💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › albert-camus-the-myth-of-sisyphus.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:41:25. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Myth of Sisyphus
Author: Albert Camus
Date: 1955
Language: en
Topics: absurdism, philosophy, existentialism, Sisyphus, myths
Source: https://postarchive.files.wordpress.com/2015/03/myth-of-sisyphus-and-other-essays-the-albert-camus.pdf
Notes: Translated by Justin O'Brien

Albert Camus

The Myth of Sisyphus

Preface

For me “The Myth of Sisyphus” marks the beginning of an idea which I was

to pursue in The Rebel. It attempts to resolve the problem of suicide,

as The Rebel attempts to resolve that of murder, in both cases without

the aid of eternal values which, temporarily perhaps, are absent or

distorted in contemporary Europe. The fundamental subject of “The Myth

of Sisyphus” is this: it is legitimate and necessary to wonder whether

life has a meaning; therefore it is legitimate to meet the problem of

suicide face to face. The answer, underlying and appearing through the

paradoxes which cover it, is this: even if one does not believe in God,

suicide is not legitimate. Written fifteen years ago, in 1940, amid the

French and European disaster, this book declares that even within the

limits of nihilism it is possible to find the means to proceed beyond

nihilism. In all the books I have written since, I have attempted to

pursue this direction. Although “The Myth of Sisyphus” poses mortal

problems, it sums itself up for me as a lucid invitation to live and to

create, in the very midst of the desert.

It has hence been thought possible to append to this philosophical

argument a series of essays, of a kind I have never ceased writing,

which are somewhat marginal to my other books.

In a more lyrical form, they all illustrate that essential fluctuation

from assent to refusal which, in my view, defines the artist and his

difficult calling. The unity of this book, that I should like to be

apparent to American readers as it is to me, resides in the reflection,

alternately cold and impassioned, in which an artist may indulge as to

his reasons for living and for creating. After fifteen years I have

progressed beyond several of the positions which are set down here; but

I have remained faithful, it seems to me, to the exigency which prompted

them. That is why this hook is in a certain sense the most personal of

those I have published in America. More than the others, therefore, it

has need of the indulgence and understanding of its readers.

—Albert Camus, Paris, March 1955

for PASCAL PIA

O my soul, do not aspire to immortal life, but exhaust the limits of the

possible.

—Pindar, Pythian iii

The pages that follow deal with an absurd sensitivity that can be found

widespread in the age—and not with an absurd philosophy which our time,

properly speaking, has not known. It is therefore simply fair to point

out, at the outset, what these pages owe to certain contemporary

thinkers. It is so far from my intention to hide this that they Will be

found cited and commented upon throughout this work.

But it is useful to note at the same time that the absurd, hitherto

taken as a conclusion, is considered in this essay as a starting- point.

In this sense it may be said that there is something provisional in my

commentary: one cannot prejudge the position it entails. There will be

found here merely the description, in the pure state, of an intellectual

malady. No metaphysic, no belief is involved in it for the moment. These

are the limits and the only bias of this book. Certain personal

experiences urge me to make this clear.

The Myth Of Sisyphus

An Absurd Reasoning

Absurdity and Suicide

There is but one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is

suicide. Judging whether life is or is not worth living amounts to

answering the fundamental question of philosophy. All the rest— whether

or not the world has three dimensions, whether the mind has nine or

twelve categories—comes afterwards. These are games; one must first

answer. And if it is true, as Nietzsche claims, that a philosopher, to

deserve our respect, must preach by example, you can appreciate the

importance of that reply, for it will precede the definitive act. These

are facts the heart can feel; yet they call for careful study before

they become clear to the intellect.

If I ask myself how to judge that this question is more urgent than

that, I reply that one judges by the actions it entails. I have never

seen anyone die for the ontological argument. Galileo, who held a

scientific truth of great importance, abjured it with the greatest ease

as soon as it endangered his life. In a certain sense, he did right.[1]

That truth was not worth the stake. Whether the earth or the sun

revolves around the other is a matter of profound indifference. To tell

the truth, it is a futile question. On the other hand, I see many people

die because they judge that life is not worth living. I see others

paradoxically getting killed for the ideas or illusions that give them a

reason for living (what is called a reason for living is also an

excellent reason for dying). I therefore conclude that the meaning of

life is the most urgent of questions.

How to answer it? On all essential problems (I mean thereby those that

run the risk of leading to death or those that intensify the passion of

living) there are probably but two methods of thought: the method of La

Palisse and the method of Don Quixote. Solely the balance between

evidence and lyricism can allow us to achieve simultaneously emotion and

lucidity. In a subject at once so humble and so heavy with emotion, the

learned and classical dialectic must yield, one can see, to a more

modest attitude of mind deriving at one and the same time from common

sense and understanding.

Suicide has never been dealt with except as a social phenomenon. On the

contrary, we are concerned here, at the outset, with the relationship

between individual thought and suicide. An act like this is prepared

within the silence of the heart, as is a great work of art. The man

himself is ignorant of it. One evening he pulls the trigger or jumps. Of

an apartment-building manager who had killed himself I was told that he

had lost his daughter five years before, that be bad changed greatly

since, and that that experience had “undermined” him. A more exact word

cannot be imagined. Beginning to think is beginning to be undermined.

Society has but little connection with such beginnings. The worm is in

man’s heart. That is where it must be sought. One must follow and

understand this fatal game that leads from lucidity in the face of

existence to flight from light.

There are many causes for a suicide, and generally the most obvious ones

were not the most powerful. Rarely is suicide committed (yet the

hypothesis is not excluded) through reflection.

What sets off the crisis is almost always unverifiable. Newspapers often

speak of “personal sorrows” or of “incurable illness.” These

explanations are plausible. But one would have to know whether a friend

of the desperate man had not that very day addressed him indifferently.

He is the guilty one. For that is enough to precipitate all the rancors

and all the boredom still in suspension.[2]

But if it is hard to fix the precise instant, the subtle step when the

mind opted for death, it is easier to deduce from the act itself the

consequences it implies. In a sense, and as in melodrama, killing

yourself amounts to confessing. It is confessing that life is too much

for you or that you do not understand it. Let’s not go too far in such

analogies, however, but rather return to everyday words. It is merely

confessing that that “is not worth the trouble.” Living, naturally, is

never easy. You continue making the gestures commanded by existence for

many reasons, the first of which is habit. Dying voluntarily implies

that you have recognized, even instinctively, the ridiculous character

of that habit, the absence of any profound reason for living, the insane

character of that daily agitation, and the uselessness of suffering.

What, then, is that incalculable feeling that deprives the mind of the

sleep necessary to life? A world that can be explained even with bad

reasons is a familiar world. But, on the other hand, in a universe

suddenly divested of illusions and lights, man feels an alien, a

stranger. His exile is without remedy since he is deprived of the memory

of a lost home or the hope of a promised land. This divorce between man

and this life, the actor and his setting, is properly the feeling of

absurdity. All healthy men having thought of their own suicide, it can

be seen, without further explanation, that there is a direct connection

between this feeling and the longing for death.

The subject of this essay is precisely this relationship between the

absurd and suicide, the exact degree to which suicide is a solution to

the absurd. The principle can be established that for a man who does not

cheat, what he believes to be true must determine his action. Belief in

the absurdity of existence must then dictate his conduct. It is

legitimate to wonder, clearly and without false pathos, whether a

conclusion of this importance requires forsaking as rapidly as possible

an incomprehensible condition. I am speaking, of course, of men inclined

to be in harmony with themselves.

Stated clearly, this problem may seem both simple and insoluble. But it

is wrongly assumed that simple questions involve answers that are no

less simple and that evidence implies evidence.

A priori and reversing the terms of the problem, just as one does or

does not kill oneself, it seems that there are but two philosophical

solutions, either yes or no. This would be too easy. But allowance must

be made for those who, without concluding, continue questioning. Here I

am only slightly indulging in irony: this is the majority. I notice also

that those who answer “no” act as if they thought “yes.” As a matter of

fact, if I accept the Nietzschean criterion, they think “yes” in one way

or another. On the other hand, it often happens that those who commit

suicide were assured of the meaning of life. These contradictions are

constant. It may even be said that they have never been so keen as on

this point where, on the contrary, logic seems so desirable. It is a

commonplace to compare philosophical theories and the behavior of those

who profess them. But it must be said that of the thinkers who refused a

meaning to life none except Kirilov who belongs to literature,

Peregrinos who is born of legend,[3] and Jules Lequier who belongs to

hypothesis, admitted his logic to the point of refusing that life.

Schopenhauer is often cited, as a fit subject for laughter, because he

praised suicide while seated at a well-set table. This is no subject for

joking. That way of not taking the tragic seriously is not so grievous,

but it helps to judge a man.

In the face of such contradictions and obscurities must we conclude that

there is no relationship between the opinion one has about life and the

act one commits to leave it? Let us not exaggerate in this direction. In

a man’s attachment to life there is something stronger than all the ills

in the world. The body’s judgment is as good as the mind’s and the body

shrinks from annihilation. We get into the habit of living before

acquiring the habit of thinking. In that race which daily hastens us

toward death, the body maintains its irreparable lead. In short, the

essence of that contradiction lies in what I shall call the act of

eluding because it is both less and more than diversion in the Pascalian

sense. Eluding is the invariable game. The typical act of eluding, the

fatal evasion that constitutes the third theme of this essay, is hope.

Hope of another life one must “deserve” or trickery of those who live

not for life itself but for some great idea that will transcend it,

refine it, give it a meaning, and betray it.

Thus everything contributes to spreading confusion. Hitherto, and it has

not been wasted effort, people have played on words and pretended to

believe that refusing to grant a meaning to life necessarily leads to

declaring that it is not worth living. In truth, there is no necessary

common measure between these two judgments. One merely has to refuse to

he misled by the confusions, divorces, and inconsistencies previously

pointed out.

One must brush everything aside and go straight to the real problem. One

kills oneself because life is not worth living, that is certainly a

truth yet an unfruitful one because it is a truism. But does that insult

to existence, that flat denial in which it is plunged come from the fact

that it has no meaning? Does its absurdity require one to escape it

through hope or suicide—this is what must be clarified, hunted down, and

elucidated while brushing aside all the rest. Does the Absurd dictate

death? This problem must be given priority over others, outside all

methods of thought and all exercises of the disinterested mind. Shades

of meaning, contradictions, the psychology that an “objective” mind can

always introduce into all problems have no place in this pursuit and

this passion. It calls simply for an unjust—in other words, logical—

thought. That is not easy. It is always easy to be logical. It is almost

impossible to be logical to the bitter end. Men who die by their own

hand consequently follow to its conclusion their emotional inclination.

Reflection on suicide gives me an opportunity to raise the only problem

to interest me: is there a logic to the point of death? I cannot know

unless I pursue, without reckless passion, in the sole light of

evidence, the reasoning of which I am here suggesting the source. This

is what I call an absurd reasoning. Many have begun it. I do not yet

know whether or not they kept to it.

When Karl Jaspers, revealing the impossibility of constituting the world

as a unity, exclaims: “This limitation leads me to myself, where I can

no longer withdraw behind an objective point of view that I am merely

representing, where neither I myself nor the existence of others can any

longer become an object for me,” he is evoking after many others those

waterless deserts where thought reaches its confines. After many others,

yes indeed, but how eager they were to get out of them! At that last

crossroad where thought hesitates, many men have arrived and even some

of the humblest.

They then abdicated what was most precious to them, their life.

Others, princes of the mind, abdicated likewise, but they initiated the

suicide of their thought in its purest revolt. The real effort is to

stay there, rather, in so far as that is possible, and to examine

closely the odd vegetation of those distant regions. Tenacity and acumen

are privileged spectators of this inhuman show in which absurdity, hope,

and death carry on their dialogue. The mind can then analyze the figures

of that elementary yet subtle dance before illustrating them and

reliving them itself.

Absurd Walls

Like great works, deep feelings always mean more than they are conscious

of saying. The regularity of an impulse or a repulsion in a soul is

encountered again in habits of doing or thinking, is reproduced in

consequences of which the soul itself knows nothing. Great feelings take

with them their own universe, splendid or abject. They light up with

their passion an exclusive world in which they recognize their climate.

There is a universe of jealousy, of ambition, of selfishness, or of

generosity. A universe in other words, a metaphysic and an attitude of

mind. What is true of already specialized feelings will be even more so

of emotions basically as indeterminate, simultaneously as vague and as

“definite,” as remote and as “present” as those furnished us by beauty

or aroused by absurdity.

At any streetcorner the feeling of absurdity can strike any man in the

face. As it is, in its distressing nudity, in its light without

effulgence, it is elusive. But that very difficulty deserves reflection.

It is probably true that a man remains forever unknown to us and that

there is in him something irreducible that escapes us. But practically I

know men and recognize them by their behavior, by the totality of their

deeds, by the consequences caused in life by their presence. Likewise,

all those irrational feelings which offer no purchase to analysis. I can

define them practically, appreciate them practically, by gathering

together the sum of their consequences in the domain of the

intelligence, by seizing and noting all their aspects, by outlining

their universe. It is certain that apparently, though I have seen the

same actor a hundred times, I shall not for that reason know him any

better personally. Yet if I add up the heroes he has personified and if

I say that I know him a little better at the hundredth character counted

off, this will be felt to contain an element of truth. For this apparent

paradox is also an apologue. There is a moral to it. It teaches that a

man defines himself by his make-believe as well as by his sincere

impulses.

There is thus a lower key of feelings, inaccessible in the heart but

partially disclosed by the acts they imply and the attitudes of mind

they assume. It is clear that in this way I am defining a method.

But it is also evident that that method is one of analysis and not of

knowledge. For methods imply metaphysics; unconsciously they disclose

conclusions that they often claim not to know yet.

Similarly, the last pages of a book are already contained in the first

pages. Such a link is inevitable. The method defined here acknowledges

the feeling that all true knowledge is impossible. Solely appearances

can be enumerated and the climate make itself felt.

Perhaps we shall be able to overtake that elusive feeling of absurdity

in the different but closely related worlds of intelligence, of the art

of living, or of art itself. The climate of absurdity is in the

beginning. The end is the absurd universe and that attitude of mind

which lights the world with its true colors to bring out the privileged

and implacable visage which that attitude has discerned in it.

All great deeds and all great thoughts have a ridiculous beginning.

Great works are often born on a street-corner or in a restaurant’s

revolving door. So it is with absurdity. The absurd world more than

others derives its nobility from that abject birth.

In certain situations, replying “nothing” when asked what one is

thinking about may be pretense in a man. Those who are loved are well

aware of this. But if that reply is sincere, if it symbolizes that odd

state of soul in which the void be-comes eloquent, in which the chain of

daily gestures is broken, in which the heart vainly seeks the link that

will connect it again, then it is as it were the first sign of

absurdity.

It happens that the stage sets collapse. Rising, streetcar, four hours

in the office or the factory, meal, streetcar, four hours of work, meal,

sleep, and Monday Tuesday Wednesday Thursday Friday and Saturday

according to the same rhythm—this path is easily followed most of the

time. But one day the “why” arises and everything begins in that

weariness tinged with amazement.

“Begins”—this is important. Weariness comes at the end of the acts of a

mechanical life, but at the same time it inaugurates the impulse of

consciousness. It awakens consciousness and provokes what follows. What

follows is the gradual return into the chain or it is the definitive

awakening. At the end of the awakening comes, in time, the consequence:

suicide or recovery. In itself weariness has something sickening about

it. Here, I must conclude that it is good.

For everything be-gins with consciousness and nothing is worth anything

except through it. There is nothing original about these remarks. But

they are obvious; that is enough for a while, during a sketchy

reconnaissance in the origins of the absurd. Mere “anxiety,” as

Heidegger says, is at the source of everything.

Likewise and during every day of an unillustrious life, time carries us.

But a moment always comes when we have to carry it.

We live on the future: “tomorrow,” “later on,” “when you have made your

way,” “you will understand when you are old enough.”

Such irrelevancies are wonderful, for, after all, it’s a matter of

dying. Yet a day comes when a man notices or says that he is thirty.

Thus he asserts his youth. But simultaneously he situates himself in

relation to time. He takes his place in it. He admits that he stands at

a certain point on a curve that he acknowledges having to travel to its

end. He belongs to time, and by the horror that seizes him, he

recognizes his worst enemy. Tomorrow, he was longing for tomorrow,

whereas everything in him ought to reject it.

That revolt of the flesh is the absurd.[4]

A step lower and strangeness creeps in: perceiving that the world is

“dense,” sensing to what a degree a stone is foreign and irreducible to

us, with what intensity nature or a landscape can negate us. At the

heart of all beauty lies something inhuman, and these hills, the

softness of the sky, the outline of these trees at this very minute lose

the illusory meaning with which we had clothed them, henceforth more

remote than a lost paradise. The primitive hostility of the world rises

up to face us across millennia, for a second we cease to understand it

because for centuries we have understood in it solely the images and

designs that we had attributed to it beforehand, because henceforth we

lack the power to make use of that artifice. The world evades us because

it becomes itself again. That stage scenery masked by habit becomes

again what it is. It withdraws at a distance from us. Just as there are

days when under the familial face of a woman, we see as a stranger her

we had loved months or years ago, perhaps we shall come even to desire

what suddenly leaves us so alone. But the time has not yet come. Just

one thing: that denseness and that strangeness of the world is the

absurd.

Men, too, secrete the inhuman. At certain moments of lucidity, the

mechanical aspect of their gestures, their meaningless pantomime makes

silly everything that surrounds them. A man is talking on the telephone

behind a glass partition; you cannot hear him, but you see his

incomprehensible dumb show: you wonder why he is alive. This discomfort

in the face of man’s own inhumanity, this incalculable tumble before the

image of what we are, this “nausea,” as a writer of today calls it, is

also the absurd.

Likewise the stranger who at certain seconds comes to meet us in a

mirror, the familiar and yet alarming brother we encounter in our own

photographs is also the absurd.

I come at last to death and to the attitude we have toward it. On this

point everything has been said and it is only proper to avoid pathos.

Yet one will never be sufficiently surprised that everyone lives as if

no one “knew.” This is because in reality there is no experience of

death. Properly speaking, nothing has been experienced but what has been

lived and made conscious. Here, it is barely possible to speak of the

experience of others’ deaths. It is a substitute, an illusion, and it

never quite convinces us. That melancholy convention cannot be

persuasive. The horror comes in reality from the mathematical aspect of

the event. If time frightens us, this is because it works out the

problem and the solution comes afterward. All the pretty speeches about

the soul will have their contrary convincingly proved, at least for a

time. From this inert body on which a slap makes no mark the soul has

disappeared.

This elementary and definitive aspect of the adventure constitutes the

absurd feeling. Under the fatal lighting of that destiny, its

uselessness becomes evident. No code of ethics and no effort are

justifiable a priori in the face of the cruel mathematics that command

our condition.

Let me repeat: all this has been said over and over. I am limiting

myself here to making a rapid classification and to pointing out these

obvious themes. They run through all literatures and all philosophies.

Everyday conversation feeds on them. There is no question of reinventing

them. But it is essential to be sure of these facts in order to be able

to question oneself subsequently on the primordial question. I am

interested let me repeat again—not go much in absurd discoveries as in

their consequences. If one is assured of these facts, what is one to

conclude, how far is one to go to elude nothing? Is one to die

voluntarily or to hope in spite of everything? Beforehand, it is

necessary to take the same rapid inventory on the plane of the

intelligence.

The mind’s first step is to distinguish what is true from what is false.

However, as soon as thought reflects on itself, what it first discovers

is a contradiction. Useless to strive to be convincing in this case.

Over the centuries no one has furnished a clearer and more elegant

demonstration of the business than Aristotle: “The often ridiculed

consequence of these opinions is that they destroy themselves. For by

asserting that all is true we assert the truth of the contrary assertion

and consequently the falsity of our own thesis (for the contrary

assertion does not admit that it can be true).

And if one says that all is false, that assertion is itself false. If we

declare that solely the assertion opposed to ours is false or else that

solely ours is not false, we are nevertheless forced to admit an

infinite number of true or false judgments. For the one who expresses a

true assertion proclaims simultaneously that it is true, and so on ad

infinitum.”

This vicious circle is but the first of a series in which the mind that

studies itself gets lost in a giddy whirling. The very simplicity of

these paradoxes makes them irreducible. Whatever may be the plays on

words and the acrobatics of logic, to understand is, above all, to

unify. The mind’s deepest desire, even in its most elaborate operations,

parallels man’s unconscious feeling in the face of his universe: it is

an insistence upon familiarity, an appetite for clarity.

Understanding the world for a man is reducing it to the human, stamping

it with his seal. The cat’s universe is not the universe of the anthill.

The truism “All thought is anthropomorphic” has no other meaning.

Likewise, the mind that aims to understand reality can consider itself

satisfied only by reducing it to terms of thought.

If man realized that the universe like him can love and suffer, he would

be reconciled. If thought discovered in the shimmering mirrors of

phenomena eternal relations capable of summing them up and summing

themselves up in a single principle, then would be seen an intellectual

joy of which the myth of the blessed would be but a ridiculous

imitation. That nostalgia for unity, that appetite for the absolute

illustrates the essential impulse of the human drama.

But the fact of that nostalgia’s existence does not imply that it is to

be immediately satisfied. For if, bridging the gulf that separates

desire from conquest, we assert with Parmenides the reality of the One

(whatever it may be), we fall into the ridiculous contradiction of a

mind that asserts total unity and proves by its very assertion its own

difference and the diversity it claimed to resolve. This other vicious

circle is enough to stifle our hopes.

These are again truisms. I shall again repeat that they are not

interesting in themselves but in the consequences that can be deduced

from them. I know another truism: it tells me that man is mortal. One

can nevertheless count the minds that have deduced the extreme

conclusions from it. It is essential to consider as a constant point of

reference in this essay the regular hiatus between what we fancy we know

and what we really know, practical assent and simulated ignorance which

allows us to live with ideas which, if we truly put them to the test,

ought to upset our whole life. Faced with this inextricable

contradiction of the mind, we shall fully grasp the divorce separating

us from our own creations. So long as the mind keeps silent in the

motionless world of its hopes, everything is reflected and arranged in

the unity of its nostalgia.

But with its first move this world cracks and tumbles: an infinite

number of shimmering fragments is offered to the understanding. We must

despair of ever reconstructing the familiar, calm surface which would

give us peace of heart. After so many centuries of inquiries, so many

abdications among thinkers, we are well aware that this is true for all

our knowledge. With the exception of professional rationalists, today

people despair of true knowledge. If the only significant history of

human thought were to be written, it would have to be the history of its

successive regrets and its impotences.

Of whom and of what indeed can I say: “I know that!” This heart within

me I can feel, and I judge that it exists. This world I can touch, and I

likewise judge that it exists. There ends all my knowledge, and the rest

is construction. For if I try to seize this self of which I feel sure,

if I try to define and to summarize it, it is nothing but water slipping

through my fingers. I can sketch one by one all the aspects it is able

to assume, all those likewise that have been attributed to it, this

upbringing, this origin, this ardor or these silences, this nobility or

this vileness. But aspects cannot be added up. This very heart which is

mine will forever remain indefinable to me. Between the certainty I have

of my existence and the content I try to give to that assurance, the gap

will never be filled.

Forever I shall be a stranger to myself. In psychology as in logic,

there are truths but no truth. Socrates’”Know thyself” has as much value

as the “Be virtuous” of our confessionals. They reveal a nostalgia at

the same time as an ignorance. They are sterile exercises on great

subjects. They are legitimate only in precisely so far as they are

approximate.

And here are trees and I know their gnarled surface, water and I feel

its taste. These scents of grass and stars at night, certain evenings

when the heart relaxes—how shall I negate this world whose power and

strength I feel? Yet all the knowledge on earth will give me nothing to

assure me that this world is mine. You describe it to me and you teach

me to classify it. You enumerate its laws and in my thirst for knowledge

I admit that they are true. You take apart its mechanism and my hope

increases. At the final stage you teach me that this wondrous and

multicolored universe can be reduced to the atom and that the atom

itself can be reduced to the electron. All this is good and I wait for

you to continue. But you tell me of an invisible planetary system in

which electrons gravitate around a nucleus. You explain this world to me

with an image. I realize then that you have been reduced to poetry: I

shall never know. Have I the time to become indignant? You have already

changed theories. So that science that was to teach me everything ends

up in a hypothesis, that lucidity founders in metaphor, that uncertainty

is resolved in a work of art. What need had I of so many efforts? The

soft lines of these hills and the hand of evening on this troubled heart

teach me much more. I have returned to my beginning. I realize that if

through science I can seize phenomena and enumerate them, I cannot, for

all that, apprehend the world. Were I to trace its entire relief with my

finger, I should not know any more. And you give me the choice between a

description that is sure but that teaches me nothing and hypotheses that

claim to teach me but that are not sure. A stranger to myself and to the

world, armed solely with a thought that negates itself as soon as it

asserts, what is this condition in which I can have peace only by

refusing to know and to live, in which the appetite for conquest bumps

into walls that defy its assaults? To will is to stir up paradoxes.

Everything is ordered in such a way as to bring into being that poisoned

peace produced by thoughtlessness, lack of heart, or fatal

renunciations.

Hence the intelligence, too, tells me in its way that this world is

absurd. Its contrary, blind reason, may well claim that all is clear; I

was waiting for proof and longing for it to be right. But despite so

many pretentious centuries and over the heads of so many eloquent and

persuasive men, I know that is false. On this plane, at least, there is

no happiness if I cannot know. That universal reason, practical or

ethical, that determinism, those categories that explain everything are

enough to make a decent man laugh. They have nothing to do with the

mind. They negate its profound truth, which is to be enchained. In this

unintelligible and limited universe, man’s fate henceforth assumes its

meaning. A horde of irrationals has sprung up and surrounds him until

his ultimate end. In his recovered and now studied lucidity, the feeling

of the absurd becomes clear and definite. I said that the world is

absurd, but I was too hasty. This world in itself is not reasonable,

that is all that can be said. But what is absurd is the confrontation of

this irrational and the wild longing for clarity whose call echoes in

the human heart. The absurd depends as much on man as on the world.

For the moment it is all that links them together. It binds them one to

the other as only hatred can weld two creatures together. This is all I

can discern clearly in this measureless universe where my adventure

takes place. Let us pause here. If I hold to be true that absurdity that

determines my relationship with life, if I become thoroughly imbued with

that sentiment that seizes me in face of the world’s scenes, with that

lucidity imposed on me by the pursuit of a science, I must sacrifice

everything to these certainties and I must see them squarely to be able

to maintain them. Above all, I must adapt my behavior to them and pursue

them in all their consequences. I am speaking here of decency. But I

want to know beforehand if thought can live in those deserts.

I already know that thought has at least entered those deserts.

There it found its bread. There it realized that it had previously been

feeding on phantoms. It justified some of the most urgent themes of

human reflection.

From the moment absurdity is recognized, it becomes a passion, the most

harrowing of all. But whether or not one can live with one’s passions,

whether or not one can accept their law, which is to burn the heart they

simultaneously exalt—that is the whole question. It is not, however, the

one we shall ask just yet. It stands at the center of this experience.

There will be time to come back to it. Let us recognize rather those

themes and those impulses born of the desert. It will suffice to

enumerate them. They, too, are known to all today. There have always

been men to defend the rights of the irrational. The tradition of what

may be called humiliated thought has never ceased to exist. The

criticism of rationalism has been made so often that it seems

unnecessary to begin again. Yet our epoch is marked by the rebirth of

those paradoxical systems that strive to trip up the reason as if truly

it had always forged ahead. But that is not so much a proof of the

efficacy of the reason as of the intensity of its hopes. On the plane of

history, such a constancy of two attitudes illustrates the essential

passion of man torn between his urge toward unity and the clear vision

he may have of the walls enclosing him.

But never perhaps at any time has the attack on reason been more violent

than in ours. Since Zarathustra’s great outburst: “By chance it is the

oldest nobility in the world. I conferred it upon all things when I

proclaimed that above them no eternal will was exercised,” since

Kierkegaard’s fatal illness, “that malady that leads to death with

nothing else following it,” the significant and tormenting themes of

absurd thought have followed one another.

Or at least, and this proviso is of capital importance, the themes of

irrational and religious thought. From Jaspers to Heidegger, from

Kierkegaard to Che-stov, from the phenomenologists to Scheler, on the

logical plane and on the moral plane, a whole family of minds related by

their nostalgia but opposed by their methods or their aims, have

persisted in blocking the royal road of reason and in recovering the

direct paths of truth. Here I assume these thoughts to be known and

lived. Whatever may be or have been their ambitions, all started out

from that indescribable universe where contradiction, antinomy, anguish,

or impotence reigns. And what they have in common is precisely the

themes so far disclosed.

For them, too, it must be said that what matters above all is the

conclusions they have managed to draw from those discoveries. That

matters so much that they must be examined separately. But for the

moment we are concerned solely with their discoveries and their initial

experiments. We are concerned solely with noting their agreement. If it

would be presumptuous to try to deal with their philosophies, it is

possible and sufficient in any case to bring out the climate that is

common to them.

Heidegger considers the human condition coldly and announces that that

existence is humiliated. The only reality is “anxiety” in the whole

chain of beings. To the man lost in the world and its diversions this

anxiety is a brief, fleeting fear. But if that fear becomes conscious of

itself, it becomes anguish, the perpetual climate of the lucid man “in

whom existence is concentrated.” This professor of philosophy writes

without trembling and in the most abstract language in the world that

“the finite and limited character of human existence is more primordial

than man himself.” His interest in Kant extends only to recognizing the

restricted character of his “pure Reason.” This is to coincide at the

end of his analyses that “the world can no longer offer anything to the

man filled with anguish.” This anxiety seems to him so much more

important than all the categories in the world that he thinks and talks

only of it. He enumerates its aspects: boredom when the ordinary man

strives to quash it in him and benumb it; terror when the mind

contemplates death. He too does not separate consciousness from the

absurd. The consciousness of death is the call of anxiety and “existence

then delivers itself its own summons through the intermediary of

consciousness.” It is the very voice of anguish and it adjures existence

“to return from its loss in the anonymous They.” For him, too, one must

not sleep, but must keep alert until the consummation. He stands in this

absurd world and points out its ephemeral character. He seeks his way

amid these ruins.

Jaspers despairs of any ontology because he claims that we have lost

“naivete.” He knows that we can achieve nothing that will transcend the

fatal game of appearances. He knows that the end of the mind is failure.

He tarries over the spiritual adventures revealed by history and

pitilessly discloses the flaw in each system, the illusion that saved

everything, the preaching that hid nothing.

In this ravaged world in which the impossibility of knowledge is

established, in which everlasting nothingness seems the only reality and

irremediable despair seems the only attitude, he tries to recover the

Ariadne’s thread that leads to divine secrets.

Chestov, for his part, throughout a wonderfully monotonous work,

constantly straining toward the same truths, tirelessly demonstrates

that the tightest system, the most universal rationalism always stumbles

eventually on the irrational of human thought. None of the ironic facts

or ridiculous contradictions that depreciate the reason escapes him. One

thing only interests him, and that is the exception, whether in the

domain of the heart or of the mind. Through the Dostoevskian experiences

of the condemned man, the exacerbated adventures of the Nietzschean

mind, Hamlet’s imprecations, or the bitter aristocracy of an Ibsen, he

tracks down, il-luminates, and magnifies the human revolt against the

irremediable. He refuses the reason its reasons and begins to advance

with some decision only in the middle of that colorless desert where all

certainties have become stones.

Of all perhaps the most engaging, Kierkegaard, for a part of his

existence at least, does more than discover the absurd, he lives it.

The man who writes: “The surest of stubborn silences is not to hold

one’s tongue but to talk” makes sure in the beginning that no truth is

absolute or can render satisfactory an existence that is impossible in

itself. Don Juan of the understanding, he multiplies pseudonyms and

contradictions, writes his Discourses of Edification at the same time as

that manual of cynical spiritualism, The Diary of the Seducer. He

refuses consolations, ethics, reliable principles. As for that thorn he

feels in his heart, he is careful not to quiet its pain. On the

contrary, he awakens it and, in the desperate joy of a man crucified and

happy to be so, he builds up piece by piece—lucidity, refusal, make

believe—a category of the man possessed. That face both tender and

sneering, those pirouettes followed by a cry from the heart are the

absurd spirit itself grappling with a reality beyond its comprehension.

And the spiritual adventure that leads Kierkegaard to his beloved

scandals begins likewise in the chaos of an experience divested of its

setting and relegated to its original incoherence.

On quite a different plane, that of method, Husserl and the

phenomenologists, by their very extravagances, reinstate the world in

its diversity and deny the transcendent power of the reason. The

spiritual universe becomes incalculably enriched through them.

The rose petal, the milestone, or the human hand are as important as

love, desire, or the laws of gravity. Thinking ceases to be unifying or

making a semblance familiar in the guise of a major principle. Thinking

is learning all over again to see, to be attentive, to focus

consciousness; it is turning every idea and every image, in the manner

of Proust, into a privileged moment. What justifies thought is its

extreme consciousness. Though more positive than Kierkegaard’s or

Chestov’s, Husserl’s manner of proceeding, in the beginning,

nevertheless negates the classic method of the reason, disappoints hope,

opens to intuition and to the heart a whole proliferation of phenomena,

the wealth of which has about it something inhuman. These paths lead to

all sciences or to none.

This amounts to saying that in this case the means are more important

than the end. All that is involved is “an attitude for understanding”

and not a consolation. Let me repeat: in the beginning, at very least.

How can one fail to feel the basic relationship of these minds!

How can one fail to see that they take their stand around a privileged

and bitter moment in which hope has no further place? I want everything

to be explained to me or nothing. And the reason is impotent when it

hears this cry from the heart. The mind aroused by this insistence seeks

and finds nothing but contradictions and nonsense. What I fail to

understand is nonsense. The world is peopled with such irrationals. The

world itself, whose single meaning I do not understand, is but a vast

irrational. If one could only say just once: “This is clear,” all would

be saved. But these men vie with one another in proclaiming that nothing

is clear, all is chaos, that all man has is his lucidity and his

definite knowledge of the walls surrounding him.

All these experiences agree and confirm one another. The mind, when it

reaches its limits, must make a judgment and choose its conclusions.

This is where suicide and the reply stand. But I wish to reverse the

order of the inquiry and start out from the intelligent adventure and

come back to daily acts. The experiences called to mind here were born

in the desert that we must not leave behind. At least it is essential to

know how far they went. At this point of his effort man stands face to

face with the irrational. He feels within him his longing for happiness

and for reason. The absurd is born of this confrontation between the

human need and the unreasonable silence of the world. This must not be

forgotten.

This must be clung to because the whole consequence of a life can depend

on it. The irrational, the human nostalgia, and the absurd that is born

of their encounter—these are the three characters in the drama that must

necessarily end with all the logic of which an existence is capable.

Philosophical Suicide

The feeling of the absurd is not, for all that, the notion of the

absurd. It lays the foundations for it, and that is all. It is not

limited to that notion, except in the brief moment when it passes

judgment on the universe. Subsequently it has a chance of going further.

It is alive; in other words, it must die or else reverberate. So it is

with the themes we have gathered together. But there again what

interests me is not works or minds, criticism of which would call for

another form and another place, but the discovery of what their

conclusions have in common. Never, perhaps, have minds been so

different. And yet we recognize as identical the spiritual landscapes in

which they get under way. Likewise, despite such dissimilar zones of

knowledge, the cry that terminates their itinerary rings out in the same

way. It is evident that the thinkers we have just recalled have a common

climate.

To say that that climate is deadly scarcely amounts to playing on words.

Living under that stifling sky forces one to get away or to stay. The

important thing is to find out how people get away in the first case and

why people stay in the second case. This is how I define the problem of

suicide and the possible interest in the conclusions of existential

philosophy.

But first I want to detour from the direct path. Up to now we have

managed to circumscribe the absurd from the outside. One can, however,

wonder how much is clear in that notion and by direct analysis try to

discover its meaning on the one hand and, on the other, the consequences

it involves.

If I accuse an innocent man of a monstrous crime, if I tell a virtuous

man that he has coveted his own sister, he will reply that this is

absurd. His indignation has its comical aspect. But it also has its

fundamental reason. The virtuous man illustrates by that reply the

definitive antinomy existing between the deed I am attributing to him

and his lifelong principles. “It’s absurd” means “It’s impossible” but

also “It’s contradictory.” If I see a man armed only with a sword attack

a group of machine guns, I shall consider his act to be absurd. But it

is so solely by virtue of the disproportion between his intention and

the reality he will encounter, of the contradiction I notice between his

true strength and the aim he has in view. Likewise we shall deem a

verdict absurd when we contrast it with the verdict the facts apparently

dictated. And, similarly, a demonstration by the absurd is achieved by

comparing the consequences of such a reasoning with the logical reality

one wants to set up. In all these cases, from the simplest to the most

complex, the magnitude of the absurdity will be in direct ratio to the

distance between the two terms of my comparison. There are absurd

marriages, challenges, rancors, silences, wars, and even peace treaties.

For each of them the absurdity springs from a comparison. I am thus

justified in saying that the feeling of absurdity does not spring from

the mere scrutiny of a fact or an impression, but that it bursts from

the comparison between a bare fact and a certain reality, between an

action and the world that transcends it. The absurd is essentially a

divorce. It lies in neither of the elements compared; it is born of

their confrontation.

In this particular case and on the plane of intelligence, I can

therefore say that the Absurd is not in man (if such a metaphor could

have a meaning) nor in the world, but in their presence together. For

the moment it is the only bond uniting them. If wish to limit myself to

facts, I know what man wants, I know what the world offers him, and now

I can say that I also know what links them. I have no need to dig

deeper. A single certainty is enough for the seeker. He simply has to

derive all the consequences from it.

The immediate consequence is also a rule of method. The odd trinity

brought to light in this way is certainly not a startling discovery. But

it resembles the data of experience in that it is both infinitely simple

and infinitely complicated. Its first distinguishing feature in this

regard is that it cannot be divided. To destroy one of its terms is to

destroy the whole. There can be no absurd outside the human mind. Thus,

like everything else, the absurd ends with death. But there can be no

absurd outside this world either. And it is by this elementary criterion

that I judge the notion of the absurd to be essential and consider that

it can stand as the first of my truths. The rule of method alluded to

above appears here. If I judge that a thing is true, I must preserve it.

If I attempt to solve a problem, at least I must not by that very

solution conjure away one of the terms of the problem. For me the sole

datum is the absurd.

The first and, after all, the only condition of my inquiry is to

preserve the very thing that crushes me, consequently to respect what I

consider essential in it. I have just defined it as a confrontation and

an unceasing struggle.

And carrying this absurd logic to its conclusion, I must admit that that

struggle implies a total absence of hope (which has nothing to do with

despair), a continual rejection (which must not be confused with

renunciation), and a conscious dissatisfaction (which must not be

compared to immature unrest). Everything that destroys, conjures away,

or exorcises these requirements (and, to begin with, consent which

overthrows divorce) ruins the absurd and devaluates the attitude that

may then be proposed. The absurd has meaning only in so far as it is not

agreed to.

There exists an obvious fact that seems utterly moral: namely, that a

man is always a prey to his truths. Once he has admitted them, he cannot

free himself from them. One has to pay something.

A man who has be-come conscious of the absurd is forever bound to it. A

man devoid of hope and conscious of being so has ceased to belong to the

future. That is natural. But it is just as natural that he should strive

to escape the universe of which he is the creator.

All the foregoing has significance only on account of this paradox.

Certain men, starting from a critique of rationalism, have admitted the

absurd climate. Nothing is more instructive in this regard than to

scrutinize the way in which they have elaborated their consequences.

Now, to limit myself to existential philosophies, I see that all of them

without exception suggest escape. Through an odd reasoning, starting out

from the absurd over the ruins of reason, in a closed universe limited

to the human, they deify what crushes them and find reason to hope in

what impoverishes them. That forced hope is religious in all of them. It

deserves attention.

I shall merely analyze here as examples a few themes dear to Chestov and

Kierkegaard. But Jaspers will provide us, in caricatural form, a typical

example of this attitude. As a result the rest will be clearer. He is

left powerless to realize the transcendent, incapable of plumbing the

depth of experience, and conscious of that universe upset by failure.

Will he advance or at least draw the conclusions from that failure? He

contributes nothing new. He has found nothing in experience but the

confession of his own impotence and no occasion to infer any

satisfactory principle. Yet without justification, as he says to

himself, he suddenly asserts all at once the transcendent, the essence

of experience, and the superhuman significance of life when he writes:

“Does not the failure reveal, beyond any possible explanation and

interpretation, not the absence but the existence of transcendence?”

That existence which, suddenly and through a blind act of human

confidence, explains everything, he defines as “the unthinkable unity of

the general and the particular.” Thus the absurd becomes god (in the

broadest meaning of this word) and that inability to understand becomes

the existence that illuminates everything.

Nothing logically prepares this reasoning. I can call it a leap. And

para-doxically can be understood Jaspers’s insistence, his infinite

patience devoted to making the experience of the transcendent impossible

to realize. For the more fleeting that approximation is, the more empty

that definition proves to be, and the more real that transcendent is to

him; for the passion he devotes to asserting it is in direct proportion

to the gap between his powers of explanation and the irrationality of

the world and of experience. It thus appears that the more bitterly

Jaspers destroys the reason’s preconceptions, the more radically he will

explain the world. That apostle of humiliated thought will find at the

very end of humiliation the means of regenerating being to its very

depth.

Mystical thought has familiarized us with such devices. They are just as

legitimate as any attitude of mind. But for the moment I am acting as if

I took a certain problem seriously. Without judging beforehand the

general value of this attitude or its educative power, I mean simply to

consider whether it answers the conditions I set myself, whether it is

worthy of the conflict that concerns me. Thus I return to Chestov. A

commentator relates a remark of his that deserves interest:

“The only true solution,” he said, “is precisely where human judgment

sees no solution. Otherwise, what need would we have of God? We turn

toward God only to obtain the impossible. As for the possible, men

suffice.” If there is a Chestovian philosophy, I can say that it is

altogether summed up in this way. For when, at the conclusion of his

passionate analyses, Chestov discovers the fundamental absurdity of all

existence, he does not say: “This is the absurd,” but rather: “This is

God: we must rely on him even if he does not correspond to any of our

rational categories.” So that confusion may not be possible, the Russian

philosopher even hints that this God is perhaps full of hatred and

hateful, incomprehensible and contradictory; but the more hideous is his

face, the more he asserts his power. His greatness is his incoherence.

His proof is his inhumanity. One must spring into him and by this leap

free oneself from rational illusions. Thus, for Chestov acceptance of

the absurd is contemporaneous with the absurd itself. Being aware of it

amounts to accepting it, and the whole logical effort of his thought is

to bring it out so that at the same time the tremendous hope it involves

may burst forth. Let me repeat that this attitude is legitimate. But I

am persisting here in considering a single problem and all its

consequences. I do not have to examine the emotion of a thought or of an

act of faith. I have a whole lifetime to do that. I know that the

rationalist finds Chestov’s attitude annoying. But I also feel that

Chestov is right rather than the rationalist, and I merely want to know

if he remains faithful to the commandments of the absurd.

Now, if it is admitted that the absurd is the contrary of hope, it is

seen that existential thought for Chestov presupposes the absurd but

proves it only to dispel it. Such subtlety of thought is a conjuror’s

emotional trick. When Chestov elsewhere sets his absurd in opposition to

current morality and reason, he calls it truth and redemption. Hence,

there is basically in that definition of the absurd an approbation that

Chestov grants it. If it is admitted that all the power of that notion

lies in the way it runs counter to our elementary hopes, if it is felt

that to remain, the absurd requires not to be consented to, then it can

be clearly seen that it has lost its true aspect, its human and relative

character in order to enter an eternity that is both incomprehensible

and satisfying. If there is an absurd, it is in man’s universe. The

moment the notion transforms itself into eternity’s springboard, it

ceases to be linked to human lucidity.

The absurd is no longer that evidence that man ascertains without

consenting to it. The struggle is eluded. Man integrates the absurd and

in that communion causes to disappear its essential character, which is

opposition, laceration, and divorce. This leap is an escape. Chestov,

who is so fond of quoting Hamlet’s remark: “The time is out of joint,”

writes it down with a sort of savage hope that seems to belong to him in

particular. For it is not in this sense that Hamlet says it or

Shakespeare writes it. The intoxication of the irrational and the

vocation of rapture turn a lucid mind away from the absurd. To Chestov

reason is useless but there is something beyond reason. To an absurd

mind reason is useless and there is nothing beyond reason.

This leap can at least enlighten us a little more as to the true nature

of the absurd. We know that it is worthless except in an equilibrium,

that it is, above all, in the comparison and not in the terms of that

comparison. But it so happens that Chestov puts all the emphasis on one

of the terms and destroys the equilibrium. Our appetite for

understanding, our nostalgia for the absolute are explicable only in so

far, precisely, as we can understand and explain many things. It is

useless to negate the reason absolutely. It has its order in which it is

efficacious. It is properly that of human experience. Whence we wanted

to make everything clear. If we cannot do so, if the absurd is born on

that occasion, it is born precisely at the very meeting-point of that

efficacious but limited reason with the ever resurgent irrational. Now,

when Chestov rises up against a Hegelian proposition such as “the motion

of the solar system takes place in conformity with immutable laws and

those laws are its reason,” when he devotes all his passion to upsetting

Spinoza’s rationalism, he concludes, in effect, in favor of the vanity

of all reason. Whence, by a natural and illegitimate reversal, to the

pre-eminence of the irrational.[5] But the transition is not evident.

For here may intervene the notion of limit and the notion of level. The

laws of nature may be operative up to a certain limit, beyond which they

turn against themselves to give birth to the absurd. Or else, they may

justify themselves on the level of description without for that reason

being true on the level of explanation.

Everything is sacrificed here to the irrational, and, the demand for

clarity being conjured away, the absurd disappears with one of the terms

of its comparison. The absurd man, on the other hand, does not undertake

such a leveling process. He recognizes the struggle, does not absolutely

scorn reason, and admits the irrational. Thus he again embraces in a

single glance all the data of experience and he is little inclined to

leap before knowing. He knows simply that in that alert awareness there

is no further place for hope.

What is perceptible in Leo Chestov will be perhaps even more so in

Kierkegaard. To be sure, it is hard to outline clear propositions in so

elusive a writer. But, despite apparently opposed writings, beyond the

pseudonyms, the tricks, and the smiles, can be felt throughout that

work, as it were, the presentiment (at the same time as the

apprehension) of a truth which eventually bursts forth in the last

works: Kierkegaard likewise takes the leap. His childhood having been so

frightened by Christianity, he ultimately returns to its harshest

aspect. For him, too, antinomy and paradox become criteria of the

religious. Thus, the very thing that led to despair of the meaning and

depth of this life now gives it its truth and its clarity. Christianity

is the scandal, and what Kierkegaard calls for quite plainly is the

third sacrifice required by Ignatius Loyola, the one in which God most

rejoices: “The sacrifice of the intellect.”[6]

This effect of the “leap” is odd, but must not surprise us any longer.

He makes of the absurd the criterion of the other world, whereas it is

simply a residue of the experience of this world. “In his failure,” says

Kierkegaard, “the believer finds his triumph.”

It is not for me to wonder to what stirring preaching this attitude is

linked. I merely have to wonder if the spectacle of the absurd and its

own character justifies it. On this point, I know that it is not so.

Upon considering again the content of the absurd, one understands better

the method that inspired Kierkegaard. Between the irrational of the

world and the insurgent nostalgia of the absurd, he does not maintain

the equilibrium. He does not respect the relationship that constitutes,

properly speaking, the feeling of absurdity. Sure of being unable to

escape the irrational, he wants at least to save himself from that

desperate nostalgia that seems to him sterile and devoid of implication.

But if he may be right on this point in his judgment, he could not be in

his negation. If he substitutes for his cry of revolt a frantic

adherence, at once he is led to blind himself to the absurd which

hitherto enlightened him and to deify the only certainty he henceforth

possesses, the irrational. The important thing, as Abbe Galiani said to

Mme d’Epinay, is not to be cured, but to live with one’s ailments.

Kierkegaard wants to be cured. To be cured is his frenzied wish, and it

runs throughout his whole journal. The entire effort of his intelligence

is to escape the antinomy of the human condition. An all the more

desperate effort since he intermittently perceives its vanity when he

speaks of himself, as if neither fear of God nor piety were capable of

bringing him to peace. Thus it is that, through a strained subterfuge,

he gives the irrational the appearance and God the attributes of the

absurd: unjust, incoherent, and incomprehensible. Intelligence alone in

him strives to stifle the underlying demands of the human heart. Since

nothing is proved, everything can be proved.

Indeed, Kierkegaard himself shows us the path taken. I do not want to

suggest anything here, but how can one fail to read in his works the

signs of an almost intentional mutilation of the soul to balance the

mutilation accepted in regard to the absurd? It is the leitmotiv of the

Journal. “What I lacked was the animal which also belongs to human

destiny

But give me a body then.” And further on: “Oh! especially in my early

youth what should I not have given to be a man, even for six months ...

what I lack, basically, is a body and the physical conditions of

existence.”

Elsewhere, the same man nevertheless adopts the great cry of hope that

has come down through so many centuries and quickened so many hearts,

except that of the absurd man. “But for the Christian death is certainly

not the end of everything and it implies infinitely more hope than life

implies for us, even when that life is overflowing with health and

vigor.” Reconciliation through scandal is still reconciliation. It

allows one perhaps, as can be seen, to derive hope of its contrary,

which is death. But even if fellow- feeling inclines one toward that

attitude, still it must be said that excess justifies nothing. That

transcends, as the saying goes, the human scale; therefore it must be

superhuman. But this “therefore” is superfluous. There is no logical

certainty here. There is no experimental probability either. All I can

say is that, in fact, that transcends my scale. If I do not draw a

negation from it, at least I do not want to found anything on the

incomprehensible. I want to know whether I can live with what I know and

with that alone. I am told again that here the intelligence must

sacrifice its pride and the reason bow down. But if I recognize the

limits of the reason, I do not therefore negate it, recognizing its

relative powers. I merely want to remain in this middle path where the

intelligence can remain clear. If that is its pride, I see no sufficient

reason for giving it up. Nothing more profound, for example, than

Kierkegaard’s view according to which despair is not a fact but a state:

the very state of sin. For sin is what alienates from God. The absurd,

which is the metaphysical state of the conscious man, does not lead to

God.[7] Perhaps this notion will become clearer if I risk this shocking

statement: the absurd is sin without God.

It is a matter of living in that state of the absurd I know on what it

is founded, this mind and this world straining against each other

without being able to embrace each other. I ask for the rule— of life of

that state, and what I am offered neglects its basis, negates one of the

terms of the painful opposition, demands of me a resignation. I ask what

is involved in the condition I recognize as mine; I know it implies

obscurity and ignorance; and I am assured that this ignorance explains

everything and that this darkness is my light. But there is no reply

here to my intent, and this stirring lyricism cannot hide the paradox

from me. One must therefore turn away. Kierkegaard may shout in warning:

“If man had no eternal consciousness, if, at the bottom of everything,

there were merely a wild, seething force producing everything, both

large and trifling, in the storm of dark passions, if the bottomless

void that nothing can fill underlay all things, what would life be but

despair?” This cry is not likely to stop the absurd man. Seeking what is

true is not seeking what is desirable. If in order to elude the anxious

question:

“What would life be?” one must, like the donkey, feed on the roses of

illusion, then the absurd mind, rather than resigning itself to

falsehood, prefers, to adopt fearlessly Kierkegaard’s reply: “despair.”

Everything considered, a determined soul will always manage.

I am taking the liberty at this point of calling the existential

attitude philosophical suicide. But this does not imply a judgment.

It is a convenient way of indicating the movement by which a thought

negates itself and tends to transcend itself in its very negation. For

the existentials negation is their God. To be precise, that god is

maintained only through the negation of human reason.[8] But, like

suicides, gods change with men. There are many ways of leaping, the

essential being to leap. Those redeeming negations, those ultimate

contradictions which negate the obstacle that has not yet been leaped

over, may spring just as well (this is the paradox at which this

reasoning aims) from a certain religious inspiration as from the

rational order. They always lay claim to the eternal, and it is solely

in this that they take the leap.

It must be repeated that the reasoning developed in this essay leaves

out altogether the most widespread spiritual attitude of our enlightened

age: the one, based on the principle that all is reason, which aims to

explain the world. It is natural to give a clear view of the world after

accepting the idea that it must be clear. That is even legitimate, but

does not concern the reasoning we are following out here. In fact, our

aim is to shed light upon the step taken by the mind when, starting from

a philosophy of the world’s lack of meaning, it ends up by finding a

meaning and depth in it.

The most touching of those steps is religious in essence; it becomes

obvious in the theme of the irrational. But the most paradoxical and

most significant is certainly the one that attributes rational reasons

to a world it originally imagined as devoid of any guiding principle. It

is impossible in any case to reach the consequences that concern us

without having given an idea of this new attainment of the spirit of

nostalgia.

I shall examine merely the theme of “the Intention” made fashionable by

Husserl and the phenomenologists. I have already alluded to it.

Originally Husserl’s method negates the classic procedure of the reason.

Let me repeat. Thinking is not unifying or making the appearance

familiar under the guise of a great principle. Thinking is learning all

over again how to see, directing one’s consciousness, making of every

image a privileged place. In other words, phenomenology declines to

explain the world, it wants to be merely a description of actual

experience. It confirms absurd thought in its initial assertion that

there is no truth, but merely truths. From the evening breeze to this

hand on my shoulder, everything has its truth. Consciousness illuminates

it by paying attention to it. Consciousness does not form the object of

its understanding, it merely focuses, it is the act of attention, and,

to borrow a Bergsonian image, it resembles the projector that suddenly

focuses on an image. The difference is that there is no scenario, but a

successive and incoherent illustration. In that magic lantern all the

pictures are privileged. Consciousness suspends in experience the

objects of its attention. Through its miracle it isolates them.

Henceforth they are beyond all judgments. This is the “intention” that

characterizes consciousness. But the word does not imply any idea of

finality; it is taken in its sense of “direction”: its only value is

topographical.

At first sight, it certainly seems that in this way nothing contradicts

the absurd spirit. That apparent modesty of thought that limits itself

to describing what it declines to explain, that intentional discipline

whence results paradoxically a profound enrichment of experience and the

rebirth of the world in its prolixity are absurd procedures. At least at

first sight. For methods of thought, in this case as elsewhere, always

assume two aspects, one psychological and the other metaphysical.[9]

Thereby they harbor two truths. If the theme of the intentional claims

to illustrate merely a psychological attitude, by which reality is

drained instead of being explained, nothing in fact separates it from

the absurd spirit. It aims to enumerate what it cannot transcend. It

affirms solely that without any unifying principle thought can still

take delight in describing and understanding every aspect of experience.

The truth involved then for each of those aspects is psychological in

nature. It simply testifies to the “interest” that reality can offer.

It is a way of awaking a sleeping world and of making it vivid to the

mind. But if one attempts to extend and give a rational basis to that

notion of truth, if one claims to discover in this way the “essence” of

each object of knowledge, one restores its depth to experience. For an

absurd mind that is incomprehensible. Now, it is this wavering between

modesty and assurance that is noticeable in the intentional attitude,

and this shimmering of phenomenological thought will illustrate the

absurd reasoning better than anything else.

For Husserl speaks likewise of “extra-temporal essences” brought to

light by the intention, and he sounds like Plato. All things are not

explained by one thing but by all things. I see no difference. To be

sure, those ideas or those essences that consciousness “effectuates” at

the end of every description are not yet to be considered perfect

models. But it is asserted that they are directly present in each datum

of perception. There is no longer a single idea explaining everything,

but an infinite number of essences giving a meaning to an infinite

number of objects. The world comes to a stop, but also lights up.

Platonic realism becomes intuitive, but it is still realism. Kierkegaard

was swallowed up in his God; Parmenides plunged thought into the One.

But here thought hurls itself into an abstract polytheism. But this is

not all: hallucinations and fictions likewise belong to “extra-temporal

essences.” In the new world of ideas, the species of centaurs

collaborates with the more modest species of metropolitan man.

For the absurd man, there was a truth as well as a bitterness in that

purely psychological opinion that all aspects of the world are

privileged. To say that everything is privileged is tantamount to saying

that everything is equivalent. But the metaphysical aspect of that truth

is so far-reaching that through an elementary reaction he feels closer

perhaps to Plato. He is taught, in fact, that every image presupposes an

equally privileged essence. In this ideal world without hierarchy, the

formal army is composed solely of generals.

To be sure, transcendency had been eliminated. But a sudden shift in

thought brings back into the world a sort of fragmentary immanence which

restores to the universe its depth.

Am I to fear having carried too far a theme handled with greater

circumspection by its creators? I read merely these assertions of

Husserl, apparently paradoxical yet rigorously logical if what precedes

is accepted: “That which is true is true absolutely, in itself; truth is

one, identical with itself, however different the creatures who perceive

it, men, monsters, angels or gods.” Reason triumphs and trumpets forth

with that voice, I cannot deny. What can its assertions mean in the

absurd world? The perception of an angel or a god has no meaning for me.

That geometrical spot where divine reason ratifies mine will always be

incomprehensible to me. There, too, I discern a leap, and though

performed in the abstract, it nonetheless means for me forgetting just

what I do not want to forget. When farther on Husserl exclaims: “If all

masses subject to attraction were to disappear, the law of attraction

would not be destroyed but would simply remain without any possible

application,” I know that I am faced with a metaphysic of consolation.

And if I want to discover the point where thought leaves the path of

evidence, I have only to reread the parallel reasoning that Husserl

voices regarding the mind: “If we could contemplate clearly the exact

laws of psychic processes, they would be seen to be likewise eternal and

invariable, like the basic laws of theoretical natural science. Hence

they would be valid even if there were no psychic process.” Even if the

mind were not, its laws would be! I see then that of a psychological

truth Husserl aims to make a rational rule: after having denied the

integrating power of human reason, he leaps by this expedient to eternal

Reason.

Husserl’s theme of the “concrete universe” cannot then surprise me. If I

am told that all essences are not formal but that some are material,

that the first are the object of logic and the second of science, this

is merely a question of definition. The abstract, I am told, indicates

but a part, without consistency in itself, of a concrete universal. But

the wavering already noted allows me to throw light on the confusion of

these terms. For that may mean that the concrete object of my attention,

this sky, the reflection of that water on this coat, alone preserve the

prestige of the real that my interest isolates in the world. And I shall

not deny it. But that may mean also that this coat itself is universal,

has its particular and sufficient essence, belongs to the world of

forms. I then realize that merely the order of the procession has been

changed. This world has ceased to have its reflection in a higher

universe, but the heaven of forms is figured in the host of images of

this earth. This changes nothing for me. Rather than encountering here a

taste for the concrete, the meaning of the human condition, I find an

intellectualism sufficiently unbridled to generalize the concrete

itself.

It is futile to be amazed by the apparent paradox that leads thought to

its own negation by the opposite paths of humiliated reason and

triumphal reason. From the abstract god of Husserl to the dazzling god

of Kierkegaard the distance is not so great.

Reason and the irrational lead to the same preaching. In truth the way

matters but little; the will to arrive suffices. The abstract

philosopher and the religious philosopher start out from the same

disorder and support each other in the same anxiety. But the essential

is to explain. Nostalgia is stronger here than knowledge.

It is significant that the thought of the epoch is at once one of the

most deeply imbued with a philosophy of the non-significance of the

world and one of the most divided in its conclusions. It is constantly

oscillating between extreme rationalization of reality which tends to

break up that thought into standard reasons and its extreme

irrationalization which tends to deify it. But this divorce is only

apparent. It is a matter of reconciliation, and, in both cases, the leap

suffices. It is always wrongly thought that the notion of reason is a

oneway notion. To tell the truth, however rigorous it may be in its

ambition, this concept is nonetheless just as unstable as others. Reason

bears a quite human aspect, but it also is able to turn toward the

divine. Since Plotinus, who was the first to reconcile it with the

eternal climate, it has learned to turn away from the most cherished of

its principles, which is contradiction, in order to integrate into it

the strangest, the quite magic one of participation.[10] It is an

instrument of thought and not thought itself. Above all, a man’s thought

is his nostalgia.

Just as reason was able to soothe the melancholy of Plotinus, it

provides modern anguish the means of calming itself in the familiar

setting of the eternal. The absurd mind has less luck. For it the world

is neither so rational nor so irrational. It is unreasonable and only

that. With Husserl the reason eventually has no limits at all. The

absurd, on the contrary, establishes its lim-its since it is powerless

to calm its anguish. Kierkegaard independently asserts that a single

limit is enough to negate that anguish. But the absurd does not go so

far. For it that limit is directed solely at the reason’s ambitions. The

theme of the irrational, as it is conceived by the existentials, is

reason becoming confused and escaping by negating itself. The absurd is

lucid reason noting its limits.

Only at the end of this difficult path does the absurd man recognize his

true motives. Upon comparing his inner exigence and what is then offered

him, he suddenly feels he is going to turn away. In the universe of

Husserl the world becomes clear and that longing for familiarity that

man’s heart harbors becomes useless.

In Kierkegaard’s apocalypse that desire for clarity must be given up if

it wants to be satisfied. Sin is not so much knowing (if it were,

everybody would be innocent) as wanting to know. Indeed, it is the only

sin of which the absurd man can feel that it constitutes both his guilt

and his innocence. He is offered a solution in which all the past

contradictions have become merely polemical games.

But this is not the way he experienced them. Their truth must be

preserved, which consists in not being satisfied. He does not want

preaching.

My reasoning wants to be faithful to the evidence that aroused it. That

evidence is the absurd. It is that divorce between the mind that desires

and the world that disappoints, my nostalgia for unity, this fragmented

universe and the contradiction that binds them together. Kierkegaard

suppresses my nostalgia and Husserl gathers together that universe. That

is not what I was expecting. It was a matter of living and thinking with

those dislocations, of knowing whether one had to accept or refuse.

There can be no question of masking the evidence, of suppressing the

absurd by denying one of the terms of its equation. It is essential to

know whether one can live with it or whether, on the other hand, logic

commands one to die of it. I am not interested in philosophical suicide,

but rather in plain suicide. I merely wish to purge it of its emotional

content and know its logic and its integrity. Any other position implies

for the absurd mind deceit and the mind’s retreat before what the mind

itself has brought to light. Husserl claims to obey the desire to escape

“the inveterate habit of living and thinking in certain well- known and

convenient conditions of existence,” but the final leap restores in him

the eternal and its comfort. The leap does not represent an extreme

danger as Kierkegaard would like it to do.

The danger, on the contrary, lies in the subtle instant that precedes

the leap. Being able to remain on that dizzying crest—that is integrity

and the rest is subterfuge. I know also that never has helplessness

inspired such striking harmonies as those of Kierkegaard. But if

helplessness has its place in the indifferent landscapes of history, it

has none in a reasoning whose exigence is now known.

Absurd Freedom

Now the main thing is done, I hold certain facts from which I cannot

separate. What I know, what is certain, what I cannot deny, what I

cannot reject—this is what counts. I can negate everything of that part

of me that lives on vague nostalgias, except this desire for unity, this

longing to solve, this need for clarity and cohesion. I can refute

everything in this world surrounding me that offends or enraptures me,

except this chaos, this sovereign chance and this divine equivalence

which springs from anarchy. I don’t know whether this world has a

meaning that transcends it. But I know that I do not know that meaning

and that it is impossible for me just now to know it. What can a meaning

outside my condition mean to me? I can understand only in human terms.

What I touch, what resists me—that is what I understand. And these two

certainties—my appetite for the absolute and for unity and the

impossibility of reducing this world to a rational and reasonable

principle—I also know that I cannot reconcile them. What other truth can

I admit without lying, without bringing in a hope I lack and which means

nothing within the limits of my condition?

If I were a tree among trees, a cat among animals, this life would have

a meaning, or rather this problem would not arise, for I should belong

to this world. I should be this world to which I am now opposed by my

whole consciousness and my whole insistence upon familiarity. This

ridiculous reason is what sets me in opposition to all creation. I

cannot cross it out with a stroke of the pen. What I believe to be true

I must therefore preserve. What seems to me so obvious, even against me,

I must support. And what constitutes the basis of that conflict, of that

break between the world and my mind, but the awareness of it? If

therefore I want to preserve it, I can through a constant awareness,

ever revived, ever alert. This is what, for the moment, I must remember.

At this moment the absurd, so obvious and yet so hard to win, returns to

a man’s life and finds its home there. At this moment, too, the mind can

leave the arid, dried-up path of lucid effort. That path now emerges in

daily life. It encounters the world of the anonymous impersonal pronoun

“one,” but henceforth man enters in with his revolt and his lucidity. He

has forgotten how to hope. This hell of the present is his Kingdom at

last. All problems recover their sharp edge. Abstract evidence retreats

before the poetry of forms and colors. Spiritual conflicts become

embodied and return to the abject and magnificent shelter of man’s

heart. None of them is settled. But all are transfigured. Is one going

to die, escape by the leap, rebuild a mansion of ideas and forms to

one’s own scale? Is one, on the contrary, going to take up the

heart-rending and marvelous wager of the absurd? Let’s make a final

effort in this regard and draw all our conclusions. The body, affection,

creation, action, human nobility will then resume their places in this

mad world. At last man will again find there the wine of the absurd and

the bread of indifference on which he feeds his greatness.

Let us insist again on the method: it is a matter of persisting. At a

certain point on his path the absurd man is tempted. History is not

lacking in either religions or prophets, even without gods. He is asked

to leap. All he can reply is that he doesn’t fully understand, that it

is not obvious. Indeed, he does not want to do anything but what he

fully understands. He is assured that this is the sin of pride, but he

does not understand the notion of sin; that perhaps hell is in store,

but he has not enough imagination to visualize that strange future; that

he is losing immortal life, but that seems to him an idle consideration.

An attempt is made to get him to admit his guilt. He feels innocent. To

tell the truth, that is all he feels—his irreparable innocence. This is

what allows him everything. Hence, what he demands of himself is to live

solely with what he knows, to accommodate himself to what is, and to

bring in nothing that is not certain. He is told that nothing is. But

this at least is a certainty.

And it is with this that he is concerned: he wants to find out if it is

possible to live without appeal.

Now I can broach the notion of suicide. It has already been felt what

solution might be given. At this point the problem is reversed. It was

previously a question of finding out whether or not life had to have a

meaning to be lived. It now becomes clear, on the contrary, that it will

be lived all the better if it has no meaning.

Living an experience, a particular fate, is accepting it fully. Now, no

one will live this fate, knowing it to be absurd, unless he does

everything to keep before him that absurd brought to light by

consciousness. Negating one of the terms of the opposition on which he

lives amounts to escaping it. To abolish conscious revolt is to elude

the problem. The theme of permanent revolution is thus carried into

individual experience. Living is keeping the absurd alive. Keeping it

alive is, above all, contemplating it. Unlike Eurydice, the absurd dies

only when we turn away from it. One of the only coherent philosophical

positions is thus revolt. It is a constant confrontation between man and

his own obscurity. It is an insistence upon an impossible transparency.

It challenges the world anew every second. Just as danger provided man

the unique opportunity of seizing awareness, so metaphysical revolt

extends awareness to the whole of experience. It is that constant

presence of man in his own eyes. It is not aspiration, for it is devoid

of hope.

That revolt is the certainly of a crushing fate, without the resignation

that ought to accompany it.

This is where it is seen to what a degree absurd experience is remote

from suicide. It may be thought that suicide follows revolt—but wrongly.

For it does not represent the logical outcome of revolt. It is just the

contrary by the consent it presupposes. Suicide, like the leap, is

acceptance at its extreme. Everything is over and man returns to his

essential history. His future, his unique and dreadful future—he sees

and rushes toward it. In its way, suicide settles the absurd. It engulfs

the absurd in the same death.

But I know that in order to keep alive, the absurd cannot be settled.

It escapes suicide to the extent that it is simultaneously awareness and

rejection of death. It is, at the extreme limit of the condemned man’s

last thought, that shoelace that despite everything he sees a few yards

away, on the very brink of his dizzying fall. The contrary of suicide,

in fact, is the man condemned to death.

That revolt gives life its value. Spread out over the whole length of a

life, it restores its majesty to that life. To a man devoid of blinders,

there is no finer sight than that of the intelligence at grips with a

reality that transcends it. The sight of human pride is unequaled. No

disparagement is of any use. That discipline that the mind imposes on

itself, that will conjured up out of nothing, that face-to-face struggle

have something exceptional about them. To impoverish that reality whose

inhumanity constitutes man’s majesty is tantamount to impoverishing him

himself. I understand then why the doctrines that explain everything to

me also debilitate me at the same time. They relieve me of the weight of

my own life, and yet I must carry it alone. At this juncture, I cannot

conceive that a skeptical metaphysics can be joined to an ethics of

renunciation.

Consciousness and revolt, these rejections are the contrary of

renunciation. Everything that is indomitable and passionate in a human

heart quickens them, on the contrary, with its own life. It is essential

to die unrecon-ciled and not of one’s own free will.

Suicide is a repudi—ation. The absurd man can only drain everything to

the bitter end, and deplete himself. The absurd is his extreme tension,

which he maintains constantly by solitary effort, for he knows that in

that consciousness and in that day-to-day revolt he gives proof of his

only truth, which is defiance. This is a first consequence.

If I remain in that prearranged position which consists in drawing all

the conclusions (and nothing else) involved in a newly discovered

notion, I am faced with a second paradox. In order to remain faithful to

that method, I have nothing to do with the problem of metaphysical

liberty. Knowing whether or not man is free doesn’t interest me. I can

experience only my own freedom.

As to it, I can have no general notions, but merely a few clear

insights. The problem of “freedom as such” has no meaning, for it is

linked in quite a different way with the problem of God.

Knowing whether or not man is free involves knowing whether he can have

a master. The absurdity peculiar to this problem comes from the fact

that the very notion that makes the problem of freedom possible also

takes away all its meaning. For in the presence of God there is less a

problem of freedom than a problem of evil. You know the alternative:

either we are not free and God the all-powerful is responsible for evil.

Or we are free and responsible but God is not all powerful. All the

scholastic subtleties have neither added anything to nor subtracted

anything from the acuteness of this paradox.

This is why I cannot act lost in the glorification or the mere

definition of a notion which eludes me and loses its meaning as soon as

it goes beyond the frame of reference of my individual experience. I

cannot understand what kind of freedom would be given me by a higher

being. I have lost the sense of hierarchy. The only conception of

freedom I can have is that of the prisoner or the individual in the

midst of the State. The only one I know is freedom of thought and

action. Now if the absurd cancels all my chances of eternal freedom, it

restores and magnifies, on the other hand, my freedom of action. That

privation of hope and future means an increase in man’s availability.

Before encountering the absurd, the everyday man lives with aims, a

concern for the future or for justification (with regard to whom or what

is not the question). He weighs his chances, he counts on “someday,” his

retirement or the labor of his sons. He still thinks that something in

his life can be directed. In truth, he acts as if he were free, even if

all the facts make a point of contradicting that liberty. But after the

absurd, everything is upset.

That idea that “I am,” my way of acting as if everything has a meaning

(even if, on occasion, I said that nothing has)—all that is given the

lie in vertiginous fashion by the absurdity of a possible death.

Thinking of the future, establishing aims for oneself, having

preferences—all this presupposes a belief in freedom, even if one

occasionally ascertains that one doesn’t feel it. But at that moment I

am well aware that that higher liberty, that freedom to be, which alone

can serve as basis for a truth, does not exist. Death is there as the

only reality. After death the chips are down. I am not even free,

either, to perpetuate myself, but a slave, and, above all, a slave

without hope of an eternal revolution, without recourse to contempt. And

who without revolution and without contempt can remain a slave? What

freedom can exist in the fullest sense without assurance of eternity?

But at the same time the absurd man realizes that hitherto he was bound

to that postulate of freedom on the illusion of which he was living. In

a certain sense, that hampered him. To the extent to which he imagined a

purpose to his life, he adapted himself to the demands of a purpose to

be achieved and became the slave of his liberty. Thus I could not act

otherwise than as the father (or the engineer or the leader of a nation,

or the post-office sub-clerk) that I am preparing to be. I think I can

choose to be that rather than something else. I think so unconsciously,

to be sure. But at the same time I strengthen my postulate with the

beliefs of those around me, with the presumptions of my human

environment (others are so sure of being free, and that cheerful mood is

so contagious!). However far one may remain from any presumption, moral

or social, one is partly influenced by them and even, for the best among

them (there are good and bad presumptions), one adapts one’s life to

them. Thus the absurd man realizes that he was not really free. To speak

clearly, to the extent to which I hope, to which I worry about a truth

that might be individual to me, about a way of being or creating, to the

extent to which I arrange my life and prove thereby that I accept its

having a meaning, I create for myself barriers between which I confine

my life. I do like so many bureaucrats of the mind and heart who only

fill me with disgust and whose only vice, I now see clearly, is to take

man’s freedom seriously.

The absurd enlightens me on this point: there is no future.

Henceforth this is the reason for my inner freedom. I shall use two

comparisons here. Mystics, to begin with, find freedom in giving

themselves. By losing themselves in their god, by accepting his rules,

they become secretly free. In spontaneously accepted slavery they

recover a deeper independence. But what does that freedom mean? It may

be said, above all, that they feel free with regard to themselves, and

not so much free as liberated. Likewise, completely turned toward death

(taken here as the most obvious absurdity), the absurd man feels

released from everything outside that passionate attention crystallizing

in him. He enjoys a freedom with regard to common rules. It can be seen

at this point that the initial themes of existential philosophy keep

their entire value. The return to consciousness, the escape from

everyday sleep represent the first steps of absurd freedom. But it is

existential preaching that is alluded to, and with it that spiritual

leap which basically escapes consciousness. In the same way (this is my

second comparison) the slaves of antiquity did not belong to themselves.

But they knew that freedom which consists in not feeling

responsible.[11] Death, too, has patrician hands which, while crushing,

also liberate.

Losing oneself in that bottomless certainty, feeling henceforth

sufficiently remote from one’s own life to increase it and take a broad

view of it—this involves the principle of a liberation. Such new

independence has a definite time limit, like any freedom of action. It

does not write a check on eternity. But it takes the place of the

illusions of freedom, which all stopped with death. The divine

availability of the condemned man before whom the prison doors open in a

certain early dawn, that unbelievable disinterestedness with regard to

everything except for the pure flame of life—it is clear that death and

the absurd are here the principles of the only reasonable freedom: that

which a human heart can experience and live. This is a second

consequence. The absurd man thus catches sight of a burning and frigid,

transparent and limited universe in which nothing is possible but

everything is given, and beyond which all is collapse and nothingness.

He can then decide to accept such a universe and draw from it his

strength, his refusal to hope, and the unyielding evidence of a life

without consolation.

But what does life mean in such a universe? Nothing else for the moment

but indifference to the future and a desire to use up everything that is

given. Belief in the meaning of life always implies a scale of values, a

choice, our preferences. Belief in the absurd, according to our

definitions, teaches the contrary. But this is worth examining.

Knowing whether or not one can live without appeal is all that interests

me. I do not want to get out of my depth. This aspect of life being

given me, can I adapt myself to it? Now, faced with this particular

concern, belief in the absurd is tantamount to substituting the quantity

of experiences for the quality. If I convince myself that this life has

no other aspect than that of the absurd, if I feel that its whole

equilibrium depends on that perpetual opposition between my conscious

revolt and the darkness in which it struggles, if I admit that my

freedom has no meaning except in relation to its limited fate, then I

must say that what counts is not the best living but the most living. It

is not up to me to wonder if this is vulgar or revolting, elegant or

deplorable. Once and for all, value judgments are discarded here in

favor of factual judgments. I have merely to draw the conclusions from

what I can see and to risk nothing that is hypothetical. Supposing that

living in this way were not honorable, then true propriety would command

me to be dishonorable.

The most living; in the broadest sense, that rule means nothing.

It calls for definition. It seems to begin with the fact that the notion

of quantity has not been sufficiently explored. For it can account for a

large share of human experience. A man’s rule of conduct and his scale

of values have no meaning except through the quantity and variety of

experiences he has been in a position to accumulate. Now, the conditions

of modern life impose on the majority of men the same quantity of

experiences and consequently the same profound experience. To be sure,

there must also be taken into consideration the individual’s spontaneous

contribution, the “given” element in him. But I cannot judge of that,

and let me repeat that my rule here is to get along with the immediate

evidence. I see, then, that the individual character of a common code of

ethics lies not so much in the ideal importance of its basic principles

as in the norm of an experience that it is possible to measure. To

stretch a point somewhat, the Greeks had the code of their leisure just

as we have the code of our eight-hour day. But already many men among

the most tragic cause us to foresee that a longer experience changes

this table of values. They make us imagine that adventurer of the

everyday who through mere quantity of experiences would break all

records (I am purposely using this sports expression) and would thus win

his own code of ethics.[12] Yet let’s avoid romanticism and just ask

ourselves what such an attitude may mean to a man with his mind made up

to take up his bet and to observe strictly what he takes to be the rules

of the game.

Breaking all the records is first and foremost being faced with the

world as often as possible. How can that be done without contradictions

and without playing on words? For on the one hand the absurd teaches

that all experiences are unimportant, and on the other it urges toward

the greatest quantity of experiences. How, then, can one fail to do as

so many of those men I was speaking of earlier—choose the form of life

that brings us the most possible of that human matter, thereby

introducing a scale of values that on the other hand one claims to

reject?

But again it is the absurd and its contradictory life that teaches us.

For the mistake is thinking that that quantity of experiences depends on

the circumstances of our life when it depends solely on us. Here we have

to be over-simple. To two men living the same number of years, the world

always provides the same sum of experiences. It is up to us to be

conscious of them. Being aware of one’s life, one’s revolt, one’s

freedom, and to the maximum, is living, and to the maximum. Where

lucidity dominates, the scale of values becomes useless. Let’s be even

more simple. Let us say that the sole obstacle, the sole deficiency to

be made good, is constituted by premature death. Thus it is that no

depth, no emotion, no passion, and no sacrifice could render equal in

the eyes of the absurd man (even if he wished it so) a conscious life of

forty years and a lucidity spread over sixty years.[13] Madness and

death are his irreparables. Man does not choose. The absurd and the

extra life it involves therefore do not defend on man’s will, but on its

contrary, which is death.[14] Weighing words carefully, it is altogether

a question of luck. One just has to be able to consent to this. There

will never be any substitute for twenty years of life and experience.

By what is an odd inconsistency in such an alert race, the Greeks

claimed that those who died young were beloved of the gods. And that is

true only if you are willing to believe that entering the ridiculous

world of the gods is forever losing the purest of joys, which is

feeling, and feeling on this earth. The present and the succession of

presents before a constantly conscious soul is the ideal of the absurd

man. But the word “ideal” rings false in this connection. It is not even

his vocation, but merely the third consequence of his reasoning. Having

started from an anguished awareness of the inhuman, the meditation on

the absurd returns at the end of its itinerary to the very heart of the

passionate flames of human revolt.[15]

Thus I draw from the absurd three consequences, which are my revolt, my

freedom, and my passion. By the mere activity of consciousness I

transform into a rule of life what was an invitation to death—and I

refuse suicide. I know, to be sure, the dull resonance that vibrates

throughout these days. Yet I have but a word to say: that it is

necessary. When Nietzsche writes: “It clearly seems that the chief thing

in heaven and on earth is to obey at length and in a single direction:

in the long run there results something for which it is worth the

trouble of living on this earth as, for example, virtue, art, music, the

dance, reason, the mind— something that transfigures, something

delicate, mad, or divine,” he elucidates the rule of a really

distinguished code of ethics. But he also points the way of the absurd

man. Obeying the flame is both the easiest and the hardest thing to do.

However, it is good for man to judge himself occasionally. He is alone

in being able to do so.

“Prayer,” says Alain, “is when night descends over thought.”

“But the mind must meet the night,” reply the mystics and the

existentials. Yes, indeed, but not that night that is born under closed

eyelids and through the mere will of man—dark, impenetrable night that

the mind calls up in order to plunge into it.

If it must encounter a night, let it be rather that of despair, which

remains lucid—polar night, vigil of the mind, whence will arise perhaps

that white and virginal brightness which outlines every object in the

light of the intelligence. At that degree, equivalence encounters

passionate understanding. Then it is no longer even a question of

judging the existential leap. It resumes its place amid the age-old

fresco of human attitudes. For the spectator, if he is conscious, that

leap is still absurd. In so far as it thinks it solves the paradox, it

reinstates it intact. On this score, it is stirring. On this score,

everything resumes its place and the absurd world is reborn in all its

splendor and diversity.

But it is bad to stop, hard to be satisfied with a single way of seeing,

to go without contradiction, perhaps the most subtle of all spiritual

forces. The preceding merely defines a way of thinking.

But the point is to live.

The Absurd Man

If Stavrogin believes, he does not think he believes. If he does not

believe, he does not think he does not believe.

—The Possessed

My field,” said Goethe, “is time.” That is indeed the absurd speech.

What, in fact, is the absurd man? He who, without negating it, does

nothing for the eternal. Not that nostalgia is foreign to him. But he

prefers his courage and his reasoning. The first teaches him to live

without appeal and to get along with what he has; the second informs him

of his limits. Assured of his temporally limited freedom, of his revolt

devoid of future, and of his mortal consciousness, he lives out his

adventure within the span of his lifetime. That is his field, that is

his action, which he shields from any judgment but his own. A greater

life cannot mean for him another life. That would be unfair. I am not

even speaking here of that paltry eternity that is called posterity. Mme

Roland relied on herself. That rashness was taught a lesson. Posterity

is glad to quote her remark, but forgets to judge it. Mme Roland is

indifferent to posterity.

There can be no question of holding forth on ethics. I have seen people

behave badly with great morality and I note every day that integrity has

no need of rules. There is but one moral code that the absurd man can

accept, the one that is not separated from God: the one that is

dictated. But it so happens that he lives outside that God. As for the

others (I mean also immoralism), the absurd man sees nothing in them but

justifications and he has nothing to justify. I start out here from the

principle of his innocence.

That innocence is to be feared.

“Everything is permitted,” exclaims Ivan Karamazov. That, too, smacks of

the absurd. But on condition that it not be taken in the vulgar sense. I

don’t know whether or not it has been sufficiently pointed out that it

is not an outburst of relief or of joy, but rather a bitter

acknowledgment of a fact. The certainty of a God giving a meaning to

life far surpasses in attractiveness the ability to behave badly with

impunity. The choice would not be hard to make. But there is no choice,

and that is where the bitterness comes in. The absurd does not liberate;

it binds. It does not authorize all actions. “Everything is permitted”

does not mean that nothing is forbidden. The absurd merely confers an

equivalence on the consequences of those actions. It does not recommend

crime, for this would be childish, but it restores to remorse its

futility. Likewise, if all experiences are indifferent, that of duty is

as legitimate as any other. One can be virtuous through a whim.

All systems of morality are based on the idea that an action has

consequences that legitimize or cancel it. A mind imbued with the absurd

merely judges that those consequences must be considered calmly. It is

ready to pay up. In other words, there may be responsible persons, but

there are no guilty ones, in its opinion. At very most, such a mind will

consent to use past experience as a basis for its future actions. Time

will prolong time, and life will serve life. In this field that is both

limited and bulging with possibilities, everything in himself, except

his lucidity, seems unforeseeable to him. What rule, then, could emanate

from that unreasonable order? The only truth that might seem instructive

to him is not formal: it comes to life and unfolds in men. The absurd

mind cannot so much expect ethical rules at the end of its reasoning as,

rather, illustrations and the breath of human lives.

The few following images are of this type. They prolong the absurd

reasoning by giving it a specific attitude and their warmth.

Do I need to develop the idea that an example is not necessarily an

example to be followed (even less so, if possible, in the absurd world)

and that these illustrations are not therefore models?

Besides the fact that a certain vocation is required for this, one

becomes ridiculous, with all due allowance, when drawing from Rousseau

the conclusion that one must walk on all fours and from Nietzsche that

one must maltreat one’s mother. “It is essential to be absurd,” writes a

modern author, “it is not essential to be a dupe.”

The attitudes of which I shall treat can assume their whole meaning only

through consideration of their contraries. A sub- clerk in the post

office is the equal of a conqueror if consciousness is common to them.

All experiences are indifferent in this regard.

There are some that do either a service or a disservice to man.

They do him a service if he is conscious. Otherwise, that has no

importance: a man’s failures imply judgment, not of circumstances, but

of himself.

I am choosing solely men who aim only to expend themselves or whom I see

to be expending themselves. That has no further implications. For the

moment I want to speak only of a world in which thoughts, like lives,

are devoid of future. Everything that makes man work and get excited

utilizes hope. The sole thought that is not mendacious is therefore a

sterile thought. In the absurd world the value of a notion or of a life

is measured by its sterility.

Don Juanism

If it were sufficient to love, things would be too easy. The more one

loves, the stronger the absurd grows. It is not through lack of love

that Don Juan goes from woman to woman. It is ridiculous to represent

him as a mystic in quest of total love. But it is indeed because he

loves them with the same passion and each time with his whole self that

he must repeat his gift and his profound quest.

Whence each woman hopes to give him what no one has ever given him. Each

time they are utterly wrong and merely manage to make him feel the need

of that repetition. “At last,” exclaims one of them, “I have given you

love.” Can we be surprised that Don Juan laughs at this? “At last? No,”

he says, “but once more.” Why should it be essential to love rarely in

order to love much?

Is Don Juan melancholy? This is not likely. I shall barely have recourse

to the legend. That laugh, the conquering insolence, that playfulness

and love of the theater are all clear and joyous. Every healthy creature

tends to multiply himself. So it is with Don Juan.

But, furthermore, melancholy people have two reasons for being so: they

don’t know or they hope. Don Juan knows and does not hope. He reminds

one of those artists who know their limits, never go beyond them, and in

that precarious interval in which they take their spiritual stand enjoy

all the wonderful ease of masters. And that is indeed genius: the

intelligence that knows its frontiers. Up to the frontier of physical

death Don Juan is ignorant of melancholy. The moment he knows, his laugh

bursts forth and makes one forgive everything. He was melancholy at the

time when he hoped. Today, on the mouth of that woman he recognizes the

bitter and comforting taste of the only knowledge. Bitter?

Barely: that necessary imperfection that makes happiness perceptible!

It is quite false to try to see in Don Juan a man brought up on

Ecclesiastes. For nothing is vanity to him except the hope of another

life. He proves this because he gambles that other life against heaven

itself. Longing for desire killed by satisfaction, that commonplace of

the impotent man, does not belong to him. That is all right for Faust,

who believed in God enough to sell himself to the devil. For Don Juan

the thing is simpler. Molina’s Burlador ever replies to the threats of

hell: “What a long respite you give me!” What comes after death is

futile, and what a long succession of days for whoever knows how to be

alive! Faust craved worldly goods; the poor man had only to stretch out

his hand. It already amounted to selling his soul when he was unable to

gladden it. As for satiety, Don Juan insists upon it, on the contrary.

If he leaves a woman it is not absolutely because he has ceased to

desire her. A beautiful woman is always desirable. But he desires

another, and no, this is not the same thing.

This life gratifies his every wish, and nothing is worse than losing it.

This madman is a great wise man. But men who live on hope do not thrive

in this universe where kindness yields to generosity, affection to

virile silence, and communion to solitary courage. And all hasten to

say: “He was a weakling, an idealist or a saint.” One has to disparage

the greatness that insults.

People are sufficiently annoyed (or that smile of complicity that

debases what it admires) by Don Juan’s speeches and by that same remark

that he uses on all women. But to anyone who seeks quantity in his joys,

the only thing that matters is efficacy. What is the use of complicating

the passwords that have stood the test? No one, neither the woman nor

the man, listens to them, but rather to the voice that pronounces them.

They are the rule, the convention, and the courtesy. After they are

spoken the most important still remains to be done. Don Juan is already

getting ready for it. Why should he give himself a problem in morality?

He is not like Milosz’s Manara, who damns himself through a desire to be

a saint. Hell for him is a thing to be provoked. He has but one reply to

divine wrath, and that is human honor: “I have honor,” he says to the

Commander, “and I am keeping my promise because I am a knight.” But it

would be just as great an error to make an immoralist of him. In this

regard, he is “like everyone else”: he has the moral code of his likes

and dislikes. Don Juan can be properly understood only by constant

reference to what he commonly symbolizes: the ordinary seducer and the

sexual athlete. He is an ordinary seducer.[16] Except for the difference

that he is conscious, and that is why he is absurd. A seducer who has

become lucid will not change for all that. Seducing is his condition in

life. Only in novels does one change condition or become better. Yet it

can be said that at the same time nothing is changed and everything is

transformed. What Don Juan realizes in action is an ethic of quantity,

whereas the saint, on the contrary, tends toward quality.

Not to believe in the profound meaning of things belongs to the absurd

man. As for those cordial or wonder-struck faces, he eyes them, stores

them up, and does not pause over them. Time keeps up with him. The

absurd man is he who is not apart from time. Don Juan does not think of

“collecting” women. He exhausts their number and with them his chances

of life. “Collecting” amounts to being capable of living off one’s past.

But he rejects regret, that other form of hope. He is incapable of

looking at portraits.

Is he selfish for all that? In his way, probably. But here, too, it is

essential to understand one another. There are those who are made for

living and those who are made for loving. At least Don Juan would be

inclined to say so. But he would do so in a very few words such as he is

capable of choosing. For the love we are speaking of here is clothed in

illusions of the eternal. As all the specialists in passion teach us,

there is no eternal love but what is thwarted. There is scarcely any

passion without struggle. Such a love culminates only in the ultimate

contradiction of death. One must be Werther or nothing.

There, too, there are several ways of committing suicide, one of which

is the total gift and forget-fulness of self. Don Juan, as well as

anyone else, knows that this can be stirring. But he is one of the very

few who know that this is not the important thing. He knows just as well

that those who turn away from all personal life through a great love

enrich themselves perhaps but certainly impoverish those their love has

chosen. A mother or a passionate wife necessarily has a closed heart,

for it is turned away from the world.

A single emotion, a single creature, a single face, but all is devoured.

Quite a different love disturbs Don Juan, and this one is liberating. It

brings with it all the faces in the world, and its tremor comes from the

fact that it knows itself to be mortal. Don Juan has chosen to be

nothing.

For him it is a matter of seeing clearly. We call love what binds us to

certain creatures only by reference to a collective way of seeing for

which books and legends are responsible. But of love I know only that

mixture of desire, affection, and intelligence that binds me to this or

that creature. That compound is not the same for another person. I do

not have the right to cover all these experiences with the same name.

This exempts one from conducting them with the same gestures. The absurd

man multiplies here again what he cannot unify. Thus he discovers a new

way of being which liberates him at least as much as it liberates those

who approach him. There is no noble love but that which recognizes

itself to be both short-lived and exceptional. All those deaths and all

those rebirths gathered together as in a sheaf make up for Don Juan the

flowering of his life. It is his way of giving and of vivifying. I let

it be decided whether or not one can speak of selfishness.

I think at this point of all those who absolutely insist that Don Juan

be punished. Not only in another life, but even in this one. I think of

all those tales, legends, and laughs about the aged Don Juan. But Don

Juan is already ready. To a conscious man old age and what it portends

are not a surprise. Indeed, he is conscious only in so far as he does

not conceal its horror from himself. There was in Athens a temple

dedicated to old age. Children were taken there. As for Don Juan, the

more people laugh at him, the more his figure stands out. Thereby he

rejects the one the romantics lent him. No one wants to laugh at that

tormented, pitiful Don Juan. He is pitied; heaven itself will redeem

him? But that’s not it. In the universe of which Don Juan has a glimpse,

ridicule too is included.

He would consider it normal to be chastised. That is the rule of the

game. And, indeed, it is typical of his nobility to have accepted all

the rules of the game. Yet he knows he is right and that there can be no

question of punishment. A fate is not a punishment.

That is his crime, and how easy it is to understand why the men of God

call down punishment on his head. He achieves a knowledge without

illusions which negates everything they profess. Loving and possessing,

conquering and consuming—that is his way of knowing.

(There is significance in that favorite Scriptural word that calls the

carnal act “knowing.”) He is their worst enemy to the extent that he is

ignorant of them. A chronicler relates that the true Burlador died

assassinated by Fransciscans who wanted “to put an end to the excesses

and blasphemies of Don Juan, whose birth assured him impunity.” Then

they proclaimed that heaven had struck him down. No one has proved that

strange end. Nor has anyone proved the contrary. But without wondering

if it is probable, I can say that it is logical. I want merely to single

out at this point the word “birth” and to play on words: it was the fact

of living that assured his innocence. It was from death alone that he

derived a guilt now become legendary.

What else does that stone Commander signify, that cold statue set in

motion to punish the blood and courage that dared to think?

All the powers of eternal Reason, of order, of universal morality, all

the foreign grandeur of a God open to wrath are summed up in him. That

gigantic and soulless stone merely symbolizes the forces that Don Juan

negated forever. But the Commander’s mission stops there. The thunder

and lightning can return to the imitation heaven whence they were called

forth. The real tragedy takes place quite apart from them. No, it was

not under a stone hand that Don Juan met his death. I am inclined to

believe in the legendary bravado, in that mad laughter of the healthy

man provoking a non- existent God. But, above all, I believe that on

that evening when Don Juan was waiting at Anna’s the Commander didn’t

come, and that after midnight the blasphemer must have felt the dreadful

bitterness of those who have been right. I accept even more readily the

account of his life that has him eventually burying himself in a

monastery. Not that the edifying aspect of the story can he considered

probable. What refuge can he go ask of God? But this symbolizes rather

the logical outcome of a life completely imbued with the absurd, the

grim ending of an existence turned toward short lived joys. At this

point sensual pleasure winds up in asceticism. It is essential to

realize that they may be, as it were, the two aspects of the same

destitution. What more ghastly image can be called up than that of a man

betrayed by his body who, simply because he did not die in time, lives

out the comedy while awaiting the end, face to face with that God he

does not adore, serving him as he served life, kneeling before a void

and arms outstretched toward a heaven without eloquence that he knows to

he also without depth?

I see Don Juan in a cell of one of those Spanish monasteries lost on a

hilltop. And if he contemplates anything at all, it is not the ghosts of

past loves, but perhaps, through a narrow slit in the sun- baked wall,

some silent Spanish plain, a noble, soulless land in which he recognizes

himself. Yes, it is on this melancholy and radiant image that the

curtain must be rung down. The ultimate end, awaited but never desired,

the ultimate end is negligible.

Drama

“The play’s the thing,” says Hamlet, “wherein I’ll catch the conscience

of the king.”

“Catch” is indeed the word. For conscience moves swiftly or withdraws

within itself. It has to be caught on the wing, at that barely

perceptible moment when it glances fleetingly at itself. The everyday

man does not enjoy tarrying. Everything, on the contrary, hurries him

onward. But at the same time nothing interests him more than himself,

especially his potentialities. Whence his interest in the theater, in

the show, where so many fates are offered him, where he can accept the

poetry without feeling the sorrow. There at least can be recognized the

thoughtless man, and he continues to hasten toward some hope or other.

The absurd man begins where that one leaves off, where, ceasing to

admire the play, the mind wants to enter in. Entering into all these

lives, experiencing them in their diversity, amounts to acting them out.

I am not saying that actors in general obey that impulse, that they are

absurd men, but that their fate is an absurd fate which might charm and

attract a lucid heart. It is necessary to establish this in order to

grasp without misunderstanding what will follow.

The actor’s realm is that of the fleeting. Of all kinds of fame, it is

known, his is the most ephemeral. At least, this is said in

conversation. But all kinds of fame are ephemeral. From the point of

view of Sirius, Goethe’s works in ten thousand years will be dust and

his name forgotten. Perhaps a handful of archaeologists will look for

“evidence” as to our era. That idea has always contained a lesson.

Seriously meditated upon, it reduces our perturbations to the profound

nobility that is found in indifference.

Above all, it directs our concerns toward what is most certain— that is,

toward the immediate. Of all kinds of fame the least deceptive is the

one that is lived.

Hence the actor has chosen multiple fame, the fame that is hallowed and

tested. From the fact that everything is to die someday he draws the

best conclusion. An actor succeeds or does not succeed. A writer has

some hope even if he is not appreciated.

He assumes that his works will bear witness to what he was. At best the

actor will leave us a photograph, and nothing of what he was himself,

his gestures and his silences, his gasping or his panting with love,

will come down to us. For him, not to be known is not to act, and not

acting is dying a hundred times with all the creatures he would have

brought to life or resuscitated.

Why should we be surprised to find a fleeting fame built upon the most

ephemeral of creations? The actor has three hours to be Iago or Alceste,

Phedre or Gloucester. In that short space of time he makes them come to

life and die on fifty square yards of boards.

Never has the absurd been so well illustrated or at such length.

What more revelatory epitome can be imagined than those marvelous lives,

those exceptional and total destinies unfolding for a few hours within a

stage set? Off the stage, Sigismundo ceases to count. Two hours later he

is seen dining out.

Then it is, perhaps, that life is a dream. But after Sigismundo comes

another. The hero suffering from uncertainty takes the place of the man

roaring for his revenge. By thus sweeping over centuries and minds, by

miming man as he can be and as he is, the actor has much in common with

that other absurd individual, the traveler. Like him, he drains

something and is constantly on the move. He is a traveler in time and,

for the best, the hunted traveler, pursued by souls. If ever the ethics

of quantity could find sustenance, it is indeed on that strange stage.

To what degree the actor benefits from the characters is hard to say.

But that is not the important thing. It is merely a matter of knowing

how far he identifies himself with those irreplaceable lives. It often

happens that he carries them with him, that they somewhat overflow the

time and place in which they were born. They accompany the actor, who

cannot very readily separate himself from what he has been. Occasionally

when reaching for his glass he resumes Hamlet’s gesture of raising his

cup. No, the distance separating him from the creatures into whom he

infuses life is not so great. He abundantly illustrates every month or

every day that so suggestive truth that there is no frontier between

what a man wants to be and what he is. Always concerned with better

representing, he demonstrates to what a degree appearing creates being.

For that is his art—to simulate absolutely, to project himself as deeply

as possible into lives that are not his own. At the end of his effort

his vocation becomes clear: to apply himself wholeheartedly to being

nothing or to being several. The narrower the limits allotted him for

creating his character, the more necessary his talent. He will die in

three hours under the mask he has assumed today. Within three hours he

must experience and express a whole exceptional life.

That is called losing oneself to find oneself. In those three hours he

travels the whole course of the dead-end path that the man in the

audience takes a lifetime to cover.

A mime of the ephemeral, the actor trains and perfects himself only in

appearances. The theatrical convention is that the heart expresses

itself and communicates itself only through gestures and in the body—or

through the voice, which is as much of the soul as of the body. The rule

of that art insists that everything be magnified and translated into

flesh. If it were essential on the stage to love as people really love,

to employ that irreplaceable voice of the heart, to look as people

contemplate in life, our speech would be in code. But here silences must

make themselves heard. Love speaks up louder, and immobility itself

becomes spectacular. The body is king, Not everyone can be “theatrical,”

and this unjustly maligned word covers a whole aesthetic and a whole

ethic. Half a man’s life is spent in implying, in turning away, and in

keeping silent. Here the actor is the intruder. He breaks the spell

chaining that soul, and at last the passions can rush onto their stage.

They speak in every gesture; they live only through shouts and cries.

Thus the actor creates his characters for display. He outlines or

sculptures them and slips into their imaginary form, transfusing his

blood into their phantoms. I am of course speaking of great drama, the

kind that gives the actor an opportunity to fulfill his wholly physical

fate. Take Shakespeare, for instance. In that impulsive drama the

physical passions lead the dance. They explain everything. Without them

all would collapse. Never would King Lear keep the appointment set by

madness without the brutal gesture that exiles Cordelia and condemns

Edgar. It is just that the unfolding of that tragedy should thenceforth

be dominated by madness. Souls are given over to the demons and their

saraband.

No fewer than four madmen: one by trade, another by intention, and the

last two through suffering—four disordered bodies, four unutterable

aspects of a single condition.

The very scale of the human body is inadequate. The mask and the buskin,

the make-up that reduces and accentuates the face in its essential

elements, the costume that exaggerates and simplifies— that universe

sacrifices everything to appearance and is made solely for the eye.

Through an absurd miracle, it is the body that also brings knowledge. I

should never really understand Iago unless I played his part. It is not

enough to hear him, for I grasp him only at the moment when I see him.

Of the absurd character the actor consequently has the monotony, that

single, oppressive silhouette, simultaneously strange and familiar, that

he carries about from hero to hero. There, too, the great dramatic work

contributes to this unity of tone.[17] This is where the actor

contradicts himself: the same and yet so various, so many souls summed

up in a single body. Yet it is the absurd contradiction itself, that

individual who wants to achieve everything and live everything, that

useless attempt, that ineffectual persistence. What always contradicts

itself nevertheless joins in him. He is at that point where body and

mind converge, where the mind, tired of its defeats, turns toward its

most faithful ally. “And blest are those,” says Hamlet, “whose blood and

judgment are so well commingled that they are not a pipe for fortune’s

finger to sound what stop she please.”

How could the Church have failed to condemn such a practice on the part

of the actor? She repudiated in that art the heretical multiplication of

souls, the emotional debauch, the scandalous presumption of a mind that

objects to living but one life and hurls itself into all forms of

excess. She proscribed in them that preference for the present and that

triumph of Proteus which are the negation of everything she teaches.

Eternity is not a game. A mind foolish enough to prefer a comedy to

eternity has lost its salvation. Between “everywhere” and “forever”

there is no compromise. Whence that much maligned profession can give

rise to a tremendous spiritual conflict. “What matters,” said Nietzsche,

“is not eternal life but eternal vivacity.” All drama is, in fact, in

this choice. Celimene against Elianthe, the whole subject in the absurd

consequence of a nature carried to its extreme, and the verse itself,

the “bad verse,” barely accented like the monotony of the character’s

nature.

Adrienne Lecouvreur on her deathbed was willing to confess and receive

communion, but refused to abjure her profession. She thereby lost the

benefit of the confession. Did this not amount, in effect, to choosing

her absorbing passion in preference to God?

And that woman in the death throes refusing in tears to repudiate what

she called her art gave evidence of a greatness that she never achieved

behind the footlights. This was her finest role and the hardest one to

play. Choosing between heaven and a ridiculous fidelity, preferring

oneself to eternity or losing oneself in God is the age-old tragedy in

which each must play his part.

The actors of the era knew they were excommunicated.

Entering the profession amounted to choosing Hell. And the Church

discerned in them her worst enemies. A few men of letters protest:

“What! Refuse the last rites to Moliere!” But that was just, and

especially in one who died onstage and finished under the actor’s

make-up a life entirely devoted to dispersion. In his case genius is

invoked, which excuses everything. But genius excuses nothing, just

because it refuses to do so.

The actor knew at that time what punishment was in store for him. But

what significance could such vague threats have compared to the final

punishment that life itself was reserving for him? This was the one that

he felt in advance and accepted wholly.

To the actor as to the absurd man, a premature death is irreparable.

Nothing can make up for the sum of faces and centuries he would

otherwise have traversed. But in any case, one has to die. For the actor

is doubtless everywhere, but time sweeps him along, too, and makes its

impression with him.

It requires but a little imagination to feel what an actor’s fate means.

It is in time that he makes up and enumerates his characters. It is in

time likewise that he learns to dominate them.

The greater number of different lives he has lived, the more aloof he

can be from them. The time comes when he must die to the stage and for

the world. What he has lived faces him. He sees clearly. He feels the

harrowing and irreplaceable quality of that adventure. He knows and can

now die. There are homes for aged actors.

Conquest

“No,” says the conqueror, “don’t assume that because I love action I

have had to forget how to think. On the contrary I can throughly define

what I believe. For I believe it firmly and I see it surely and clearly.

Beware of those who say: ‘I know this too well to be able to express

it.’ For if they cannot do so, this is because they don’t know it or

because out of laziness they stopped at the outer crust.

“I have not many opinions. At the end of a life man notices that he has

spent years becoming sure of a single truth. But a single truth, if it

is obvious, is enough to guide an existence. As for me, I decidedly have

something to say about the individual. One must speak of him bluntly

and, if need be, with the appropriate contempt.

“A man is more a man through the things he keeps to himself than through

those he says. There are many that I shall keep to myself. But I firmly

believe that all those who have judged the individual have done so with

much less experience than we on which to base their judgment. The

intelligence, the stirring intelligence perhaps foresaw what it was

essential to note. But the era, its ruins, and its blood overwhelm us

with facts. It was possible for ancient nations, and even for more

recent ones down to our machine age, to weigh one against the other the

virtues of society and of the individual, to try to find out which was

to serve the other. To begin with, that was possible by virtue of that

stubborn aberration in man’s heart according to which human beings were

created to serve or be served. In the second place, it was possible

because neither society nor the individual had yet revealed all their

ability.

“I have seen bright minds express astonishment at the masterpieces of

Dutch painters born at the height of the bloody wars in Flanders, be

amazed by the prayers of Silesian mystics brought up during the

frightful Thirty Years’ War. Eternal values survive secular turmoils

before their astonished eyes. But there has been progress since. The

painters of today are deprived of such serenity. Even if they have

basically the heart the creator needs—I mean the closed heart—it is of

no use; for everyone, including the saint himself, is mobilized. This is

perhaps what I have felt most deeply. At every form that miscarries in

the trenches, at every outline, metaphor, or prayer crushed under steel,

the eternal loses a round. Conscious that I cannot stand aloof from my

time, I have decided to be an integral part of it. This is why I esteem

the individual only because he strikes me as ridiculous and humiliated.

Knowing that there are no victorious causes, I have a liking for lost

causes: they require an uncontaminated soul, equal to its defeat as to

its temporary victories. For anyone who feels bound up with this world’s

fate, the clash of civilizations has something agonizing about it. I

have made that anguish mine at the same time that I wanted to join in.

Between history and the eternal I have chosen history because I like

certainties. Of it, at least, I am certain, and how can I deny this

force crushing me?

“There always comes a time when one must choose between contemplation

and action. This is called becoming a man. Such wrenches are dreadful.

But for a proud heart there can be no compromise. There is God or time,

that cross or this sword. This world has a higher meaning that

transcends its worries, or nothing is true but those worries. One must

live with time and die with it, or else elude it for a greater life. I

know that one can compromise and live in the world while believing in

the eternal. That is called accepting. But I loathe this term and want

all or nothing. If I choose action, don’t think that contemplation is

like an unknown country to me. But it cannot give me everything, and,

deprived of the eternal, I want to ally myself with time. I do not want

to put down to my account either nostalgia or bitterness, and I merely

want to see clearly. I tell you, tomorrow you will be mobilized. For you

and for me that is a liberation. The individual can do nothing and yet

he can do everything. In that wonderful unattached state you understand

why I exalt and crush him at one and the same time. It is the world that

pulverizes him and I who liberate him. I provide him with all his

rights.

“Conquerors know that action is in itself useless. There is but one

useful action, that of remaking man and the earth. I shall never remake

men. But one must do ’as if.’ For the path of struggle leads me to the

flesh. Even humiliated, the flesh is my only certainty. I can live only

on it. The creature is my native land. This is why I have chosen this

absurd and ineffectual effort. This is why I am on the side of the

struggle. The epoch lends itself to this, as I have said. Hitherto the

greatness of a conqueror was geographical. It was measured by the extent

of the conquered territories. There is a reason why the word has changed

in meaning and has ceased to signify the victorious general. The

greatness has changed camp. It lies in protest and the blind-alley

sacrifice. There, too, it is not through a preference for defeat.

Victory would be desirable. But there is but one victory, and it is

eternal. That is the one I shall never have. That is where I stumble and

cling. A revolution is always accomplished against the gods, beginning

with the revolution of Prometheus, the first of modern conquerors. It is

man’s demands made against his fate; the demands of the poor are but a

pretext. Yet I can seize that spirit only in its historical act, and

that is where I make contact with it. Don’t assume, however, that I take

pleasure in it: opposite the essential contradiction, I maintain my

human contradiction. I establish my lucidity in the midst of what

negates it. I exalt man be-fore what crushes him, and my freedom, my

revolt, and my passion come together then in that tension, that

lucidity, and that vast repetition.

“Yes, man is his own end. And he is his only end. If he aims to be

something, it is in this life. Now I know it only too well.

Conquerors sometimes talk of vanquishing and overcoming. But it is

always ‘overcoming oneself’ that they mean. You are well aware of what

that means. Every man has felt himself to be the equal of a god at

certain moments. At least, this is the way it is expressed.

But this comes from the fact that in a flash he felt the amazing

grandeur of the human mind. The conquerors are merely those among men

who are conscious enough of their strength to be sure of living

constantly on those heights and fully aware of that grandeur. It is a

question of arithmetic, of more or less. The conquerors are capable of

the more. But they are capable of no more than man himself when he

wants. This is why they never leave the human crucible, plunging into

the seething soul of revolutions.

“There they find the creature mutilated, but they also encounter there

the only values they like and admire, man and his silence.

This is both their destitution and their wealth. There is but one luxury

for them—that of human relations. How can one fail to realize that in

this vulnerable universe everything that is human and solely human

assumes a more vivid meaning? Taut faces, threatened fraternity, such

strong and chaste friendship among men—these are the true riches because

they are transitory. In their midst the mind is most aware of its powers

and limitations. That is to say, its efficacity. Some have spoken of

genius. But genius is easy to say; I prefer the intelligence. It must be

said that it can be magnificent then. It lights up this desert and

dominates it. It knows its obligations and illustrates them. It will die

at the same time as this body. But knowing this constitutes its freedom.

“We are not ignorant of the fact that all churches are against us. A

heart so keyed up eludes the eternal, and all churches, divine or

political, lay claim to the eternal. Happiness and courage, retribution

or justice are secondary ends for them. It is a doctrine they bring, and

one must subscribe to it. But I have no concern with ideas or with the

eternal. The truths that come within my scope can be touched with the

hand. I cannot separate from them.

This is why you cannot base anything on me: nothing of the conqueror

lasts, not even his doctrines.

“At the end of all that, despite everything, is death. We know also that

it ends everything. This is why those cemeteries all over Europe, which

obsess some among us, are hideous. People beautify only what they love,

and death repels us and tires our patience. It, too, is to be conquered.

The last Carrara, a prisoner in Padua emptied by the plague and besieged

by the Venetians, ran screaming through the halls of his deserted

palace: he was calling on the devil and asking him for death. This was a

way of overcoming it. And it is likewise a mark of courage

characteristic of the Occident to have made so ugly the places where

death thinks itself honored. In the rebel s universe, death exalts

injustice. It is the supreme abuse.

“Others, without compromising either, have chosen the eternal and

denounced the illusion of this world. Their cemeteries smile amid

numerous flowers and birds. That suits the conqueror and gives him a

clear image of what he has rejected. He has chosen, on the contrary, the

black iron fence or the potter’s field. The best among the men of God

occasionally are seized with fright mingled with consideration and pity

for minds that can live with such an image of their death. Yet those

minds derive their strength and justification from this. Our fate stands

before us and we provoke him. Less out of pride than out of awareness of

our ineffectual condition. We, too, sometimes feel pity for ourselves.

It is the only compassion that seems acceptable to us: a feeling that

perhaps you hardly understand and that seems to you scarcely virile. Yet

the most daring among us are the ones who feel it. But we call the lucid

ones virile and we do not want a strength that is apart from lucidity.”

Let me repeat that these images do not propose moral codes and involve

no judgments: they are sketches. They merely represent a style of life.

The lover, the actor, or the adventurer plays the absurd. But equally

well, if he wishes, the chaste man, the civil servant, or the president

of the Republic. It is enough to know and to mask nothing. In Italian

museums are sometimes found little painted screens that the priest used

to hold in front of the face of condemned men to hide the scaffold from

them. The leap in all its forms, rushing into the divine or the eternal,

surrendering to the illusions of the everyday or of the idea—all these

screens hide the absurd. But there are civil servants without screens,

and they are the ones of whom I mean to speak. I have chosen the most

extreme ones. At this level the absurd gives them a royal power. It is

true that those princes are without a kingdom.

But they have this advantage over others: they know that all royalties

are illusory. They know that is their whole nobility, and it is useless

to speak in relation to them of hidden misfortune or the ashes of

disillusion. Being deprived of hope is not despairing. The flames of

earth are surely worth celestial perfumes. Neither I nor anyone can

judge them here. They are not striving to be better; they are attempting

to be consistent. If the term “wise man” can be applied to the man who

lives on what he has without speculating on what he has not, then they

are wise men. One of them, a conqueror but in the realm of mind, a Don

Juan but of knowledge, an actor but of the intelligence, knows this

better than anyone:

“You nowise deserve a privilege on earth and in heaven for having

brought to perfection your dear little meek sheep; you nonetheless

continue to be at best a ridiculous dear little sheep with horns and

nothing more—even supposing that you do not burst with vanity and do not

create a scandal by posing as a judge.”

In any case, it was essential to restore to the absurd reasoning more

cordial examples. The imagination can add many others, inseparable from

time and exile, who likewise know how to live in harmony with a universe

without future and without weakness.

This absurd, godless world is, then, peopled with men who think clearly

and have ceased to hope. And I have not yet spoken of the most absurd

character, who is the creator.

Absurd Creation

Philosophy and Fiction

All those lives maintained in the rarefied air of the absurd could not

persevere without some profound and constant thought to infuse its

strength into them. Right here, it can be only a strange feeling of

fidelity. Conscious men have been seen to fulfill their task amid the

most stupid of wars without considering themselves in contradiction.

This is because it was essential to elude nothing.

There is thus a metaphysical honor in enduring the world’s absurdity.

Conquest or play-acting, multiple loves, absurd revolt are tributes that

man pays to his dignity in a campaign in which he is defeated in

advance.

It is merely a matter of being faithful to the rule of the battle.

That thought may suffice to sustain a mind; it has supported and still

supports whole civilizations. War cannot be negated. One must live it or

die of it. So it is with the absurd: it is a question of breathing with

it, of recognizing its lessons and recovering their flesh. In this

regard the absurd joy par excellence is creation. “Art and nothing but

art,” said Nietzsche; “we have art in order not to die of the truth.”

In the experience that I am attempting to describe and to stress on

several modes, it is certain that a new torment arises wherever another

dies. The childish chasing after forgetfulness, the appeal of

satisfaction are now devoid of echo. But the constant tension that keeps

man face to face with the world, the ordered delirium that urges him to

be receptive to everything leave him another fever. In this universe the

work of art is then the sole chance of keeping his consciousness and of

fixing its adventures. Creating is living doubly. The groping, anxious

quest of a Proust, his meticulous collecting of flowers, of wallpapers,

and of anxieties, signifies nothing else. At the same time, it has no

more significance than the continual and imperceptible creation in which

the actor, the conqueror, and all absurd men indulge every day of their

lives. All try their hands at miming, at repeating, and at recreating

the reality that is theirs. We always end up by having the appearance of

our truths. All existence for a man turned away from the eternal is but

a vast mime under the mask of the absurd. Creation is the great mime.

Such men know to begin with, and then their whole effort is to examine,

to enlarge, and to enrich the ephemeral island on which they have just

landed. But first they must know. For the absurd discovery coincides

with a pause in which future passions are prepared and justified. Even

men without a gospel have their Mount of Olives. And one must not fall

asleep on theirs either. For the absurd man it is not a matter of

explaining and solving, but of experiencing and describing. Everything

begins with lucid indifference.

Describing—that is the last ambition of an absurd thought.

Science likewise, having reached the end of its paradoxes, ceases to

propound and stops to contemplate and sketch the ever virgin landscape

of phenomena. The heart learns thus that the emotion delighting us when

we see the world’s aspects comes to us not from its depth but from their

diversity. Explanation is useless, but the sensation remains and, with

it, the constant attractions of a universe inexhaustible in quantity.

The place of the work of art can be understood at this point.

It marks both the death of an experience and its multiplication.

It is a sort of monotonous and passionate repetition of the themes

already orchestrated by the world: the body, inexhaustible image on the

pediment of temples, forms or colors, number or grief. It is therefore

not indifferent, as a conclusion, to encounter once again the principal

themes of this essay in the wonderful and childish world of the creator.

It would be wrong to see a symbol in it and to think that the work of

art can be considered at last as a refuge for the absurd. It is itself

an absurd phenomenon, and we are concerned merely with its description.

It does not offer an escape for the intellectual ailment. Rather, it is

one of the symptoms of that ailment which reflects it throughout a man’s

whole thought.

But for the first time it makes the mind get outside of itself and

places it in opposition to others, not for it to get lost but to show it

clearly the blind path that all have entered upon. In the time of the

absurd reasoning, creation follows indifference and discovery. It marks

the point from which absurd passions spring and where the reasoning

stops. Its place in this essay is justified in this way.

It will suffice to bring to light a few themes common to the creator and

the thinker in order to find in the work of art all the contradictions

of thought involved in the absurd. Indeed, it is not so much identical

conclusions that prove minds to be related as the contradictions that

are common to them. So it is with thought and creation. I hardly need to

say that the same anguish urges man to these two attitudes. This is

where they coincide in the beginning.

But among all the thoughts that start from the absurd, I have seen that

very few remain within it. And through their deviations or infidelities

I have best been able to measure what belonged to the absurd. Similarly

I must wonder: is an absurd work of art possible?

It would be impossible to insist too much on the arbitrary nature of the

former opposition between art and philosophy. If you insist on taking it

in too limited a sense, it is certainly false. If you mean merely that

these two disciplines each have their peculiar climate, that is probably

true but remains vague. The only acceptable argument used to lie in the

contradiction brought up between the philosopher enclosed within his

system and the artist placed before his work. But this was pertinent for

a certain form of art and of philosophy which we consider secondary

here. The idea of an art detached from its creator is not only outmoded;

it is false.

In opposition to the artist, it is pointed out that no philosopher ever

created several systems. But that is true in so far, indeed, as no

artist ever expressed more than one thing under different aspects.

The instantaneous perfection of art, the necessity for its renewal— this

is true only through a preconceived notion. For the work of art likewise

is a construction and everyone knows how monotonous the great creators

can be. For the same reason as the thinker, the artist commits himself

and becomes himself in his work. That osmosis raises the most important

of aesthetic problems.

Moreover, to anyone who is convinced of the mind’s singleness of

purpose, nothing is more futile than these distinctions based on methods

and objects. There are no frontiers between the disciplines that man

sets himself for understanding and loving. They interlock, and the same

anxiety merges them.

It is necessary to state this to begin with. For an absurd work of art

to be possible, thought in its most lucid form must be involved in it.

But at the same time thought must not be apparent except as the

regulating intelligence. This paradox can be explained according to the

absurd. The work of art is born of the intelligence’s refusal to reason

the concrete. It marks the triumph of the carnal. It is lucid thought

that provokes it, but in that very act that thought repudiates itself.

It will not yield to the temptation of adding to what is described a

deeper meaning that it knows to be illegitimate. The work of art

embodies a drama of the intelligence, but it proves this only

indirectly. The absurd work requires an artist conscious of these

limitations and an art in which the concrete signifies nothing more than

itself. It cannot be the end, the meaning, and the consolation of a

life. Creating or not creating changes nothing. The absurd creator does

not prize his work. He could repudiate it. He does sometimes repudiate

it. An Abyssinia suffices for this, as in the case of Rimbaud.

At the same time a rule of aesthetics can be seen in this. The true work

of art is always on the human scale. It is essentially the one that says

“less.” There is a certain relationship between the global experience of

the artist and the work that reflects that experience, between Wilhelm

Meister and Goethe’s maturity. That relationship is bad when the work

aims to give the whole experience in the lace-paper of an explanatory

literature. That relationship is good when the work is but a piece cut

out of experience, a facet of the diamond in which the inner luster is

epitomized without being limited. In the first case there is overloading

and pretension to the eternal. In the second, a fecund work because of a

whole implied experience, the wealth of which is suspected. The problem

for the absurd artist is to acquire this savoir-vivre which transcends

savoir-faire. And in the end, the great artist under this climate is,

above all, a great living being, it being understood that living in this

case is just as much experiencing as reflecting. The work then embodies

an intellectual drama. The absurd work illustrates thought’s renouncing

of its prestige and its resignation to being no more than the

intelligence that works up appearances and covers with images what has

no reason. If the world were clear, art would not exist.

I am not speaking here of the arts of form or color in which description

alone prevails in its splendid modesty.[18] Expression begins where

thought ends. Those adolescents with empty eyesockets who people temples

and museums—their philosophy has been expressed in gestures. For an

absurd man it is more educative than all libraries. Under another aspect

the same is true for music. If any art is devoid of lessons, it is

certainly music. It is too closely related to mathematics not to have

borrowed their gratuitousness. That game the mind plays with itself

according to set and measured laws takes place in the sonorous compass

that belongs to us and beyond which the vibrations nevertheless meet in

an inhuman universe. There is no purer sensation. These examples are too

easy. The absurd man recognizes as his own these harmonies and these

forms.

But I should like to speak here of a work in which the temptation to

explain remains greatest, in which illusion offers itself automatically,

in which conclusion is almost inevitable. I mean fictional creation. I

propose to inquire whether or not the absurd can hold its own there.

To think is first of all to create a world (or to limit one’s own world,

which comes to the same thing). It is starting out from the basic

disagreement that separates man from his experience in order to find a

common ground according to one’s nostalgia, a universe hedged with

reasons or lighted up with analogies but which, in any case, gives an

opportunity to rescind the unbearable divorce. The philosopher, even if

he is Kant, is a creator. He has his characters, his symbols, and his

secret action. He has his plot endings. On the contrary, the lead taken

by the novel over poetry and the essay merely represents, despite

appearances, a greater intellectualization of the art. Let there be no

mistake about it; I am speaking of the greatest. The fecundity and the

importance of a literary form are often measured by the trash it

contains. The number of bad novels must not make us forget the value of

the best. These, indeed, carry with them their universe. The novel has

its logic, its reasonings, its intuition, and its postulates. It also

has its requirements of clarity.[19]

The classical opposition of which I was speaking above is even less

justified in this particular case. It held in the time when it was easy

to separate philosophy from its authors. Today when thought has ceased

to lay claim to the universal, when its best history would be that of

its repentances, we know that the system, when it is worth while, cannot

be separated from its author. The Ethics itself, in one of its aspects,

is but a long and reasoned personal confession. Abstract thought at last

returns to its prop of flesh.

And, likewise, the fictional activities of the body and of the passions

are regulated a little more according to the requirements of a vision of

the world. The writer has given up telling “stories” and creates his

universe. The great novelists are philosophical novelists—that is, the

contrary of thesis-writers. For instance, Balzac, Sade, Melville,

Stendhal, Dostoevsky, Proust, Malraux, Kafka, to cite but a few.

But in fact the preference they have shown for writing in images rather

than in reasoned arguments is revelatory of a certain thought that is

common to them all, convinced of the uselessness of any principle of

explanation and sure of the educative message of perceptible appearance.

They consider the work of art both as an end and a beginning. It is the

outcome of an often unexpressed philosophy, its illustration and its

consummation. But it is complete only through the implications of that

philosophy. It justifies at last that variant of an old theme that a

little thought estranges from life whereas much thought reconciles to

life.

Incapable of refining the real, thought pauses to mimic it. The novel in

question is the instrument of that simultaneously relative and

inexhaustible knowledge, so like that of love. Of love, fictional

creation has the initial wonder and the fecund rumination.

These at least are the charms I see in it at the outset. But I saw them

likewise in those princes of humiliated thought whose suicides I was

later able to witness.

What interests me, indeed, is knowing and describing the force that

leads them back toward the common path of illusion. The same method will

consequently help me here. The fact of having already utilized it will

allow me to shorten my argument and to sum it up without delay in a

particular example. I want to know whether, accepting a life without

appeal, one can also agree to work and create without appeal and what is

the way leading to these liberties. I want to liberate my universe of

its phantoms and to people it solely with flesh-and-blood truths whose

presence I cannot deny. I can perform absurd work, choose the creative

attitude rather than another. But an absurd attitude, if it is to remain

so, must remain aware of its gratuitousness. So it is with the work of

art. If the commandments of the absurd are not respected, if the work

does not illustrate divorce and revolt, if it sacrifices to illusions

and arouses hope, it ceases to be gratuitous. I can no longer detach

myself from it. My life may find a meaning in it, but that is trifling.

It ceases to be that exercise in detachment and passion which crowns the

splendor and futility of a man’s life.

In the creation in which the temptation to explain is the strongest, can

one overcome that temptation? In the fictional world in which awareness

of the real world is keenest, can I remain faithful to the absurd

without sacrificing to the desire to judge? So many questions to be

taken into consideration in a last effort. It must be already clear what

they signify. They are the last scruples of an awareness that fears to

forsake its initial and difficult lesson in favor of a final illusion.

What holds for creation, looked upon as one of the possible attitudes

for the man conscious of the absurd, holds for all the styles of life

open to him. The conqueror or the actor, the creator or Don Juan may

forget that their exercise in living could not do without awareness of

its mad character. One becomes accustomed so quickly. A man wants to

earn money in order to be happy, and his whole effort and the best of a

life are devoted to the earning of that money. Happiness is forgotten;

the means are taken for the end. Likewise, the whole effort of this

conqueror will be diverted to ambition, which was but a way toward a

greater life. Don Juan in turn will likewise yield to his fate, be

satisfied with that existence whose nobility is of value only through

revolt. For one it is awareness and for the other, revolt; in both cases

the absurd has disappeared. There is so much stubborn hope in the human

heart. The most destitute men often end up by accepting illusion. That

approval prompted by the need for peace inwardly parallels the

existential consent. There are thus gods of light and idols of mud. But

it is essential to find the middle path leading to the faces of man.

So far, the failures of the absurd exigence have best informed us as to

what it is. In the same way, if we are to be informed, it will suffice

to notice that fictional creation can present the same ambiguity as

certain philosophies. Hence I can choose as illustration a work

comprising everything that denotes awareness of the absurd, having a

clear starting-point and a lucid climate. Its consequences will

enlighten us. If the absurd is not respected in it, we shall know by

what expedient illusion enters in. A particular example, a theme, a

creator’s fidelity will suffice, then. This involves the same analysis

that has already been made at greater length.

I shall examine a favorite theme of Dostoevsky. I might just as well

have studied other works.[20] But in this work the problem is treated

directly, in the sense of nobility and emotion, as for the existential

philosophies already discussed. This parallelism serves my purpose.

Kirilov

All of Dostoevsky’s heroes question themselves as to the meaning of

life. In this they are modern: they do not fear ridicule.

What distinguishes modern sensibility from classical sensibility is that

the latter thrives on moral problems and the former on metaphysical

problems. In Dostoevsky’s novels the question is propounded with such

intensity that it can only invite extreme solutions. Existence is

illusory or it is eternal. If Dostoevsky were satisfied with this

inquiry, he would be a philosopher. But he illustrates the consequences

that such intellectual pastimes may have in a man’s life, and in this

regard he is an artist. Among those consequences, his attention is

arrested particularly by the last one, which he himself calls logical

suicide in his Diary of a Writer. In the installments for December 1876,

indeed, he imagines the reasoning of “logical suicide.” Convinced that

human existence is an utter absurdity for anyone without faith in

immortality, the desperate man comes to the following conclusions:

“Since in reply to my questions about happiness, I am told, through the

intermediary of my consciousness, that I cannot be happy except in

harmony with the great all, which I cannot conceive and shall never be

in a position to conceive, it is evident ...”

“Since, finally, in this connection, I assume both the role of the

plaintiff and that of the defendant, of the accused and of the judge,

and since I consider this comedy perpetrated by nature altogether

stupid, and since I even deem it humiliating for me to deign to play it

...”

“In my indisputable capacity of plaintiff and defendant, of judge and

accused, I condemn that nature which, with such impudent nerve, brought

me into being in order to suffer—I condemn it to be annihilated with

me.”

There remains a little humor in that position. This suicide kills

himself because, on the metaphysical plane, he is vexed. In a certain

sense he is taking his revenge. This is his way of proving that he “will

not be had.” It is known, however, that the same theme is embodied, but

with the most wonderful generality, in Kirilov of The Possessed,

likewise an advocate of logical suicide.

Kirilov the engineer declares somewhere that he wants to take his own

life because it “is his idea.” Obviously the word must be taken in its

proper sense. It is for an idea, a thought, that he is getting ready for

death. This is the superior suicide. Progressively, in a series of

scenes in which Kirilov’s mask is gradually illuminated, the fatal

thought driving him is revealed to us. The engineer, in fact, goes back

to the arguments of the Diary. He feels that God is necessary and that

he must exist. But he knows that he does not and cannot exist. “Why do

you not realize,” he exclaims, “that this is sufficient reason for

killing oneself?” That attitude involves likewise for him some of the

absurd consequences. Through indifference he accepts letting his suicide

be used to the advantage of a cause he despises. “I decided last night

that I didn’t care.” And finally he prepares his deed with a mixed

feeling of revolt and freedom. “I shall kill myself in order to assert

my insubordination, my new and dreadful liberty.” It is no longer a

question of revenge, but of revolt. Kirilov is consequently an absurd

character—yet with this essential reservation: he kills himself. But he

himself explains this contradiction, and in such a way that at the same

time he reveals the absurd secret in all its purity. In truth, he adds

to his fatal logic an extraordinary ambition which gives the character

its full perspective: he wants to kill himself to become god.

The reasoning is classic in its clarity. If God does not exist, Kirilov

is god. If God does not exist, Kirilov must kill himself.

Kirilov must therefore kill himself to become god. That logic is absurd,

but it is what is needed. The interesting thing, however, is to give a

meaning to that divinity brought to earth. That amounts to clarifying

the premise: “If God does not exist, I am god,” which still remains

rather obscure. It is important to note at the outset that the man who

flaunts that mad claim is indeed of this world. He performs his

gymnastics every morning to preserve his health. He is stirred by the

joy of Chatov recovering his wife. On a sheet of paper to be found after

his death he wants to draw a face sticking out his tongue at “them.” He

is childish and irascible, passionate, methodical, and sensitive. Of the

superman he has nothing but the logic and the obsession, whereas of man

he has the whole catalogue. Yet it is he who speaks calmly of his

divinity. He is not mad, or else Dostoevsky is. Consequently it is not a

megalomaniac’s illusion that excites him. And taking the words in their

specific sense would, in this instance, be ridiculous. Kirilov himself

helps us to understand. In reply to a question from Stavrogin, he makes

clear that he is not talking of a god-man.

It might be thought that this springs from concern to distinguish

himself from Christ. But in reality it is a matter of annexing Christ.

Kirilov in fact fancies for a moment that Jesus at his death did not

find himself in Paradise. He found out then that his torture had been

useless.

“The laws of nature,” says the engineer, “made Christ live in the midst

of falsehood and die for a falsehood.”

Solely in this sense Jesus indeed personifies the whole human drama. He

is the complete man, being the one who realized the most absurd

condition. He is not the God-man but the man-god.

And, like him, each of us can be crucified and victimized—and is to a

certain degree.

The divinity in question is therefore altogether terrestrial. “For three

years,” says Kirilov, “I sought the attribute of my divinity and I have

found it. The attribute of my divinity is independence.”

Now can be seen the meaning of Kirilov’s premise: “If God does not

exist, I am god.” To become god is merely to be free on this earth, not

to serve an immortal being. Above all, of course, it is drawing all the

inferences from that painful independence. If God exists, all depends on

him and we can do nothing against his will.

If he does not exist, everything depends on us. For Kirilov, as for

Nietzsche, to kill God is to become god oneself; it is to realize on

this earth the eternal life of which the Gospel speaks.[21] But if this

metaphysical crime is enough for man’s fulfillment, why add suicide? Why

kill oneself and leave this world after having won freedom? That is

contradictory. Kirilov is well aware of this, for he adds: “If you feel

that, you are a tsar and, far from killing yourself, you will live

covered with glory.” But men in general do not know it. They do not feel

“that.” As in the time of Prometheus, they entertain blind hopes.[22]

They need to be shown the way and cannot do without preaching.

Consequently, Kirilov must kill himself out of love for humanity. He

must show his brothers a royal and difficult path on which he will be

the first. It is a pedagogical suicide. Kirilov sacrifices himself,

then. But if he is crucified, he will not be victimized. He remains the

man-god, convinced of a death without future, imbued with evangelical

melancholy. “I,” he says, “am unhappy because I am obliged to assert my

freedom.”

But once he is dead and men are at last enlightened, this earth will be

peopled with tsars and lighted up with human glory.

Kirilov’s pistol shot will be the signal for the last revolution. Thus,

it is not despair that urges him to death, but love of his neighbor for

his own sake. Before terminating in blood an indescribable spiritual

adventure, Kirilov makes a remark as old as human suffering: “All is

well.”

This theme of suicide in Dostoevsky, then, is indeed an absurd theme.

Let us merely note before going on that Kirilov reappears in other

characters who themselves set in motion additional absurd themes.

Stavrogin and Ivan Karamazov try out the absurd truths in practical

life. They are the ones liberated by Kirilov’s death. They try their

skill at being tsars. Stavrogin leads an “ironic” life, and it is well

known in what regard. He arouses hatred around him. And yet the key to

the character is found in his farewell letter: “I have not been able to

detest anything.” He is a tsar in indifference. Ivan is likewise by

refusing to surrender the royal powers of the mind.

To those who, like his brother, prove by their lives that it is

essential to humiliate oneself in order to believe, he might reply that

the condition is shameful. His key word is: “Everything is permitted,”

with the appropriate shade of melancholy. Of course, like Nietzsche, the

most famous of God’s assassins, he ends in madness. But this is a risk

worth running, and, faced with such tragic ends, the essential impulse

of the absurd mind is to ask:

“What does that prove?”

Thus the novels, like the Diary, propound the absurd question.

They establish logic unto death, exaltation, “dreadful” freedom, the

glory of the tsars become human. All is well, everything is permitted,

and nothing is hateful—these are absurd judgments. But what an amazing

creation in which those creatures of fire and ice seem so familiar to

us. The passionate world of indifference that rumbles in their hearts

does not seem at all monstrous to us. We recognize in it our everyday

anxieties. And probably no one so much as Dostoevsky has managed to give

the absurd world such familiar and tormenting charms.

Yet what is his conclusion? Two quotations will show the complete

metaphysical reversal that leads the writer to other revelations. The

argument of the one who commits logical suicide having provoked protests

from the critics, Dostoevsky in the following installments of the Diary

amplifies his position and concludes thus:

“If faith in immortality is so necessary to the human being (that

without it he comes to the point of killing himself), it must therefore

be the normal state of humanity. Since this is the case, the immortality

of the human soul exists without any doubt.” Then again in the last

pages of his last novel, at the conclusion of that gigantic combat with

God, some children ask Aliocha: “Karamazov, is it true what religion

says, that we shall rise from the dead, that we shall see one another

again?” And Aliocha answers: “Certainly, we shall see one another again,

we shall joyfully tell one another everything that has happened.’’

Thus Kirilov, Stavrogin, and Ivan are defeated. The Brothers Karamazov

replies to The Possessed. And it is indeed a conclusion.

Aliocha’s case is not ambiguous, as is that of Prince Muichkin. Ill, the

latter lives in a perpetual present, tinged with smiles and

indifference, and that blissful state might be the eternal life of which

the Prince speaks. On the contrary, Aliocha clearly says:

“We shall meet again.” There is no longer any question of suicide and of

madness. What is the use, for anyone who is sure of immortality and of

its joys? Man exchanges his divinity for happiness. “We shall joyfully

tell one another everything that has happened.” Thus again Kirilov’s

pistol rang out somewhere in Russia, but the world continued to cherish

its blind hopes. Men did not understand “that.”

Consequently, it is not an absurd novelist addressing us, but an

existential novelist. Here, too, the leap is touching and gives its

nobility to the art that inspires it. It is a stirring acquiescence,

riddled with doubts, uncertain and ardent. Speaking of The Brothers

Karamazov, Dostoevsky wrote: “The chief question that will be pursued

throughout this book is the very one from which I have suffered

consciously or unconsciously all life long: the existence of God.” It is

hard to believe that a novel sufficed to transform into joyful certainty

the suffering of a lifetime. One commentator[23] correctly pointed out

that Dostoevsky is on Ivan’s side and that the affirmative chapters took

three months of effort whereas what he called “the blasphemies” were

written in three weeks in a state of excitement. There is not one of his

characters who does not have that thorn in the flesh, who does not

aggravate it or seek a remedy for it in sensation or immortality.[24] In

any case, let us remain with this doubt. Here is a work which, in a

chiaroscuro more gripping than the light of day, permits us to seize

man’s struggle against his hopes. Having reached the end, the creator

makes his choice against his characters. That contradiction thus allows

us to make a distinction. It is not an absurd work that is involved

here, but a work that propounds the absurd problem. Dostoevsky’s reply

is humiliation, “shame” according to Stavrogin. An absurd work, on the

contrary, does not provide a reply; that is the whole difference. Let us

note this carefully in conclusion: what contradicts the absurd in that

work is not its Christian character, but rather its announcing a future

life. It is possible to be Christian and absurd. There are examples of

Christians who do not believe in a future life. In regard to the work of

art, it should therefore be possible to define one of the directions of

the absurd analysis that could have been anticipated in the preceding

pages. It leads to propounding “the absurdity of the Gospel.” It throws

light upon this idea, fertile in repercussions, that convictions do not

prevent incredulity. On the contrary, it is easy to see that the author

of The Possessed, familiar with these paths, in conclusion took a quite

different way. The surprising reply of the creator to his characters, of

Do-stoevsky to Kirilov, can indeed be summed up thus: existence is

illusory and it is eternal.

Ephemeral Creation

At this point I perceive, therefore, that hope cannot be eluded forever

and that it can beset even those who wanted to be free of it.

This is the interest I find in the works discussed up to this point. I

could, at least in the realm of creation, list some truly absurd

works.[25] But everything must have a beginning. The object of this

quest is a certain fidelity. The Church has been so harsh with heretics

only because she deemed that there is no worse enemy than a child who

has gone astray. But the record of Gnostic effronteries and the

persistence of Manichean currents have contributed more to the

construction of orthodox dogma than all the prayers. With due allowance,

the same is true of the absurd.

One recognizes one’s course by discovering the paths that stray from it.

At the very conclusion of the absurd reasoning, in one of the attitudes

dictated by its logic, it is not a matter of indifference to find hope

coming back in under one of its most touching guises.

That shows the difficulty of the absurd ascesis. Above all, it shows the

necessity of unfailing alertness and thus confirms the general plan of

this essay.

But if it is still too early to list absurd works, at least a conclusion

can be reached as to the creative attitude, one of those which can

complete absurd existence. Art can never be so well served as by a

negative thought. Its dark and humiliated proceedings are as necessary

to the understanding of a great work as black is to white. To work and

create “for nothing,” to sculpture in clay, to know that one’s creation

has no future, to see one’s work destroyed in a day while being aware

that fundamentally this has no more importance than building for

centuries—this is the difficult wisdom that absurd thought sanctions.

Performing these two tasks simultaneously, negating on the one hand and

magnifying on the other, is the way open to the absurd creator. He must

give the void its colors.

This leads to a special conception of the work of art. Too often the

work of a creator is looked upon as a series of isolated testimonies.

Thus, artist and man of letters are confused. A profound thought is in a

constant state of becoming; it adopts the experience of a life and

assumes its shape, likewise, a man’s sole creation is strengthened in

its successive and multiple aspects: his works. One after another, they

complement one an-other, correct or overtake one another, contradict one

another too. If something brings creation to an end, it is not the

victorious and illusory cry of the blinded artist: “I have said

everything,” but the death of the creator which closes his experience

and the book of his genius.

That effort, that superhuman consciousness are not necessarily apparent

to the reader. There is no mystery in human creation. Will performs this

miracle. But at least there is no true creation without a secret. To be

sure, a succession of works can be but a series of approximations of the

same thought. But it is possible to conceive of another type of creator

proceeding by juxtaposition. Their works may seem to be devoid of

interrelations. To a certain degree, they are contradictory.

But viewed all together, they resume their natural grouping.

From death, for instance, they derive their definitive significance.

They receive their most obvious light from the very life of their

author. At the moment of death, the succession of his works is but a

collection of failures. But if those failures all have the same

resonance, the creator has managed to repeat the image of his own

condition, to make the air echo with the sterile secret he possesses.

The effort to dominate is considerable here. But human intelligence is

up to much more. It will merely indicate clearly the voluntary aspect of

creation. Elsewhere I have brought out the fact that human will had no

other purpose than to maintain awareness.

But that could not do without discipline. Of all the schools of patience

and lucidity, creation is the most effective. It is also the staggering

evidence of man’s sole dignity: the dogged revolt against his condition,

perseverance in an effort considered sterile.

It calls for a daily effort, self-mastery, a precise estimate of the

limits of truth, measure, and strength. It constitutes an ascesis. All

that “for nothing,” in order to repeat and mark time. But perhaps the

great work of art has less importance in itself than in the ordeal it

demands of a man and the opportunity it provides him of overcoming his

phantoms and approaching a little closer to his naked reality.

Let there be no mistake in aesthetics. It is not patient inquiry, the

unceasing, sterile illustration of a thesis that I am calling for here.

Quite the contrary, if I have made myself clearly understood.

The thesis-novel, the work that proves, the most hateful of all, is the

one that most often is inspired by a smug thought. You demonstrate the

truth you feel sure of possessing. But those are ideas one launches, and

ideas are the contrary of thought. Those creators are philosophers,

ashamed of themselves. Those I am speaking of or whom I imagine are, on

the contrary, lucid thinkers.

At a certain point where thought turns back on itself, they raise up the

images of their works like the obvious symbols of a limited, mortal, and

rebellious thought.

They perhaps prove something. But those proofs are ones that the

novelists provide for themselves rather than for the world in general.

The essential is that the novelists should triumph in the concrete and

that this constitute their nobility. This wholly carnal triumph has been

prepared for them by a thought in which abstract powers have been

humiliated. When they are completely so, at the same time the flesh

makes the creation shine forth in all its absurd luster. After all,

ironic philosophies produce passionate works.

Any thought that abandons unity glorifies diversity. And diversity is

the home of art. The only thought to liberate the mind is that which

leaves it alone, certain of its limits and of its impending end. No

doctrine tempts it. It awaits the ripening of the work and of life.

Detached from it, the work will once more give a barely muffled voice to

a soul Forever freed from hope. Or it will give voice to nothing if the

creator, tired of his activity, intends to turn away. That is

equivalent.

Thus, I ask of absurd creation what I required from thought— revolt,

freedom, and diversity. Later on it will manifest its utter futility. In

that daily effort in which intelligence and passion mingle and delight

each other, the absurd man discovers a discipline that will make up the

greatest of his strengths. The required diligence, the doggedness and

lucidity thus resemble the conqueror’s attitude. To create is likewise

to give a shape to one’s fate. For all these characters, their work

defines them at least as much as it is defined by them. The actor taught

us this: there is no frontier between being and appearing.

Let me repeat. None of all this has any real meaning. On the way to that

liberty, there is still a progress to be made. The final effort for

these related minds, creator or conqueror, is to manage to free

themselves also from their undertakings: succeed in granting that the

very work, whether it be conquest, love, or creation, may well not be;

consummate thus the utter futility of any individual life. Indeed, that

gives them more freedom in the realization of that work, just as

becoming aware of the absurdity of life authorized them to plunge into

it with every excess.

All that remains is a fate whose outcome alone is fatal. Outside of that

single fatality of death, everything, joy or happiness, is liberty. A

world remains of which man is the sole master. What bound him was the

illusion of another world. The outcome of his thought, ceasing to be

renunciatory, flowers in images. It frolics— in myths, to be sure, but

myths with no other depth than that of human suffering and, like it,

inexhaustible. Not the divine fable that amuses and blinds, but the

terrestrial face, gesture, and drama in which are summed up a difficult

wisdom and an ephemeral passion.

The Myth Of Sisyphus

The gods had condemned Sisyphus to ceaselessly rolling a rock to the top

of a mountain, whence the stone would fall back of its own weight. They

had thought with some reason that there is no more dreadful punishment

than futile and hopeless labor.

If one believes Homer, Sisyphus was the wisest and most prudent of

mortals. According to another tradition, however, he was disposed to

practice the profession of highwayman. I see no contradiction in this.

Opinions differ as to the reasons why he became the futile laborer of

the underworld. To begin with, he is accused of a certain levity in

regard to the gods. He stole their secrets. AEgina, the daughter of

AEsopus, was carried off by Jupiter. The father was shocked by that

disappearance and complained to Sisyphus. He, who knew of the abduction,

offered to tell about it on condition that AEsopus would give water to

the citadel of Corinth. To the celestial thunderbolts he preferred the

benediction of water. He was punished for this in the underworld. Homer

tells us also that Sisyphus had put Death in chains. Pluto could not

endure the sight of his deserted, silent empire. He dispatched the god

of war, who liberated Death from the hands of her conqueror.

It is said also that Sisyphus, being near to death, rashly wanted to

test his wife’s love. He ordered her to cast his unburied body into the

middle of the public square. Sisyphus woke up in the underworld. And

there, annoyed by an obedience so contrary to human love, he obtained

from Pluto permission to return to earth in order to chastise his wife.

But when he had seen again the face of this world, enjoyed water and

sun, warm stones and the sea, he no longer wanted to go back to the

infernal darkness. Recalls, signs of anger, warnings were of no avail.

Many years more he lived facing the curve of the gulf, the sparkling

sea, and the smiles of earth. A decree of the gods was necessary.

Mercury came and seized the impudent man by the collar and, snatching

him from his joys, led him forcibly back to the underworld, where his

rock was ready for him.

You have already grasped that Sisyphus is the absurd hero. He is, as

much through his passions as through his torture. His scorn of the gods,

his hatred of death, and his passion for life won him that unspeakable

penalty in which the whole being is exerted toward accomplishing

nothing. This is the price that must be paid for the passions of this

earth. Nothing is told us about Sisyphus in the underworld. Myths are

made for the imagination to breathe life into them. As for this myth,

one sees merely the whole effort of a body straining to raise the huge

stone, to roll it and push it up a slope a hundred times over; one sees

the face screwed up, the cheek tight against the stone, the shoulder

bracing the clay-covered mass, the foot wedging it, the fresh start with

arms outstretched, the wholly human security of two earth-clotted hands.

At the very end of his long effort measured by skyless space and time

without depth, the purpose is achieved. Then Sisyphus watches the stone

rush down in a few moments toward that lower world whence he will have

to push it up again toward the summit. He goes back down to the plain.

It is during that return, that pause, that Sisyphus interests me. A face

that toils so close to stones is already stone itself! I see that man

going back down with a heavy yet measured step toward the torment of

which he will never know the end. That hour like a breathing-space which

returns as surely as his suffering, that is the hour of consciousness.

At each of those moments when he leaves the heights and gradually sinks

toward the lairs of the gods, he is superior to his fate. He is stronger

than his rock.

If this myth is tragic, that is because its hero is conscious. Where

would his torture be, indeed, if at every step the hope of succeeding

upheld him? The workman of today works every day in his life at the same

tasks, and this fate is no less absurd. But it is tragic only at the

rare moments when it becomes conscious.

Sisyphus, proletarian of the gods, powerless and rebellious, knows the

whole extent of his wretched condition: it is what he thinks of during

his descent. The lucidity that was to constitute his torture at the same

time crowns his victory. There is no fate that cannot be surmounted by

scorn.

If the descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can also take

place in joy. This word is not too much. Again I fancy Sisyphus

returning toward his rock, and the sorrow was in the beginning. When the

images of earth cling too tightly to memory, when the call of happiness

becomes too insistent, it happens that melancholy rises in man’s heart:

this is the rock’s victory, this is the rock itself. The boundless grief

is too heavy to bear. These are our nights of Gethsemane. But crushing

truths perish from being acknowledged. Thus, CEdipus at the outset obeys

fate without knowing it. But from the moment he knows, his tragedy

begins.

Yet at the same moment, blind and desperate, he realizes that the only

bond linking him to the world is the cool hand of a girl. Then a

tremendous remark rings out: “Despite so many ordeals, my advanced age

and the nobility of my soul make me conclude that all is well.”

Sophocles’ CEdipus, like Dostoevsky’s Kirilov, thus gives the recipe for

the absurd victory. Ancient wisdom confirms modern heroism.

One does not discover the absurd without being tempted to write a manual

of happiness. “What! by such narrow ways—?”

There is but one world, however. Happiness and the absurd are two sons

of the same earth. They are inseparable. It would be a mistake to say

that happiness necessarily springs from the absurd discovery. It happens

as well that the feeling of the absurd springs from happiness. “I

conclude that all is well,” says CEdipus, and that remark is sacred. It

echoes in the wild and limited universe of man. It teaches that all is

not, has not been, exhausted. It drives out of this world a god who had

come into it with dissatisfaction and a preference for futile

sufferings. It makes of fate a human matter, which must be settled among

men.

All Sisyphus’ silent joy is contained therein. His fate belongs to him.

His rock is his thing. Likewise, the absurd man, when he contemplates

his torment, silences all the idols. In the universe suddenly restored

to its silence, the myriad wondering little voices of the earth rise up.

Unconscious, secret calls, invitations from all the faces, they are the

necessary reverse and price of victory. There is no sun without shadow,

and it is es-sential to know the night.

The absurd man says yes and his effort will henceforth be unceasing. If

there is a personal fate, there is no higher destiny, or at least there

is but one which he concludes is inevitable and despicable. For the

rest, he knows himself to be the master of his days. At that subtle

moment when man glances backward over his life, Sisyphus returning

toward his rock, in that slight pivoting he contemplates that series of

unrelated actions which becomes his fate, created by him, combined under

his memory’s eye and soon sealed by his death. Thus, convinced of the

wholly human origin of all that is human, a blind man eager to see who

knows that the night has no end, he is still on the go. The rock is

still rolling.

I leave Sisyphus at the foot of the mountain! One always finds one’s

burden again. But Sisyphus teaches the higher fidelity that negates the

gods and raises rocks. He too concludes that all is well.

This universe henceforth without a master seems to him neither sterile

nor futile. Each atom of that stone, each mineral flake of that

night-filled mountain, in itself forms a world. The struggle itself

toward the heights is enough to fill a man’s heart. One must imagine

Sisyphus happy.

Appendix: Hope and the Absurd in the Work of Franz Kafka

The whole art of Kafka consists in forcing the reader to reread.

His endings, or his absence of endings, suggest explanations which,

however, are not revealed in clear language but, before they seem

justified, require that the story be reread from another point of view.

Sometimes there is a double possibility of interpretation, whence

appears the necessity for two readings. This is what the author wanted.

But it would be wrong to try to interpret everything in Kafka in detail.

A symbol is always in general and, however precise its translation, an

artist can restore to it only its movement: there is no word-for-word

rendering. Moreover, nothing is harder to understand than a symbolic

work. A symbol always transcends the one who makes use of it and makes

him say in reality more than he is aware of expressing. In this regard,

the surest means of getting hold of it is not to provoke it, to begin

the work without a preconceived attitude and not to look for its hidden

currents. For Kafka in particular it is fair to agree to his rules, to

approach the drama through its externals and the novel through its form.

At first glance and for a casual reader, they are disturbing adventures

that carry off quaking and dogged characters into pursuit of problems

they never formulate. In The Trial, Joseph K. is accused. But he doesn’t

know of what. He is doubtless eager to defend himself, but he doesn’t

know why. The lawyers find his case difficult. Meanwhile, he does not

neglect to love, to eat, or to read his paper. Then he is judged. But

the courtroom is very dark.

He doesn’t understand much. He merely assumes that he is condemned, but

to what he barely wonders. At times he suspects just the same, and he

continues living. Some time later two well- dressed and polite gentlemen

come to get him and invite him to follow them. Most courteously they

lead him into a wretched suburb, put his head on a stone, and slit his

throat. Before dying the condemned man says merely: “Like a dog.”

You see that it is hard to speak of a symbol in a tale whose most

obvious quality just happens to be naturalness. But naturalness is a

hard category to understand. There are works in which the event seems

natural to the reader. But there are others (rarer, to be sure) in which

the character considers natural what happens to him. By an odd but

obvious paradox, the more extraordinary the character’s adventures are,

the more noticeable will be the naturalness of the story: it is in

proportion to the divergence we feel between the strangeness of a man’s

life and the simplicity with which that man accepts it. It seems that

this naturalness is Kafka’s. And, precisely, one is well aware what The

Trial means. People have spoken of an image of the human condition. To

be sure. Yet it is both simpler and more complex. I mean that the

significance of the novel is more particular and more personal to Kafka.

To a certain degree, he is the one who does the talking, even though it

is me he confesses. He lives and he is condemned. He learns this on the

first pages of the novel he is pursuing in this world, and if he tries

to cope with this, he nonetheless does so without surprise. He will

never show sufficient astonishment at this lack of astonishment. It is

by such contradictions that the first signs of the absurd work are

recognized. The mind projects into the concrete its spiritual tragedy.

And it can do so solely by means of a perpetual paradox which confers on

colors the power to express the void and on daily gestures the strength

to translate eternal ambitions.

Likewise, The Castle is perhaps a theology in action, but it is first of

all the individual adventure of a soul in quest of its grace, of a man

who asks of this world’s objects their royal secret and of women the

signs of the god that sleeps in them. Metamorphosis, in turn, certainly

represents the horrible imagery of an ethic of lucidity. But it is also

the product of that incalculable amazement man feels at being conscious

of the beast he becomes effortlessly.

In this fundamental ambiguity lies Kafka’s secret. These perpetual

oscillations between the natural and the extraordinary, the individual

and the universal, the tragic and the everyday, the absurd and the

logical, are found throughout his work and give it both its resonance

and its meaning. These are the paradoxes that must be enumerated, the

contradictions that must be strengthened, in order to understand the

absurd work.

A symbol, indeed, assumes two planes, two worlds of ideas and

sensations, and a dictionary of correspondences between them.

This lexicon is the hardest thing to draw up. But awaking to the two

worlds brought face to face is tantamount to getting on the trail of

their secret relationships. In Kafka these two worlds are that of

everyday life on the one hand and, on the other, that of supernatural

anxiety.[26] It seems that we are witnessing here an interminable

exploitation of Nietzsche’s remark: “Great problems are in the street.”

There is in the human condition (and this is a commonplace of all

literatures) a basic absurdity as well as an implacable nobility.

The two coincide, as is natural. Both of them are represented, let me

repeat, in the ridiculous divorce separating our spiritual excesses and

the ephemeral joys of the body. The absurd thing is that it should be

the soul of this body which it transcends so inordinately. Whoever would

like to represent this absurdity must give it life in a series of

parallel contrasts. Thus it is that Kafka expresses tragedy by the

everyday and the absurd by the logical. An actor lends more force to a

tragic character the more careful he is not to exaggerate it. If he is

moderate, the horror he inspires will be immoderate. In this regard

Greek tragedy is rich in lessons.

In a tragic work fate always makes itself felt better in the guise of

logic and naturalness. CEdipus’s fate is announced in advance. It is

decided supernaturally that he will commit the murder and the incest.

The drama’s whole effort is to show the logical system which, from

deduction to deduction, will crown the hero’s misfortune. Merely to

announce to us that uncommon fate is scarcely horrible, because it is

improbable. But if its necessity is demonstrated to us in the framework

of everyday life, society, state, familiar emotion, then the horror is

hallowed. In that revolt that shakes man and makes him say: “That is not

possible,” there is an element of desperate certainty that “that” can

be.

This is the whole secret of Greek tragedy, or at least of one of its

aspects. For there is another which, by a reverse method, would help us

to understand Kafka better. The human heart has a tiresome tendency to

label as fate only what crushes it. But happiness likewise, in its way,

is without reason, since it is inevitable.

Modern man, however, takes the credit for it himself, when he doesn’t

fail to recognize it. Much could be said, on the contrary, about the

privileged fates of Greek tragedy and those favored in legend who, like

Ulysses, in the midst of the worst adventures are saved from themselves.

It was not so easy to return to Ithaca.

What must be remembered in any case is that secret complicity that joins

the logical and the everyday to the tragic. This is why Samsa, the hero

of Metamorphosis, is a traveling salesman. This is why the only thing

that disturbs him in the strange adventure that makes a vermin of him is

that his boss will be angry at his absence.

Legs and feelers grow out on him, his spine arches up, white spots

appear on his belly and—I shall not say that this does not astonish him,

for the effect would be spoiled—but it causes him a “slight annoyance.”

The whole art of Kafka is in that distinction. In his central work, The

Castle, the details of everyday life stand out, and yet in that strange

novel in which nothing concludes and everything begins over again, it is

the essential adventure of a soul in quest of its grace that is

represented. That translation of the problem into action, that

coincidence of the general and the particular are recognized likewise in

the little artifices that belong to every great creator. In The Trial

the hero might have been named Schmidt or Franz Kafka. But he is named

Joseph K. He is not Kafka and yet he is Kafka. He is an average

European. He is like everybody else. But he is also the entity K. who is

the x of this flesh-and-blood equation.

Likewise, if Kafka wants to express the absurd, he will make use of

consistency. You know the story of the crazy man who was fishing in a

bathtub. A doctor with ideas as to psychiatric treatments asked him “if

they were biting,” to which he received the harsh reply: “Of course not,

you fool, since this is a bathtub.”

That story belongs to the baroque type. But in it can be grasped quite

clearly to what a degree the absurd effect is linked to an excess of

logic. Kafka’s world is in truth an indescribable universe in which man

allows himself the tormenting luxury of fishing in a bathtub, knowing

that nothing will come of it.

Consequently, I recognize here a work that is absurd in its principles.

As for The Trial, for instance, I can indeed say that it is a complete

success. Flesh wins out.

Nothing is lacking, neither the unexpressed revolt (but it is what is

writing), nor lucid and mute despair (but it is what is creating), nor

that amazing freedom of manner which the characters of the novel

exemplify until their ultimate death.

Yet this world is not so closed as it seems. Into this universe devoid

of progress, Kafka is going to introduce hope in a strange form. In this

regard The Trial and The Castle do not follow the same direction. They

complement each other. The barely perceptible progression from one to

the other represents a tremendous conquest in the realm of evasion. The

Trial propounds a problem which The Castle, to a certain degree, solves.

The first describes according to a quasi scientific method and without

concluding. The second, to a certain degree, explains. The Trial

diagnoses, and The Castle imagines a treatment. But the remedy proposed

here does not cure. It merely brings the malady back into normal life.

It helps to accept it. In a certain sense (let us think of Kierkegaard),

it makes people cherish it. The Land Surveyor K. cannot imagine another

anxiety than the one that is tormenting him. The very people around him

become attached to that void and that nameless pain, as if suffering

assumed in this case a privileged aspect. “How I need you,” Frieda says

to K. “How forsaken I feel, since knowing you, when you are not with

me.” This subtle remedy that makes us love what crushes us and makes

hope spring up in a world without issue, this sudden “leap” through

which everything is changed, is the secret of the existential revolution

and of The Castle itself.

Few works are more rigorous in their development than The Castle. K. is

named Land Surveyor to the Castle and he arrives in the village. But

from the village to the Castle it is impossible to communicate. For

hundreds of pages K. persists in seeking his way, makes every advance,

uses trickery and expedients, never gets angry, and with disconcerting

good will tries to assume the duties entrusted to him. Each chapter is a

new frustration. And also a new beginning. It is not logic, but

consistent method. The scope of that insistence constitutes the work’s

tragic quality. When K. telephones to the Castle, he hears confused,

mingled voices, vague laughs, distant invitations. That is enough to

feed his hope, like those few signs appearing in summer skies or those

evening anticipations which make up our reason for living. Here is found

the secret of the melancholy peculiar to Kafka. The same, in truth, that

is found in Proust’s work or in the landscape of Plotinus: a nostalgia

for a lost paradise.

“I become very sad,” says Olga, “when Barnabas tells me in the morning

that he is going to the Castle: that probably futile trip, that probably

wasted day, that probably empty hope.”

“Probably”—on this implication Kafka gambles his entire work. But

nothing avails; the quest of the eternal here is meticulous. And those

inspired automata, Kafka’s characters, provide us with a precise image

of what we should be if we were deprived of our distractions[27] and

utterly consigned to the humiliations of the divine.

In The Castle that surrender to the everyday becomes an ethic.

The great hope of K. is to get the Castle to adopt him. Unable to

achieve this alone, his whole effort is to deserve this favor by

becoming an inhabitant of the village, by losing the status of foreigner

that everyone makes him feel. What he wants is an occupation, a home,

the life of a healthy, normal man. He can’t stand his madness any

longer. He wants to be reasonable. He wants to cast off the peculiar

curse that makes him a stranger to the village. The episode of Frieda is

significant in this regard. If he takes as his mistress this woman who

has known one of the Castle’s officials, this is because of her past. He

derives from her something that transcends him while being aware of what

makes her forever unworthy of the Castle. This makes one think of

Kierkegaard’s strange love for Regina Olsen. In certain men, the fire of

eternity consuming them is great enough for them to burn in it the very

heart of those closest to them. The fatal mistake that consists in

giving to God what is not God’s is likewise the subject of this episode

of The Castle. But for Kafka it seems that this is not a mistake. It is

a doctrine and a “leap.” There is nothing that is not God’s.

Even more significant is the fact that the Land Surveyor breaks with

Frieda in order to go toward the Barnabas sisters. For the Barnabas

family is the only one in the village that is utterly forsaken by the

Castle and by the village itself. Amalia, the elder sister, has rejected

the shameful propositions made her by one of the Castle’s officials. The

immoral curse that followed has forever cast her out from the love of

God. Being incapable of losing one’s honor for God amounts to making

oneself unworthy of his grace.

You recognize a theme familiar to existential philosophy: truth contrary

to morality. At this point things are far-reaching. For the path pursued

by Kafka’s hero from Frieda to the Barnabas sisters is the very one that

leads from trusting love to the deification of the absurd. Here again

Kafka’s thought runs parallel to Kierkegaard. It is not surprising that

the “Barnabas story” is placed at the end of the book. The Land

Surveyor’s last attempt is to recapture God through what negates him, to

recognize him, not according to our categories of goodness and beauty,

but behind the empty and hideous aspects of his indifference, of his

injustice, and of his hatred. That stranger who asks the Castle to adopt

him is at the end of his voyage a little more exiled because this time

he is unfaithful to himself, forsaking morality, logic, and intellectual

truths in order to try to enter, endowed solely with his mad hope, the

desert of divine grace.[28]

The word “hope” used here is not ridiculous. On the contrary, the more

tragic the condition described by Kafka, the firmer and more aggressive

that hope becomes. The more truly absurd The Trial is, the more moving

and illegitimate the impassioned “leap” of The Castle seems. But we find

here again in a pure state the paradox of existential thought as it is

expressed, for instance, by Kierkegaard: “Earthly hope must be killed;

only then can one be saved by true hope,”[29]which can be translated:

“One has to have written The Trial to undertake The Castle.”

Most of those who have spoken of Kafka have indeed defined his work as a

desperate cry with no recourse left to man. But this calls for review.

There is hope and hope. To me the optimistic work of Henri Bordeaux

seems peculiarly discouraging. This is because it has nothing for the

discriminating. Malraux’s thought, on the other hand, is always bracing.

But in these two cases neither the same hope nor the same despair is at

issue. I see merely that the absurd work itself may lead to the

infidelity I want to avoid. The work which was but an ineffectual

repetition of a sterile condition, a lucid glorification ol the

ephemeral, becomes here a cradle of illusions. It explains, it gives a

shape to hope. The creator can no longer divorce himself from it. It is

not the tragic game it was to be. It gives a meaning to the author’s

life.

It is strange in any case that works of related inspiration like those

of Kafka, Kierkegaard, or Chestov—those, in short, of existential

novelists and philosophers completely oriented toward the Absurd and its

consequences—should in the long run lead to that tremendous cry of hope.

They embrace the God that consumes them. It is through humility that

hope enters in. For the absurd of this existence assures them a little

more of supernatural reality. If the course of this life leads to God,

there is an outcome after all. And the perseverance, the insistence with

which Kierkegaard, Chestov, and Kafka’s heroes repeat their itineraries

are a special warrant of the uplifting power of that certainty.[30]

Kafka refuses his god moral nobility, evidence, virtue, coherence, but

only the better to fall into his arms. The absurd is recognized,

accepted, and man is resigned to it, but from then on we know that it

has ceased to be the absurd. Within the limits of the human condition,

what greater hope than the hope that allows an escape from that

condition? As I see once more, existential thought in this regard (and

contrary to current opinion) is steeped in a vast hope. The very hope

which at the time of early Christianity and the spreading of the good

news inflamed the ancient world. But in that leap that characterizes all

existential thought, in that insistence, in that surveying of a divinity

devoid of surface, how can one fail to see the mark of a lucidity that

repudiates itself? It is merely claimed that this is pride abdicating to

save itself. Such a repudiation would be fecund. But this does not

change that. The moral value of lucidity cannot be diminished in my eyes

by calling it sterile like all pride. For a truth also, by its very

definition, is sterile. All facts are. In a world where everything is

given and nothing is explained, the fecundity of a value or of a

metaphysic is a notion devoid of meaning.

In any case, you see here in what tradition of thought Kafka’s work

takes its place. It would indeed be intelligent to consider as

inevitable the progression leading from The Trial to The Castle. Joseph

K. and the Land Surveyor K. are merely two poles that attract Kafka.[31]

I shall speak like him and say that his work is probably not absurd. But

that should not deter us from seeing its nobility and universality. They

come from the fact that he managed to represent so fully the everyday

passage from hope to grief and from desperate wisdom to intentional

blindness. His work is universal (a really absurd work is not universal)

to the extent to which it represents the emotionally moving face of man

fleeing humanity, deriving from his contradictions reasons for

believing, reasons for hoping from his fecund despairs, and calling life

his terrifying apprenticeship in death. It is universal because its

inspiration is religious. As in all religions, man is freed of the

weight of his own life. But if I know that, if I can even admire it, I

also know that I am not seeking what is universal, but what is true.

The two may well not coincide.

This particular view will be better understood if I say that truly

hopeless thought just happens to be defined by the opposite criteria and

that the tragic work might be the work that, after all future hope is

exiled, describes the life of a happy man. The more exciting life is,

the more absurd is the idea of losing it. This is perhaps the secret of

that proud aridity felt in Nietzsche’s work. In this connection,

Nietzsche appears to be the only artist to have derived the extreme

consequences of an aesthetic of the Absurd, inasmuch as his final

message lies in a sterile and conquering lucidity and an obstinate

negation of any supernatural consolation.

The preceding should nevertheless suffice to bring out the capital

importance of Kafka in the framework of this essay. Here we are carried

to the confines of human thought. In the fullest sense of the word, it

can be said that everything in that work is essential. In any case, it

propounds the absurd problem altogether.

If one wants to compare these conclusions with our initial remarks, the

content with the form, the secret meaning of The Castle with the natural

art in which it is molded, K.’s passionate, proud quest with the

everyday setting against which it takes place, then one will realize

what may be its greatness. For if nostalgia is the mark of the human,

perhaps no one has given such flesh and volume to these phantoms of

regret. But at the same time will be sensed what exceptional nobility

the absurd work calls for, which is perhaps not found here. If the

nature of art is to bind the general to the particular, ephemeral

eternity of a drop of water to the play of its lights, it is even truer

to judge the greatness of the absurd writer by the distance he is able

to introduce between these two worlds. His secret consists in being able

to find the exact point where they meet in their greatest disproportion.

And, to tell the truth, this geometrical locus of man and the inhuman is

seen everywhere by the pure in heart. If Faust and Don Quixote are

eminent creations of art, this is because of the immeasurable nobilities

they point out to us with their earthly hands. Yet a moment always comes

when the mind negates the truths that those hands can touch. A moment

comes when the creation ceases to be taken tragically; it is merely

taken seriously.

Then man is concerned with hope. But that is not his business. His

business is to turn away from subterfuge. Yet this is just what I find

at the conclusion of the vehement proceedings Kafka institutes against

the whole universe. His unbelievable verdict is this hideous and

upsetting world in which the very moles dare to hope.[32]

Summer In Algiers

for JACQUES HEURGON

The loves we share with a city are often secret loves. Old walled towns

like Paris, Prague, and even Florence are closed in on themselves and

hence limit the world that belongs to them. But Algiers (together with

certain other privileged places such as cities on the sea) opens to the

sky like a mouth or a wound. In Algiers one loves the commonplaces: the

sea at the end of every street, a certain volume of sunlight, the beauty

of the race. And, as always, in that unashamed offering there is a

secret fragrance. In Paris it is possible to be homesick for space and a

beating of wings. Here at least man is gratified in every wish and, sure

of his desires, can at last measure his possessions.

Probably one has to live in Algiers for some time in order to realize

how paralyzing an excess of nature’s bounty can be. There is nothing

here for whoever would learn, educate himself, or better himself. This

country has no lessons to teach. It neither promises nor affords

glimpses. It is satisfied to give, but in abundance. It is completely

accessible to the eyes, and you know it the moment you enjoy it. Its

pleasures are without remedy and its joys without hope. Above all, it

requires clairvoyant souls—that is, without solace. It insists upon

one’s performing an act of lucidity as one performs an act of faith.

Strange country that gives the man it nourishes both his splendor and

his misery! It is not surprising that the sensual riches granted to a

sensitive man of these regions should coincide with the most extreme

destitution. No truth fails to carry with it its bitterness. How can one

be surprised, then, if I never feel more affection for the face of this

country than amid its poorest men?

During their entire youth men find here a life in proportion to their

beauty. Then, later on, the downhill slope and obscurity. They wagered

on the flesh, but knowing they were to lose. In Algiers whoever is young

and alive finds sanctuary and occasion for triumphs everywhere: in the

bay, the sun, the red and white games on the seaward terraces, the

flowers and sports stadiums, the cool- legged girls. But for whoever has

lost his youth there is nothing to cling to and nowhere where melancholy

can escape itself.

Elsewhere, Italian terraces, European cloisters, or the profile of the

Provencal hills—all places where man can flee his humanity and gently

liberate himself from himself. But everything here calls for solitude

and the blood of young men. Goethe on his deathbed calls for light and

this is a historic remark. At Belcourt and Bab-el-Oued old men seated in

the depths of cafes listen to the bragging of young men with plastered

hair.

Summer betrays these beginnings and ends to us in Algiers.

During those months the city is deserted. But the poor remain, and the

sky. We join the former as they go down toward the harbor and man’s

treasures: warmth of the water and the brown bodies of women. In the

evening, sated with such wealth, they return to the oilcloth and

kerosene lamp that constitute the whole setting of their life.

In Algiers no one says “go for a swim,” but rather “indulge in a swim.”

The implications are clear. People swim in the harbor and go to rest on

the buoys. Anyone who passes near a buoy where a pretty girl already is

sunning herself shouts to his friends: “I tell you it’s a seagull.”

These are healthy amusements. They must obviously constitute the ideal

of those youths, since most of them continue the same life in the

winter, undressing every day at noon for a frugal lunch in the sun. Not

that they have read the boring sermons of the nudists, those Protestants

of the flesh (there is a theory of the body quite as tiresome as that of

the mind). But they are simply “comfortable in the sunlight.” The

importance of this custom for our epoch can never be overestimated. For

the first time in two thousand years the body has appeared naked on

beaches.

For twenty centuries men have striven to give decency to Greek insolence

and naivete, to diminish the flesh and complicate dress.

Today, despite that history, young men running on Mediterranean beaches

repeat the gestures of the athletes of Delos. And living thus among

bodies and through one’s body, one becomes aware that it has its

connotations, its life, and, to risk nonsense, a psychology of its

own.[33] The body’s evolution, like that of the mind, has its history,

its vicissitudes, its progress, and its deficiency. With this

distinction, however: color. When you frequent the beach in summer you

become aware of a simultaneous progression of all skins from white to

golden to tanned, ending up in a tobacco color which marks the extreme

limit of the effort of transformation of which the body is capable.

Above the harbor stands the set of white cubes of the Kasbah. When you

are at water level, against the sharp while background of the Arab town

the bodies describe a copper-colored frieze. And as the month of August

progresses and the sun grows, the white of the houses becomes more

blinding and skins take on a darker warmth. How can one fail to

participate, then, in that dialogue of stone and flesh in tune with the

sun and seasons? The whole morning has been spent in diving, in bursts

of laughter amid splashing water, in vigorous paddles around the red and

black freighters (those from Norway with all the scents of wood, those

that come from Germany full of the smell of oil, those that go up and

down the coast and smell of wine and old casks). At the hour when the

sun overflows from every corner of the sky at once, the orange canoe

loaded with brown bodies brings us home in a mad race. And when, having

suddenly interrupted the cadenced beat of the double paddle’s

bright-colored wings, we glide slowly in the calm water of the inner

harbor, how can I fail to feel that I am piloting through the smooth

waters a savage cargo of gods in whom I recognize my brothers?

But at the other end of the city summer is already offering us, by way

of contrast, its other riches: I mean its silence and its boredom. That

silence is not always of the same quality, depending on whether it

springs from the shade or the sunlight. There is the silence of noon on

the Place du Gouvernement. In the shade of the trees surrounding it,

Arabs sell for five sous glasses of iced lemonade flavored with

orange-flowers. Their cry “Cool, cool” can be heard across the empty

square. After their cry silence again falls under the burning sun: in

the vendor’s jug the ice moves and I can hear its tinkle. There is the

silence of the siesta. In the streets of the Marine, in front of the

dirty barbershops it can be measured in the melodious buzzing of flies

behind the hollow reed curtains.

Elsewhere, in the Moorish cafes of the Kasbah the body is silent, unable

to tear itself away, to leave the glass of tea and rediscover time with

the pulsing of its own blood. But, above all, there is the silence of

summer evenings.

Those brief moments when day topples into night must be peopled with

secret signs and summons for my Algiers to be so closely linked to them.

When I spend some time far from that town, I imagine its twilights as

promises of happiness. On the hills above the city there are paths among

the mastics and olive trees.

And toward them my heart turns at such moments. I see flights of black

birds rise against the green horizon. In the sky suddenly divested of

its sun something relaxes. A whole little nation of red clouds stretches

out until it is absorbed in the air. Almost immediately afterward

appears the first star that had been seen taking shape and consistency

in the depth of the sky. And then suddenly, all consuming, night. What

exceptional quality do the fugitive Algerian evenings possess to be able

to release so many things in me? I haven’t time to tire of that

sweetness they leave on my lips before it has disappeared into night. Is

this the secret of its persistence? This country’s affection is

overwhelming and furtive.

But during the moment it is present, one’s heart at least surrenders

completely to it. At Padovani Beach the dance hall is open every day.

And in that huge rectangular box with its entire side open to the sea,

the poor young people of the neighborhood dance until evening. Often I

used to await there a moment of exceptional beauty. During the day the

hall is protected by sloping wooden awnings. When the sun goes down they

are raised. Then the hall is filled with an odd green light born of the

double shell of the sky and the sea. When one is seated far from the

windows, one sees only the sky and, silhouetted against it, the faces of

the dancers passing in succession. Sometimes a waltz is being played,

and against the green background the black profiles whirl obstinately

like those cut-out silhouettes that are attached to a phonograph’s

turntable. Night comes rapidly after this, and with it the lights. But I

am unable to relate the thrill and secrecy that subtle instant holds for

me. I recall at least a magnificent tall girl who had danced all

afternoon. She was wearing a jasmine garland on her tight blue dress,

wet with perspiration from the small of her back to her legs.

She was laughing as she danced and throwing back her head. As she passed

the tables, she left behind her a mingled scent of flowers and flesh.

When evening came, I could no longer see her body pressed tight to her

partner, but against the sky whirled alternating spots of white jasmine

and black hair, and when she would throw back her swelling breast I

would hear her laugh and see her partner’s profile suddenly plunge

forward. I owe to such evenings the idea I have of innocence. In any

case, I learn not to separate these creatures bursting with violent

energy from the sky where their desires whirl.

In the neighborhood movies in Algiers peppermint lozenges are sometimes

sold with, stamped in red, all that is necessary to the awakening of

love: (1) questions: “When will you marry me?” “Do you love me?” and (2)

replies: “Madly,” “Next spring.” After having prepared the way, you pass

them to your neighbor, who answers likewise or else turns a deaf ear. At

Belcourt marriages have been arranged this way and whole lives been

pledged by the mere exchange of peppermint lozenges. And this really

depicts the childlike people of this region.

The distinguishing mark of youth is perhaps a magnificent vocation for

facile joys. But, above all, it is a haste to live that borders on

waste. At Belcourt, as at Bab-el-Oued, people get married young. They go

to work early and in ten years exhaust the experience of a lifetime. A

thirty-year-old workman has already played all the cards in his hand. He

awaits the end between his wife and his children. His joys have been

sudden and merciless, as has been his life. One realizes that he is born

of this country where everything is given to be taken away. In that

plenty and profusion life follows the sweep of great passions, sudden,

exacting, and generous. It is not to be built up, but to be burned up.

Stopping to think and becoming better are out of the question. The

notion of hell, for instance, is merely a funny joke here. Such

imaginings are allowed only to the very virtuous. And I really think

that virtue is a meaningless word in all Algeria. Not that these men

lack principles. They have their code, and a very special one. You are

not disrespectful to your mother. You see that your wife is respected in

the street. You show consideration for a pregnant woman. You don’t

double up on an adversary, because “that looks bad.” Whoever does not

observe these elementary commandments “is not a man,” and the question

is decided. This strikes me as fair and strong. There are still many of

us who automatically observe this code of the street, the only

disinterested one I know. But at the same time the shopkeeper’s ethics

are unknown. I have always seen faces around me filled with pity at the

sight of a man between two policemen. And before knowing whether the man

had stolen, killed his father, or was merely a nonconformist, they would

say:

“The poor fellow,” or else, with a hint of admiration: “He’s a pirate,

all right.”

There are races born for pride and life. They are the ones that nourish

the strangest vocation for boredom. It is also among them that the

attitude toward death is the most repulsive. Aside from sensual

pleasure, the amusements of this race are among the silliest. A society

of bowlers and association banquets, the three- franc movies and parish

feasts have for years provided the recreation of those over thirty.

Algiers Sundays are among the most sinister. How, then, could this race

devoid of spirituality clothe in myths the profound horror of its life?

Everything related to death is either ridiculous or hateful here. This

populace without religion and without idols dies alone after having

lived in a crowd.

I know no more hideous spot than the cemetery on Boulevard Bru, opposite

one of the most beautiful landscapes in the world. An accumulation of

bad taste among the black fencings allows a dreadful melancholy to rise

from this spot where death shows her true likeness. “Everything fades,”

say the heart-shaped ex-votos, “except memory.” And all insist on that

paltry eternity provided us cheaply by the hearts of those who loved us.

The same words fit all despairs. Addressed to the dead man, they speak

to him in the second person (our memory will never forsake you);

lugubrious pretense which attributes a body and desires to what is at

best a black liquid. Elsewhere, amid a deadly profusion of marble

flowers and birds, this bold assertion: “Never will your grave be

without flowers.” But never fear: the inscription surrounds a gilded

stucco bouquet, very time-saving for the living (like those immortelles

which owe their pompous name to the gratitude of those who still jump

onto moving buses). Inasmuch as it is essential to keep up with the

times, the classic warbler is sometimes replaced by an astounding pearl

airplane piloted by a silly angel who, without regard for logic, is

provided with an impressive pair of wings.

Yet how to bring out that these images of death are never separated from

life? Here the values are closely linked. The favorite joke of Algerian

undertakers, when driving an empty hearse, is to shout: “Want a ride,

sister?” to any pretty girls they meet on the way. There is no objection

to seeing a symbol in this, even if somewhat untoward. It may seem

blasphemous, likewise, to reply to the announcement of a death while

winking one’s left eye: “Poor fellow, he’ll never sing again,” or, like

that woman of Oran who bad never loved her husband: “God gave him to me

and God has taken him from me.” But, all in all, I see nothing sacred in

death and am well aware, on the other hand, of the distance there is

between fear and respect. Everything here suggests the horror of dying

in a country that invites one to live. And yet it is under the very

walls of this cemetery that the young of Belcourt have their

assignations and that the girls offer themselves to kisses and caresses.

I am well aware that such a race cannot be accepted by all.

Here intelligence has no place as in Italy. This race is indifferent to

the mind. It has a cult for and admiration of the body. Whence its

strength, its innocent cynicism, and a puerile vanity which explains why

it is so severely judged. It is commonly blamed for its “mentality”—that

is, a way of seeing and of living. And it is true that a certain

intensity of life is inseparable from injustice. Yet here is a rate

without past, without tradition, and yet not without poetry—but a poetry

whose quality I know well, harsh, carnal, far from tenderness, that of

their very sky, the only one in truth to move me and bring me inner

peace. The contrary of a civilized nation is a creative nation. I have

the mad hope that, without knowing it perhaps, these barbarians lounging

on beaches are actually modeling the image of a culture in which the

greatness of man will at last find its true likeness. This race, wholly

cast into its present, lives without myths, without solace. It has put

all its possessions on this earth and therefore remains without defense

against death. All the gifts of physical beauty have been lavished on

it. And with them, the strange avidity that always accompanies that

wealth without future. Everything that is done here shows a horror of

stability and a disregard for the future. People are in haste to live,

and if an art were to be born here it would obey that hatred of

permanence that made the Dorians fashion their first column in wood. And

yet, yes, one can find measure as well as excess in the violent and keen

face of this race, in this summer sky with nothing tender in it, before

which all truths can be uttered and on which no deceptive divinity has

traced the signs of hope or of redemption.

Between this sky and these faces turned toward it, nothing on which to

hang a mythology, a literature, an ethic, or a religion, but stones,

flesh, stars, and those truths the hand can touch.

To feel one’s attachment to a certain region, one’s love for a certain

group of men, to know that there is always a spot where one’s heart will

feel at peace these are many certainties for a single human life. And

yet this is not enough. But at certain moments everything yearns for

that spiritual home. “Yes, we must go back there—there, indeed.” Is

there anything odd in finding on earth that union that Plotinus longed

for? Unity is expressed here in terms of sun and sea. The heart is

sensitive to it through a certain savor of flesh which constitutes its

bitterness and its grandeur. I learn that there is no superhuman

happiness, no eternity outside the sweep of days. These paltry and

essential belongings, these relative truths are the only ones to stir

me. As for the others, the “ideal” truths, I have not enough soul to

understand them. Not that one must be an animal, but I find no meaning

in the happiness of angels. I know simply that this sky will last longer

than I. And what shall I call eternity except what will continue after

my death? I am not expressing here the creature’s satisfaction with his

condition. It is quite a different matter. It is not always easy to be a

man, still less to be a pure man. But being pure is recovering that

spiritual home where one can feel the world’s relationship, where one’s

pulse- beats coincide with the violent throbbing of the two-o’clock sun.

It is well known that one’s native land is always recognized at the

moment of losing it. For those who are too uneasy about themselves,

their native land is the one that negates them. I should not like to be

brutal or seem extravagant. But, after all, what negates me in this life

is first of all what kills me. Everything that exalts life at the same

time increases its absurdity. In the Algerian summer I learn that one

thing only is more tragic than suffering, and that is the life of a

happy man. But it may be also the way to a greater life because it leads

to not cheating.

Many, in fact, feign love of life to evade love itself. They try their

skill at enjoyment and at “indulging in experiences.” But this is

illusory. It requires a rare vocation to be a sensualist. The life of a

man is fulfilled without the aid of his mind, with its backward and

forward movements, at one and the same time its solitude and its

presences. To see these men of Belcourt working, protecting their wives

and children, and often without a reproach, I think one can feel a

secret shame. To be sure, I have no illusions about it.

There is not much love in the lives I am speaking of. I ought to say

that not much remains. But at least they have evaded nothing.

There are words I have never really understood, such as “sin.” Yet I

believe these men have never sinned against life. For if there is a sin

against life, it consists perhaps not so much in despairing of life as

in hoping for another life and in eluding the implacable grandeur of

this life. These men have not cheated. Gods of summer they were at

twenty by their enthusiasm for life, and they still are, deprived of all

hope. I have seen two of them die. They were full of horror, but silent.

It is better thus. From Pandora’s box, where all the ills of humanity

swarmed, the Greeks drew out hope after all the others, as the most

dreadful of all. I know no more stirring symbol; for, contrary to the

general belief, hope equals resignation.

And to live is not to resign oneself. This, at least, is the bitter

lesson of Algerian summers. But already the season is wavering and

summer totters. The first September rains, after such violence and

hardening, are like the liberated earth’s first tears, as if for a few

days this country tried its hand at tenderness. Yet at the same period

the carob trees cover all of Algeria with a scent of love. In the

evening or after the rain, the whole earth, its womb moist with a seed

redolent of bitter almond, rests after having given herself to the sun

all summer long. And again that scent hallows the union of man and earth

and awakens in us the only really virile love in this world: ephemeral

and noble.

(1936)

The Minotaur or The Stop In Oran

for PIERRE GALINDO

This essay dates from 1939. The reader will have to bear this in mind to

judge of the present-day Oran. Impassioned protests from that beautiful

city assure me, as a matter of fact, that all the imperfections have

been (or will be) remedied. On the other hand, the beauties extolled in

this essay have been jealously respected.

Happy and realistic city, Oran has no further need of writers: she is

awaiting tourists.

(1953)

There are no more deserts. There are no more islands. Yet there is a

need for them. In order to understand the world, one has to turn away

from it on occasion; in order to serve men better, one has to hold them

at a distance for a time. But where can one find the solitude necessary

to vigor, the deep breath in which the mind collects itself and courage

gauges its strength? There remain big cities. Simply, certain conditions

are required.

The cities Europe offers us are too full of the din of the past. A

practiced ear can make out the flapping of wings, a fluttering of souls.

The giddy whirl of centuries, of revolutions, of fame can be felt there.

There one cannot forget that the Occident was forged in a series of

uproars. All that does not make for enough silence. Paris is often a

desert for the heart, but at certain moments from the heights of

Pere-Lachaise there blows a revolutionary wind that suddenly fills that

desert with flags and fallen glories. So it is with certain Spanish

towns, with Florence or with Prague.

Salzburg would be peaceful without Mozart. But from time to time there

rings out over the Salzach the great proud cry of Don Juan as he plunges

toward hell. Vienna seems more silent; she is a youngster among cities.

Her stones are no older than three centuries and their youth is ignorant

of melancholy. But Vienna stands at a crossroads of history. Around her

echoes the clash of empires. Certain evenings when the sky is suffused

with blood, the stone horses on the Ring monuments seem to take wing. In

that fleeting moment when everything is reminiscent of power and

history, can he distinctly heard, under the charge of the Polish

squadrons, the crashing fall of the Ottoman Empire. That does not make

for enough silence either.

To be sure, it is just that solitude amid others that men come looking

for in European cities. At least, men with a purpose in life.

There they can choose their company, take it or leave it. How many minds

have been tempered in the trip between their hotel room and the old

stones of the Ile Saint Louis! It is true that others have died there of

isolation. As for the first, at any rate, there they found their reasons

for growing and asserting themselves. They were alone and they weren’t

alone. Centuries of history and beauty, the ardent testimony of a

thousand lives of the past accompanied them along the Seine and spoke to

them both of traditions and of conquests. But their youth urged them to

invite such company. There comes a time, there come periods, when it is

unwelcome. “It’s between us two!” exclaims Rasti-gnac, facing the vast

mustiness of Paris. Two, yes, but that is still too many!

The desert itself has assumed significance; it has been glutted with

poetry. For all the world’s sorrows it is a hallowed spot. But at

certain moments the heart wants nothing so much as spots devoid of

poetry. Descartes, planning to meditate, chose his desert: the most

mercantile city of his era. There he found his solitude and the occasion

for perhaps the greatest of our virile poems: “The first [precept] was

never to accept anything as true unless I knew it to be obviously so.”

It is possible to have less ambition and the same nostalgia. But during

the last three centuries Amsterdam has spawned museums. In order to flee

poetry and yet recapture the peace of stones, other deserts are needed,

other spots without soul and without reprieve. Oran is one of these.

The Street

I have often heard the people of Oran complain: “There is no interesting

circle.” No, indeed! You wouldn’t want one! A few right-thinking people

tried to introduce the customs of another world into this desert,

faithful to the principle that it is impossible to advance art or ideas

without grouping together.[34] The result is such that the only

instructive circles remain those of poker-players, boxing enthusiasts,

bowlers, and the local associations. There at least the unsophisticated

prevails. After all, there exists a certain nobility that does not lend

itself to the lofty. It is sterile by nature.

And those who want to find it leave the “circles” and go out into the

street.

The streets of Oran are doomed to dust, pebbles, and heat. If it rains,

there is a deluge and a sea of mud. But rain or shine, the shops have

the same extravagant and absurd look. All the bad taste of Europe and

the Orient has managed to converge in them. One finds, helter-skelter,

marble greyhounds, ballerinas with swans, versions of Diana the huntress

in green galalith, discus-throwers and reapers, everything that is used

for birthday and wedding gifts, the whole race of painful figurines

constantly called forth by a commercial and playful genie on our

mantelpieces. But such perseverance in bad taste takes on a baroque

aspect that makes one forgive all. Here, presented in a casket of dust,

are the contents of a show window: frightful plaster models of deformed

feet, a group of Rembrandt drawings “sacrificed at 150 francs each,”

practical jokes, tricolored wallets, an eighteenth-century pastel, a

mechanical donkey made of plush, bottles of Provence water for

preserving green olives, and a wretched wooden virgin with an indecent

smile.

(So that no one can go away ignorant, the “management” has propped at

its base a card saying: “Wooden Virgin.”) There can be found in Oran:

1) Cafes with filter-glazed counters sprinkled with the legs and wings

of flies, the proprietor always smiling despite his always empty cafe. A

small black coffee used to cost twelve sous and a large one eighteen.

2) Photographers’ studios where there has been no progress in technique

since the invention of sensitized paper. They exhibit a strange fauna

impossible to encounter in the streets, from the pseudo-sailor leaning

on a console table to the marriageable girl, badly dressed and arms

dangling, standing in front of a sylvan background. It is possible to

assume that these are not portraits from life: they are creations.

3) An edifying abundance of funeral establishments. It is not that

people die more in Oran than elsewhere, but I fancy merely that more is

made of it.

The attractive naivete of this nation of merchants is displayed even in

their advertising. I read, in the handbill of an Oran movie theater, the

advertisement for a third-rate film. I note the adjectives “sumptuous,”

splendid, extraordinary, amazing, staggering, and “tremendous.” At the

end the management informs the public of the considerable sacrifices it

has undertaken to be able to present this startling “realization.”

Nevertheless, the price of tickets will not be increased.

It would be wrong to assume that this is merely a manifestation of that

love of exaggeration characteristic of the south. Rather, the authors of

this marvelous handbill are revealing their sense of psychology. It is

essential to overcome the indifference and profound apathy felt in this

country the moment there is any question of choosing between two shows,

two careers, and, often, even two women. People make up their minds only

when forced to do so. And advertising is well aware of this. It will

assume American proportions, having the same reasons, both here and

there, for getting desperate.

The streets of Oran inform us as to the two essential pleasures of the

local youth: getting one’s shoes shined and displaying those same shoes

on the boulevard. In order to have a clear idea of the first of these

delights, one has to entrust one’s shoes, at ten o’clock on a Sunday

morning, to the shoe-shiners in Boulevard Gal-lieni. Perched on high

armchairs, one can enjoy that peculiar satisfaction produced, even upon

a rank outsider, by the sight of men in love with their job, as the

shoe-shiners of Oran obviously are.

Everything is worked over in detail. Several brushes, three kinds of

cloths, the polish mixed with gasoline. One might think the operation is

finished when a perfect shine comes to life under the soft brush. But

the same insistent hand covers the glossy surface again with polish,

rubs it, dulls it, makes the cream penetrate the heart of the leather,

and then brings forth, under the same brush, a double and really

definitive gloss sprung from the depths of the leather. The wonders

achieved in this way are then exhibited to the connoisseurs. In order to

appreciate such pleasures of the boulevard, you ought to see the

masquerade of youth taking place every evening on the main arteries of

the city. Between the ages of sixteen and twenty the young people of

Oran “Society” borrow their models of elegance from American films and

put on their fancy dress before going out to dinner. With wavy, oiled

hair protruding from under a felt hat slanted over the left ear and

peaked over the right eye, the neck encircled by a collar big enough to

accommodate the straggling hair, the microscopic knot of the necktie

kept in place by a regulation pin, with thigh-length coat and waist

close to the hips, with light-colored and noticeably short trousers,

with dazzlingly shiny triple-soled shoes, every evening those youths

make the sidewalks ring with their metal- tipped soles. In all things

they are bent on imitating the bearing, forthrightness, and superiority

of Mr. Clark Gable. For this reason the local carpers commonly nickname

those youths, by favor of a casual pronunciation, “Clarques.”

At any rate, the main boulevards of Oran are invaded late in the

afternoon by an army of attractive adolescents who go to the greatest

trouble to look like a bad lot. Inasmuch as the girls of Oran feel

traditionally engaged to these softhearted gangsters, they likewise

flaunt the make-up and elegance of popular American actresses.

Consequently, the same wits call them “Marlenes.” Thus on the evening

boulevards when the sound of birds rises skyward from the palm trees,

dozens of Clarques and Marlenes meet, eye and size up one another, happy

to be alive and to cut a figure, indulging for an hour in the

intoxication of perfect existences.

There can then be witnessed, the jealous say, the meetings of the

American Commission. But in these words lies the bitterness of those

over thirty who have no connection with such diversions.

They fail to appreciate those daily congresses of youth and romance.

These are, in truth, the parliaments of birds that are met in Hindu

literature. But no one on the boulevards of Oran debates the problem of

being or worries about the way to perfection. There remains nothing but

flappings of wings, plumed struttings, coquettish and victorious graces,

a great burst of carefree song that disappears with the night.

From here I can hear Klestakov: “I shall soon have to be concerned with

something lofty.” Alas, he is quite capable of it! If he were urged, he

would people this desert within a few years. But for the moment a

somewhat secret soul must liberate itself in this facile city with its

parade of painted girls unable, nevertheless, to simulate emotion,

feigning coyness so badly that the pretense is immediately obvious. Be

concerned with something lofty! Just see:

Santa-Cruz cut out of the rock, the mountains, the flat sea, the violent

wind and the sun, the great cranes of the harbor, the trains, the

hangars, the quays, and the huge ramps climbing up the city’s rock, and

in the city itself these diversions and this boredom, this hubbub and

this solitude. Perhaps, indeed, all this is not sufficiently lofty. But

the great value of such overpopulated islands is that in them the heart

strips bare. Silence is no longer possible except in noisy cities. From

Amsterdam Descartes writes to the aged Guez de Balzac: “I go out walking

every day amid the confusion of a great crowd, with as much freedom and

tranquillity as you could do on your garden paths.”[35]

The Desert in Oran

Obliged to live facing a wonderful landscape, the people of Oran have

overcome this fearful ordeal by covering their city with very ugly

constructions. One expects to find a city open to the sea, washed and

refreshed by the evening breeze. And aside from the Spanish quarter,[36]

one finds a walled town that turns its back to the sea, that has been

built up by turning back on itself like a snail. Oran is a great

circular yellow wall covered over with a leaden sky. In the beginning

you wander in the labyrinth, seeking the sea like the sign of Ariadne.

But you turn round and round in pale and oppressive streets, and

eventually the Minotaur devours the people of Oran: the Minotaur is

boredom. For some time the citizens of Oran have given up wandering.

They have accepted being eaten.

It is impossible to know what stone is without coming to Oran.

In that dustiest of cities, the pebble is king. It is so much

appreciated that shopkeepers exhibit it in their show windows to hold

papers in place or even for mere display. Piles of them are set up along

the streets, doubtless for the eyes’ delight, since a year later the

pile is still there. Whatever elsewhere derives its poetry from the

vegetable kingdom here takes on a stone face. The hundred or so trees

that can be found in the business section have been carefully covered

with dust. They are petrified plants whose branches give off an acrid,

dusty smell. In Algiers the Arab cemeteries have a well-known

mellowness. In Oran, above the Ras-el-Ain ravine, facing the sea this

time, flat against the blue sky, are fields of chalky, friable pebbles

in which the sun blinds with its fires. Amid these bare bones of the

earth a purple geranium, from time to time, contributes its life and

fresh blood to the landscape. The whole city has solidified in a stony

matrix. Seen from Les Planteurs, the depth of the cliffs surrounding it

is so great that the landscape becomes unreal, so mineral it is. Man is

outlawed from it. So much heavy beauty seems to come from another world.

If the desert can be defined as a soulless place where the sky alone is

king, then Oran is awaiting her prophets. All around and above the city

the brutal nature of Africa is indeed clad in her burning charms. She

bursts the unfortunate stage setting with which she is covered; she

shrieks forth between all the houses and over all the roofs. If one

climbs one of the roads up the mountain of Santa-Cruz, the first thing

to be visible is the scattered colored cubes of Oran. But a little

higher and already the jagged cliffs that surround the plateau crouch in

the sea like red beasts. Still a little higher and a great vortex of sun

and wind sweeps over, airs out, and obscures the untidy city scattered

in disorder all over a rocky landscape. The opposition here is between

magnificent human anarchy and the permanence of an unchanging sea. This

is enough to make a staggering scent of life rise toward the

mountainside road.

There is something implacable about the desert. The mineral sky of Oran,

her streets and trees in their coating of dust— everything contributes

to creating this dense and impassible universe in which the heart and

mind are never distracted from themselves, nor from their sole object,

which is man. I am speaking here of difficult places of retreat. Books

are written on Florence or Athens. Those cities have formed so many

European minds that they must have a meaning. They have the means of

moving to tears or of uplifting. They quiet a certain spiritual hunger

whose bread is memory. But can one be moved by a city where nothing

attracts the mind, where the very ugliness is anonymous, where the past

is reduced to nothing? Emptiness, boredom, an indifferent sky, what are

the charms of such places?

Doubtless solitude and, perhaps, the human creature.

For a certain race of men, wherever the human creature is beautiful is a

bitter native land. Oran is one of its thousand capitals.

Sports

The Central Sporting Club, on rue du Fondouk in Oran, is giving an

evening of boxing which it insists will be appreciated by real

enthusiasts. Interpreted, this means that the boxers on the bill are far

from being stars, that some of them are entering the ring for the first

time, and that consequently you can count, if not on the skill, at least

on the courage of the opponents. A native having thrilled me with the

firm promise that “blood would flow,” I find myself that evening among

the real enthusiasts.

Apparently the latter never insist on comfort. To be sure, a ring has

been set up at the back of a sort of whitewashed garage, covered with

corrugated iron and violently lighted. Folding chairs have been lined up

in a square around the ropes. These are the “honor rings.” Most of the

length of the hall has been filled with seats, and behind them opens a

large free space called “lounge” by reason of the fact that not one of

the five hundred persons in it could take out a handkerchief without

causing serious accidents. In this rectangular box live and breathe some

thousand men and two or three women—the kind who, according to my

neighbor, always insist on “attracting attention.” Everybody is sweating

fiercely.

While waiting for the fights of the “young hopefuls” a gigantic

phonograph grinds out a Tino Rossi record. This is the sentimental song

before the murder.

The patience of a true enthusiast is unlimited. The fight announced for

nine o’clock has not even begun at nine thirty and no one has protested.

The spring weather is warm and the smell of a humanity in shirt sleeves

is exciting. Lively discussion goes on among the periodic explosions of

lemon-soda corks and the tireless lament of the Corsican singer. A few

late arrivals are wedged into the audience when a spotlight throws a

blinding light onto the ring.

The fights of the young hopefuls begin.

The young hopefuls, or beginners, who are fighting for the fun of it,

are always eager to prove this by massacring each other at the earliest

opportunity, in defiance of technique. They were never able to last more

than three rounds. The hero of the evening in this regard is young “Kid

Airplane,” who in regular life sells lottery tickets on cafe terraces.

His opponent, indeed, hurtled awkwardly out of the ring at the beginning

of the second round after contact with a fist wielded like a propeller.

The crowd got somewhat excited, but this is still an act of courtesy.

Gravely it breathes in the hallowed air of the embrocation. It watches

these series of slow rites and unregulated sacrifices, made even more

authentic by the propitiatory designs, on the white wall, of the

fighters’ shadows. These are the deliberate ceremonial prologues of a

savage religion. The trance will not come until later.

And it so happens that the loudspeaker announces Amar, “the tough

Oranese who has never disarmed,” against Perez, “the slugger from

Algiers.” An uninitiate would misinterpret the yelling that greets the

introduction of the boxers in the ring. He would imagine some

sensational combat in which the boxers were to settle a personal quarrel

known to the public. To tell the truth, it is a quarrel they are going

to settle. But it is the one that for the past hundred years has

mortally separated Algiers and Oran. Back in history, these two North

African cities would have already bled each other white as Pisa and

Florence did in happier times. Their rivalry is all the stronger just

because it probably has no basis.

Having every reason to like each other, they loathe each other

proportionately. The Oranese accuse the citizens of Algiers of “sham.”

The people of Algiers imply that the Oranese are rustic. These are

bloodier insults than they might seem because they are metaphysical. And

unable to lay siege to each other, Oran and Algiers meet, compete, and

insult each other on the field of sports, statistics, and public works.

Thus a page of history is unfolding in the ring. And the tough Oranese,

backed by a thousand yelling voices, is defending against Perez a way of

life and the pride of a province. Truth forces me to admit that Amar is

not conducting his discussion well. His argument has a flaw: he lacks

reach. The slugger from Algiers, on the contrary, has the required reach

in his argument. It lands persuasively between his contradictor’s eyes.

The Oranese bleeds magnificently amid the vociferations of a wild

audience. Despite the repeated encouragements of the gallery and of my

neighbor, despite the dauntless shouts of “Kill him!”, “Floor him!”, the

insidious “Below the belt,”

“Oh, the referee missed that one!”, the optimistic “He’s pooped,” “He

can’t take any more,” nevertheless the man from Algiers is proclaimed

the winner on points amid interminable catcalls. My neighbor, who is

inclined to talk of sportsmanship, applauds ostensibly, while slipping

to me in a voice made faint by so many shouts: “So that he won’t be able

to say back there that we of Oran are savages.”

But throughout the audience, fights not included on the program have

already broken out. Chairs are brandished, the police clear a path,

excitement is at its height. In order to calm these good people and

contribute to the return of silence, the “management,” without losing a

moment, commissions the loudspeaker to boom out “Sambre-et-Meuse.” For a

few minutes the audience has a really warlike look. Confused clusters of

com-batants and voluntary referees sway in the grip of policemen; the

gallery exults and calls for the rest of the program with wild cries,

cock-a- doodle-doo’s, and mocking catcalls drowned in the irresistible

flood from the military band.

But the announcement or the big fight is enough to restore calm. This

takes place suddenly, without flourishes, just as actors leave the stage

once the play is finished. With the greatest unconcern, hats are dusted

off, chairs are put back in place, and without transition all faces

assume the kindly expression of the respectable member of the audience

who has paid for his ticket to a family concert.

The last fight pits a French champion of the Navy against an Oran boxer.

This time the difference in reach is to the advantage of the latter. But

his superiorities, during the first rounds, do not stir the crowd. They

are sleeping off the effects of their first excitement; they are

sobering up. They are still short of breath. If they applaud, there is

no passion in it. They hiss without animosity.

The audience is divided into two camps, as is appropriate in the

interest of fairness. But each individual’s choice obeys that

indifference that follows on great expenditures of energy. If the

Frenchman holds his own, if the Oranese forgets that one doesn’t lead

with the head, the boxer is bent under a volley of hisses, but

immediately pulled upright again by a burst of applause. Not until the

seventh round does sport rise to the surface again, at the same time

that the real enthusiasts begin to emerge from their fatigue.

The Frenchman, to tell the truth, has touched the mat and, eager to win

back points, has hurled himself on his opponent. “What did I tell you?”

said my neighbor; “it’s going to be a fight to the finish.”

Indeed, it is a fight to the finish. Covered with sweat under the

pitiless light, both boxers open their guard, close their eyes as they

hit, shove with shoulders and knees, swap their blood, and snort with

rage. As one man, the audience has stood up and punctuates the efforts

of its two heroes. It receives the blows, returns them, echoes them in a

thousand hollow, panting voices. The same ones who had chosen their

favorite in indifference cling to their choice through obstinacy and

defend it passionately. Every ten seconds a shout from my neighbor

pierces my right ear: “Go to it, gob; come on, Navy!” while another man

in front of us shouts to the Oranese:

“Anda! hombre!” The man and the gob go to it, and together with them, in

this temple of whitewash, iron, and cement, an audience completely given

over to gods with cauliflower ears. Every blow that gives a dull sound

on the shining pectorals echoes in vast vibrations in the very body of

the crowd, which, with the boxers, is making its last effort.

In such an atmosphere a draw is badly received. Indeed, it runs counter

to a quite Manichean tendency in the audience. There is good and there

is evil, the winner and the loser. One must be either right or wrong.

The conclusion of this impeccable logic is immediately provided by two

thousand energetic lungs accusing the judges of being sold, or bought.

But the gob has walked over and embraced his rival in the ring, drinking

in his fraternal sweat.

This is enough to make the audience, reversing its view, burst out in

sudden applause. My neighbor is right: they are not savages.

The crowd pouring out, under a sky full of silence and stars, has just

fought the most exhausting fight. It keeps quiet and disappears

furtively, without any energy left for post mortems.

There is good and there is evil; that religion is merciless. The band of

faithful is now no more than a group of black-and-white shadows

disappearing into the night. For force and violence are solitary gods.

They contribute nothing to memory. On the contrary, they distribute

their miracles by the handful in the present. They are made for this

race without past which celebrates its communions around the prize ring.

These are rather difficult rites but ones that simplify everything. Good

and evil, winner and loser.

At Corinth two temples stood side by side, the temple of Violence and

the temple of Necessity.

Monuments

For many reasons due as much to economics as to metaphysics, it may be

said that the Oranese style, if there is one, forcefully and clearly

appears in the extraordinary edifice called the Maison du Colon. Oran

hardly lacks monuments. The city has its quota of imperial marshals,

ministers, and local benefactors. They are found on dusty little

squares, resigned to rain and sun, they too converted to stone and

boredom. But, in any case, they represent contributions from the

outside. In that happy barbary they are the regrettable marks of

civilization.

Oran, on the other hand, has raised up her altars and rostra to her own

honor. In the very heart of the mercantile city, having to construct a

common home for the innumerable agricultural organizations that keep

this country alive, the people of Oran conceived the idea of building

solidly a convincing image of their virtues: the Maison du Colon. To

judge from the edifice, those virtues are three in number: boldness in

taste, love of violence, and a feeling for historical syntheses. Egypt,

Byzantium, and Munich collaborated in the delicate construction of a

piece of pastry in the shape of a bowl upside down. Multicolored stones,

most vigorous in effect, have been brought in to outline the roof. These

mosaics are so exuberantly persuasive that at first you see nothing but

an amorphous effulgence. But with a closer view and your attention

called to it, you discover that they have a meaning: a graceful

colonist, wearing a bow tie and white pith helmet, is receiving the

homage of a procession of slaves dressed in classical style.[37] The

edifice and its colored illustrations have been set down in the middle

of a square in the to-and-fro of the little two-car trams whose filth is

one of the charms of the city.

Oran greatly cherishes also the two lions of its Place d’Armes, or

parade ground. Since 1888 they have been sitting in state on opposite

sides of the municipal stairs. Their author was named ( ain. They have

majesty and a stubby torso. It is said that at night they get down from

their pedestal one after the other, silently pace around the dark

square, and on occasion uninate at length under the big, dusty ficus

trees. These, of course, are rumors to which the people of Oran lend an

indulgent ear. But it is unlikely.

Despite a certain amount of research, I have not been able to get

interested in Cain. I merely learned that he had the reputation of being

a skillful animal-sculptor. Yet I often think of him. This is an

intellectual bent that comes naturally in Oran. Here is a sonorously

named artist who left an unimportant work here.

Several hundred thousand people are familiar with the easygoing beasts

he put in front of a pretentious town hall. This is one way of

succeeding in art. To be sure, these two lions, like thousands of works

of the same type, are proof of something else than talent.

Others have created “The Night Watch,” “Saint Francis Receiving the

Stigmata,” “David,” or the Pharsalian bas-relief called “The

Glorification of the Flower.” Cain, on the other hand, set up two

hilarious snouts on the square of a mercantile province overseas.

But the David will go down one day with Florence and the lions will

perhaps be saved from the catastrophe. Let me repeat, they are proof of

something else.

Can one state this idea clearly? In this work there are insignificance

and solidity. Spirit counts for nothing and matter for a great deal.

Mediocrity insists upon lasting by all means, including bronze. It is

refused a right to eternity, and every day it takes that right. Is it

not eternity itself? In any event, such perseverance is capable of

stirring, and it involves its lesson, that of all the monuments of Oran,

and of Oran herself. An hour a day, every so often, it forces you to pay

attention to something that has no importance. The mind profits from

such recurrences. In a sense this is its hygiene, and since it

absolutely needs its moments of humility, it seems to me that this

chance to indulge in stupidity is better than others. Everything that is

ephemeral wants to last. Let us say that everything wants to last. Human

productions mean nothing else, and in this regard Cain’s lions have the

same chances as the ruins of Angkor. This disposes one toward modesty.

There are other Oranese monuments. Or at least they deserve this name

because they, too, stand for their city, and perhaps in a more

significant way. They are the public works at present covering the coast

for some ten kilometers. Apparently it is a matter of transforming the

most luminous of bays into a gigantic harbor. In reality it is one more

chance for man to come to grips with stone.

In the paintings of certain Flemish masters a theme of strikingly

general application recurs insistently: the building of the Tower of

Babel. Vast landscapes, rocks climbing up to heaven, steep slopes

teeming with workmen, animals, ladders, strange machines, cords,

pulleys. Man, moreover, is there only to give scale to the inhuman scope

of the construction. This is what the Oran coast makes one think of,

west of the city.

Clinging to vast slopes, rails, dump-cars, cranes, tiny trains ... Under

a broiling sun, toy-like locomotives round huge blocks of stone amid

whistles, dust, and smoke. Day and night a nation of ants bustles about

on the smoking carcass of the mountain.

Clinging all up and down a single cord against the side of the cliff,

dozens of men, their bellies pushing against the handles of automatic

drills, vibrate in empty space all day long and break off whole masses

of rock that hurtle down in dust and rumbling.

Farther on, dump-carts tip their loads over the slopes; and the rocks,

suddenly poured seaward, bound and roll into the water, each large lump

followed by a scattering of lighter stones. At regular intervals, at

dead of night or in broad daylight, detonations shake the whole mountain

and stir up the sea itself.

Man, in this vast construction field, makes a frontal attack on stone.

And if one could forget, for a moment at least, the harsh slavery that

makes this work possible, one would have to admire.

These stones, torn from the mountain, serve man in his plans. They pile

up under the first waves, gradually emerge, and finally take their place

to form a jetty, soon covered with men and machines which advance, day

after day, toward the open sea. Without stopping, huge steel jaws bite

into the cliff’s belly, turn round, and disgorge into the water their

overflowing gravel. As the coastal cliff is lowered, the whole coast

encroaches irresistibly on the sea.

Of course, destroying stone is not possible. It is merely moved from one

place to another. In any case, it will last longer than the men who use

it. For the moment, it satisfies their will to action.

That in itself is probably useless. But moving things about is the work

of men; one must choose doing that or nothing.[38] Obviously the people

of Oran have chosen. In front of that indifferent bay, for many years

more they will pile up stones along the coast. In a hundred

years—tomorrow, in other words—they will have to begin again. But today

these heaps of rocks testify for the men in masks of dust and sweat who

move about among them. The true monuments of Oran are still her stones.

Ariadne’s Stone

It seems that the people of Oran are like that friend of Flaubert who,

on the point of death, casting a last glance at this irreplaceable

earth, exclaimed:

“Close the window; it’s too beautiful.” They have closed the window,

they have walled themselves in, they have cast out the landscape. But

Flaubert’s friend, Le Poittevin, died, and after him days continued to

be added to days. Likewise, beyond the yellow walls of Oran, land and

sea continue their indifferent dialogue. That permanence in the world

has always had contrary charms for man. It drives him to despair and

excites him. The world never says but one thing; first it interests,

then it bores. But eventually it wins out by dint of obstinacy. It is

always right.

Already, at the very gates of Oran, nature raises its voice. In the

direction of Canastel there are vast wastelands covered with fragrant

brush. There sun and wind speak only of solitude. Above Oran there is

the mountain of Santa-Cruz, the plateau and the myriad ravines leading

to it. Roads, once carriageable, cling to the slopes overhanging the

sea. In the month of January some are covered with flowers. Daisies and

buttercups turn them into sumptuous paths, embroidered in yellow and

white. About Sant- Cruzz everything has been said. But if I were to

speak of it, I should forget the sacred processions that climb the

rugged hill on feast days, in order to recall other pilgrimages.

Solitary, they walk in the red stone, rise above the motionless bay, and

come to dedicate to nakedness a luminous, perfect hour.

Oran has also its deserts of sand: its beaches. Those encountered near

the gates are deserted only in winter and spring.

Then they are plateaus covered with asphodels, peopled with bare little

cottages among the flowers. The sea rumbles a bit, down below. Yet

already the sun, the faint breeze, the whiteness of the asphodels, the

sharp blue of the sky, everything makes one fancy summer—the golden

youth then covering the beach, the long hours on the sand and the sudden

softness of evening. Each year on these shores there is a new harvest of

girls in flower. Apparently they have but one season. The following

year, other cordial blossoms take their place, which, the summer before,

were still little girls with bodies as hard as buds. At eleven a.m.,

coming down from the plateau, all that young flesh, lightly clothed in

motley materials, breaks on the sand like a multicolored wave.

One has to go farther (strangely close, however, to that spot where two

hundred thousand men are laboring) to discover a still virgin landscape:

long, deserted dunes where the passage of men has left no other trace

than a worm-eaten hut. From time to time an Arab shepherd drives along

the top of the dunes the black and beige spots of his flock of goats. On

the beaches of the Oran country every summer morning seems to be the

first in the world.

Each twilight seems to be the last, solemn agony, announced at sunset by

a final glow that darkens every hue. The sea is ultramarine, the road

the color of clotted blood, the beach yellow.

Everything disappears with the green sun; an hour later the dunes are

bathed in moonlight. Then there are incomparable nights under a rain of

stars. Occasionally storms sweep over them, and the lightning flashes

flow along the dunes, whiten the sky, and give the sand and one’s eyes

orange-colored glints.

But this cannot be shared. One has to have lived it. So much solitude

and nobility give these places an unforgettable aspect. In the warm

moment before daybreak, after confronting the first bitter, black waves,

a new creature breasts night’s heavy, enveloping water. The memory of

those joys does not make me regret them, and thus I recognize that they

were good. After so many years they still last, somewhere in this heart

which finds unswerving loyalty so difficult. And I know that today, if I

were to go to the deserted dune, the same sky would pour down on me its

cargo of breezes and stars. These are lands of innocence.

But innocence needs sand and stones. And man has forgotten how to live

among them. At least it seems so, for he has taken refuge in this

extraordinary city where boredom sleeps.

Nevertheless, that very confrontation constitutes the value of Oran.

The capital of boredom, besieged by innocence and beauty, it is

surrounded by an army in which every stone is a soldier. In the city,

and at certain hours, however, what a temptation to go over to the

enemy! What a temptation to identify oneself with those stones, to melt

into that burning and impassive universe that defies history and its

ferments! That is doubtless futile. But there is in every man a profound

instinct which is neither that of destruction nor that of creation. It

is merely a matter of resembling nothing. In the shadow of the warm

walls of Oran, on its dusty asphalt, that invitation is sometimes heard.

It seems that, for a time, the minds that yield to it are never

disappointed. This is the darkness of Eurydice and the sleep of Isis.

Here are the deserts where thought will collect itself, the cool hand of

evening on a troubled heart. On this Mount of Olives, vigil is futile;

the mind recalls and approves the sleeping Apostles. Were they really

wrong? They nonetheless had their revelation.

Just think of Sakyamuni in the desert. He remained there for years on

end, squatting motionless with his eyes on heaven. The very gods envied

him that wisdom and that stone-like destiny. In his outstretched hands

the swallows had made their nest. But one day they flew away, answering

the call of distant lands. And he who had stifled in himself desire and

will, fame and suffering, began to cry. It happens thus that flowers

grow on rocks. Yes, let us accept stone when it is necessary. That

secret and that rapture we ask of faces can also be given us by stone.

To be sure, this cannot last. But what can last, after all? The secret

of faces fades away, and there we are, cast back to the chain of

desires. And if stone can do no more for us than the human heart, at

least it can do just as much.

“Oh, to be nothing!” For thousands of years this great cry has roused

millions of men to revolt against desire and pain. Its dying echoes have

reached this far, across centuries and oceans, to the oldest sea in the

world. They still reverberate dully against the compact cliffs of Oran.

Everybody in this country follows this advice without knowing it. Of

course, it is almost futile.

Nothingness cannot be achieved any more than the absolute can.

But since we receive as favors the eternal signs brought us by roses or

by human suffering, let us not refuse either the rare invitations to

sleep that the earth addresses us. Each has as much truth as the other.

This, perhaps, is the Ariadne’s thread of this somnambulist and frantic

city. Here one learns the virtues, provisional to be sure, of a certain

kind of boredom. In order to be spared, one must say “yes” to the

Minotaur. This is an old and fecund wisdom. Above the sea, silent at the

base of the red cliffs, it is enough to maintain a delicate equilibrium

halfway between the two massive headlands which, on the right and left,

dip into the clear water. In the puffing of a coast-guard vessel

crawling along the water far out bathed in radiant light, is distinctly

heard the muffled call of inhuman and glittering forces: it is the

Minotaur’s farewell.

It is noon; the very day is being weighed in the balance. His rite

accomplished, the traveler receives the reward of his liberation: the

little stone, dry and smooth as an asphodel, that he picks up on the

cliff. For the initiate the world is no heavier to bear than this stone.

Atlas’s task is easy; it is sufficient to choose one’s hour.

Then one realizes that for an hour, a month, a year, these shores can

indulge in freedom. They welcome pell-mell, without even looking at

them, the monk, the civil servant, or the conqueror.

There are days when I expected to meet, in the streets of Oran,

Descartes or Cesare Borgia. That did not happen. But perhaps another

will be more fortunate. A great deed, a great work, virile meditation

used to call for the solitude of sands or of the convent.

There were kept the spiritual vigils of arms. Where could they be better

celebrated now than in the emptiness of a big city established for some

time in unintellectual beauty?

Here is the little stone, smooth as an asphodel. It is at the beginning

of everything. Flowers, tears (if you insist), departures, and struggles

are for tomorrow. In the middle of the day when the sky opens its

fountains of light in the vast, sonorous space, all the headlands of the

coast look like a fleet about to set out. Those heavy galleons of rock

and light are trembling on their keels as if they were preparing to

steer for sunlit isles. O mornings in the country of Oran! From the high

plateaus the swallows plunge into huge troughs where the air is

seething. The whole coast is ready for departure; a shiver of adventure

ripples through it. Tomorrow, perhaps, we shall leave together.

(1939)

Helen’s Exile

The mediterranean sun has something tragic about it, quite different

from the tragedy of fogs. Certain evenings at the base of the seaside

mountains, night falls over the flawless curve of a little bay, and

there rises from the silent waters a sense of anguished fulfillment. In

such spots one can understand that if the Greeks knew despair, they

always did so through beauty and its stifling quality. In that gilded

calamity, tragedy reaches its highest point.

Our time, on the other hand, has fed its despair on ugliness and

convulsions. This is why Europe would be vile, if suffering could ever

be so. We have exiled beauty; the Greeks took up arms for her. First

difference, but one that has a history. Greek thought always took refuge

behind the conception of limits. It never carried anything to extremes,

neither the sacred nor reason, because it negated nothing, neither the

sacred nor reason. It took everything into consideration, balancing

shadow with light. Our Europe, on the other hand, off in the pursuit of

totality, is the child of disproportion. She negates beauty, as she

negates whatever she does not glorify. And, through all her diverse

ways, she glorifies but one thing, which is the future rule of reason.

In her madness she extends the eternal limits, and at that very moment

dark Erinyes fall upon her and tear her to pieces. Nemesis, the goddess

of measure and not of revenge, keeps watch. All those who overstep the

limit are pitilessly punished by her.

The Greeks, who for centuries questioned themselves as to what is just,

could understand nothing of our idea of justice. For them equity implied

a limit, whereas our whole continent is convulsed in its search for a

justice that must be total. At the dawn of Greek thought Hera-clitus was

already imagining that justice sets limits for the physical universe

itself:

“The sun will not overstep his measures; if he does, the Erinyes, the

handmaids of justice, will find him out.”1 We who have cast the universe

and spirit out of our sphere laugh at that threat. In a drunken sky we

light up the suns we want. But nonetheless the boundaries exist, and we

know it. In our wildest aberrations we dream of an equilibrium we have

left behind, which we naively expect to find at the end of our errors.

Childish presumption which justifies the fact that child-nations,

inheriting our follies, are now directing our history.

A fragment attributed to the same Heraclitus simply states:

“Presumption, regression of progress.” And, many centuries after the man

of Ephesus, Socrates, facing the threat of being condemned to death,

acknowledged only this one superiority in himself: what he did not know

he did not claim to know. The most exemplary life and thought of those

centuries close on a proud confession of ignorance. Forgetting that, we

have forgotten our virility. We have preferred the power that apes

greatness, first Alexander and then the Roman conquerors whom the

authors of our schoolbooks, through some incomparable vulgarity, teach

us to admire. We, too, have conquered, moved boundaries, mastered heaven

and earth. Our reason has driven all away. Alone at last, we end up by

ruling over a desert. What imagination could we have left for that

higher equilibrium in which nature balanced history, beauty, virtue, and

which applied the music of numbers even to blood-tragedy? We turn our

backs on nature; we are ashamed of beauty. Our wretched tragedies have a

smell of the office clinging to them, and the blood that trickles from

them is the color of printer’s ink.

This is why it is improper to proclaim today that we are the sons of

Greece. Or else we are the renegade sons. Placing history on the throne

of God, we are progressing toward theocracy like those whom the Greeks

called Barbarians and whom they fought to death in the waters of

Salamis. In order to realize how we differ, one must turn to him among

our philosophers who is the true rival of Plato. “Only the modern city,”

Hegel dares write, “offers the mind a field in which it can become aware

of itself.” We are thus living in the period of big cities.

Deliberately, the world has been amputated of all that constitutes its

permanence: nature, the sea, hilltops, evening meditation. Consciousness

is to be found only in the streets, because history is to be found only

in the streets—this is the edict. And consequently our most significant

works show the same bias. Landscapes are not to be found in great

European literature since Dostoevsky. History explains neither the

natural universe that existed before it nor the beauty that exists above

it. Hence it chose to be ignorant of them. Whereas Plato contained

everything—nonsense, reason, and myth—our philosophers contain nothing

but nonsense or reason because they have closed their eyes to the rest.

The mole is meditating.

It is Christianity that began substituting the tragedy of the soul for

contemplation of the world. But, at least, Christianity referred to a

spiritual nature and thereby preserved a certain fixity. With God dead,

there remains only history and power. For some time the entire effort of

our philosophers has aimed solely at replacing the notion of human

nature with that of situation, and replacing ancient harmony with the

disorderly advance of chance or reason’s pitiless progress. Whereas the

Greeks gave to will the boundaries of reason, we have come to put the

will’s impulse in the very center of reason, which has, as a result,

become deadly. For the Greeks, values pre-existed all action, of which

they definitely set the limits. Modern philosophy places its values at

the end of action. They are not but are becoming, and we shall know them

fully only at the completion of history. With values, all limit

disappears, and since conceptions differ as to what they will be, since

all struggles, without the brake of those same values, spread

indefinitely, today’s Messianisms confront one another and their clamors

mingle in the clash of empires. Disproportion is a conflagration,

according to Heraclitus. The conflagration is spreading; Nietzsche is

outdistanced. Europe no longer philosophizes by striking a hammer, but

by shooting a cannon.

Nature is still there, however. She contrasts her calm skies and her

reasons with the madness of men. Until the atom too catches fire and

history ends in the triumph of reason and the agony of the species. But

the Greeks never said that the limit could not he overstepped. They said

it existed and that whoever dared to exceed it was mercilessly struck

down. Nothing in present history can contradict them.

The historical spirit and the artist both want to remake the world. But

the artist, through an obligation of his nature, knows his limits, which

the historical spirit fails to recognize. This is why the latter’s aim

is tyranny whereas the former’s passion is freedom. All those who are

struggling for freedom today are ultimately fighting for beauty. Of

course, it is not a question of defending beauty for itself. Beauty

cannot do without man, and we shall not give our era its nobility and

serenity unless we follow it in its misfortune. Never again shall we be

hermits. But it is no less true that man cannot do without beauty, and

this is what our era pretends to want to disregard. It steels itself to

attain the absolute and authority; it wants to transfigure the world

before having exhausted it, to set it to rights before having understood

it. Whatever it may say, our era is deserting this world. Ulysses can

choose at Calypso’s bidding between immortality and the land of his

fathers. He chooses the land, and death with it. Such simple nobility is

foreign to us today.

Others will say that we lack humility; but, all things considered, this

word is ambiguous. Like Dostoevsky’s fools who boast of everything, soar

to heaven, and end up flaunting their shame in any public place, we

merely lack man’s pride, which is fidelity to his limits, lucid love of

his condition.

“I hate my time,” Saint-Exupery wrote shortly before his death, for

reasons not far removed from those I have spoken of. But, however

upsetting that exclamation, coming from him who loved men for their

admirable qualities, we shall not accept responsibility for it. Yet what

a temptation, at certain moments, to turn one’s back on this bleak,

fleshless world! But this time is ours, and we cannot live hating

ourselves. It has fallen so low only through the excess of its virtues

as well as through the extent of its vices. We shall fight for the

virtue that has a history. What virtue? The horses of Patroclus weep for

their master killed in battle. All is lost. But Achilles resumes the

fight, and victory is the outcome, because friendship has just been

assassinated: friendship is a virtue.

Admission of ignorance, rejection of fanaticism, the limits of the world

and of man, the beloved face, and finally beauty—this is where we shall

be on the side of the Greeks. In a certain sense, the direction history

will take is not the one we think. It lies in the struggle between

creation and inquisition. Despite the price which artists will pay for

their empty hands, we may hope for their victory. Once more the

philosophy of darkness will break and fade away over the dazzling sea. O

midday thought, the Trojan war is being fought far from the

battlefields! Once more the dreadful walls of the modern city will fall

to deliver up—“soul serene as the ocean’s calm”—the beauty of Helen.

(1948)

Return To Tipasa

You have navigated with raging soul far from the paternal home, passing

beyond the sea’s double rocks, and you now inhabit a foreign land.

—Medea

For five days rain had been falling ceaselessly on Algiers and had

finally wet the sea itself. From an apparently inexhaustible sky,

constant downpours, viscous in their density, streamed down upon the

gulf. Gray and soft as a huge sponge, the sea rose slowly in the

ill-defined bay. But the surface of the water seemed almost motionless

under the steady rain. Only now and then a barely perceptible swelling

motion would raise above the sea’s surface a vague puff of smoke that

would come to dock in the harbor, under an arc of wet boulevards. The

city itself, all its white walls dripping, gave off a different steam

that went out to meet the first steam. Whichever way you turned, you

seemed to be breathing water, to be drinking the air.

In front of the soaked sea I walked and waited in that December Algiers,

which was for me the city of summers. I had fled Europe’s night, the

winter of faces. But the summer city herself had been emptied of her

laughter and offered me only bent and shining backs. In the evening, in

the crudely lighted cafes where I took refuge, I read my age in faces I

recognized without being able to name them. I merely knew that they had

been young with me and that they were no longer so.

Yet I persisted without very well knowing what I was waiting for, unless

perhaps the moment to go back to Tipasa. To be sure, it is sheer

madness, almost always punished, to return to the sites of one’s youth

and try to relive at forty what one loved or keenly enjoyed at twenty.

But I was forewarned of that madness. Once already I had returned to

Tipasa, soon after those war years that marked for me the end of youth.

I hoped, I think, to recapture there a freedom I could not forget. In

that spot, indeed, more than twenty years ago, I had spent whole

mornings wandering among the ruins, breathing in the wormwood, warming

myself against the stones, discovering little roses, soon plucked of

their petals, which outlive the spring. Only at noon, at the hour when

the cicadas themselves fell silent as if overcome, I would flee the

greedy glare of an all- consuming light. Sometimes at night I would

sleep open-eyed under a sky dripping with stars. I was alive then.

Fifteen years later I found my ruins, a few feet from the first waves, I

followed the streets of the forgotten walled city through fields covered

with bitter trees, and on the slopes overlooking the hay I still

caressed the bread-colored columns. But the ruins were now surrounded

with barbed wire and could be entered only through certain openings. It

was also forbidden, for reasons which it appears that morality approves,

to walk there at night; by day one encountered an official guardian. It

just happened, that morning, that it was raining over the whole extent

of the ruins.

Disoriented, walking through the wet, solitary countryside, I tried at

least to recapture that strength, hitherto always at hand, that helps me

to accept what is when once I have admitted that I cannot change it. And

I could not, indeed, reverse the course of time and restore to the world

the appearance I had loved which had disappeared in a day, long before.

The second of September 1939, in fact, I had not gone to Greece, as I

was to do. War, on the contrary, had come to us, then it had spread over

Greece herself.

That distance, those years separating the warm ruins from the barbed

wire were to be found in me, too, that day as I stood before the

sarcophaguses full of black water or under the sodden tamarisks.

Originally brought up surrounded by beauty which was my only wealth, I

had begun in plenty. Then had come the barbed wire—I mean tyrannies,

war, police forces, the era of revolt. One had had to put oneself right

with the authorities of night: the day’s beauty was but a memory. And in

this muddy Tipasa the memory itself was becoming dim. It was indeed a

question of beauty, plenty, or youth! In the light from conflagrations

the world had suddenly shown its wrinkles and its wounds, old and new.

It had aged all at once, and we with it. I had come here looking for a

certain “lift”; but I realized that it inspires only the man who is

unaware that he is about to launch forward. No love without a little

innocence. Where was the innocence? Empires were tumbling down; nations

and men were tearing at one another’s throats; our hands were soiled.

Originally innocent without knowing it, we were now guilty without

meaning to be: the mystery was increasing with our knowledge. This is

why, O mockery, we were concerned with morality. Weak and disabled, I

was dreaming of virtue! In the days of innocence I didn’t even know that

morality existed. I knew it now, and I was not capable of living up to

its standard. On the promontory that I used to love, among the wet

columns of the ruined temple, I seemed to be walking behind someone

whose steps I could still hear on the stone slabs and mosaics but whom I

should never again overtake. I went back to Paris and remained several

years before returning home.

Yet I obscurely missed something during all those years. When one has

once had the good luck to love intensely, life is spent in trying to

recapture that ardor and that illumination. Forsaking beauty and the

sensual happiness attached to it, exclusively serving misfortune, calls

for a nobility I lack. But, after all, nothing is true that forces one

to exclude. Isolated beauty ends up simpering; solitary justice ends up

oppressing. Whoever aims to serve one exclusive of the other serves no

one, not even himself, and eventually serves injustice twice. A day

comes when, thanks to rigidity, nothing causes wonder any more,

everything is known, and life is spent in beginning over again. These

are the days of exile, of desiccated life, of dead souls. To come alive

again, one needs a special grace, self-forgetfulness, or a homeland.

Certain mornings, on turning a corner, a delightful dew falls on the

heart and then evaporates. But its coolness remains, and this is what

the heart requires always. I had to set out again.

And in Algiers a second time, still walking under the same downpour

which seemed not to have ceased since a departure I had thought

definitive, amid the same vast melancholy smelling of rain and sea,

despite this misty sky, these backs fleeing under the shower, these

cafes whose sulphureous light distorted faces, I persisted in hoping.

Didn’t I know, besides, that Algiers rains, despite their appearance of

never meaning to end, nonetheless stop in an instant, like those streams

in my country which rise in two hours, lay waste acres of land, and

suddenly dry up? One evening, in fact, the rain ceased. I waited one

night more. A limpid morning rose, dazzling, over the pure sea. From the

sky, fresh as a daisy, washed over and over again by the rains, reduced

by these repeated washings to its finest and clearest texture, emanated

a vibrant light that gave to each house and each tree a sharp outline,

an astonished newness. In the world’s morning the earth must have sprung

forth in such a light. I again took the road for Tipasa.

For me there is not a single one of those sixty-nine kilometers that is

not filled with memories and sensations. Turbulent childhood, adolescent

daydreams in the drone of the bus’s motor, mornings, unspoiled girls,

beaches, young muscles always at the peak of their effort, evening’s

slight anxiety in a sixteen-year-old heart, lust for life, fame, and

ever the same sky throughout the years, unfailing in strength and light,

itself insatiable, consuming one by one over a period of months the

victims stretched out in the form of crosses on the beach at the

deathlike hour of noon. Always the same sea, too, almost impalpable in

the morning light, which I again saw on the horizon as soon as the road,

leaving the Sahel and its bronze-colored vineyards, sloped down toward

the coast. But I did not stop to look at it. I wanted to see again the

Chenoua, that solid, heavy mountain cut out of a single block of stone,

which borders the bay of Tipasa to the west before dropping down into

the sea itself. It is seen from a distance, long before arriving, a

light, blue haze still confused with the sky. But gradually it is

condensed, as you advance toward it, until it takes on the color of the

surrounding waters, a huge motionless wave whose amazing leap upward has

been brutally solidified above the sea calmed all at once. Still nearer,

almost at the gates of Tipasa, here is its frowning bulk, brown and

green, here is the old mossy god that nothing will ever shake, a refuge

and harbor for its sons, of whom I am one.

While watching it I finally got through the barbed wire and found myself

among the ruins. And under the glorious December light, as happens but

once or twice in lives which ever after can consider themselves favored

to the full, I found exactly what I had come seeking, what, despite the

era and the world, was offered me, truly to me alone, in that forsaken

nature. From the forum strewn with olives could be seen the village down

below. No sound came from it; wisps of smoke rose in the limpid air. The

sea likewise was silent as if smothered under the unbroken shower of

dazzling, cold light. From the Chenoua a distant cock’s crow alone

celebrated the day’s fragile glory. In the direction of the ruins, as

far as the eye could see, there was nothing but pock-marked stones and

wormwood, trees and perfect columns in the transparence of the

crystalline air. It seemed as if the morning were stabilized, the sun

stopped for an incalculable moment. In this light and this silence,

years of wrath and night melted slowly away. I listened to an almost

forgotten sound within myself as if my heart, long stopped, were calmly

beginning to beat again. And awake now, I recognized one by one the

imperceptible sounds of which the silence was made up: the figured bass

of the birds, the sea’s faint, brief sighs at the foot of the rocks, the

vibration of the trees, the blind singing of the columns, the rustling

of the wormwood plants, the furtive lizards. I heard that; I also

listened to the happy torrents rising within me. It seemed to me that I

had at last come to harbor, for a moment at least, and that henceforth

that moment would be endless. But soon after, the sun rose visibly a

degree in the sky. A magpie preluded briefly, and at once, from all

directions, birds’ songs burst out with energy, jubilation, joyful

discordance, and infinite rapture. The day started up again. It was to

carry me to evening.

At noon on the half-sandy slopes covered with heliotropes like a foam

left by the furious waves of the last few days as they withdrew, I

watched the sea barely swelling at that hour with an exhausted motion,

and I satisfied the two thirsts one cannot long neglect without drying

up—I mean loving and admiring. For there is merely bad luck in not being

loved; there is misfortune in not loving. All of us, today, are dying of

this misfortune. For violence and hatred dry up the heart itself; the

long fight for justice exhausts the love that nevertheless gave birth to

it. In the clamor in which we live, love is impossible and justice does

not suffice. This is why Europe hates daylight and is only able to set

injustice up against injustice. But in order to keep justice from

shriveling up like a beautiful orange fruit containing nothing but a

bitter, dry pulp, I discovered once more at Tipasa that one must keep

intact in oneself a freshness, a cool wellspring of joy, love the day

that escapes injustice, and return to combat having won that light. Here

I recaptured the former beauty, a young sky, and I measured my luck,

realizing at last that in the worst years of our madness the memory of

that sky had never left me. This was what in the end had kept me from

despairing. I had always known that the ruins of Tipasa were younger

than our new constructions or our bomb damage. There the world began

over again every day in an ever new light. O light! This is the cry of

all the characters of ancient drama brought face to face with their

fate. This last resort was ours, too, and I knew it now. In the middle

of winter I at last discovered that there was in me an invincible

summer.

I have again left Tipasa; I have returned to Europe and its struggles.

But the memory of that day still uplifts me and helps me to welcome

equally what delights and what crushes. In the difficult hour we are

living, what else can I desire than to exclude nothing and to learn how

to braid with white thread and black thread a single cord stretched to

the breaking-point? In everything I have done or said up to now, I seem

to recognize these two forces, even when they work at cross-purposes. I

have not been able to disown the light into which I was born and yet I

have not wanted to reject the servitudes of this time. It would be too

easy to contrast here with the sweet name of Tipasa other more sonorous

and crueler names. For men of today there is an inner way, which I know

well from having taken it in both directions, leading from the spiritual

hilltops to the capitals of crime. And doubtless one can always rest,

fall asleep on the hilltop or board with crime. But if one forgoes a

part of what is, one must forgo being oneself; one must forgo living or

loving otherwise than by proxy. There is thus a will to live without

rejecting anything of life, which is the virtue I honor most in this

world. From time to time, at least, it is true that I should like to

have practiced it. Inasmuch as few epochs require as much as ours that

one should be equal to the best as to the worst, I should like, indeed,

to shirk nothing and to keep faithfully a doubl memory. Yes, there is

beauty and there are the humiliated.

Whatever may be the difficulties of the undertaking, I should like never

to be unfaithful either to one or to the others.

But this still resembles a moral code, and we live for something that

goes farther than morality. If we could only name it, what silence! On

the hill of Sainte-Salsa, to the east of Tipasa, the evening is

inhabited. It is still light, to tell the truth, but in this light an

almost invisible fading announces the day’s end. A wind rises, young

like the night, and suddenly the waveless sea chooses a direction and

flows like a great barren river from one end of the horizon to the

other. The sky darkens. Then begins the mystery, the gods of night, the

beyond-pleasure. But how to translate this? The little coin I am

carrying away from here has a visible surface, a woman’s beautiful face

which repeats to me all I have learned in this day, and a worn surface

which I feel under my fingers during the return. What can that lipless

mouth be saying, except what I am told by another mysterious voice,

within me, which every day informs me of my ignorance and my happiness:

“The secret I am seeking lies hidden in a valley full of olive trees,

under the grass and the cold violets, around an old house that smells of

wood smoke. For more than twenty years I rambled over that valley and

others resembling it, I questioned mute goatherds, I knocked at the door

of deserted ruins. Occasionally, at the moment of the first star in the

still bright sky, under a shower of shimmering light, I thought I knew.

I did know, in truth. I still know, perhaps. But no one wants any of

this secret; I don’t want any myself, doubtless; and I cannot stand

apart from my people. I live in my family, which thinks it rules over

rich and hideous cities built of stones and mists. Day and night it

speaks up, and everything bows before it, which bows before nothing: it

is deaf to all secrets. Its power that carries me bores me,

nevertheless, and on occasion its shouts weary me. But its misfortune is

mine, and we are of the same blood. A cripple, likewise, an accomplice

and noisy, have I not shouted among the stones? Consequently, I strive

to forget, I walk in our cities of iron and fire, I smile bravely at the

night, I hail the storms, I shall be faithful. I have forgotten, in

truth: active and deaf, henceforth. But perhaps someday, when we are

ready to die of exhaustion and ignorance, I shall be able to disown our

garish tombs and go and stretch out in the valley, under the same light,

and learn for the last time what I know.”

(1952)

The Artist And His Time

I. As an artist, have you chosen the role of witness?

This would take considerable presumption or a vocation I lack.

Personally I don’t ask for any role and I have but one real vocation.

As a man, I have a preference for happiness; as an artist, it seems to

me that I still have characters to bring to life without the help of

wars or of law-courts. But I have been sought out, as each individual

has been sought out. Artists of the past could at least keep silent in

the face of tyranny. The tyrannies of today are improved; they no longer

admit of silence or neutrality. One has to take a stand, be either for

or against. Well, in that case, I am against. But this does not amount

to choosing the comfortable role of witness. It is merely accepting the

time as it is, minding one’s own business, in short. Moreover, you are

forgetting that today judges, accused, and witnesses exchange positions

with exemplary rapidity. My choice, if you think I am making one, would

at least be never to sit on a judge’s bench, or beneath it, like so many

of our philosophers. Aside from that, there is no dearth of

opportunities for action, in the relative. Trade-unionism is today the

first, and the most fruitful among them.

II. Is not the quixotism that has been criticized in your recent

works an idealistic and romantic definition of the artist’s role?

However words are perverted, they provisionally keep their meaning. And

it is clear to me that the romantic is the one who chooses the perpetual

motion of history, the grandiose epic, and the announcement of a

miraculous event at the end of time. If I have tried to define

something, it is, on the contrary, simply the common existence of

history and of man, everyday life with the most possible light thrown

upon it, the dogged struggle against one’s own degradation and that of

others.

It is likewise idealism, and of the worse kind, to end up by hanging all

action and all truth on a meaning of history that is not implicit in

events and that, in any case, implies a mythical aim. Would it therefore

be realism to take as the laws of history the future—in other words,

just what is not yet history, something of whose nature we know nothing?

It seems to me, on the contrary, that I am arguing in favor of a true

realism against a mythology that is both illogical and deadly, and

against romantic nihilism whether it be bourgeois or allegedly

revolutionary. To tell the truth, far from being romantic, I believe in

the necessity of a rule and an order. I merely say that there can be no

question of just any rule whatsoever. And that it would be surprising if

the rule we need were given us by this disordered society, or, on the

other hand, by those doctrinaires who declare themselves liberated from

all rules and all scruples.

III. The Marxists and their followers likewise think they are

humanists. But for them human nature will be formed in the classless

society of the future.

To begin with, this proves that they reject at the present moment what

we all are: those humanists are accusers of man.

How can we be surprised that such a claim should have developed in the

world of court trials? They reject the man of today in the name of the

man of the future. That claim is religious in nature.

Why should it be more justified than the one which announces the kingdom

of heaven to come? In reality the end of history cannot have, within the

limits of our condition, any definable significance.

It can only be the object of a faith and of a new mystification. A

mystification that today is no less great than the one that of old based

colonial oppression on the necessity of saving the souls of infidels.

IV. Is not that what in reality separates you from the intellectuals

of the left?

You mean that is what separates those intellectuals from the left?

Traditionally the left has always been at war against injustice,

obscurantism, and oppression. It always thought that those phenomena

were interdependent. The idea that obscurantism can lead to justice, the

national interest to liberty, is quite recent. The truth is that certain

intellectuals of the left (not all, fortunately) are today hypnotized by

force and efficacy as our intellectuals of the right were before and

during the war. Their attitudes are different, but the act of

resignation is the same. The first wanted to be realistic nationalists;

the second want to be realistic socialists. In the end they betray

nationalism and socialism alike in the name of a realism henceforth

without content and adored as a pure, and illusory, technique of

efficacy.

This is a temptation that can, after all, be understood. But still,

however the question is looked at, the new position of the people who

call themselves, or think themselves, leftists consists in saying:

certain oppressions are justifiable because they follow the direction,

which cannot be justified, of history. Hence there are presumably

privileged executioners, and privileged by nothing.

This is about what was said in another context by Joseph de Maistre, who

has never been taken for an incendiary. But this is a thesis which,

personally, I shall always reject. Allow me to set up against it the

traditional point of view of what has been hitherto called the left: all

executioners are of the same family.

V. What can the artist do in the world of today?

He is not asked either to write about co-operatives or, conversely, to

lull to sleep in himself the sufferings endured by others throughout

history. And since you have asked me to speak personally, I am going to

do so as simply as I can. Considered as artists, we perhaps have no need

to interfere in the affairs of the world. But considered as men, yes.

The miner who is exploited or shot down, the slaves in the camps, those

in the colonies, the legions of persecuted throughout the world—they

need all those who can speak to communicate their silence and to keep in

touch with them. I have not written, day after day, fighting articles

and texts, I have not taken part in the common struggles because I

desire the world to be covered with Greek statues and masterpieces. The

man who has such a desire does exist in me.

Except that he has something better to do in trying to instill life into

the creatures of his imagination. But from my first articles to my

latest book I have written so much, and perhaps too much, only because I

cannot keep from being drawn toward everyday life, toward those, whoever

they may be, who are humiliated and debased. They need to hope, and if

all keep silent or if they are given a choice between two kinds of

humiliation, they will be forever deprived of hope and we with them. It

seems to me impossible to endure that idea, nor can he who cannot endure

it lie down to sleep in his tower. Not through virtue, as you see, but

through a sort of almost organic intolerance, which you feel or do not

feel. Indeed, I see many who fail to feel it, but I cannot envy their

sleep. This does not mean, however, that we must sacrifice our artist’s

nature to some social preaching or other. I have said elsewhere why the

artist was more than ever necessary. But if we intervene as men, that

experience will have an effect upon our language. And if we are not

artists in our language first of all, what sort of artists are we? Even

if, militants in our lives, we speak in our works of deserts and of

selfish love, the mere fact that our lives are militant causes a special

tone of voice to people with men that desert and that love. I shall

certainly not choose the moment when we are beginning to leave nihilism

behind to stupidly deny the values of creation in favor of the values of

humanity, or vice versa.

In my mind neither one is ever separated from the other and I measure

the greatness of an artist (Moliere, Tolstoy, Melville) by the balance

he managed to maintain between the two. Today, under the pressure of

events, we are obliged to transport that tension into our lives

likewise. This is why so many artists, bending under the burden, take

refuge in the ivory tower or, conversely, in the social church. But as

for me, I see in both choices a like act of resignation. We must

simultaneously serve suffering and beauty.

The long patience, “The strength, the secret cunning such service calls

for are the virtues that establish the very renascence we need.

One word more. This undertaking, I know, cannot be accomplished without

dangers and bitterness. We must accept the dangers: the era of

chairbound artists is over. But we must reject the bitterness. One of

the temptations of the artist is to believe himself solitary, and in

truth he bears this shouted at him with a certain base delight. But this

is not true. He stands in the midst of all, in the same rank, neither

higher nor lower, with all those who are working and struggling. His

very vocation, in the face of oppression, is to open the prisons and to

give a voice to the sorrows and joys of all. This is where art, against

its enemies, justifies itself by proving precisely that it is no one’s

enemy. By itself art could probably not produce the renascence which

implies justice and liberty. But without it, that renascence would be

without forms and, consequently, would be nothing. Without culture, and

the relative freedom it implies, society, even when perfect, is but a

jungle. This is why any authentic creation is a gift to the future.

(1953)

[1] From the point of view of the relative value of truth. On the other

hand, from the point of view of virile behavior, this scholar’s

fragility may well make us smile.

[2] Let us not miss this opportunity to point out the relative character

of this essay. Suicide may indeed be related to much more honorable

considerations— for example, the political suicides of protest, as they

were called, during the Chinese revolution.

[3] I have heard of an emulator of Peregrinos, a post-war writer who,

after having finished his first hook, committed suicide to attract

attention to his work. Attention was in fact attracted, but the book was

judged no good.

[4] But not in the proper sense. This is not a definition, but rather an

enumeration of the feelings that may admit of the absurd. Still, the

enumeration finished, the absurd has nevertheless not been exhausted.

[5] Apropos of the notion of exception particularly and against

Aristotle.

[6] It may be thought that I am neglecting here the essential problem,

that of faith. But I am not examining the philosophy of Kierkegaard or

of Chestov or, later on, of Husserl (this would call for a different

place and a different attitude of mind); I am simply borrowing a theme

from them and examining whether its consequences can fit the already

established rules. It is merely a matter of persistence.

[7] I did not say “excludes God,” which would still amount to asserting.

[8] Let me assert again: it is not the affirmation of God that is

questioned here, but rather the logic leading to that affirmation.

[9] Even the most rigorous epistemologies imply metaphysics. And to such

a degree that the metaphysic of many contemporary thinkers consists in

having nothing but an epistemology.

[10] A.—At that time reason had to adapt itself or die. It adapts

itself. With Plotinus, after being logical it becomes aesthetic.

Metaphor takes the place of the syllogism. B.—Moreover, this is not

Plotinus’ only contribution to phenomenology. This whole attitude is

already contained in the concept so dear to the Alexandrian thinker that

there is not only an idea of man but also an idea of Socrates.

[11] I am concerned here with a factual comparison, not with an apology

of humility. The absurd man is the contrary of the reconciled man.

[12] Quantity sometimes constitutes quality. If I can believe the latest

restatements of scientific theory, all matter is constituted by centers

of energy. Their greater or lesser quantity makes its specificity more

or less remarkable. A billion ions and one ion differ not only in

quantity but also in quality. It is easy to find an analogy in human

experience.

[13] Same reflection on a notion as different as the idea of eternal

nothingness. It neither adds anything to nor subtracts anything from

reality. In psychological experience of nothingness, it is by the

consideration of what will happen in two thousand years that our own

nothingness truly takes on meaning. In one of its aspects, eternal

nothingness is made up precisely of the sum of lives to come which will

not be ours.

[14] The will is only the agent here: it tends to maintain

consciousness. It provides a discipline of life, and that is

appreciable.

[15] What matters is coherence. We start out here from acceptance of the

world. But Oriental thought teaches that one can indulge in the same

effort of logic by choosing against the world. That is just as

legitimate and gives this essay its perspectives and its limits. But

when the negation of the world is pursued just as rigorously, one often

achieves ( in certain Vedantic schools) similar results regarding, for

instance, the indifference of works. In a book of great importance, Le

Choix, Jean Grenier establishes in this way a veritable “philosophy of

indifference.”

[16] In the fullest sense and with his faults. A healthy attitude also

includes faults.

[17] At this point I am thinking of Moliere’s Alceste. Everything is so

simple, so obvious and so coarse. Alceste against Philinte,

[18] It is curious to note that the most intellectual kind of painting,

the one that tries to reduce reality to its essential elements, is

ultimately but a visual delight. All it has kept of the world is its

color. (This is apparent particularly in Leger.)

[19] If you stop to think of it, this explains the worst novels. Almost

everybody considers himself capable of thinking and, to a certain

degree, whether right or wrong, really does think. Very few, on the

contrary, can fancy themselves poets or artists in words. But from the

moment when thought won out over style, the mob invaded the novel. That

is not such a great evil as is said. The best are led to make greater

demands upon themselves. As for those who succumb, they did not deserve

to survive.

[20] Malraux’s work, for instance. But it would have been necessary to

deal at the same time with the social question which in fact cannot be

avoided by absurd thought (even though that thought may put forward

several solutions, very different from one another). One must, however,

limit oneself.

[21] “Stavrogin: ‘Do you believe in eternal life in the other world?’

Kirilov: ‘No, but in eternal life in this world.’”

[22] “Man simply invented God in order not to kill himself. That is the

summary of universal history down to this moment.”

[23] Boris de Schloezer.

[24] Gide’s curious and penetrating remark: almost all Dostoevsky’s

heroes are polygamous.

[25] Melville’s Moby Dick, for instance.

[26] It is worth noting that the works of Kafka can quite as

legitimately be interpreted in the sense of a social criticism (for

instance in The Trial). It is probable, moreover, that there is no need

to choose. Both interpretations are good. In absurd terms, as we have

seen, revolt against men is also directed against God: great revolutions

are always metaphysical.

[27] In The Castle it seems that “distractions” in the Pascalian sense

are represented by the assistants who “distract” K. from his anxiety. If

Frieda eventually becomes the mistress of one of the assistants, this is

because she prefers the stage setting to truth, everyday life to shared

anguish.

[28] This is obviously true only of the unfinished version of The Castle

that Kafka left us. But it is doubtful that the writer would have

destroyed in the last chapters his novel’s unity of tone.

[29] Purity of heart.

[30] The only character without hope in The Castle is Amalia. She is the

one with whom the Land Surveyor is most violently contrasted.

[31] On the two aspects of Kafka’s thought, compare “In the Penal

Colony,” published by the Cahiers du Sud (and in America by Partisan

Review— translator’s note): “Guilt [‘of man’ is understood] is never

doubtful” and a fragment of The Castle (Momus’s report): “The guilt of

the Land Surveyor K. is hard to establish.”

[32] What is offered above is obviously an interpretation of Kafka’s

work. But it is only fair to add that nothing prevents its being

considered, aside from any interpretation, from a purely aesthetic point

of view. For instance, B. Groethuysen in his remarkable preface to The

Trial limits himself, more wisely than we, to following merely the

painful fancies of what he calls, most strikingly, a daydreamer. It is

the fate and perhaps the greatness of that work that it offers

everything and confirms nothing.

[33] May I take the ridiculous position of saying that I do not like the

way Gide exalts the body? He asks it to restrain its desire to make it

keener. Thus he comes dangerously near to those who in brothel slang are

called involved or brain-workers. Christianity also wants to suspend

desire. But, more natural, it sees a mortification in this. My friend

Vincent, who is a cooper and junior breast-stroke champion, has an even

clearer view. He drinks when he is thirsty, if he desires a woman tries

to go to bed with her, and would marry her if he loved her (this hasn’t

yet happened). Afterward he always says: “I feel better”— and this sums

up vigorously any apology that might be made for satiety.

[34] Gogol’s Klestakov is met in Oran. He yawns and then: “I feel I

shall soon have to be concerned with something lofty.”

[35] Doubtless in memory of these good words, an Oran lecture-and-

discussion group has been founded under the name of Cogito-Club.

[36] And the new boulevard called Front-de-Mer.

[37] Another quality of the Algerian race is, as you see, candor.

[38] This essay deals with a certain temptation. It is essential to have

known it. One can then act or not, but with full knowledge of the facts.