💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › shawn-p-wilbur-are-hotels-immoral.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:08:22. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Are Hotels Immoral? Author: Shawn P. Wilbur Date: October 27, 2012 Language: en Topics: mutualism; occupany and use; rent Source: Retrieved on November 8, 2022 from https://www.libertarian-labyrinth.org/contrun/are-hotels-immoral/
Q: Are Hotels Immoral?
A: No. If someone is actively maintaining a hotel, then they are
obviously occupying and using it. A large hotel is likely to be a
collectively owned affair, like most large enterprises under usufructory
ownership.
Q: Can that somebody hire people to help him or her occupy it and
maintain it?
A: Well, not without leaving the regime of occupancy and use property.
It is possible that there might be reasons to respect such an
arrangement in the midst of an occupancy-and-use-based community, but at
the point where it looks like there is rent-seeking and exploitation of
labor going on in a mutualist community, I suspect both the labor force
and the customers are likely to start looking elsewhere. Mutualists
markets are most likely to manifest profits in the form of a general
reduction in costs, and capitalist profits will probably stick out like
a sore thumb in that context.
<br/>
Contracts can solve many underlying problems, and there are plenty of
other ways to establish rules for human interaction. Mutualist markets
would have their particular character, and forms of profit, precisely
because the rules for interaction within them are governed by norms of
reciprocity, “cost the limit of price,” etc., rather than the norms
dominant within capitalist markets.
Most uses of natural resources or real property have a basic cycle to
them. For example, it is expected that we will be out of our homes as
much as we are in them. A home is, in part, a fixed place where we keep
the stuff we don’t want or need to carry around all day — just as it is,
in part, a place where we sleep, a potentially private space, etc. If
we’re talking about agriculture, then it is expected that the land we
are using will lie fallow sometimes, because of seasonal cycles or crop
rotation. The folks running a hotel will be there, day in and day out,
while guests will come and go, and staff will maintain the hotel for
themselves and the guests alike.
Q: Doesn’t that seem somewhat arbitrary, especially for things that have
multiple uses?
A: Not particularly, since all we need to establish is that something is
being used according the natural patterns of someform of use.
These use cycles are determined by the usual demands and conditions of
particular kinds of resource use.
The argument against mutualist hotels depends on an understanding of
“occupancy and use” which I’ve never seen a mutualist advance, and which
also appears very different from the ways we customarily think about
these issues now.
Presumably, though, any new process will also have its logical cycles.
And, of course, experimentation is something we’ve done before, and
should have no trouble recognizing as a use.
Actually, I’ve already given a number of examples. Cycles for
agricultural use are determined by a mix of seasonal factors and
developing conventions regarding “best practices” for crop rotation,
fallow periods, etc. Our mutualist hotel will have guests who come and
go, primarily for short stays, and hosts who are relatively stable. Etc.
If I’m experimenting with a different agricultural method, then the
nature of the experiment will determine how long I put resources to that
use, and how much of the time during the experiment some or all of the
resources might be idle. If I’m brewing small-batch beer, each
experimental cycle will tend to be considerably shorter than an
agricultural cycle — unless perhaps I’m aging a batch.
It’s a simple standard, easily adaptable to a range of resources and
uses.
This all started because somebody thought mutualists thought hotels were
“immoral.” That’s just a version of the “mutualists will take your house
when you nip out for a quart of milk” claim, and both seem to fall
rather decisively before the fact that occupancy and use always seems to
involve some pattern of absence and presence, fairly predictably tied to
the particular resources and the particular uses. Now, in some cases,
that means that knowing whether or not a resource is currently in use
might take a little research, but we expect that with all property
regimes, so that can’t really be a very serious objection.
Now, the “why” of occupancy and use comes from the proudhonian critique
of property theories. Nothing stronger seems to hold up to scrutiny.