💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › benjamin-tucker-proudhon-and-his-critic.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:15:32. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Proudhon and His Critic Author: Benjamin Tucker Date: 1876 Language: en Topics: a reply, individualism, Libertarian Labyrinth, mutualism, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Stephen Pearl Andrews, The Index Source: Retrieved 11/24/2021 from https://www.libertarian-labyrinth.org/proudhon-library/benjamin-r-tucker-proudhon-and-his-critic-1876/ Notes: Benjamin R. Tucker, “Proudhon and His Critic,” The Index 7 no. 342 (July 13, 1876): 333. A reply to Stephen Pearl Andrews’s “Proudhon and His Translator” (1876).
The student of Proudhon must have laid down The Index of June 22d,
containing Stephen Pearl Andrews’ article on “Proudhon and his
Translator,” with a feeling of pleasure not unmixed with pain; pleasure
at meeting at last with an elaborate and scholarly criticism of this
author and his work, dealing in argument rather than ridicule; and pain
at finding this same criticism so alloyed with error and careless
misstatement as to greatly detract from its value. The wicked lies and
stupid sneers with which the press has almost uniformly greeted the
translation into English of What is Property? I have chosen not to
notice, believing that a book which cannot defend itself against
assaults of such a character had better die at once; but when so able
and keen a critic as Mr. Andrews is known to be carelessly
misrepresents—by implication rather than direct statement—the theories
advocated in the work, justice to his author’s memory compels the
translator to fulfil the duty imposed upon him by the function which he
has assumed, by entering a protest and insisting on fair play. Those who
have intelligently read the book already, will discover, without further
help of mine, the discrepancy between Proudhon’s doctrines as stated by
himself and the idea that a novice would form of them in taking them at
secondhand from Mr. Andrews. That those also, whose knowledge of
Proudhon is yet to be acquired, may appreciate this discrepancy, I shall
endeavor, as far as possible, in this article, to “let the master speak
for himself.” Before proceeding, however, to a detailed examination of
the matter in hand, I must first thank Mr. Andrews for his handsome
recognition of Proudhon’s virtues and abilities, and his clear and
accurate insight into his character. Had he understood his writings as
well as he understands the man, there would be no call for this
expression of dissent.
The first point calling for attention is the critic’s assumption that
Proudhon, in saying that “property is impossible,” meant that it cannot
exist even temporarily or contingently. He says: “But if property is
impossible, then it cannot exist; and if it cannot exist, then it does
not exist; and why should M. Proudhon write a big book to do away with
what does not and never did have any existence?” Now let us listen to
Proudhon (page 40, outlining his arguments): “Considering the fact of
property in itself, we shall inquire whether this fact is real, whether
it exists, whether it is possible. Then we shall discover, singularly
enough, that property may indeed manifest itself accidentally; but that,
as an institution and principle, it is mathematically impossible. So
that the axiom of the school—abactu ad posse valet consecutio: from the
actual to the possible the inference is good—is given the lie as far as
property is concerned.” True, Mr. Andrews says immediately afterwards:
“Of course the literal meaning of what he says is absurd”; and proceeds
to show what he really did mean; but then where is the pertinency of our
critic’s first argument? Why should Mr. Andrews write half a paragraph
to refute what Proudhon never did mean? The only effect of such a course
is the same as that which the former repeatedly charges upon the
latter’s writings, viz.; the confusing of the reader’s mind. It is
virtual misrepresentation.
In the next two paragraphs we find the same thing repeated. The critic
first makes the following lucid statement of Proudhon’s understanding of
the word property, for which he deserves great credit, nearly all
previous critics having failed to grasp and state this vital point:
“What he means by property is that subtle fiction which makes that mine
or thine of which we are out of possession, for which we have no present
use, but which by this subtle tie we may recall at our option, using it,
in the meantime, to subjugate others to our service, by taking increase
for its use, in the form of rent, interest, and the like.” Then, after
warning (very properly) his readers that unless this sense of the term
property is constantly borne in mind, the author is certain to be
misunderstood, he immediately dismisses it from his own mind, and
indulges in the following remarks: “It is, however, not true that
property, even so restricted in definition, is robbery, pure and simple.
It is not proprietorship, but the use of proprietorship, to extort
increase, which is vicious in principle.” What is the meaning of this
sudden twist in the critic’s logic? If this “vicious use of
proprietorship” is the very thing which Proudhon regards as the essence
of proprietorship, how can Mr. Andrews deny that property, according to
Proudhon’s restricted definition, is robbery? The state of the reader’s
mind, when he reached this point of the criticism, must have been
“confusion worse confounded.” Indeed, the present writer hardly dares
follow this line of thought further, for fear that, despite his intimacy
with the views in question, he will begin to feel muddled himself.
The critic next falls into the error of supposing that his author favors
the forcible intervention of society to control the property relations
of individuals. This misapprehension, in view of the slightly misleading
character of some of Proudhon’s phrases, is partially excusable; but a
close reading reveals the fact that the only control which he favored is
that which is exercised, not through institutions based on physical
force, but through the natural operation of the law of equitable
exchange. “He (Proudhon) also leaves us very much in the dark as to the
precise social machinery by which he would have the world organized and
run. He is far more specific with regard to what he would abolish than
with regard to what he would construct.” Why should he treat of
organization in a work devoted to analysis? This objection is thus
answered by Proudhon in the closing passage of his preface: “On the
following conditions, then, of subsequent evidence, depends the
correctness of my preceding arguments: the discovery of a system of
absolute equality in which all existing institutions, save property, not
only may find a place, but may themselves serve as instruments of
equality: individual liberty, the division of power, the public
ministry, etc.,—a system which better than property, guarantees the
formation of capital and keeps up the courage of all; which, from a
superior point of view, explains, corrects, and completes the theories
of association hitherto proposed, from Plato and Pythagoras to Babeuf,
Saint Simon, and Fourier; a system, finally, which, serving as a means
of transition, is immediately applicable.” Proudhon was no less keenly
alive to the necessity of organization than is Mr. Andrews himself. He
fulfilled the above promise in his subsequent works by developing his
theory of mutualism, which was to find its first external expression in
the organization of credit on a gratuitous basis by a system of banking
which he devised, the results of which would be so vast and beneficent
that one fears to present even the barest outline of them, for fear of
so awakening the incredulity of the reader as to blind him to the truth
of the principles involved.
Mr. Andrews next objects to Proudhon’s use of the term anarchy to denote
order, for the reason that, while the Greek arche, from which it is
derived, meant both “personal government by arbitrium and the government
of inherent laws and principles,” Proudhon confined it to the former of
these ideas. It is difficult to see why he had not as good a right to
confine it to the former, as had Mr. Andrews, when coining the word
Pantarchy, to confine it to the latter.
The worst instance of misrepresentation, however, contained in the whole
criticism, occurs in the following sentences: “At the 56^(th) page the
author propounds the theory that there was a primitive state of social
equality; that our departure from it is a degeneracy; that we are to
return to that state of nature, etc. Surely our social theories are in
advance of that idea now. Man never returns to prior conditions. He
advances to new conditions which reproduce the spirit of primal states,
but in still newer forms, which embody also the good of what now is. We
pass from an undifferentiated state to differentiation, and thence not
backward but forward to integration. So the equality which Proudhon so
aspired after will never come in the simple primitive form, but it will
come in a higher and scientifically adjusted form.” Now, it is assumed
here that Proudhon said the precise opposite of what he really did say.
Suppose we compare this rendering of the 56^(th) page with the 56^(th)
page itself (and I ask any fair-minded person if it is not expressed in
terms so unmistakably plain that no ordinarily careful reader could fail
to understand it): “To suppose original equality in human society is to
admit by implication that the present inequality is a degeneration from
the nature of this society,—a thing which the defenders of property
cannot explain. But I infer therefrom that, if Providence placed the
first human beings in a condition of equality, it was an indication of
its desires, a model that it wished them to realize in other forms; just
as the religious sentiment, which it planted in their hearts, has
developed and manifested itself in various ways. Man has but one nature,
constant and unalterable: he pursues it through instinct, he wanders
from it through reflection, he returns to it through judgment; who shall
say that we are not returning now?” And yet, in the face of this, Mr.
Andrews would have us believe that Proudhon wanted to go back, not only
to the old spirit, but to old forms! The fact is, the idea expressed by
Mr. Andrews in his formula of unism, duism, and trinism, was completely
developed by Proudhon in 1845 in his Contradictions Economiques (the
only difference being that the latter used the terms thesis, antithesis,
and synthesis), and for him to say that “Proudhon never attained to it”
is almost impudent. Proudhon borrowed it from Hegel, to whom he credited
it; and Colonel William B. Greene traces it back even further than this,
finding its origin in the Jewish Kabbala.
The criticism of Proudhon’s remarks upon equality is, I confess,
partially correct. He claimed too much when he said that equality was
synonymous with society, and made a more accurate statement afterwards
in calling it a sine qua non of society; but that this trivial error
affords a “loophole of escape to the proprietor of every grade” from the
crushing logic of the rest of the work, I utterly fail to see. I must
not close without referring to the animus of Mr. Andrews’ article, which
is best exhibited in his statement that “Proudhon belongs as
definitively to the past, at this day, and to the mere history of ideas,
as Ptolemy after Copernicus.” Has it come to this, then, that in this
fast age we progress so rapidly that a single decade suffices to blot
out the memory and destroy the usefulness of one of whom the Pantarch
even is compelled to speak so highly? The hint is a very broad one; and
it does not take the eye of Argus to discover that the Copernicus of our
social system is named Stephen Pearl Andrews; and when Proudhon’s
translator is advised to waste no further time on such a useless task,
but to be sure that he is doing the “best thing possible,” it is evident
that the best thing possible, in the critic’s view, is to join the
Pantarchy, and work therein. The whole article is an almost shocking
revelation of the practice of the Pantarch in persisting in selfishly
subordinating what he considers the comparative worthlessness of others
to what he considers his own superlative worth.