💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › benjamin-tucker-proudhon-and-his-critic.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:15:32. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Proudhon and His Critic
Author: Benjamin Tucker
Date: 1876
Language: en
Topics: a reply, individualism, Libertarian Labyrinth, mutualism, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Stephen Pearl Andrews, The Index
Source: Retrieved 11/24/2021 from https://www.libertarian-labyrinth.org/proudhon-library/benjamin-r-tucker-proudhon-and-his-critic-1876/
Notes: Benjamin R. Tucker, “Proudhon and His Critic,” The Index 7 no. 342 (July 13, 1876): 333. A reply to Stephen Pearl Andrews’s “Proudhon and His Translator” (1876).

Benjamin Tucker

Proudhon and His Critic

The student of Proudhon must have laid down The Index of June 22d,

containing Stephen Pearl Andrews’ article on “Proudhon and his

Translator,” with a feeling of pleasure not unmixed with pain; pleasure

at meeting at last with an elaborate and scholarly criticism of this

author and his work, dealing in argument rather than ridicule; and pain

at finding this same criticism so alloyed with error and careless

misstatement as to greatly detract from its value. The wicked lies and

stupid sneers with which the press has almost uniformly greeted the

translation into English of What is Property? I have chosen not to

notice, believing that a book which cannot defend itself against

assaults of such a character had better die at once; but when so able

and keen a critic as Mr. Andrews is known to be carelessly

misrepresents—by implication rather than direct statement—the theories

advocated in the work, justice to his author’s memory compels the

translator to fulfil the duty imposed upon him by the function which he

has assumed, by entering a protest and insisting on fair play. Those who

have intelligently read the book already, will discover, without further

help of mine, the discrepancy between Proudhon’s doctrines as stated by

himself and the idea that a novice would form of them in taking them at

secondhand from Mr. Andrews. That those also, whose knowledge of

Proudhon is yet to be acquired, may appreciate this discrepancy, I shall

endeavor, as far as possible, in this article, to “let the master speak

for himself.” Before proceeding, however, to a detailed examination of

the matter in hand, I must first thank Mr. Andrews for his handsome

recognition of Proudhon’s virtues and abilities, and his clear and

accurate insight into his character. Had he understood his writings as

well as he understands the man, there would be no call for this

expression of dissent.

The first point calling for attention is the critic’s assumption that

Proudhon, in saying that “property is impossible,” meant that it cannot

exist even temporarily or contingently. He says: “But if property is

impossible, then it cannot exist; and if it cannot exist, then it does

not exist; and why should M. Proudhon write a big book to do away with

what does not and never did have any existence?” Now let us listen to

Proudhon (page 40, outlining his arguments): “Considering the fact of

property in itself, we shall inquire whether this fact is real, whether

it exists, whether it is possible. Then we shall discover, singularly

enough, that property may indeed manifest itself accidentally; but that,

as an institution and principle, it is mathematically impossible. So

that the axiom of the school—abactu ad posse valet consecutio: from the

actual to the possible the inference is good—is given the lie as far as

property is concerned.” True, Mr. Andrews says immediately afterwards:

“Of course the literal meaning of what he says is absurd”; and proceeds

to show what he really did mean; but then where is the pertinency of our

critic’s first argument? Why should Mr. Andrews write half a paragraph

to refute what Proudhon never did mean? The only effect of such a course

is the same as that which the former repeatedly charges upon the

latter’s writings, viz.; the confusing of the reader’s mind. It is

virtual misrepresentation.

In the next two paragraphs we find the same thing repeated. The critic

first makes the following lucid statement of Proudhon’s understanding of

the word property, for which he deserves great credit, nearly all

previous critics having failed to grasp and state this vital point:

“What he means by property is that subtle fiction which makes that mine

or thine of which we are out of possession, for which we have no present

use, but which by this subtle tie we may recall at our option, using it,

in the meantime, to subjugate others to our service, by taking increase

for its use, in the form of rent, interest, and the like.” Then, after

warning (very properly) his readers that unless this sense of the term

property is constantly borne in mind, the author is certain to be

misunderstood, he immediately dismisses it from his own mind, and

indulges in the following remarks: “It is, however, not true that

property, even so restricted in definition, is robbery, pure and simple.

It is not proprietorship, but the use of proprietorship, to extort

increase, which is vicious in principle.” What is the meaning of this

sudden twist in the critic’s logic? If this “vicious use of

proprietorship” is the very thing which Proudhon regards as the essence

of proprietorship, how can Mr. Andrews deny that property, according to

Proudhon’s restricted definition, is robbery? The state of the reader’s

mind, when he reached this point of the criticism, must have been

“confusion worse confounded.” Indeed, the present writer hardly dares

follow this line of thought further, for fear that, despite his intimacy

with the views in question, he will begin to feel muddled himself.

The critic next falls into the error of supposing that his author favors

the forcible intervention of society to control the property relations

of individuals. This misapprehension, in view of the slightly misleading

character of some of Proudhon’s phrases, is partially excusable; but a

close reading reveals the fact that the only control which he favored is

that which is exercised, not through institutions based on physical

force, but through the natural operation of the law of equitable

exchange. “He (Proudhon) also leaves us very much in the dark as to the

precise social machinery by which he would have the world organized and

run. He is far more specific with regard to what he would abolish than

with regard to what he would construct.” Why should he treat of

organization in a work devoted to analysis? This objection is thus

answered by Proudhon in the closing passage of his preface: “On the

following conditions, then, of subsequent evidence, depends the

correctness of my preceding arguments: the discovery of a system of

absolute equality in which all existing institutions, save property, not

only may find a place, but may themselves serve as instruments of

equality: individual liberty, the division of power, the public

ministry, etc.,—a system which better than property, guarantees the

formation of capital and keeps up the courage of all; which, from a

superior point of view, explains, corrects, and completes the theories

of association hitherto proposed, from Plato and Pythagoras to Babeuf,

Saint Simon, and Fourier; a system, finally, which, serving as a means

of transition, is immediately applicable.” Proudhon was no less keenly

alive to the necessity of organization than is Mr. Andrews himself. He

fulfilled the above promise in his subsequent works by developing his

theory of mutualism, which was to find its first external expression in

the organization of credit on a gratuitous basis by a system of banking

which he devised, the results of which would be so vast and beneficent

that one fears to present even the barest outline of them, for fear of

so awakening the incredulity of the reader as to blind him to the truth

of the principles involved.

Mr. Andrews next objects to Proudhon’s use of the term anarchy to denote

order, for the reason that, while the Greek arche, from which it is

derived, meant both “personal government by arbitrium and the government

of inherent laws and principles,” Proudhon confined it to the former of

these ideas. It is difficult to see why he had not as good a right to

confine it to the former, as had Mr. Andrews, when coining the word

Pantarchy, to confine it to the latter.

The worst instance of misrepresentation, however, contained in the whole

criticism, occurs in the following sentences: “At the 56^(th) page the

author propounds the theory that there was a primitive state of social

equality; that our departure from it is a degeneracy; that we are to

return to that state of nature, etc. Surely our social theories are in

advance of that idea now. Man never returns to prior conditions. He

advances to new conditions which reproduce the spirit of primal states,

but in still newer forms, which embody also the good of what now is. We

pass from an undifferentiated state to differentiation, and thence not

backward but forward to integration. So the equality which Proudhon so

aspired after will never come in the simple primitive form, but it will

come in a higher and scientifically adjusted form.” Now, it is assumed

here that Proudhon said the precise opposite of what he really did say.

Suppose we compare this rendering of the 56^(th) page with the 56^(th)

page itself (and I ask any fair-minded person if it is not expressed in

terms so unmistakably plain that no ordinarily careful reader could fail

to understand it): “To suppose original equality in human society is to

admit by implication that the present inequality is a degeneration from

the nature of this society,—a thing which the defenders of property

cannot explain. But I infer therefrom that, if Providence placed the

first human beings in a condition of equality, it was an indication of

its desires, a model that it wished them to realize in other forms; just

as the religious sentiment, which it planted in their hearts, has

developed and manifested itself in various ways. Man has but one nature,

constant and unalterable: he pursues it through instinct, he wanders

from it through reflection, he returns to it through judgment; who shall

say that we are not returning now?” And yet, in the face of this, Mr.

Andrews would have us believe that Proudhon wanted to go back, not only

to the old spirit, but to old forms! The fact is, the idea expressed by

Mr. Andrews in his formula of unism, duism, and trinism, was completely

developed by Proudhon in 1845 in his Contradictions Economiques (the

only difference being that the latter used the terms thesis, antithesis,

and synthesis), and for him to say that “Proudhon never attained to it”

is almost impudent. Proudhon borrowed it from Hegel, to whom he credited

it; and Colonel William B. Greene traces it back even further than this,

finding its origin in the Jewish Kabbala.

The criticism of Proudhon’s remarks upon equality is, I confess,

partially correct. He claimed too much when he said that equality was

synonymous with society, and made a more accurate statement afterwards

in calling it a sine qua non of society; but that this trivial error

affords a “loophole of escape to the proprietor of every grade” from the

crushing logic of the rest of the work, I utterly fail to see. I must

not close without referring to the animus of Mr. Andrews’ article, which

is best exhibited in his statement that “Proudhon belongs as

definitively to the past, at this day, and to the mere history of ideas,

as Ptolemy after Copernicus.” Has it come to this, then, that in this

fast age we progress so rapidly that a single decade suffices to blot

out the memory and destroy the usefulness of one of whom the Pantarch

even is compelled to speak so highly? The hint is a very broad one; and

it does not take the eye of Argus to discover that the Copernicus of our

social system is named Stephen Pearl Andrews; and when Proudhon’s

translator is advised to waste no further time on such a useless task,

but to be sure that he is doing the “best thing possible,” it is evident

that the best thing possible, in the critic’s view, is to join the

Pantarchy, and work therein. The whole article is an almost shocking

revelation of the practice of the Pantarch in persisting in selfishly

subordinating what he considers the comparative worthlessness of others

to what he considers his own superlative worth.