💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › herbert-read-the-paradox-of-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:49:24. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Paradox of Anarchism Author: Herbert Read Date: 1941 Language: en Topics: political philosophy Source: Retrieved on October 5th, 2009 from http://www.panarchy.org/read/anarchism.html Notes: In this interesting essay Herbert Read presents the concept of the functional contract in opposition to the social contract. The functional contract characterizes the anarchic society where individuals arrange their affairs and follow rules on the basis of functional aims voluntarily aimed at by the participants. The social contract, on the other hand, is at the basis of democratic statism where everybody is automatically bound, from birth, to follow the rules of the sovereign body. The affirmation of the social contract has been made possible by replacing the natural law (rational norms) with the positive law (state commands) originating from a supposedly existing Volkgeist (national spirit) of which the state is the personification.
It has been the fashion, especially among orthodox Marxists, to hold in
contempt any theory of politics which did not justify itself in action,
and this emphasis on action has often led to a confusion of means and
ends — the means too often overshadowing the ends and becoming a
substitute for them. The dictatorship of the proletariat, for example,
at first put forward as a means towards the classless society, becomes
stabilized in Russia as the sovereignty of a new class.
Anarchism does not confuse means and ends, theory and practice. As a
theory it relies on reason alone, and if the conception of society which
it thus arrives at seems utopian and even chimerical, it does not
matter, for what is established by right reasoning cannot be surrendered
to expediency. Our practical activity may be a gradual approximation
towards the ideal, or it may be a sudden revolutionary realization of
that ideal, but it must never be a compromise. Proudhon was often
accused of being an anarchist in theory, but only a reformist in
practice: he was, in fact, an anarchist, all the time, who refused to
commit himself to the hazards of dictatorship. He would not play the
game of politics because he knew that economics were the fundamental
reality. And so to-day it is conceivable that a change in the control of
financial credit, or a new system of land tenure, might bring us nearer
to anarchism than a political revolution which merely transferred the
power of the state into the hands of a new set of ambitious gangsters.
Anarchism means literally a society without an arkhos, that is to say,
without a ruler. It does not mean a society without law and therefore it
does not mean a society without order. The anarchist accepts the social
contract, but he interprets that contract in a particular way, which he
believes to be the way most justified by reason.
The social contract, as expounded by Rousseau, implies that each
individual in society surrenders his independence for the common good,
with the assumption that only in this way can the liberty of the
individual be guaranteed. Liberty is guaranteed by law, and law, to use
Rousseau’s phrase, is the expression of the general will.
So far we are on common ground, not only with Rousseau, but with the
whole democratic tradition which has been built up on the theoretical
foundation laid by Rousseau. Where the anarchist diverges from Rousseau,
and from that aspect of the democratic tradition which has found
expression in parliamentary socialism, is in his interpretation of the
manner in which the general will should be formulated and enforced.
Rousseau himself was not consistent on this question. He was quite
convinced that some form of state must exist as an expression of the
general will, and that the power invested in the state by general
consent must be absolute. He was equally convinced that the individual
must retain his liberty, and that upon the individual’s enjoyment of
liberty depended all progress and civilization. He realized that as an
historical fact the state and the individual had always come into
conflict, and for a solution of this dilemma he fell back upon his
theory of education. If every citizen could be brought up to appreciate
the beauty and harmony of the laws inherent in nature, he would be as
incapable of establishing a tyranny as of enduring one. The society in
which he lived would automatically be a natural society, a society of
free consent in which law and liberty are but two aspects of the same
reality. But such a system of education implies a pre-existing authority
to establish it and that authority must be absolute.
The system of government recommended by Rousseau in The Social Contract
is an elective aristocracy rather than a true democracy, and to control
this aristocracy he imagines a state so small that every individual
within it would be able to watch and criticize the government. He
probably had something like the Greek city-state in mind as the real
unit. He certainly had no prevision of the vast complexes of millions of
individuals which constitute most modern states, and we can be quite
sure that he would have been the first to admit that his system of
checks on authority would not work under such conditions.
But his theory of the state, which has had such a profound influence on
the development of modern socialism, has been taken over as applicable
to these vast conglomerates, and it then becomes a justification for the
most absolute kind of authoritarianism. This danger was recognized as
long ago as 1815 by Benjamin Constant, who described The Social Contract
as “le plus terrible auxiliaire de tous les genres de despotisme”.
If what Rousseau calls an aristocratic form of government is more or
less identical with modern democracy, what he calls democracy is more or
less identical with the modern theory of anarchism, and it is
interesting to see why he rejects democracy. He does so for two reasons
— first because he regards it as an executive impossibility. A people
cannot be continuously assembled to govern; it must delegate authority
as a mere matter of convenience, and once you have delegated authority,
you no longer have a democracy.
His second reason is a typical example of his inconsistency. If there
were a people of gods, he says, they could govern themselves
democratically, but a government so perfect is unsuitable for men.
But if democracy is the perfect form of government, it is not for one
who has proclaimed his faith in the perfectibility of man to restrict it
to the gods. What is good enough for the gods is all the better for man
— as an ideal. If the ideal exists we must recognize it and strive,
however approximately, to attain it.
But the fundamental question in all this sophistry is ignored by
Rousseau. It is the unreality of the notion of the general will. There
is probably only one issue on which a people ever expresses unanimous or
general will: the defence of their physical liberty. Otherwise they
divide according to their temperaments, and though these are limited in
number, they are sufficiently diverse and so mutually opposed that in
any given geographical area they will give rise to incompatible groups.
On that very account, say Rousseau and many other philosophers, a
democracy is impossible.
They are forced to this conclusion because they adhere obstinately to
the arbitrary boundaries of the modern state — boundaries established by
rivers, seas, mountains and military treaties, and not by reason.
Suppose we were to ignore these boundaries, or abolish them. The
realities are, after all, human beings with certain desires: with
certain primitive needs. These human beings, according to their needs
and sympathies, will spontaneously associate themselves into groups for
mutual aid, will voluntarily organize an economy which ensures the
satisfaction of their needs. This is the principle of mutual aid, and it
has been explained and justified with much historical and scientific
evidence by Kropotkin. It is this principle which the anarchist makes
the foundation of the social order, and upon which he believes he can
build that democratic form of society which Rousseau felt was reserved
for the gods.
It is not necessary here to repeat the empirical evidence for this
belief: Kropotkin’s great book can now be obtained for sixpence in the
Penguin Series, and it is a work whose scholarship is acknowledged by
sociologists of all schools. The difficulty is not to justify a
principle which has sound psychological and empirical evidence to
support it, but to apply this principle to the existing state of
society.
This we do tentatively by taking the voluntary organizations which
already exist and seeing to what extent they are capable of becoming the
units in a democratic society. Such organizations are trade unions,
syndicates, professional unions and associations — all those groups
which crystallize around a human function. We then consider the
functions which are now performed by the state, and which are necessary
for our well-being, and we ask ourselves to what extent these functions
could be entrusted to such voluntary organizations. We come to the
conclusion that there are no essential functions which could not thus be
transferred. It is true that there are functions like making war and
charging rent which are not the expression of an impulse towards mutual
aid, but it does not need much consideration of such functions to see
that they would naturally disappear if the central authority of the
state was abolished.
The mistakes of every political thinker from Aristotle to Rousseau have
been due to their use of the abstract conception man. Their systems
assume the substantial uniformity of this creature of their
imaginations, and what they actually propose are various forms of
authority to enforce uniformity on man.
But the anarchist recognizes the uniqueness of the person, and only
allows for organization to the extent that the person seeks sympathy and
mutual aid among his fellows. In reality, therefore, the anarchist
replaces the social contract by the functional contract, and the
authority of the contract only extends to the fulfilling of a specific
function.
The political unitarian or authoritarian conceives society as one body
compelled to uniformity. The anarchist conceives society as a balance or
harmony of groups, and most of us belong to one or more such groups. The
only difficulty is their harmonious interrelation.
But is it so difficult? It is true that trade unions sometimes quarrel
with one another, but analyse these quarrels and you will find, either
that they proceed from causes outside their function (such as their
different conception of their place in a non-functional, e.g.
capitalist, society) or from personal rivalries, which are a reflection
of the struggle for survival in a capitalist world. Such differences of
aim bear no relation to the principle of voluntary organization and are
indeed excluded by that very concept. In general, trade unions can agree
with one another well enough even in a capitalist society, in spite of
all its incitement to rivalry and aggressiveness.
If we go outside our own time to the Middle Ages, far example, we find
that the functional organization of society, though imperfectly
realized, was proved to be quite possible, and its gradual perfection
was only thwarted by the rise of capitalism. Other periods and other
forms of society, as Kropotkin has shown, fully confirm the possibility
of the harmonious interrelationships of functional groups.
Admitted, it may be said, that we can transfer all the economic
functions of the state in this way, what about other functions — the
administration of criminal law, relationships with foreign countries not
at the same stage of social development, education, etc.?
To this question the anarchist has two replies. In the first place he
argues that most of these non-functional activities are incidental to a
non-functional state — that crime, for example, is largely a reaction to
the institution of private property, and that foreign affairs are
largely economic in origin and motivation. But it is agreed that there
questions, such as certain aspects of common law, infant education,
public morality, which may be outside the province of the functional
organizations. These, he argues, are matters of common sense, solved by
reference to the innate good will of the community. But the community,
for this purpose need not necessarily be anything so impersonal and so
grandiose as a state — in fact, it will be effective in inverse ratio to
its size. The most effective community is the smallest — the family.
Beyond the family is the parish, the local association of men in
contiguous dwellings. Such local associations may form their courts and
these courts are sufficient to administer a common law based on common
sense. The manor courts in the Middle Ages, for example, dealt with all
crimes and misdemeanours save those committed against the artificial
entities of the state and the Church.
In this sense anarchism implies a universal decentralization of
authority, and a universal simplification of life. Inhuman entities like
the modern city will disappear. But anarchism does not necessarily imply
a reversion to handicraft and outdoor sanitation. There is no
contradiction between anarchism and electric power, anarchism and air
transport, anarchism and the division of labour, anarchism and
industrial efficiency. Since the functional groups will all be working
for their mutual benefit, and not for other people’s profit or for
mutual destruction, the measure of efficiency will be the appetite, for
fullness of living.
There is a further consideration of a more topical and pressing nature.
In a remarkable book published recently, The Crisis of Civilization,
Alfred Cobban has shown that the disasters which have fallen on the
Western world are a direct consequence of the adoption by Germany of the
theory of popular or national sovereignty, in place of the theory of
natural law which had been evolved by the rational movement of thought
in the eighteenth century known as the Enlightenment. German thought,
writes Mr. Cobban,
substituted historical rights for natural rights, and will of the
nation, or the Volk, for reason as the basis of law and government. ...
The ultimate result of the theory of popular sovereignty was thus the
substitution of history for ethics. This tendency was present in the
contemporary thought of all countries. It has only achieved a complete
triumph in Germany. The distinguishing mark of modern German thought is
dissolution of ethics in the Volkgeist; its practical conclusion is that
the state is the source of all morality and the individual must accept
the laws and actions of his own state as having ultimate ethical
validity.
I will not repeat the detailed evidence which Mr. Cobban, who is a
professional historian, offers in support of this statement, but its
truth is obvious enough. “Sovereignty, whether it adopts the democratic,
nationalist, or socialist disguise, or some amalgam of all three, is the
political religion of to-day.” It follows that if we are to rid Europe
permanently of the menace to peace which Germany represents, we must
first of all refute the German conception sovereignty. So long as this
conception remains, as a national religion, there will be a continual
resurgence of the instruments of such a policy — armed might and
arbitrary aggression.
It was a great German, already alarmed by the tendencies then taking
shape, as an immediate reaction from the French Revolution, who warned
his countrymen against the monster they were creating.
It is thus [wrote Schiller] that concrete individual life is
extinguished, in order that the abstract whole may continue its
miserable life, and the state remains for ever a stranger to its
citizens, because nowhere does it touch their feelings. The governing
authorities find themselves compelled to classify, and thereby simplify,
the multiplicity of citizens, and only to know humanity in a
representative form and at second hand. Accordingly they end by entirely
losing sight of humanity, and by confounding it with a simple artificial
creation of the understanding, whilst on their part the subject classes
cannot help receiving coldly laws that address themselves so little to
their personality. At length society, weary of having a burden that the
state takes so little trouble to lighten, falls to pieces and is broken
up — a destiny that has long since attended most European states. They
are dissolved in what may be called a state of moral nature, in which
public authority is only one function more, hated and deceived by those
who think it necessary, respected only by those who can do without it.
(Letters upon the Aesthetical Education of Man, VI, 1795)
In these prescient words Schiller stated that antagonism between organic
freedom and mechanical organizations which has been ignored in the
political development of modern Europe, with results which we see all
round us now.
Anarchism is the final and most urgent protest against this fate: a
recall to those principles which alone can guarantee the harmony of
man’s being and the creative evolution of his genius.