in

English, “baron”], probably related to the Germanic baro (a man who is

fit for warfare, a warrior) and the Scandinavian boriask (to fight). It

was introduced during the 13^(th) century so it has nothing to do with

vir. [Bracketed interpolations by translator.]

[8] From this point of view, Marx’s thesis that it is not understanding

the world that is most important, but changing it (Theses on Feuerbach,

1845), also has a psychological application. If we adhere to our ideas

of the world, and the world is becoming, our intellectual attitude will

inevitably come into conflict with the goal of changing the world. The

correct attitude is therefore that of disinterested attention in order

to grasp concrete reality, and then the subordination of our

intellectual activity to the general practical goal—without succumbing

to a psychic fixation on particular interpretations of this goal, since

our intellect is also subject to becoming. It is a matter of living in a

state of creative flow, instead of one characterized by ideological

security.

[9] Please note that here I am speaking of political forms. From the

point of view of effective praxis, of concrete human activity,

decision-making is not instrumental, but is organically bound to that

activity, which is a dynamic unity of being and consciousness. What we

are discussing here are the formal guidelines that define the

institutional dynamic and its effects. Within the framework of social

activity, the atomization of decision-making with a view to practical

realization is only possible by way of a division of labor.

[10] “The reality which communism creates is precisely the true basis

for rendering it impossible that anything should exist independently of

individuals, insofar as reality is nevertheless only a product of the

preceding intercourse of individuals.” (Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,

The German Ideology, Prometheus Books, Amherst, New York, 1998, p. 90.)

[11] “... a tyrant is chosen from the people to be their protector

against the notables, and in order to prevent them from being injured.

History shows that almost all tyrants have been demagogues who gained

the favor of the people by their accusation of the notables.”

(Aristotle, Politics, Book 5, Part 10.) See:

classics.mit.edu

[12] Others have insisted that the Bolshevik regime was established by

means of a coup d’état, rather than as a direct result of mass action or

the development of the soviet system. This does not, however, obviate

the fact that the Bolshevik regime could count on the broad support of

the proletariat during the first few years of its existence.

[13] I shall not venture here to comment upon the ambiguity and

contradictory nature of the category, “the people”, which is itself one

of the ideological mainstays of populism.