💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › crimethinc-twelve-myths-about-direct-action.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:52:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Twelve Myths About Direct Action
Author: CrimethInc.
Date: 15th December 2004
Language: en
Topics: myths, direct action
Source: Retrieved on 9th September 2020 from https://crimethinc.com/2004/12/15/twelve-myths-about-direct-action

CrimethInc.

Twelve Myths About Direct Action

Direct action—that is, any kind of action that bypasses established

political channels to accomplish objectives directly—has a long and rich

heritage in North America, extending back to the Boston Tea Party and

beyond. Despite this, there are many misunderstandings about it, in part

due to the ways it has been misrepresented in the corporate media.

1. Direct action is terrorism.

Terrorism is calculated to intimidate and thus paralyze people. Direct

action, on the other hand, is intended to inspire and thus motivate

people by demonstrating the power individuals have to accomplish goals

themselves. While terrorism is the domain of a specialized class that

seeks to acquire power for itself alone, direct action demonstrates

possibilities that others can make use of, empowering people to take

control of their own lives. At most, a given direct action may obstruct

the activities of a corporation or institution that activists perceive

to be committing an injustice, but this is simply a form of civil

disobedience, not terrorism.

2. Direct action is violent.

To say that it is violent to destroy the machinery of a slaughterhouse

or to break windows belonging to a party that promotes war is to

prioritize property over human and animal life. This objection subtly

validates violence against living creatures by focusing all attention on

property rights and away from more fundamental issues.

3. Direct action is not political expression, but criminal activity.

Unfortunately, whether or not an action is illegal is a poor measure of

whether or not it is just. The Jim Crow laws were, after all, laws. To

object to an action on the grounds that it is illegal is to sidestep the

more important question of whether or not it is ethical. To argue that

we must always obey laws, even when we consider them to be unethical or

to enforce unethical conditions, is to suggest that the arbitrary

pronouncements of the legal establishment possess a higher moral

authority than our own consciences, and to demand complicity in the face

of injustice. When laws protect injustice, illegal activity is no vice,

and law-abiding docility is no virtue.

4. Direct action is unnecessary where people have freedom of speech.

In a society dominated by an increasingly narrowly focused corporate

media, it can be almost impossible to initiate a public dialogue on a

subject unless something occurs that brings attention to it. Under such

conditions, direct action can be a means of nurturing free speech, not

squelching it. Likewise, when people who would otherwise oppose an

injustice have accepted that it is inevitable, it is not enough simply

to talk about it: one must demonstrate that it is possible to do

something about it.

5. Direct action is alienating.

On the contrary, many people who find traditional party politics

alienating are inspired and motivated by direct action. Different people

find different approaches fulfilling; a movement that is to be

broad-based must include a wide range of options. Sometimes people who

share the goals of those who practice direct action while objecting to

their means spend all their energy decrying an action that has been

carried out. In doing so, they snatch defeat from the jaws of victory:

they would do better to seize the opportunity to focus all attention on

the issues raised by the action.

6. People who practice direct action should work through the

established political channels instead.

Many people who practice direct action also work within the system. A

commitment to making use of every institutional means of solving

problems does not necessarily preclude an equal commitment to picking up

where such means leave off.

7. Direct action is exclusive.

Some forms of direct action are not open to all, but this does not

necessarily mean they are without worth. Everyone has different

preferences and capabilities, and should be free to act according to

them. The important question is how the differing approaches of

individuals and groups that share the same long-term goals can be

integrated in such a way that they complement each other.

8. Direct action is cowardly.

This accusation is almost always made by those who have the privilege of

speaking and acting in public without fearing repercussions: that is to

say, those who have power in this society, and those who obediently

accept their power. Should the heroes of the French Resistance have

demonstrated their courage and accountability by acting against the Nazi

occupying army in the full light of day, thus dooming themselves to

defeat? For that matter, in a nation increasingly terrorized by police

and federal surveillance of just about everyone, is it any wonder that

those who express dissent might want to protect their privacy while

doing so?

9. Direct action is practiced only by college students/privileged

rich kids/desperate poor people/etc.

This allegation is almost always made without reference to concrete

facts, as a smear. In fact, direct action is and long has been practiced

in a variety of forms by people of all walks of life. The only possible

exception to this would be members of the wealthiest and most powerful

classes, who have no need to practice any kind of illegal or

controversial action because, as if by coincidence, the established

political channels are perfectly suited to their needs.

10. Direct action is the work of agents provocateurs.

This is another speculation generally made from a distance, without

concrete evidence. To allege that direct action is always the work of

police agent provocateurs is disempowering: it rules out the possibility

that activists could do such things themselves, overestimating the

powers of police intelligence and reinforcing the illusion that the

State is omnipotent. Likewise, it preemptively dismisses the value and

reality of a diversity of tactics. When people feel entitled to make

unfounded claims that every tactic of which they disapprove is a police

provocation, this obstructs the very possibility of constructive

dialogue about appropriate tactics.

11. Direct action is dangerous and can have negative repercussions

for others.

Direct action can be dangerous in a repressive political climate, and it

is important that those who practice it make every effort not to

endanger others. This is not necessarily an objection to it, however–on

the contrary, when it becomes dangerous to act outside established

political channels, it becomes all the more important to do so.

Authorities may use direct actions as excuses to terrorize innocents, as

Hitler did when the Reichstag was set afire, but those in power are the

ones who must answer for the injustices they commit in so doing, not

those who oppose them. Likewise, though people who practice direct

action may indeed run risks, in the face of an insufferable injustice it

can be more dangerous and irresponsible to leave it uncontested.

12. Direct action never accomplishes anything.

Every effective political movement throughout history, from the struggle

for the eight hour workday to the fight for women’s suffrage, has made

use of some form of direct action. Direct action can complement other

forms of political activity in a variety of ways. If nothing else, it

highlights the necessity for institutional reforms, giving those who

push for them more bargaining chips; but it can go beyond this

supporting role to suggest the possibility of an entirely different

organization of human life, in which power is distributed equally and

all people have an equal and direct say in all matters that affect them.