💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › simone-weil-the-iliad.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:11:51. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Iliad, or The Poem of Force
Author: Simone Weil
Date: 1945
Language: en
Topics: force, poetry, essays, review
Source: Retrieved on 6th December 2020 from http://libgen.rs/book/index.php?md5=2B8EADE7846DF424C0522D9F3FFC0348

Simone Weil

The Iliad, or The Poem of Force

The true hero, the true subject, the center of the Iliad is force. Force

employed by man, force that enslaves man, force before which man’s flesh

shrinks away. In this work, at all times, the human spirit is shown as

modified by its relations with force, as swept away, blinded, by the

very force it imagined it could handle, as deformed by the weight of the

force it submits to. For those dreamers who considered that force,

thanks to progress, would soon be a thing of the past, the Iliad could

appear as an historical document; for others, whose powers of

recognition are more acute and who perceive force, today as yesterday,

at the very center of human history, the Iliad is the purest and the

loveliest of mirrors.

To define force — it is that x that turns anybody who is subjected to it

into a thing. Exercised to the limit, it turns man into a thing in the

most literal sense: it makes a corpse out of him. Somebody was here, and

the next minute there is nobody here at all; this is a spectacle the

Iliad never wearies of showing us:

The hero becomes a thing dragged behind a chariot in the dust:

The bitterness of such a spectacle is offered us absolutely undiluted.

No comforting fiction intervenes; no consoling prospect of immortality;

and on the hero’s head no washedout halo of patriotism descends.

Still more poignant — so painful is the contrast — is the sudden

evocation, as quickly rubbed out, of another world: the faraway,

precarious, touching world of peace, of the family, the world in which

each man counts more than anything else to those about him.

Far from hot baths he was indeed, poor man. And not he alone. Nearly all

the lliad takes place far from hot baths. Nearly all of human life, then

and now, takes place far from hot baths.

Here we see force in its grossest and most summary form — the force that

kills. How much more varied in its processes, how much more surprising

in its effects is the other force, the force that does not kill, i.e.,

that does not kill just yet. It will surely kill, it will possibly kill,

or perhaps it merely hangs, poised and ready, over the head of the

creature it can kill, at any moment, which is to say at every moment. In

whatever aspect, its effect is the same: it turns a man into a stone.

From its first property (the ability to turn a human being into a thing

by the simple method of killing him) flows another, quite prodigious too

in its own way, the ability to turn a human being into a thing while he

is still alive. He is alive; he has a soul; and yet — he is a thing. An

extraordinary entity this — a thing that has a soul. And as for the

soul, what an extraordinary house it finds itself in! Who can say what

it costs it, moment by moment, to accommodate itself to this residence,

how much writhing and bending, folding and pleating are required of it?

It was not made to live inside a thing; if it does so, under pressure of

necessity, there is not a single element of its nature to which violence

is not done.

A man stands disarmed and naked with a weapon pointing at him; this

person becomes a corpse before anybody or anything touches him. Just a

minute ago, he was thinking, acting, hoping:

Soon, however, he grasps the fact that the weapon which is pointing at

him will not be diverted; and now, still breathing, he is simply matter;

still thinking, he can think no longer:

If a stranger, completely disabled, disarmed, strengthless, throws

himself on the mercy of a warrior, he is not, by this very act,

condemned to death; but a moment of impatience on the warrior’s part

will suffice to relieve him of his life. In any case, his flesh has lost

that very important property which in the laboratory distinguishes

living flesh from dead — the galvanic response. If you give a frog’s leg

an electric shock, it twitches. If you confront a human being with the

touch or sight of something horrible or terrifying, this bundle of

muscles, nerves, and flesh likewise twitches.

Alone of all living things, the suppliant we have just described neither

quivers nor trembles. He has lost the right to do so.

As his lips advance to touch the object that is for him of all things

most charged with horror, they do not draw back on his teeth — they

cannot:

The sight of a human being pushed to such an extreme of suffering chills

us like the sight of a dead body:

But this feeling lasts only a moment. Soon the very presence of the

suffering creature is forgotten:

It was not insensibility that made Achilles with a single movement of

his hand push away the old man who had been clinging to his knees;

Priam’s words, recalling his own old father, had moved him to tears. It

was merely a question of his being as free in his attitudes and

movements as if, clasping his knees, there were not a suppliant but an

inert object. Anybody who is in our vicinity exercises a certain power

over us by his very presence, and a power that belongs to him alone,

that is, the power of halting, repressing, modifying each movement that

our body sketches out. If we step aside for a passer-by on the road, it

is not the same thing as stepping aside to avoid a billboard; alone in

our rooms, we get up, walk about, sit down again quite differently from

the way we do when we have a visitor. But this indefinable influence

that the presence of another human being has on us is not exercised by

men whom a moment of impatience can deprive of life, who can die before

even thought has a chance to pass sentence on them. In their presence,

people move about as if they were not there; they, on their side,

running the risk of being reduced to nothing in a single instant,

imitate nothingness in their own persons. Pushed, they fall. Fallen,

they lie where they are, unless chance gives somebody the idea of

raising them up again. But supposing that at long last they have been

picked up, honored with cordial remarks, they still do not venture to

take this resurrection seriously; they dare not express a wish lest an

irritated voice return them forever to silence:

At least a suppliant, once his prayer is answered, becomes a human being

again, like everybody else. But there are other, more unfortunate

creatures who have become things for the rest of their lives. Their days

hold no pastimes, no free spaces, no room in them for any impulse of

their own.

It is not that their life is harder than other men’s nor that they

occupy a lower place in the social hierarchy; no, they are another human

species, a compromise between a man and a corpse. The idea of a person’s

being a thing is a logical contradiction. Yet what is impossible in

logic becomes true in life, and the contradiction lodged within the soul

tears it to shreds. This thing is constantly aspiring to be a man or a

woman, and never achieving it — here, surely, is death but death strung

out over a whole lifetime; here, surely is life, but life that death

congeals before abolishing.

This strange fate awaits the virgin, the priest’s daughter:

It awaits the young wife, the young mother, the prince’s bride:

It awaits the baby, heir to the royal scepter:

In the mother’s eyes, such a fate is, for her child, as terrible as

death; the husband would rather die than see his wife reduced to it; all

the plagues of heaven are invoked by the father against the army that

subjects his daughter to it. Yet the victims themselves are beyond all

this. Curses, feelings of rebellion, comparisons, reflections on the

future and the past, are obliterated from the mind of the captive; and

memory itself barely lingers on. Fidelity to his city and his dead is

not the slave’s privilege.

And what does it take to make the slave weep? The misfortune of his

master, his oppressor, despoiler, pillager, of the man who laid waste

his town and killed his dear ones under his very eye .... This man

suffers or dies; then the slave’s tears come. And really why not? This

is for him the only occasion on which tears are permitted, are, indeed,

required. A slave will always cry whenever he can do so with impunity —

his situation keeps tears on tap for him.

Since the slave has no license to express anything except what is

pleasing to his master, it follows that the only emotion that can touch

or enliven him a little, that can reach him in the desolation of his

life, is the emotion of love for his master.

There is no place else to send the gift of love; all other outlets are

barred, just as, with the horse in harness, bit, shafts, reins bar every

way but one. And if, by some miracle, in the slave’s breast a hope is

born, the hope of becoming, some day, through somebody’s influence,

someone once again, how far won’t these captives go to show love and

thankfulness, even though these emotions are addressed to the very men

who should, considering the very recent past, still reek with horror for

them:

To lose more than the slave does is impossible, for he loses his whole

inner life. A fragment of it he may get back if he sees the possibility

of changing his fate, but this is his only hope. Such is the empire of

force, as extensive as the empire of nature. Nature, too, when vital

needs are at stake, can erase the whole inner life, even the grief of a

mother:

Force, in the hands of another, exercises over the soul the same tyranny

that extreme hunger does; for it possesses, and in perpetuo, the power

of life and death. Its rule, moreover, is as cold and hard as the rule

of inert matter.

The man who knows himself weaker than another is more alone in the heart

of a city than a man lost in the desert.

Force is as pitiless to the man who possesses it, or thinks he does, as

it is to its victims; the second it crushes, the first it intoxicates.

The truth is, nobody really possesses it. The human race is not divided

up, in the Iliad, into conquered persons, slaves, suppliants, on the one

hand, and conquerors and chiefs on the other. In this poem there is not

a single man who does not at one time or another have to bow his neck to

force. The common soldier in the Iliad is free and has the right to bear

arms; nevertheless he is subject to the indignity of orders and abuse:

Thersites pays dear for the perfectly reasonable comments he makes,

comments not at all different, moreover, from those made by Achilles:

Achilles himself, that proud hero, the undefeated, is shown us at the

outset of the poem, weeping with humiliation and helpless grief — the

woman he wanted for his bride has been taken from under his nose, and he

has not dared to oppose it:

What has happened is that Agamemnon has deliberately humiliated

Achilles, to show that he himself is the master:

But a few days pass and now the supreme commander is weeping in his

turn. He must humble himself, he must plead, and have, moreover, the

added misery of doing it all in vain.

In the same way, there is not a single one of the combatants who is

spared the shameful experience of fear. The heroes quake like everybody

else. It only needs a challenge from Hector to throw the whole Greek

force into consternation--except for Achilles and his men, and they did

not happen to be present:

But once Ajax comes forward and offers himself, fear quickly changes

sides:

Two days later, it is Ajax’s turn to be terrified:

Even to Achilles the moment comes; he too must shake and stammer with

fear, though it is a river that has this effect on him, not a man. But,

with the exception of Achilles, every man in the Iliad tastes a moment

of defeat in battle. Victory is less a matter of valor than of blind

destiny, which is symbolized in the poem by Zeus’s golden scales:

By its very blindness, destiny establishes a kind of justice. Blind also

is she who decrees to warriors punishment in kind. He that takes the

sword, will perish by the sword. The Iliad formulated the principle long

before the Gospels did, and in almost the same terms:

Perhaps all men, by the very act of being born, are destined to suffer

violence; yet this is a truth to which circumstance shuts men’s eyes.

The strong are, as a matter of fact, never absolutely strong, nor are

the weak absolutely weak, but neither is aware of this. They have in

common a refusal to believe that they both belong to the same species:

the weak see no relation between themselves and the strong, and vice

versa. The man who is the possessor of force seems to walk through a

non-resistant element; in the human substance that surrounds him nothing

has the power to interpose, between the impulse and the act, the tiny

interval that is reflection.

Where there is no room for reflection, there is none either for justice

or prudence. Hence we see men in arms behaving harshly and madly. We see

their sword bury itself in the breast of a disarmed enemy who is in the

very act of pleading at their knees. We see them triumph over a dying

man by describing to him the outrages his corpse will endure. We see

Achilles cut the throats of twelve Trojan boys on the funeral pyre of

Patroclus as naturally as we cut flowers for a grave.

These men, wielding power, have no suspicion of the fact that the

consequences of their deeds will at length come home to them — they too

will bow the neck in their turn. If you can make an old man fall silent,

tremble, obey, with a single word of your own, why should it occur to

you that the curses of this old man, who is after all a priest, will

have their own importance in the gods’ eyes? Why should you refrain from

taking Achilles’ girl away from him if you know that neither he nor she

can do anything but obey you? Achilles rejoices over the sight of the

Greeks fleeing in misery and confusion.

What could possibly suggest to him that this rout, which will last

exactly as long as he wants it to and end when his mood indicates it,

that this very rout will be the cause of his friend’s death, and, for

that matter, of his own? Thus it happens that those who have force on

loan from fate count on it too much and are destroyed.

But at the time their own destruction seems impossible to them. For they

do not see that the force in their possession is only a limited

quantity; nor do they see their relations with other human beings as a

kind of balance between unequal amounts of force. Since other people do

not impose on their movements that halt, that interval of hesitation,

wherein lies all our consideration for our brothers in humanity, they

conclude that destiny has given complete license to them, and none at

all to their inferiors. And at this point they exceed the measure of the

force that is actually at their disposal. Inevitably they exceed it,

since they are not aware that it is limited. And now we see them

committed irretrievably to chance; suddenly things cease to obey them.

Sometimes chance is kind to them, sometimes cruel. But in any case there

they are, exposed, open to misfortune; gone is the armor of power that

formerly protected their naked souls; nothing, no shield, stands between

them and tears.

This retribution, which has a geometrical rigor, which operates

automatically to penalize the abuse of force, was the main subject of

Greek thought. It is the soul of the epic. Under the name of Nemesis, it

functions as the mainspring of Aeschylus’s tragedies. To the

Pythagoreans, to Socrates and Plato, it was the jumping-off point of

speculation upon the nature of man and the universe. Wherever Hellenism

has penetrated, we find the idea of it familiar. In Oriental countries

which are steeped in Buddhism, it is perhaps this Greek idea that bas

lived on under the name of Kharma. The Occident, however, has lost it,

and no longer even has a word to express it in any of its languages:

conceptions of limit, measure, equilibrium, which ought to determine the

conduct of life are, in the West, restricted to a servile function in

the vocabulary of technics. We are only geometricians of matter; the

Greeks were, first of all, geometricians in their apprenticeship to

virtue.

The progress of the war in the Iliad is simply a continual game of

seesaw. The victor of the moment feels himself invincible, even though,

only a few hours before, he may have experienced defeat; he forgets to

treat victory as a transitory thing. At the end of the first day of

combat described in the Iliad, the victorious Greeks were in a position

to obtain the object of all their efforts, i.e., Helen and her riches —

assuming of course as Homer did, that the Greeks had reason to believe

that Helen was in Troy. Actually, the Egyptian priests, who ought to

have known, affirmed later on to Herodotus that she was in Egypt. In any

case, that evening the Greeks are no longer interested in her or her

possessions:

What they want is, in fact, everything. For booty, all the riches of

Troy; for their bonfires, all the palaces, temples, houses; for slaves,

all the women and children; for corpses, all the men. They forget one

detail, that everything is not within their power, for they are not in

Troy. Perhaps they will be there tomorrow; perhaps not. Hector, the same

day, makes the same mistake:

At this moment what would he not give to turn aside those horrors which

he believes to be inevitable? But at this moment nothing he could give

would be of any use. The next day but one, however, the Greeks have run

away miserably, and Agamemnon himself is in favor of putting to the sea

again.

And now Hector, by making a very few concessions, could readily secure

the enemy’s departure; yet now he is even unwilling to let them go

empty-handed:

His wish is granted; the Greeks stay; and the next day they reduce

Hector and his men to a pitiable condition:

In the course of the afternoon, Hector regains the ascendancy, withdraws

again, then puts the Greeks to flight, then is repulsed by Patroclus,

who has come in with his fresh troops.

Patroclus, pressing his advantage, ends by finding himself exposed,

wounded and without armor, to the sword of Hector.

And finally that evening the victorious Hector hears the prudent counsel

of Polydamas and repudiates it sharply:

The next day Hector is lost. Achilles has harried him across the field

and is about to kill him. He has always been the stronger of the two in

combat; how much the more so now, after several weeks of rest, ardent

for vengeance and victory, against an exhausted enemy? And Hector stands

alone, before the walls of Troy, absolutely alone, alone to wait for

death and to steady his soul to face it:

Not a jot of the grief and ignominy that fall to the unfortunate is

Hector spared. Alone, stripped of the prestige of force, he discovers

that the courage that kept him from taking to the shelter of the walls

is not enough to save him from flight:

Wounded to death, he enhances his conqueror’s triumph by vain

supplications:

But the auditors of the Iliad knew that the death of Hector would be but

a brief joy to Achilles, and the death of Achilles but a brief joy to

the Trojans, and the destruction of Troy but a brief joy to the

Achaeans.

THUS violence obliterates anybody who feels its touch. It comes to seem

just as external to its employer as to its victim. And from this springs

the idea of a destiny before which executioner and victim stand equally

innocent, before which conquered and conqueror are brothers in the same

distress. The conquered brings misfortune to the conqueror, and vice

versa:

A moderate use of force, which alone would enable man to escape being

enmeshed in its machinery, would require superhuman virtue, which is as

rare as dignity in weakness.

Moreover, moderation itself is not without its perils, since prestige,

from which force derives at least three quarters of its strength, rests

principally upon that marvelous indifference that the strong feel toward

the weak, an indifference so contagious that it infects the very people

who are the objects of it. Yet ordinarily excess is not arrived at

through prudence or politic considerations. On the contrary, man dashes

to it as to an irresistible temptation. The voice of reason is

occasionally heard in the mouths of the characters in the Iliad.

Thersites’ speeches are reasonable to the highest degree; so are the

speeches of the angry Achilles:

But words of reason drop into the void. If they come from an inferior,

he is punished and shuts up; if from a chief, his actions betray them.

And failing everything else, there is always a god handy to advise him

to be unreasonable. In the end, the very idea of wanting to escape the

role fate has allotted one — the business of killing and dying —

disappears from the mind:

Already these warriors, like Craonne’s so much later, felt themselves to

be “condemned men.”

It was the simplest trap that pitched them into this situation. At the

outset, at the embarkation, their hearts are light, as hearts always are

if you have a large force on your side and nothing but space to oppose

you. Their weapons are in their hands; the enemy is absent. Unless your

spirit has been conquered in advance by the reputation of the enemy, you

always feel yourself to be much stronger than anybody who is not there.

An absent man does not impose the yoke of necessity. To the spirits of

those embarking no necessity yet presents itself; consequently they go

off as though to a game, as though on holiday from the confinement of

daily life.

But the first contact of war does not immediately destroy the illusion

that war is a game. War’s necessity is terrible, altogether different in

kind from the necessity of peace. So terrible is it that the human

spirit will not submit to it so long as it can possibly escape; and

whenever it can escape it takes refuge in long days empty of necessity,

days of play, of revery, days arbitrary and unreal. Danger then becomes

an abstraction; the lives you destroy are like toys broken by a child,

and quite as incapable of feeling; heroism is but a theatrical gesture

and smirched with boastfulness. This becomes doubly true if a momentary

access of vitality comes to reinforce the divine hand that wards off

defeat and death. Then war is easy and basely, coarsely loved.

But with the majority of the combatants this state of mind does not

persist. Soon there comes a day when fear, or defeat, or the death of

beloved comrades touches the warrior’s spirit, and it crumbles in the

hand of necessity. At that moment war is no more a game or a dream; now

at last the warrior cannot doubt the reality of its existence. And this

reality, which he perceives, is hard, much too hard to be borne, for it

enfolds death. Once you acknowledge death to be a practical possibility,

the thought of it becomes unendurable, except in flashes. True enough,

all men are fated to die; true enough also, a soldier may grow old in

battles; yet for those whose spirits have bent under the yoke of war,

the relation between death and the future is different than for other

men. For other men death appears as a limit set in advance on the

future; for the soldier death is the future, the future his profession

assigns him. Yet the idea of man’s having death for a future is

abhorrent to nature. Once the experience of war makes visible the

possibility of death that lies locked up in each moment, our thoughts

cannot travel from one day to the next without meeting death’s face. The

mind is then strung up to a pitch it can stand for only a short time;

but each new dawn reintroduces the same necessity; and days piled on

days make years. On each one of these days the soul suffers violence.

Regularly, every morning, the soul castrates itself of aspiration, for

thought cannot journey through time without meeting death on the way.

Thus war effaces all conceptions of purpose or goal, including even its

own “war aims.” It effaces the very notion of war’s being brought to an

end. To be outside a situation so violent as this is to find it

inconceivable; to be inside it is to be unable to conceive its end.

Consequently, nobody does anything to bring this end about. In the

presence of an armed enemy, what hand can relinquish its weapon? The

mind ought to find a way out, but the mind has lost all capacity to so

much as look outward. The mind is completely absorbed in doing itself

violence. Always in human life, whether war or slavery is in question,

intolerable sufferings continue, as it were, by the force of their own

specific gravity, and so look to the outsider as though they were easy

to bear; actually, they continue because they have deprived the sufferer

of the resources which might serve to extricate him.

Nevertheless, the soul that is enslaved to war cries out for

deliverance, but deliverance itself appears to it in an extreme and

tragic aspect, the aspect of destruction. Any other solution, more

moderate, more reasonable in character, would expose the mind to

suffering so naked, so violent that it could not be borne, even as

memory. Terror, grief, exhaustion, slaughter, the annihilation of

comrades — is it credible that these things should not continually tear

at the soul, if the intoxication of force had not intervened to drown

them? The idea that an unlimited effort should bring in only a limited

profit or no profit at all is terribly painful.

But actually what is Helen to Ulysses? What indeed is Troy, full of

riches that will not compensate him for Ithaca’s ruin? For the Greeks,

Troy and Helen are in reality mere sources of blood and tears; to master

them is to master frightful memories. If the existence of an enemy has

made a soul destroy in itself the thing nature put there, then the only

remedy the soul can imagine is the destruction of the enemy. At the same

time the death of dearly loved comrades arouses a spirit of somber

emulation, a rivalry in death:

It is the same despair that drives him on toward death, on the one hand,

and slaughter on the other:

The man possessed by this twofold need for death belongs, so long as he

has not become something still different, to a different race from the

race of the living.

What echo can the timid hopes of life strike in such a heart? How can it

hear the defeated begging for another sight of the light of day? The

threatened life has already been relieved of nearly all its consequence

by a single, simple distinction: it is now unarmed; its adversary

possesses a weapon.

Furthermore, how can a man who has rooted out of himself the notion that

the light of day is sweet to the eyes respect such a notion when it

makes its appearance in some futile and humble lament?

What a reception this feeble hope gets!

To respect life in somebody else when you have had to castrate yourself

of all yearning for it demands a truly heartbreaking exertion of the

powers of generosity. It is impossible to imagine any of Homer’s

warriors being capable of such an exertion, unless it is that warrior

who dwells, in a peculiar way, at the very center of the poem-! mean

Patroclus, who “knew hew to be sweet to everybody,” and who throughout

the Iliad commits no cruel or brutal act. But then how many men do we

know, in several thousand years of human history, who would have

displayed such god-like generosity? Two or three? — even this is

doubtful. Lacking this generosity, the conquering soldier is like a

scourge of nature. Possessed by war, he, like the slave, becomes a

thing, though his manner of doing so is different--over him too, words

are as powerless as over matter itself. And both, at the touch of force,

experience its inevitable effects: they become deaf and dumb.

Such is the nature of force. Its power of converting a man into a thing

is a double one, and in its application double-edged. To the same

degree, though in different fashions, those who use it and those who

endure it are turned to stone. This property of force achieves its

maximum eflectiveness during the clash of arms, in battle, when the tide

of the day has turned, and everything is rushing toward a decision. It

is not the planning man, the man of strategy, the man acting on the

resolution taken, who wins or loses a battle; battles are fought and

decided by men deprived of these faculties, men who have undergone a

transformation, who have dropped either to the level of inert matter,

which is pure passivity, or to the level of blind force, which is pure

momentum.

Herein lies the last secret of war, a secret revealed by the Iliad in

its similes, which liken the warriors either to fire, flood, wind, wild

beasts, or God knows what blind cause of disaster, or else to frightened

animals, trees, water, sand, to anything in nature that is set into

motion by the violence of external forces. Greeks and Trojans, from one

day to the next, sometimes even from one hour to the next, experience,

turn and turn about, one or the other of these transmutations:

The art of war is simply the art of producing such transformations, and

its equipment, its processes, even the casualties it inflicts on the

enemy, are only means directed toward this end — its true object is the

warrior’s soul. Yet these transformations are always a mystery; the gods

are their authors, the gods who kindle men’s imagination. But however

caused, this petrifactive quality of force, two-fold always, is

essential to its nature; and a soul which has entered the province of

force will not escape this except by a miracle. Such miracles are rare

and of brief duration.

THE wantonness of the conqueror that knows no respect for any creature

or thing that is at its mercy or is imagined to be so, the despair of

the soldier that drives him on to destruction, the obliteration of the

slave or the conquered man, the wholesale slaughter — all these elements

combine in the Iliad to make a picture of uniform horror, of which force

is the sole hero. A monotonous desolation would result were it not for

those few luminous moments, scattered here and there throughout the

poem, those brief, celestial moments in which man possesses his soul.

The soul that awakes then, to live for an instant only and be lost

almost at once in force’s vast kingdom, awakes pure and whole; it

contains no ambiguities, nothing complicated or turbid; it has no room

for anything but courage and love. Sometimes it is in the course of

inner deliberations that a man finds his soul: he meets it, like Hector

before Troy, as he tries to face destiny on his own terms, without the

help of gods or men. At other times, it is in a moment of love that men

discover their souls — and there is hardly any form of pure love known

to humanity of which the Iliad does not treat. The tradition of

hospitality persists, even through several generations, to dispel the

blindness of combat.

The love of the son for the parents, of father for son, of mother for

son, is continually described, in a manner as touching as it is curt:

Even brotherly love:

Conjugal love, condemned to sorrow, is of an astonishing purity. Imaging

the humiliations of slavery which await a beloved wife, the husband

passes over the one indignity which even in anticipation would stain

their tenderness. What could be simpler than the words spoken by his

wife to the man about to die?

Not less touching are the words expressed to a dead husband:

The most beautiful friendship of all, the friendship between

comrades-at-arms, is the final theme of The Epic:

But the purest triumph of love, the crowning grace of war, is the

friendship that floods the hearts of mortal enemies. Before it a

murdered son or a murdered friend no longer cries out for vengeance.

Before it--even more miraculous — the distance between benefactor and

suppliant, between victor and vanquished, shrinks to nothing:

These moments of grace are rare in the Iliad, but they are enough to

make us feel with sharp regret what it is that violence has killed and

will kill again.

However, such a heaping-up of violent deeds would have a frigid effect,

were it not for the note of incurable bitterness that continually makes

itself heard, though often only a single word marks its presence, often

a mere stroke of the verse, or a run-on line. It is in this that the

Iliad is absolutely unique, in this bitterness that proceeds from

tenderness and that spreads over the whole human race, impartial as

sunlight. Never does the tone lose its coloring of bitterness; yet never

does the bitterness drop into lamentation. Justice and love, which have

hardly any place in this study of extremes and of unjust acts of

violence, nevertheless bathe the work in their light without ever

becoming noticeable themselves, except as a kind of accent. Nothing

precious is scorned, whether or not death is its destiny; everyone’s

unhappiness is laid bare without dissimulation or disdain; no man is set

above or below the condition common to all men; whatever is destroyed is

regretted. Victors and vanquished are brought equally near us; under the

same head, both are seen as counterparts of the poet, and the listener

as well. If there is any difference, it is that the enemy’s misfortunes

are possibly more sharply felt.

And what accents echo the fate of the lad Achilles sold at Lemnos!

And the fate of Euphorbus, who saw only a single day of war.

When Hector is lamented:

In these few words, chastity appears, dirtied by force, and childhood,

delivered to the sword. The fountain at the gates of Troy becomes an

object of poignant nostalgia when Hector runs by, seeking to elude his

doom:

The whole of the Iliad lies under the shadow of the greatest calamity

the human race can experience — the destruction of a city. This calamity

could not tear more at the heart had the poet been born in Troy. But the

tone is not different when the Achaeans are dying, far from home.

Insofar as this other life, the life of the living, seems calm and full,

the brief evocations of the world of peace are felt as pain:

Whatever is not war, whatever war destroys or threatens, the Iliad wraps

in poetry; the realities of war, never. No reticence veils the step from

life to death:

The cold brutality of the deeds of war is left undisguised; neither

victors nor vanquished are admired, scorned, or hated.

Almost always, fate and the gods decide the changing lot of battle.

Within the limits fixed by fate, the gods determine with sovereign

authority victory and defeat. It is always they who provoke those fits

of madness, those treacheries, which are forever blocking peace; war is

their true business; their only motives, caprice and malice. As for the

warriors, victors or vanquished, those comparisons which liken them to

beasts or things can inspire neither admiration nor contempt, but only

regret that men are capable of being so transformed.

There may be, unknown to us, other expressions of the extraordinary

sense of equity which breathes through the Iliad; certainly it has not

been imitated. One is barely aware that the poet is a Greek and not a

Trojan. The tone of the poem furnishes a direct clue to the origin of

its oldest portions; history perhaps will never be able to tell us more.

If one believes with Thucydides that eighty years after the fall of

Troy, the Achaeans in their turn were conquered, one may ask whether

these songs, with their rare references to iron, are not the songs of a

conquered people, of whom a few went into exile. Obliged to live and

die, “very far from the homeland,” like the Greeks who fell before Troy,

having lost their cities like the Trojans, they saw their own image both

in the conquerors, who had been their fathers, and in the conquered,

whose misery was like their own. They could still see the Trojan war

over that brief span of years in its true light, unglossed by pride or

shame. They could look at it as conquered and as conquerors

simultaneously, and so perceive what neither conqueror nor conquered

ever saw, for both were blinded. Of course, this is mere fancy; one can

see such distant times only in fancy’s light.

In any case, this poem is a miracle. Its bitterness is the only

justifiable bitterness, for it springs from the subjections of the human

spirit to force, that is, in the last analysis, to matter. This

subjection is the common lot, although each spirit will bear it

differently, in proportion to its own virtue. No one in the Iliad is

spared by it, as no one on earth is. No one who succumbs to it is by

virtue of this fact regarded with contempt. Whoever, within his own soul

and in human relations, escapes the dominion of force is loved but loved

sorrowfully because of the threat of destruction that constantly hangs

over him.

Such is the spirit of the only true epic the Occident possesses. The

Odyssey seems merely a good imitation, now of the Iliad, now of Oriental

poems; the Aeneid is an imitation which, however brilliant, is

disfigured by frigidity, bombast, and bad taste. The chansons de geste,

lacking the sense of equity, could not attain greatness: in the Chanson

de Roland, the death of an enemy does not come home to either author or

reader in the same way as does the death of Roland.

Attic tragedy, or at any rate the tragedy of Aeschylus and Sophocles, is

the true continuation of the epic. The conception of justice enlightens

it, without ever directly intervening in it ; here force appears in its

coldness and hardness, always attended by effects from whose fatality

neither those who use it nor those who suffer it can escape; here the

shame of the coerced spirit is neither disguised, nor enveloped in

facile pity, nor held up to scorn; here more than one spirit bruised and

degraded by misfortune is offered for our admiration. The Gospels are

the last marvelous expression of the Greek genius, as the Iliad is the

first : here the Greek spirit reveals itself not only in the injunction

given mankind to seek above all other goods, “the kingdom and justice of

our Heavenly Father,” but also in the fact that human suffering is laid

bare, and we see it in a being who is at once divine and human. The

accounts of the Passion show that a divine spirit, incarnate, is changed

by misfortune, trembles before suffering and death, feels itself, in the

depths of its agony, to be cut off from man and God.

The sense of human misery gives the Gospels that accent of simplicity

that is the mark of the Greek genius, and that endows Greek tragedy and

the Iliad with all their value. Certain phrases have a ring strangely

reminiscent of the epic, and it is the Trojan lad dispatched to Hades,

though he does not wish to go, who comes to mind when Christ says to

Peter: “Another shall gird thee and carry thee whither thou wouldst

not.” This accent cannot be separated from the idea that inspired the

Gospels, for the sense of human misery is a pre-condition of justice and

love. He who does not realize to what extent shifting fortune and

necessity hold in subjection every human spirit, cannot regard as

fellow-creatures nor love as he loves himself those whom chance

separated from him by an abyss.

The variety of constraints pressing upon man give rise to the illusion

of several distinct species that cannot communicate.

Only he who has measured the dominion of force, and knows how not to

respect it, is capable of love and justice.

The relations between destiny and the human soul, the extent to which

each soul creates its own destiny, the question of what elements in the

soul are transformed by merciless necessity as it tailors the soul to

fit the requirements of shifting fate, and of what elements can on the

other hand be preserved, through the exercise of virtue and through

grace — this whole question is fraught with temptations to falsehood,

temptations that are positively enhanced by pride, by shame, by hatred,

contempt, indifference, by the will to oblivion or to ignorance.

Moreover, nothing is so rare as to see misfortune fairly portrayed; the

tendency is either to treat the unfortunate person as though catastrophe

were his natural vocation, or to ignore the effects of misfortune on the

soul, to assume, that is, that the soul can suffer and remain unmarked

by it, can fail, in fact, to be recast in misfortune’s image. The

Greeks, generally speaking, were endowed with spiritual force that

allowed them to avoid self-deception. The rewards of this were great;

they discovered how to achieve in all their acts the greatest lucidity,

purity, and simplicity. But the spirit that was transmitted from the

Iliad to the Gospels by way of the tragic poets never jumped the borders

of Greek civilization; once Greece was destroyed, nothing remained of

this spirit but pale reflections.

Both the Romans and the Hebrews believed themselves to be exempt from

the misery that is the common human lot.

The Romans saw their country as the nation chosen by destiny to be

mistress of the world; with the Hebrews, it was their God who exalted

them and they retained their superior position just as long as they

obeyed Him. Strangers, enemies, conquered peoples, subjects, slaves,

were objects of contempt to the Romans; and the Romans had no epics, no

tragedies.

In Rome gladiatorial fights took the place of tragedy. With the Hebrews,

misfortune was a sure indication of sin and hence a legitimate object of

contempt; to them a vanquished enemy was abhorrent to God himself and

condemned to expiate all sorts of crimes — this is a view that makes

cruelty permissible and indeed indispensable. And no text of the Old

Testament strikes a note comparable to the note heard in the Greek epic,

unless it be certain parts of the book of Job.

Throughout twenty centuries of Christianity, the Romans and the Hebrews

have been admired, read, imitated, both in deed and word; their

masterpieces have yielded an appropriate quotation every time anybody

had a crime he wanted to justify.

Furthermore, the spirit of the Gospels was not handed down in a pure

state from one Christian generation to the next. To undergo suffering

and death joyfully was from the very beginning considered a sign of

grace in the Christian martyrs — as though grace could do more for a

human being than it could for Christ. Those who believe that God

himself, once he became man, could not face the harshness of destiny

without a long tremor of anguish, should have understood that the only

people who can give the impression of having risen to a higher plane,

who seem superior to ordinary human misery, are the people who resort to

the aids of illusion, exaltation, fanaticism, to conceal the harshness

of destiny from their own eyes. The man who does not wear the armor of

the lie cannot experience force without being touched by it to the very

soul.

Grace can prevent this touch from corrupting him, but it cannot spare

him the wound. Having forgotten it too well, Christian tradition can

only rarely recover that simplicity that renders so poignant every

sentence in the story of the Passion.

On the other hand, the practice of forcible proselytization threw a veil

over the effects of force on the souls of those who used it.

In spite of the brief intoxication induced at the time of the

Renaissance by the discovery of Greek literature, there has been, during

the course of twenty centuries, no revival of the Greek genius.

Something of it was seen in Villon, in Shakespeare, Cervantes, Moliere,

and — just once — in Racine. The bones of human suffering are exposed in

L’Ecole des Femmes and in Phedre, love being the context — a strange

century indeed, which took the opposite view from that of the epic

period, and would only acknowledge human suffering in the context of

love, while it insisted on swathing with glory the effects of force in

war and in politics. To the list of writers given above, a few other

names might be added. But nothing the peoples of Europe have produced is

worth the first known poem that appeared among them. Perhaps they will

yet rediscover the epic genius, when they learn that there is no refuge

from fate, learn not to admire force, not to hate the enemy, nor to

scorn the unfortunate. How soon this will happen is another question.