💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › errico-malatesta-mutual-aid-an-essay.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:42:17. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Mutual Aid: An Essay
Author: Errico Malatesta
Date: 1909
Language: en
Topics: mutualist
Source: Retrieved on March 3rd, 2009 from http://www.efn.org/~danr/mal_maid.html
Notes: from Malatesta: Life and Ideas, (Verne Richards’ ed.),London, Freedom Press, 1965

Errico Malatesta

Mutual Aid: An Essay

Since it is a fact that man is a social animal whose existence depends

on the continued physical and spiritual relations between human beings,

these relations must be based either on affinity, solidarity and love,

or on hostility and struggle. If each individual thinks only of his well

being, or perhaps that of his small consanguinary or territorial group,

he will obviously find himself in conflict with others, and will emerge

as victor or vanquished; as the oppressor if he wins, as the oppressed

if he loses. Natural harmony, the natural marriage of the good of each

with that of all, is the invention of human laziness, which rather than

struggle to achieve what it wants assumes that it will be achieved

spontaneously, by natural law. In reality, however, natural Man is in a

state of continuous conflict with his fellows in his quest for the best,

and healthiest site, the most fertile land, and in time, to exploit the

many and varied opportunities that social life creates for some or for

others. For this reason human history is full of violence, wars, carnage

(besides the ruthless exploitation of the labour of others) and

innumerable tyrannies and slavery.

If in the human spirit there had only existed this harsh instinct of

wanting to predominate and to profit at the expense of others, humanity

would have remained in its barbarous state and the development of order

as recorded in history, or in our own times, would not have been

possible. This order even at its worst, always represents a kind of

tempering of the tyrannical spirit with a minimum of social solidarity,

indispensable for a more civilised and progressive life.

But fortunately there exists in Man another feeling which draws him

closer to his neighbour, the feeling of sympathy, tolerance, of love,

and, thanks to it, mankind became more civilised, and from it grew our

idea which aims at making society a true gathering of brothers and

friends all working for the common good.

How the feeling arose which is expressed by the so-called moral precepts

and which, as it develops, denies the existing morality and substitutes

a higher morality, is a subject for research which may interest

philosophers and sociologists, but it does not detract from the fact

that it exists, independently of the explanations which may be advanced.

It is of no importance that it may stem from the primitive,

physiological fact of the sex act to perpetuate the human species; or

the satisfaction to be derived from the company of one’s fellow beings;

or the advantages to be derived from union in the struggle against the

common enemy and in revolt against the common tyrant; or from the desire

for leisure, peace and security that even the victors feel a need for;

or perhaps for these and a hundred other reasons combined. It exists and

it is on its development and growth that we base our hopes for the

future of humanity.

“The will of God”, “natural laws”, “moral laws”, the “categoric

imperative” of the Kantians, even the “interest clearly understood” of

the Utilitarians are all metaphysical fantasies which get one nowhere.

They represent the commendable desire of the human mind to want to

explain everything, to want to get to the bottom of things, and could be

accepted as provisional hypotheses for further research, were they not,

in most cases, the human tendency of never wanting to admit ignorance

and preferring wordy explanations devoid of factual content to simply

saying “I don’t know.”

Whatever the explanations anyone may or may not choose to give, the

problem remains intact: one must choose between love and hate, between

brotherly co-operation and fratricidal struggle, between “altruism” and

“egoism.”

The needs, tastes, aspirations and interests of mankind are neither

similar nor naturally harmonious; often they are diametrically opposed

and antagonistic. On the other hand, the life of each individual is so

conditioned by the life of others that it would be impossible, even

assuming it were convenient to do so, to isolate oneself and live one’s

own life. Social solidarity is a fact from which no one can escape: it

can be freely and consciously accepted and in consequence benefit all

concerned, or it can be accepted willy-nilly, consciously or otherwise,

in which case it manifests itself by the subjection of one to another,

by the exploitation of some by others.

A whole host of practical problems arise in our day-to-day lives which

can be solved in different ways, but not by all ways at the same time;

yet each individual may prefer one solution to another. If an individual

or group have the power to impose their preference on others, they will

choose the solution which best suits the interests and tastes, the

others will have to submit and sacrifice their wishes. But if no one has

the possibility of obliging others to act against their will then,

always assuming that it is not possible or considered convenient to

adopt more than one solution, one must arrive by mutual concessions at

an agreement which best suits everyone and least offends individual

interests, tastes and wishes.

History teaches us, daily observation of life around us teaches, that

where violence has no place [in human relations] everything is settled

in the best possible way, in the best interests of all concerned. But

where violence intervenes, injustice, oppression and exploitation

invariably triumph.

The fact is that human life is not possible without profiting by the

labour of others, and that there are only two ways in which this can be

done: either through a fraternal, equalitarian and libertarian

association, in which solidarity, consciously and freely expressed

unites all mankind; or the struggle of each against the other in which

the victors overrule, oppress and exploit the rest ...

We want to bring about a society in which men will consider each other

as brothers and by mutual support will achieve the greatest well-being

and freedom as well as physical and intellectual development for all ...

The strongest man is the one who is the least isolated; the most

independent is the one who has most contacts and friendships and thereby

a wider field for choosing his close collaborators; the most developed

man is he who best can, and knows how to, utilise Man’s common

inheritance as well as the achievements of his contemporaries.

In spite of the rivers of human blood; in spite of the indescribable

sufferings and humiliations inflicted; in spite of exploitation and

tyranny at the expense of the weakest (by reason of personal, or social,

inferiority); in a word, in spite of the struggle and all its

consequences, that which in human society represents its vital and

progressive characteristics, is the feeling of sympathy, the sense of a

common humanity which in normal times, places a limit on the struggle

beyond which one cannot venture without rousing deep disgust and

widespread disapproval. For what intervenes is morality.

The professional historian of the old school may prefer to present the

fruits of his research as sensational events, large-scale conflicts

between nations and classes, wars, revolutions, the ins and outs of

diplomacy and conspiracies; but what is really much more significant are

the innumerable daily contacts between individuals and between groups

which are the true substance of social life. And if one closely examines

what happens deep down, in the intimate daily lives of the mass of

humanity, one finds that as well as the struggle to snatch better

working conditions, the thirst for domination, rivalry, envy and all the

unhealthy passions which set man against man, is also valuable work,

mutual aid, unceasing and voluntary exchange of services, affection,

love, friendship and all that which draws people closer together in

brotherhood. And human collectivizes advance or decay, live or die,

depending on whether solidarity and love, or hatred and struggle,

predominate in the community’s affairs; indeed, the very existence of

any community would not be possible if the social feelings, which I

would call the good passions, were not stronger than the bad.

The existence of sentiments of affection and sympathy among mankind, and

the experience and awareness of the individual and social advantages

which stem from the development of these sentiments, have produced and

go on producing concepts of “justice” and “right” and “morality” which,

in spite of a thousand contradictions, lies and hypocrisy serving base

interests, constitute a goal, an ideal towards which humanity advances.

This “morality” is fickle and relative; it varies with the times, with

different peoples, classes and individuals; people use it to serve their

own personal interests and that of their families, class or country. But

discarding what, in official “morality”, serves to defend the privilege

and violence of the ruling class, there is always something left which

is in the general interest and is the common achievement of all mankind,

irrespective of class and race.

The bourgeoisie in its heroic period, when it still felt itself a part

of the people and fought for emancipation, had sublime gestures of love

and self-abnegation; and the best among its thinkers and martyrs had the

almost prophetic vision of that future of peace, brotherhood and

well-being which socialists are struggling for today [1909]. But if

altruism and solidarity were among the feelings of the best of them, the

germ of individualism (in the sense of struggle between individuals),

the principle of struggle (as opposed to solidarity) and the

exploitation of man by man, were in the programme of the bourgeoisie and

could not but give rise to baneful consequences. Individual property and

the principle of authority, in the new disguises of capitalism and

parliamentarism, were in that programme and had to lead, as has always

been the case, to oppression, misery and the dehumanization of the

masses.

And now that the development of capitalism and parliamentarism has borne

its fruits, and the bourgeoisie has exhausted every generous sentiment

and progressive elan by the practice of political and economic

competition, it is reduced to having to defend its privileges with force

and deceit, while its philosophers cannot defend it against the

socialist attacks except by bringing up, inopportunely, the law of vital

competition.