đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș john-moore-lived-poetry.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:26:32. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Lived poetry Author: John Moore Language: en Topics: Max Stirner, poetry, art, anti-politics, language Source: Retrieved on February 18, 2020 from https://www.manchesteropenhive.com/downloadpdf/9781526137289/9781526137289.00010.pdf
chapter, completed about two months before his death. Whilst we believe
that this stands as a finished piece in itself, because a substantial
proportion of the text is dependent on a translation of Max Stirnerâs
The ego and its own from the German, there are a number of areas which
we hoped to clarify prior to publication. This should not be seen as a
weakness, but more in the spirit of ongoing debates about the
relationship between theory, method and practice, which were always
central to Johnâs concerns. We have edited the chapter sparingly and in
keeping with the writing style to which many around the world have
become accustomed.
At the heart of the new anarchism(s) there lies a concern with
developing a whole new way of being in and acting upon the world.[1]
Contemporary revolutionary anarchism is not merely interested in
effecting changes in socioeconomic relations or dismantling the State,
but in developing an entire art of living, which is simultaneously
anti-authoritarian, anti-ideological and antipolitical. The development
of a distinctively anarchist savoir-vivre is a profoundly existential
and ontological concern and one rich in implication for the definition
of contemporary anarchist practice, activity and projects. Central to
this process is the issue of anarchist subjectivity and
intersubjectivity, as well as related concerns about language and
creativity.
Hakim Beyâs essay âOntological anarchy in a nutshellâ (1994) provides a
concise but landmark formulation of this issue. The opening passage of
the essay focuses on the existential status of the anarchist and
anarchist practice:
Since absolutely nothing can be predicated with any certainty as to the
âtrue nature of things,â all projects (as Nietzsche says) can only be
âfounded on nothing.â And yet there must be a project - if only because
we ourselves resist being categorized as ânothing.â Out of nothing we
will make something: the Uprising, the revolt against everything which
proclaims: âThe Nature of Things is such-&-suchâ. (Bey, 1994: 1)
Drawing upon Nietzschean perspectivism, Bey mounts an
anti-foundationalist argument: given the collapse of the philosophical
concept of truth, there is no foundation, no basis upon which anarchist
subjectivity or activity can be grounded - no foundation, that is,
except nothingness itself. Developing his perspective from this
epistemological premise, Bey identifies a distinctively anarchist mode
of being: ontological anarchy. The anarchist hangs suspended in space
above the abyss, certain of nothing except the nothing over which s/he
hovers and from which s/he springs. But this existential condition,
rather than a cause for despair, remains the source of limitless
freedom. For, as Bey indicates, âOut of nothing we will imagine our
values, and by this act of invention we shall liveâ (Bey, 1994: 1).
Being and nothingness are not binary oppositions in this formulation,
but elements of an overarching complementarity:
Individual vs. Group - Self vs. Other - a false dichotomy propagated
through the Media of Control, and above all through language . . . Self
and Other complement and complete one another. There is no Absolute
Category, no Ego, no Society - but only a chaotically complex web of
relation - and the âStrange Attractorâ, attraction itself, which evokes
resonances and patterns in the flow of becoming. (Bey, 1994: 3)
Nothing can be said about the nothingness underlying existence. Language
cannot penetrate and organise this space, except tentatively perhaps
through poetry and metaphor: âAs we meditate on the nothing we notice
that although it cannot be de-fined, nevertheless paradoxically we can
say something about it (even if only metaphorically): it appears to be a
âchaosââ. Through wordplay, through ludic and poetic language, Bey
attempts, not to define nothingness, but to evoke it. Nothingness
emerges in his account, not as an empty void, but as a chaos of
plenitude and abundance: âchaos-as-becoming, chaos-as-excess, the
generous outpouring of nothing into somethingâ. Or, to put it more
succinctly: âchaos is lifeâ. Binarist language, unable to constellate a
chaos which everywhere overflows its boundaries, seeks to control,
contain and domesticate it through the deployment of dualistic
categories. Against this language of order and stasis, Bey proposes the
language of poetry - a fluid language based on metaphor and thus
appropriate to the expression of the flows and patterns of passion,
desire and attraction which characterise chaos - and a âutopian poeticsâ
(Bey, 1994: 1-4).
Rooted in nothingness, the dynamic chaos that underpins existence,
anarchist subjectivity is a life-affirmative expression of becoming. For
Bey (1994: 1) âall movement . . . is chaosâ whereas stasis remains the
characteristic of order. But the anarchist subject is not merely a
subject-in-process, but a subject-in-rebel- lion, and as a result
remains nothing without a project. The anarchist affirmation of
nothingness simultaneously enacts a refusal of being categorised as a
(mere) nothing - or as a mere being. But, further, the anarchist
affirmation of nothingness is a ârevolt against everythingâ - in short
an insurrection against the totality, against the entire assemblage of
social relations structured by governance and control. In other words,
the anarchist project affirms nothing(ness) against everything that
exists, precisely because anarchy (or its synonym, chaos) is always in a
condition of becoming.
The anarchist subject - and by extension the anarchist project - is
necessarily in a constant state of flux and mutability. Characterised by
spontaneous creativity, anarchist subjectivity is marked for Bey by
imagination and invention, and hence finds its most appropriate mode of
expression in poetic language. Anarchist subjectivity emerges in his
work as a synonym for poetic subjectivity, and anarchist revolt as a
synonym for the immediate realisation of the creative or poetic
imagination in everyday life. Anarchy, in short, remains a condition of
embodied or lived poetry. The notion of lived poetry originates with the
situa- tionists, who contrast lived poetry with the language-form of the
poem. Lived poetry is a form of activity, not merely a mode of writing,
and springs up in moments of revolt and rebellion. It is life lived as
an act of spontaneous creativity and the complete embodiment of radical
theory in action (see Moore, 1997b; 2002).
The anarchist-as-poet aims to create and recreate the world endlessly
through motility and revolt. In part, this project becomes realisable
because the anarchist affirms (rather than denies) the nothingness that
underlies all things, and openly founds the anarchist project on this
nothing. This affirmation re-situates the individual within the matrix
of chaos and makes available - to itself and others - the plenitude of
its creative energy. Freedom consists of the capacity to shape this
creative energy in everyday life according to will and desire: âAny form
of âorderâ which we have not imagined and produced directly and
spontaneously in sheer âexistential freedomâ for our own celebratory
purposes - is an illusion.â (Bey, 1994: 2). But in order to achieve a
generalisation of chaos, the anarchist needs to form affinities and
create insurrectional projects based on these affinities: âFrom
Stirnerâs âUnion of Self-Owning Onesâ we proceed to Nietzscheâs circle
of âFree Spiritsâ and thence to Fourierâs âPassional Seriesâ, doubling
and redoubling ourselves even as the Other multiplies itself in the eros
of the group.â (Bey, 1994: 4). Anarchist subjectivity, then, is defined
by a complex web of interrelations between the autonomous individual,
passional affinities, and the matrix of chaos which âlies at the heart
of our projectâ. (Bey, 1994: 1). Anarchist subjectivity, in other words,
remains inseparable from anarchist intersubjectivity. The anarchist
project is formed through interactions that occur between those who
desire to dispel the illusory stases of order - those illusions which
obscure the unlimited creative potentials of chaos, which manifest
themselves as lived poetry in daily life. As Bey says of affinities
formed through free association: âthe activity of such a group will come
to replace Art as we poor PoMo bastards know it. Gratuitous creativity,
or âplayâ, and the exchange of gifts, will cause the with- ering-away of
Art as the reproduction of commoditiesâ (Bey, 1994: 4). Anarchy, a
condition of free creativity generated through motility and revolt, can
only be conceived and realised by the poetic imagination and, as far as
words are concerned, can only find expression in poetic language.
In Beyâs formulations, the anarchist subject is simultaneously unary,
multiple and heterogeneous. Under conditions of power, the multiplicity
of the subject is denied and erased. Through the production of
psychosocial stases, power manufactures an apparently unified identity
for each individual, containing and channelling otherwise free energies
on to the territories of governance and control. These stases of order
are illusory, however, in that the organised appearance of unitary
identity is based upon the introduction of division into the subject.
Power disrupts the free flows of energy within the holistic field of
subjectivity: it carves up this field and delimits the split subject,
divided from and turned against itself in ways which enhance profit
maximisation and social control. A language structured around binary
oppositions - and principally the polarity between self and other -
maintains a regime based on separation and alienation. Anarchist revolt
seeks to abolish all forms of power and control structures. In terms of
subjectivity, this project entails destruction of the illusions of a
separate self and recovery of a free-flowing and holistic sense of
subjectivity. Insurrection aims to dismantle staticity, overcome
blockages and put the subject back into process. As part of realising
this project, the anarchist uses poetic language in order to combat the
language of control and its sociolinguistic construction of the divided
self. For the anarchist, poetic language - in all its apparent
illogicality - provides the logical mode of expression for the creation
of a life of lived poetry, a means for breaking through the dominant
logic, and a repository for the savoir-vivre necessary to live in
conditions of chaos.
As a synthetic thinker, Bey constructs a bricolage of materials derived
from a variety of sources including anarchism, situationism,
existentialism and surrealism. However, his formulations concerning
ontological anarchy remain exemplary and indicative of the philosophical
underpinnings of the new anarchism(s). Although the range of sources
upon which he draws suggests that the ideational matrix from which the
new anarchism(s) emerge is not in itself particularly new, it is
nevertheless associated with newness.
In an important essay entitled âAnarchy as modernist aestheticâ, Carol
Vanderveer Hamilton (1995) has identified a discourse of anarchy which
runs through modernism and shapes and informs its aesthetics.
Subsequently obscured by liberal and Marxist interpretations of
modernism, Hamilton maintains that the discourse of anarchy structured
modernist representation through a cultural identification of the
signifier of the anarchist bomb with modernity. In modernism, then,
anarchy became a synonym for newness.
Hamiltonâs groundbreaking text opens up crucial issues, but given its
preliminary nature the discussion inevitably remains generalised.
Although the analysis is remarkably wide ranging, the focus on
propaganda by deed and the bomb as metonym for anarchism is ultimately
restrictive. Hamilton has crucially identified the existence of a
discourse of anarchy and established its significance within modernity,
yet in her account anarchism emerges as a seemingly uniform doctrine.
The reasons for this are not hard to detect. A survey of the anarchist
figures who are namechecked - notably Kropotkin, Goldman, Berkman, De
Cleyre and Reclus - suggests that the focus of Hamiltonâs essay is
effectively anarcho-communism. The Stirnerian individualist strand
within classical anarchism does not appear within Hamiltonâs discussion
of the discourse of anarchy, despite the widespread acknowledgement of
the influence of this strand on modernist thought and aesthetics.[2] In
the current context, this remains unfortunate, as it is clear that
Stirner remains not merely a crucial influence on modernist anarchism
and more generally on modernity, but (more importantly for current
purposes) also the key figure underpinning the new anarchism(s) in the
period of postmodernity. Even Murray Bookchin, the major ideological
opponent of the new anarchism(s), admits the latter point in his
splenetic survey of current developments within contemporary anarchy,
Social anarchism or lifestyle anarchism: an unbridgeable chasm
(Bookchin, 1995).[3] In order to understand the significance of Stirner
to both modernist anarchism and (more pertinently) the new anarchism(s),
the nature and significance of his thought needs to be radically
revised.
In The order of things and The archaeology of knowledge, Michel Foucault
develops a discursive archaeological methodology which âattempts to
study the structure of the discourses of the various disciplines that
have claimed to put forth theories of society, individuals, and
languageâ (Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982: 17).
To achieve this aim, he introduces the notion of the episteme, which he
defines as follows:
By episteme, we mean . . . the total set of relations that unite, at a
given period, the discursive practices that give rise to epistemological
figures, sciences, and possibly formalized systems . . . The episteme is
not a form of knowledge (connaissance) or type of rationality which,
crossing the boundaries of the most varied sciences, manifests the
sovereign unity of a subject, a spirit, or a period; it is the totality
of relations that can be discovered, for a given period, between the
sciences when one analyses them at the level of discursive regularities.
(Foucault, 1972: 191)
On this basis, Foucault then attempts to âisolate and describe the
epistemic systems that underlie three major epochs in Western thoughtâ:
the Renaissance, the Classical Age, and Modernity (Dreyfus and Rabinow,
1982: 18). In analysing these epistemic systems, however, he remains
largely concerned with the operations and regimes of power rather than
projects aimed at the abolition of power; and, where he is interested in
struggles against power, the struggles considered are usually of a
partial or reformist nature.[4]5 In examining any one epistemic system,
he is interested in conflicts and resistances, but the historical course
of these conflicts remain of limited concern, and he neglects entirely
to examine those discursive - and extra-discursive - practices which
seek to overthrow any ruling episteme and the social formation which it
articulates. In his account of modernity, for example, those anarchist
projects - and particularly the Stirnerian strain - which attempt to
initiate a total transformation of life are completely absent from
Foucaultâs discussion.
John Carrollâs seminal study Break out from the crystal palace: the
anarcho- psychological critique: Stirner, Nietzsche, Dostoevsky provides
an invaluable corrective to Foucaultâs failures, and indicates the
centrality of the Stirnerian - or what Carroll more broadly calls the
anarcho-psychological - critique to both the anarchist project and
modernity/postmodernity. Although he does not frame his analysis in
Foucauldian terms, Carrollâs study investigates the discursive conflicts
that took place within the emerging episteme of modernity during the
nineteenth century. Carroll focuses on the struggle that occurred
between what he variously terms three different intellectual,
theoretical or ideological traditions, competing social theories,
perspectives, world-views, or bodies of social theory (Carroll, 1974: 1,
2, 3, 6, 13, 14 passim). Two of these conflicting perspectives -
British, liberal, utilitarian rationalist social philosophy and Marxist
socialism - are well known and widely acknowledged elements of the
episteme of modernity. The third, however, the anarcho-psychological
critique, has been scandalously neglected and written out of accounts of
the formation of modernity.[5]
Carrollâs text restores the anarcho-psychological critique to its
rightful place as a key element in the discursive - and by extension,
extra-discursive - contestations over the modern/postmodern condition.
Break Out convincingly demonstrates that although the
anarcho-psychological critique has been obscured by the political
conflicts of the two dominant paradigms of capitalist liberal-ration-
alism and Marxist socialism, its antipolitics has acted as a persistent
underground presence, exerting a barely acknowledged and sometimes
unsuspected but often widespread influence. Taking Carrollâs analysis
further, it can be argued that with the collapse of the Marxist
paradigm, the anarcho-psycholog- ical critique is finally emerging from
its subterranean hideout and, in contemporary anarchy, catalysing the
breakout from the crystal palace of the control complex.
Carroll argues that the anarcho-psychological critique commences with
the publication of Stirnerâs Der Einzige und sein Eigentum in 1845
(translated as The ego and its own). This text âinaugurates the
reconstitution of philosophical debateâ and constitutes âa crossroads in
nineteenth-century intellectual historyâ (Carroll, 1974: 26, 88).[6] The
distinctive and innovative feature of Stirnerâs formulations in
particular and the anarcho-psychological critique in general remains its
emphasis on a unique ontology or, rather, an ontology of uniqueness:
At the basis of the philosophical innovations of Stirner and Nietzsche
is ontology: their radically new perspective on religion, on morals, on
political and social life, stems from their attitude to being. Their
entire work branches out from the stem conviction that there is a
primary order of reality about which all that can be said is that the
individual exists, that âI am!â The individual first exists, and then
begins to define himself [sic]. Essences, the communicable, socially
mediated dimension of individual character belong to the second order of
reality. Behind them lies an unconscious, irreducible, never realizable
or comprehensible force, an inviolable coherency: the individuum. This
is the ground of der Einzige, the unique one, the realm of what Stirner
calls his âcreative nothingâ. (Carroll, 1974: 39)
Carrollâs analysis proceeds from an examination of ontology to a
discussion of the epistemological anarchy developed within the
anarcho-psychological critique.
If this cluster of ideas seems familiar, this is because the
anarcho-psycholog- ical critique clearly underlies Hakim Beyâs
contemporary formulation of ontological anarchy in particular and the
new anarchism(s) more generally. Carroll makes it clear that the
antipolitics characteristic of the anarcho-psychological critique[7]
remains rooted in its ontological commitments, but this is evidently as
true for Bey as it is for Stirner:
The political anarchism of Stirner and Nietzsche is a logical
development of their ontological anarchism: their denigration of social
authorities represents one dimension of their endeavour to displace the
authority of essences and stress the primacy of the I. Both see the
springs of the human condition as anarchic, willful, problematical, a
complex of forces with their deeply individual source beneath the
superstructure of social mediation; both recognize what Plato referred
to as the âunutterableâ in each individual, a noumenal core which makes
of human thinking, of necessity, an isolated, introspective activity.
The social or essentialist superstructure is by itself lifeless; its
function is to provide the I with a means of expression. (Carroll, 1974:
39)
Stirner anticipates the Heideggerian/Sartrean emphasis on existence
preceding essence. In fact, âStirner illustrates how the individual ego,
whose ontological ground is simply the self-reflection that it exists,
is fettered as soon as it subordinates itself to qualities or essencesâ
(Carroll, 1974: 21). Historically, the Stirnerian ego comes to
consciousness in a world of socio-existential alienation. Historically
this is the case because, as Stirnerâs broad overview of history
indicates (1993: 15-151), individuals have always been subject to
governance, order and control. The anti-authoritarian insurrection
proposed in The ego and its own, however, aims to bring about a
historically unprecedented world in which socio-existential alienation
will be abolished. Born out of a creative nothingness (or
non-existence), the ego comes into existence by asserting itself,
affirming its existence - in other words, asserting the only thing
which, for the individual, has any ontological foundation: its self.
The subject, then, is self-created: it creates itself as an individual
by and through its assertion of its self. Language acquisition and use
remains crucial to this act of self-affirmation. In emerging from a
condition of non-existence to one of existence, a being issues forth
spontaneously, but then finds itself in a world requiring introspection
and self-reflection. Or, to put it another way: being emerges from a
condition of ineffability into a world of language. In some respects
this account of the construction of the self concurs with the theories
developed by Jacques Lacan (see Payne, 1993). However, on the issue of
language, the two thinkers diverge radically. Both agree that language
is the major force through which the individual is constituted and
structured. However, while Lacan maintains that the entry into language
entails a simultaneous submission to social authority, and the beginning
of alienation as the self passes from full self-presence to the
condition of absence characteristic of language systems predicated on
the signifier/signified division, Stirnerâs perspective on this issue
remains rather more radical.
Emerging from non-existence into self-consciousness, the Stirnerian
being creates itself as an individual by appropriating language: or,
more accurately, by appropriating in the first instance only those words
which it needs to bring itself into existence as an individual and
express its self-affirmation: I am! The Stirnerian being possesses the
(self-)confidence to undertake this act of (self-) assertion because, at
the deepest levels of being, it never becomes separated from the
creative nothingness which is the ontological (non-)ground of its
existence. The creative nothingness of the unutterable void beneath all
existence underlies and precedes all notions of self, signifying
systems, social mediations and authority structures. But its
inexhaustible creativity remains a wellspring at the source of the
individual being and fills the latter with confidence in its capacities
and energy with which to fulfil its potentials:
I am owner of my might, and I am so when I know myself as unique. In the
unique one the owner himself returns into his creative nothing, of which
he is born. Every higher essence above me, be it God, be it man, weakens
the feeling of my uniqueness, and pales before the sun of this
consciousness. If I concern myself for myself, the unique one, then my
concern rests on its transitory, mortal creator, who consumes himself,
and I may say: âAll things are nothing to me.â (Stirner, 1993: 366)
This sonorous passage, the closing words of Stirnerâs symphonic The ego
and its own, articulates some key themes concerning the self-creation
and self-realisation of the individual. The individual is defined by the
capacity to own, and primarily by the ability to own him or herself -
that is to say, to dispose of the self and act in any way congruent with
oneâs will, desire or interest. Ownership of self is primary; other
forms of ownership are secondary and derive from this fundamental form.
As a subject-in-process (indeed, a subject-in-rebellion, for reasons
that will become apparent subsequently), the Stirnerian self is
constantly re-creating itself and revising its modes of activity in
accordance with its changing desires and interests, but throughout these
continual changes one constant persists: the need to own oneself or be
in a condition of ownness. Being in a condition of ownness means first
and foremost that an individual is able to draw upon the fund of
creative energies which are loaned to it by the nothingness at the basis
of its being. These energies are then available at the free disposal of
the individual. The capacity to make free and unhindered use of these
energies defines the individual as unique. The individual becomes a
unique one at the moment of self-reflexivity, in the instant in which
she or he realises his or her ownness.[8] The self-created individual
wilfully creates and destroys itself. Although the energies of the void
are inexhaustible, those energies loaned to the individual are finite.
The individual uses up those energies in its progress toward
self-realisation: it creates but also consumes and ultimately burns
itself out. The individual comes from nothing and returns to nothing.
The turning point in this voyage of self-creation and self-destruction
occurs at the apogee of its attainment. At the very moment when the
individual realises itself as unique, at the exact moment when the
maximum degree of individuation and differentiation has taken place,
then âthe owner himself returns into his creative nothing, of which he
is bornâ. But at the peak of its powers the individual is less like a
comet than a sun - âthe sun of this consciousnessâ - a burning orb which
illuminates, by contrast, the dark void which contains it.
This process is set in motion with each individualâs primal assertion of
selfhood. By appropriating the words âI am!â, the Stirnerian self takes
ownership of language, or at least that little corner that she or he can
make their own at this stage of maturation. Confidently rooted in the
unutterability of the roots of its being, the Stirnerian individual
creates a self through owning language. The origins of selfhood are thus
indistinguishable from ownership. The self achieves its initial sense of
ownness through making language its own, and exalts in this first
victory of its will. The Stirnerian subject is neither intimidated nor
victimised by language as the individual is in the Lacanian schema. The
reasons for this are clear: the Stirnerian subject is not a split
subject, divided by language, because its identity is not wholly defined
by language, but remains rooted in the creative nothingness from which
it springs.[9] Hence the attitude of such a subject to language - as to
the world in general - is not one of victim or dependent, but that of
conqueror. Identity is not to be sought in and through language, because
it has not been lost; the Stirnerian subject does not need to search for
a self, but starts from it: âthe question runs, not how one can acquire
life, but how one can squander, enjoy it; or, not how one is to produce
the self in himself, but how one is to dissolve himself, to live himself
outâ (Stirner, 1993: 320).
However, in seeking self-realisation, the Stirnerian ego is immediately
confronted with other wills and forces which seek to delimit, contain
and control the self-willed individual, and hence âthe combat of
self-assertion is inevitableâ (p. 9). The Stirnerian ego maintains that
âNothing is more to me than myself!â (p. 5), but finds itself in a world
where power, in all its varied shapes and forms, wants the ego to accept
that âIt is more to me than myselfâ (p. 305). In such a world, conflict
remains inevitable unless the individual consents to submit to a life of
alienation, subordination and self-renunciation. âA human life,â the
opening chapter of The ego and its own, traces the stages of this
lifelong struggle which commences at birth: âFrom the moment when he
catches sight of the light of the world a man seeks to find out himself
and get hold of himself out of its confusion, in which he, with
everything else, is tossed about in motley mixtureâ (p. 9) (all italics
are from the original work). The ego is born into a world of illusions
which ensnare and blind the individual, and from which the ego must
disentangle itself if it is to realise itself. These delusions are
caused by the dominance of abstractions - what Stirner calls spooks
(âSpukeâ) - over concrete individuals. Abstractions - concepts, ideas,
beliefs and so on - that were once attributes and thus possessions of
individuals, now control their one-time owners, and crystallise as fixed
ideas which prevent the free flows of subjective will and desire. They
are, in short, power relations. Stirnerâs entire insurrectional
project - which, as Carroll indicates, is envisaged as a revolution
against the totality of power relations, not merely the State[10] - thus
directly derives from the ontological status of the individual. The
ramifications of this insurrectional project are manifold and beyond the
scope of this chapter. In what follows, attention will be limited to the
key issue of language.
Stirnerian ontology postulates a radical monism. The Stirnerian ego, as
indicated above, embodies a paradoxical reconciliation of opposites, as
it is simultaneously being and nothingness: a self-created autonomous
but ephemeral individual and an inexhaustible creative nothingness. The
crucial moment in the emergence of the former from the latter, however,
remains the simultaneous act of self-assertion and the subjectâs
insertion (or perhaps more accurately, incursion) into language. At this
moment, the primary instance of self-expression, but also the moment
when self-expression and self-assertion become identical, the ego moves
from the realm of the unutterable into the world of utterance (while
not, of course, entirely abandoning the former world). From that moment
onward, however, the ego increasingly discovers that the world of
utterance is characterised by conflict and delusion, and that she or he
must adopt a combative stance and a contestatory mode of procedure if
self-realisation is to occur. In the first instance, this contestation
takes place within language or in activities whose structures and
parameters are defined through language. Language, then, becomes a key
area requiring mastery by the Stirnerian ego because it remains
essential to the devising of insurrectional projects.
The importance of language in Stirnerâs work cannot be overestimated.
The world of utterance (or, at least in historical terms, the world of
power) is a world haunted by spooks - disembodied ideas, principles and
concepts, abstractions which take the form of words. The spook is a
revenant who assumes the insubstantial shape of the dominant discourse,
the language of governance, before it manifests itself in more material
forms. It is the language of order, management, utility and rationality.
Hence, the ego seeks to find and express itself in a language of
insurrection, a language of radical otherness which negates dominant
discourses and their expressive modes, as well as embodying the egoâs
selfaffirmation in a style commensurate with its uniqueness.
Carroll refers to Stirnerâs âconstant concern with revitalizing
language, repossessing it as a creative forceâ (Carroll, 1974: 36).
Power drains language of its vitality and creativity: it captures words,
domesticates them, debilitates them, debases them, instrumentalises
them, makes them prosaic, so that they may act as a means for
maintaining social control. The Stirnerian ego seeks to liberate
language, or rather repossess it so that it once again becomes available
for the free self-expression and enjoyment of the individual. However,
it is not sufficient for the egoist merely to reappropriate an enervated
or aridly rationalistic language: in making language its own, the egoist
must regenerate and reinfuse it with the creativity which lies at the
depths of his/her being. The Stirnerian ego, in other words, transforms
language: she or he does not speak in the prosaic language of authority,
but in the only language suitable for an insurrection against authority:
the language of poetry.
Stirner dreams of a âliterature that deals blows at the State itselfâ
(1993: 226) and The ego and its own is an attempt to generate such a
text. Even in transla- tion,12 Stirnerâs distinctive, poetic style of
writing remains evident. Although it is a work of philosophy, it is not
composed in the âstiff, concept-stricturedâ writing style characteristic
of the discourse, but has instead a âhighly flexible aphoristic styleâ
full of âgaiety and buoyancyâ (Carroll, 1974: 27-35). As in many other
respects, Stirner anticipates Nietzsche in becoming the first
Dichterphilosoph (poet-philosopher), penning passages of pure poetry,
such as the following indictment of the egoâs historical self-alienation
and dispossession:
I, who am really I, must pull off the lion-skin of the I from the
stalking thistle-eater [Power]. What manifold robbery have I not put up
with in the history of the world! There I let sun, moon, and stars, cats
and crocodiles, receive the honour of ranking as I; there Jehovah,
Allah, and Our Father came and were invested with the I; there families,
tribes, peoples, and at last actually mankind, came and were honoured as
Iâs; there the Church, the State, came with the pretension to be I - and
I gazed calmly on all. What wonder if then there was always a real I too
that joined the company and affirmed in my face that it was not my you
but my real I. Why the Son of Man par excellence had done the like; why
should not a son of man do it too? So I saw my I always above me and
outside me, and could never really come to myself. (Stirner, 1993:
224-5)
Due to the central value placed upon creativity by Stirner, Carroll
maintains that âthe artist is the most appropriate paradigm for . . .
the egoistâ (1974: 4). But this formulation could equally be reversed so
that the egoist becomes the paradigmatic artist. However, the art with
which the egoist remains primarily concerned is the ars vitae (the art
of living) because as a subject in process (of constant self-creation) -
âI am every moment just positing or creating myselfâ - his/her life is a
work of art (Stirner, 1993: 150). But an authentic ars vitae remains
impossible without a certain savoir-vivre - and such knowledge can only
be born of reflection; hence, given the decisive role of language
acquisition to individuation for Stirner, the importance of the text as
a means for self-expression. The ars vitae and the ars poetica are not
antithetical in Stirner, but intimately interconnected.
Although presumably possessing some kind of genealogical link with the
eighteenth-century German Romantic prose poems of Novalis, The ego and
its own is appropriately sui generis. It is not a work of poetry in the
conventionally accepted sense of the term at the time of its
publication.[11] Nevertheless, it remains a work couched in poetic
language. In order to appreciate the significance of Stirnerâs
innovation and the magnitude of his achievement in this text, it is
necessary to relate The ego and its own to the analysis of literary
discourse undertaken by Julia Kristeva in Revolution in poetic language.
For Kristeva, poetic language and poetry are not coterminous: âneither
confined to poetry as a genre nor inclusive of all poetry, poetic
language inscribes the signifying process and manifests the negativity,
rejection, and heterogeneity of the subjectâ (in Payne, 1993: 40).
Poetic language âstands for the infinite possibilities of languageâ
whereas âall other language acts are merely partial realizations of the
possibilities inherent in âpoetic languageââ (in Roudiez, 1984: 2).
Kristevan textual analysis consists of investigating the relations
between two interdependent modalities within the signifying process that
constitutes language: the semi- otic and the symbolic. These modes
manifest two aspects of the subject. The semiotic refers to the rhythms,
flows and pulsations which play across and within the body of the
subject prior to language acquisition. Semiotic rhythms are never
entirely lost, even when they are overlaid and hidden by the symbolic -
the order and syntax characteristic of language. Indeed, Kristevan
textual analysis focuses on the interplay between semiotic and symbolic
dispositions within any text. When the symbolic disposition
predominates, a text becomes a phenotext, in other words bound by
âsocietal, cultural, syntactical, and other grammatical constraintsâ (in
Roudiez, 1984: 5); when the semiotic disposition predominates, a text
becomes a genotext, a space for the actualisation of poetic language, an
anarchic language which irrupts in rebellion against the constraints of
social and semantic order. âBy erupting from its repressed or
marginalised place and by thus displacing established signifying
practices, poetic discourse corresponds, in its effects, in terms of the
subject, to revolution in the socioeconomic orderâ (in Payne, 1993:
165).
Historically, commencing with the texts of Lautreamont and Mallarme in
the last third of the nineteenth century, Kristeva discerns in the work
of certain avant-garde writers a shift in emphasis towards the
deliberate creation of geno- texts which, by actuating the revolutionary
potential inherent in poetic discourse, brings about a revolution in
poetic language. This kind of avant-garde text âmay be interpreted as an
affirmation of freedom, as an anarchic revolt (even though it openly
advocates neither freedom nor revolution) against a society that extols
material goods and profitâ (in Roudiez, 1984: 3). This remains precisely
the problem which Kristeva, her focus inclined entirely on literary
texts, remains unable to resolve. Although it
dissents from the dominant economic and ideological system, the
[avant-garde] text also plays into its hands: through the text, the
system provides itself with what it lacks - rejection - but keeps it in
a domain apart, confining it to the ego, to the âinner experienceâ of an
elite, and to esotericism. The text becomes the agent of a new religion
that is no longer universal but elitist and esoteric. (Kristeva, 1984:
186)
The avant-garde text, lacking any commitment to revolutionary social
transformation at the level of content, confines its revolution to
language and form, and thus remains subject to recuperation. Equally,
the conventional political tract, failing to draw upon the revolutionary
capacities of poetic language, confines its incendiary appeals to the
level of content, and moreover stultifies itself by embodying them in
the language of order and rule. Opaque to one another, these two forms
of discourse remain trapped within their limitations and thus incapable
of enacting radical psychosocial transformation.
Kristeva borrows from Plato the term chora to designate the space which
Stirner calls âcreative nothingnessâ. The chora is âthe place where the
subject is both generated and negated, the place where his [sic] unity
succumbs before the process of charges and stases that produce himâ
(Kristeva, 1984: 28). Like the creative nothing, it remains
unrepresentable because it is impermeable to language: âalthough the
chora can be designated and regulated, it can never be definitively
positedâ (Kristeva, 1984: 26). âIndifferent to language, enigmatic and
feminine, this space underlying the written is rhythmic, unfettered,
irreducible to its intelligible verbal translation; it is musical,
anterior to judgment, but restrained by a single guarantee: syntaxâ
(Kristeva, 1984: 29). While language (and the realm of the symbolic in
general) tends to generate a fixed identity around the personal pronoun
I, the semiotic rhythms derived from the chora undermine these
tendencies and ensure a heterogeneous subjectivity which âcannot be
grasped, contained, or synthesized by linguistic or ideological
structuresâ (in Payne, 1993: 239). As a result, the heterogeneous
subject remains continually in process, free of the stases typical of a
unary subjectivity; but, further, in terms of representation, the
signifying practices produced by such a subject set off an âexplosion of
the semiotic in the symbolicâ (Kristeva, 1984: 69).
Kristevaâs discussion helps to clarify the revolutionary nature of the
charged poetic language which runs through The ego and its own as well
as the significance of Stirnerâs concern with subjectivity and the
emergence, formation and ongoing development of the subject. Stirnerâs
consideration of these issues, however, extends beyond issues of
subjectivity to encompass an interest in intersubjectivity and its role
in shaping the self and projects for self-realisation. Contrary to the
opinion of Stirnerâs detractors, the Stirnerian egoist is not an
isolated, selfish egotist. The egoist seeks self-realisation through
owning him/herself and thus becoming unique. But from the beginning this
project is thwarted, and thus the egoist declares war on society, the
State and all the other forms of power which attempt to obstruct or
limit his/her will to self-enjoyment. At a certain stage, however, the
egoist realises that she or he does not have the capacity to combat
Power on her/his own, but must link up with other egoists who are
similarly seeking self-realisation through free activity. Stirner
recommends that the egoist seek affinities within a union of egos. The
individual egoist cannot achieve self-realisation in isolation, nor
within current social arrangements, and so, through union, egoists
mutually pursue the insurrectionary project of âthe liberation of the
worldâ (Stirner, 1993: 305) - but each for entirely egoistic reasons.
Stirner does not regard the union, however, as merely an unavoidable and
perhaps unpleasant expedient, but as a mode of affinity rooted in the
subjectâs ontological condition:
Not isolation or being alone, but society, is manâs original state. Our
existence begins with the most intimate conjunction, as we are already
living with our mother before we breathe; when we see the light of the
world, we at once lie on a human beingâs breast again, her love cradles
us in the lap, spoon-feeds us, and chains us to her person with a
thousand ties. Society is our state of nature. And this is why, the more
we learn to feel ourselves, the connection that was formerly most
intimate becomes ever looser and the dissolution of the original society
more unmistakable. To have once again for herself the child that once
lay under her heart, the mother must fetch it from the street and from
the midst of its playmates. The child prefers the intercourse that it
enters into with its fellows to the society that it has not entered
into, but been born into.
But the dissolution of society is intercourse or union. A society does
assuredly arise by union too, but only as a fixed idea arises by a
thought . . . If a union has crystallized into a society, it has ceased
to become a coalition; for coalition is an incessant self-uniting; it
has become a unitedness, come to a standstill, degenerated into a
fixity; it is - dead as a union, it is the corpse of the union or the
coalition, it is - society, community. (Stirner, (1993: 305-6)[12]
In Kristevan terms, the Stirnerian subject can be seen to inhabit the
realm of the semiotic before and immediately succeeding birth.
Intimately connected with the chora, the motherâs body, the
pre-linguistic subject lives in a condition of immediacy. However, in
the course of time, this condition comes to be regarded as a
restriction, a limitation, a shackle. The subject, made aware of its
individuality through the self-assertion and self-reflexivity provided
by language acquisition, asserts its independence in order to quit a
narrow for a wider form of interdependence. The (speaking) subject
prefers (social/sexual) intercourse or union with companions in a sphere
that has been chosen or willed, rather than one that has been purely
given. Language, openly but playfully conflated with sexuality, provides
the means whereby erotic energies are directed away from the motherâs
body and into the space of the union.[13] However, as these energies
derive from the chora, they are not lost or denied, but incorporated
into the union. As a result, the union is not a fixed but a fluid mode
of practice. The subject is formed by the synergy of the diverse erotic
fluxes which flow in and through the intercourse of the union, just as
much as, if not more than, in the initial condition of sociality with
the mother. The union acts as a means for multiplying and magnifying as
well as diversifying these motile flows and directing them toward a
maximisation of uniqueness for each participant. Language more
specifically, poetic language - plays a central role in achieving this
aim. As a fluid mode of practice, the union requires a signifying
practice commensurate with its form. The union is not based on unanimity
(âunitednessâ) but resemblance - a resemblance of interests. If
metaphor, the basic figure of poetry, comprises a pattern of
resemblances, then the union is a living metaphor, an embodiment of
lived poetry, and the words spoken in the union are in the (m)other
tongue of poetic language.
In terms of representation, Kristeva claims that investments of erotic
energy in revolutionary or reactionary projects are âtextually enacted
processes that are manifested in prosody and syntaxâ (in Payne, 1993:
193). Although a close analysis of the physical, material aspects of the
language of The ego and its own would be necessary for purposes of
substantiating the presence of the genotext in Stirnerâs work, it is my
contention that this text constitutes a veritable embodiment of the
revolution in poetic language. Further, I maintain that Stirnerâs text
not only prefigures but initiates the revolution in poetic language
which Kristeva detects in late-nineteenth-century avant-garde writing.
Stirnerâs key role in the formation of the episteme of modernity has
already been established: his inauguration of the revolution in poetic
language can now be recognised as an important aspect of that epistemic
shift. Further still, I contend that Stirner has, in advance,
anticipated and resolved the issues which for Kristeva stultify the
revolutionary impetus in textual and by extension extra-textual terms.
These are large claims, but following Carrollâs recovery of Stirnerâs
unacknowledged but seminal participation in and influence on the
discursive formation of modernity/ postmodernity, I would go so far as
to claim that the insurrectionary impulse articulated and embodied in
The ego and its own constitutes - to adapt Conradâs term - the secret
agent of (modern) history. Although driven underground by the clash of
rival political ideologies for much of the twentieth century, the anti-
ideological antipolitics of this revolutionary perspective is once again
surfacing in the new anarchism(s). And the revolution in poetic language
at the core of its textuality remains central to its insurrectionary
purpose.
[12]Green, who has himself translated the opening passage of The ego and
its own, regards the standard Byington translation as âhopelessly
turgidâ (Green, 1989: 241). Editorsâ note: having referred to the
original German ourselves, we feel that Byingtonâs translation is a
reasonably faithful representation of Stirnerâs (complex and technical)
original; therefore, we would have sought to question and clarify John
Mooreâs (secondhand) claim here. Again, we believe that John would have
relished the debate.
[1] The usefulness of the term ânew anarchism(s)â - or indeed
âanarchismâ per se in the current context remains somewhat dubious. Like
many contemporary radical antiauthoritarians, Stirner refused any
reductive ideological labelling, and neither referred to himself as an
anarchist nor labelled his perspectives as anarchist. This label has
only retrospectively - and rather unfortunately - been appended to his
writings. Some contemporary radical theorists (notably Fredy Perlman)
have not only refused labelling but have distanced themselves from the
(classical) anarchist tradition. Others have attempted to define various
post-(classical) anarchist positions and terminologies. Bob Black, for
example, has posited a âType-3 anarchismâ, neither collectivist nor
individualist - a label which Hakim Bey has characterised as a useful
âpro-tem sloganâ (Bey, 1991: 62). Black also authored an essay with the
self-explanatory title âAnarchism and other impediments to anarchyâ and
in a subsequent critique of âanarcho-leftismâ termed contemporary
proponents of anarchy as âpost-leftist anarchistsâ (Black, 1997: 150).
Bey has similarly written an essay entitled âPost-anarchism anarchyâ (in
Bey, 1991) which distances contemporary anarchy from a moribund,
dogmatic and outdated classical anarchism, and has attempted to launch
the term âchaoteâ (a proponent of chaos) as an alternative to the term
âanarchistâ. In my 1998 essay âMaximalist anarchism/anarchist
maximalismâ, I adapted the terms âmaximalist anarchismâ and âminimalist
anarchismâ to draw a comparable distinction between the first wave of
(classical) anarchism which effectively climaxed at the moment of the
Spanish Revolution, and the second wave of post-Situationist anarchy
which emerged in the wake of May 1968 (Moore, 1998a). I have since
abandoned the use of the terms âanarchismâ and âanarchistâ in my
theoretical and creative work, although like Perlman, Black and Bey
(among others), I have retained the use of the word âanarchy.â
In the present chapter, however, I use the term âanarchistâ and the
label ânew anar- chism(s)â as a kind of shorthand and for the sake of
convenience. They are not necessarily the most accurate or suitable
terms, not least because they do not do justice either to Stirnerâs
thought or the range of contemporary radical antiauthoritarian
formulations, but they are perhaps the best currently available. Readers
should bear this caveat in mind.
[2] Malcolm Green, for example, notes that Stirner âwas forgotten until
the turn of the [twentieth] century when his work influenced among
others: Scheerbart, Hausmann, Wedekind, B. Traven, Shaw, Gide, Breton,
Picabia, Kubin, indeed the whole November 1918 generation, and later
Sartre, Camus and Heidegger. Also, of course, the Vienna Groupâ (Green,
1989: 241). This roll call of modernist figures influenced by Stirner
remains very selective, however, and excludes several major names (e.g.,
Nietzsche), as well as a diverse range of individuals and currents
within the radical anti-authoritarian milieu (e.g., John Henry Mackay,
Otto Gross, Albert Libertad, and the Bonnot Gang). Stirnerâs influence
on modernism should not - perhaps cannot - be underestimated.
In scholarly terms, Redding (1998) continues the tradition of
marginalising Stirner in terms of both anarchism and modernism, but Weir
(1997) and Antliff (1997, 2001) redress the balance somewhat by
re-establishing Stirnerâs significance in both discursive spheres and at
their points of intersection.
[3] âTodayâs reactionary social context greatly explains the emergence
of a phenomenon in Euro-American anarchism that cannot be ignored: the
spread of individualist anarchism . . . In the traditionally
individualist-liberal United States and Britain, the 1990s are awash in
self-styled anarchists who . . . are cultivating a latter-day
anarcho-indi- vidualism that I will call lifestyle anarchismâ (Bookchin,
1995: 8-9). Bookchinâs jaundiced and distorted account has rightly
received numerous trenchant critiques within the anarchist press,
notably Watson (1996) and Black (1997). The accuracy of his observation
concerning the resurgence of Stirnerian anarchist individualism, even
though he sees this as a negative phenomenon, cannot be contested.
[4] See for example pp. 211-13 of Foucaultâs âAfterword on âThe subject
and powerâ â in Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982) which focuses entirely on
âforms of resistanceâ (p. 211) - i.e., struggles which are essentially
negotiations with power instead of seeking its abolition.
[5] And accounts of anarchism too. Bookchin, for example, devotes
several ill-tempered pages vainly trying to dismiss individualist
anarchism or cast it as reactionary (Bookchin, 1995: 7-11).
[6] Others - notably, for Carroll, figures as diverse as Nietzsche and
Dostoevsky (but also Freud and the existentialists) - are to develop the
anarcho-psychological paradigm in various directions, which are beyond
the scope of this chapter, but Stirnerâs formulations are originary.
[7] On the contrast between politics and antipolitics, I refer the
reader to my text Anarchy and ecstasy: âby antipolitical I do not mean
an approach that pretends it has no ideological dimensions. I do,
however, mean an approach that is not political. The Concise Oxford
Dictionary defines politics as the âscience and art of governmentâ and
political as âof the State or its governmentâ. Political praxis, in this
definition, thus remains the ideology of governance, and as such it
remains appropriate to the shared discursive territory of the forces of
control and counter-control. In attempting to transcend that territory,
therefore, it is necessary to construct an antipolitics, an anarchic
praxis that is more germane for those whose aim is the dissolution, not
the seizure, of controlâ (Moore (1988: 5-6)).
[8] The issue of gender - i.e., the question of whether the Stirnerian
notion of the individual is gendered or whether it escapes gendering, as
well as the question of the relationship between language acquisition
and gender identity in Stirnerâs work - requires consideration in its
own right, and unfortunately lies beyond the scope of this chapter.
[9] The Stirnerian entity appears to be a divided or unary subject, but
might more appropriately be characterised as a heterogeneous subject.
Despite the emphasis in The ego and its own on the ego and uniqueness,
the Stirnerian subject is not unitary because it has no essence, no
basis in being. âNothing at all is justified by being. What is thought
of is as well as what is not thought of; the stone in the street is, and
my notion of it is too. Both are only in different spaces, the former in
airy space, the latter in my head, in me; for I am space like the
streetâ (Stirner, 1993: 341). The Stirnerian subject remains a space, a
void, within which heterogeneous desires, wills and impulses arise and
are then consciously owned. Hence Stirnerâs paradoxical
self-characterisation as âI the unspeakableâ or the assertion that
âneither you and [sic] I are speakable, we are unutterableâ (Stirner,
1993: 355; 311). In this way, Stirner eludes the Derridean charge of
logocentrism, despite the importance of the logos in his work.
[10] âStirner at times uses âStateâ as no more than a convenient
shorthand for supraindi- vidual authorityâ (Carroll, 1974: 136n).
[11] The specifically French tradition of the prose poem, made famous
later in the nineteenth century by Baudelaire, Lautreamont and Rimbaud,
seems to have been initiated by Aloysius Bertrand in 1842 - only three
years prior to the publication of The ego and its own â and is therefore
unlikely to have influenced Stirner.
[12] For sound rhetorical reasons, Stirner employs the same term -
âsocietyâ (âGesellschaftâ in the original) - to designate both the
mother-child relationship and the organised social aggregation of
individuals and groups.
[13] The dissolution of the initial mother-child âsocietyâ forms a
paradigm for the disintegration of (the totality of power relations
which comprise) society. For Stirner, however, society is a form of mass
psychological regression. Social formations arise when unions lose their
motility and become subject to stasis. The erotic energies invested in
the union are no longer fluid but âcrystallisedâ and fixed - or, rather
fixated on a reunion with the motherâs body. In contrast to the
life-affirming erotic drives characteristic of the union, society
constitutes a mass reactivation of death drives, a psychological atavism
whose sociopolitical expression is obedience to authority and support
for totalitarian projects (here, John is paraphrasing p. 306 of Stirner
(1993)).