đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș anarcho-proudhon-property-and-possession.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:27:37. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Proudhon, Property and Possession Author: Anarcho Date: July 12, 2014 Language: en Topics: Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, property, mutualism Source: Retrieved on 24th April 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=802
âEither competition, â that is, monopoly and what follows; or
exploitation by the State, â that is, dearness of labour and continuous
impoverishment; or else, in short, a solution based upon equality, â in
other words, the organisation of labour, which involves the negation of
political economy and the end of property.â
â Proudhon, System of Economic Contradictions[1]
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809â1865) has been subject to many
interpretations, from the seminal (K. Steven Vincent[2]) to the
malicious (Karl Marx[3]). This, undoubtedly, has led to many concluding
that he was a contradictory thinker but not all interpretations of his
ideas have merit.[4] He was fundamentally consistent in his libertarian
socialism.[5]
Derek Ryan Strongâs âProudhon and the Labour Theory of Propertyâ[6] is,
in general, a useful account of Proudhonâs ideas in relation to
replacing wage-labour by workersâ associations. As this aspect of his
ideas is often ignored or denied by commentators, it is a welcome
addition to the scholarship. However, his discussion of Proudhonâs views
of social ownership is flawed. While quoting many of the key passages,
he does not accept them and tries to explain them away by introducing
commentary which is not justified to defend an assumption in favour of
private property. We need to place these quotes into their rightful
context to show that the Frenchman supported socialisation of property
and that the communist-anarchists extended his arguments.[7]
Proudhonâs critique of property is multi-threaded reflecting the
numerous justifications for it. His arguments for the social ownership
of land and raw materials are different from those for social ownership
of âcapitalâ (instruments of labour). The former is, as Strong indicates
(58â9), connected to the fact no one created them while the latter
relates to Proudhonâs theory of collective force but they reach the same
conclusion.[8]
While quoting the appropriate passages on social ownership of capital,
Strong introduces commentary which is not justified. He is right to note
that Proudhonâs conclusion that âsince all capital is social property,
no one has exclusive property in itâ[9] was drawn from âdiscussing the
issue of collective appropriationâ (collective force) but it is not the
case that the âparticular contextâ shows âthe capital which he refers to
is actually financial capital (i.e., money) as opposed to physical
capital (i.e., capital goods).â (59) After discussing how the capitalist
who hires workers exploits them by not paying for their collective
force, Proudhon argues that if the worker is proprietor of the value
which he createsâ then âit followsâ that since all production being
necessarily collective, the worker is entitled to a share of the
products and profits commensurate with his labourâ and so âall
accumulated capital being social property, no one can be its exclusive
proprietorâ.[10] Proudhon is clearly discussing the actual process of
production to show where and how exploitation occurs and so is referring
to âphysical capitalâ and not credit.
Strong gives only part of Proudhonâs analysis when he states that the
âvalue created within a firm results from the collective force of
workers labouring together and, therefore, his conclusion is that no one
person should be its exclusive proprietor.â (59) Proudhon extends this
to conclude that, to ensure this outcome, (physical) capital must become
âsocial propertyâ and so it is not the case that Proudhon wished it to
be âowned collectively by the workers in a particular firm, but not
society as a wholeâ. (59)
This is confirmed by Proudhonâs summation that â[a]ll human labour being
the result of collective force, all property becomes, by the same
reason, collective and undividedâ and so âevery instrument of labour, an
accumulated capitalâ is âa collective propertyâ.[11] Strong is wrong to
suggest that it only âappears as ifâ Proudhon âthought that capital
goods should be common propertyâ (59) for Proudhon takes the premise
that workers own the product of their labour, combines it with an
analysis of how exploitation occurs within production and concludes that
the means of production (âcapitalâ) must, like land and raw materials,
be âsocial propertyâ and âundividedâ.
The reason is obvious: if ownership is invested in a specific workers
association then what happens to new entrants? It is possible for a
workersâ association to be as exclusive as a capitalist company and hire
wage-workers. Only social property ensures this does not happen so that
workers leaving one co-operative can become an associate in a new
one.[12]
Property âwas theft because those who legally appropriated the products
of labour in capitalism were not actually responsible for productionâ
(53) but also because it allowed the few to appropriate the means of
production from its rightful owners (everyone) so reducing the rest to
wage-workers (salariat) who âhave sold their arms and parted with their
libertyâ to an employer which has âdegraded the worker by giving him a
masterâ and ensures âthe surplus of labour, essentially collective,
passes entirely⊠to the proprietor.â[13]
If society ensures âthe firm is a contractual relationship and not a
property rightâ (57) and if property âdenotes the exclusive rights
assigned to an individual or specific group of people to access, use,
and govern a resource, object, or set of objects in a particular wayâ
(54) then there is social and not private property. Only social
ownership means that there are no owners of a resource such as a
workplace to stop others using them without first agreeing to oppressive
or exploitative relationships.
For Proudhon, anarchism (âlibertyâ, âassociationâ, âuniversal
associationâ or âmutualismâ[14]) was the âthird form of societyâ and a
âsynthesisâ of property and âcommunityâ.[15] His opposition to both
community and capitalism should not blind us to his desire for a
âsynthesisâ between the two. This means taking Proudhon at his word
rather than, to quote George Woodcock, suggesting that he âdid not even
mean literally what he saidâ in What is Property?.[16] Strong follows
Woodcock in suggesting Proudhonâs possession is a modified form of
property rather than, as Proudhon insisted, its negation.
In What is Property? Proudhon argued that everyone becomes âa possessor
or usufructuaryâ which is âa function which excludes proprietorshipâ and
âreceives his usufruct from the hands of society, which alone is the
permanent possessor.â[17] He clarified this point by stressing that
âthis value or wealth, produced by the activity of all, is by the very
fact of its creation collective wealth, the use of which, like that of
the land, may be divided, but which as property remains undivided. And
why this undivided ownership? Because the society which creates is
itself indivisibleâ. In short: âproperty in capital is indivisible, and
consequently inalienableâ. Proudhon, then, âopposes the exclusive
appropriation of the instruments of productionâ and âthis
non-appropriation of the instruments of productionâ would be âa
destruction of property. In fact, without the appropriation of
instruments, property is nothing.â[18]
In April 1848 he argued that âto organise national workshops contains an
authentic idea, one that I endorse, for all my criticismsâ and these
âworkshops are owned by the nation, even though they remain and must
always remain free.â The âExchange Bank is the organisation of labourâs
greatest assetâ and would allow âthe new form of society to be defined
and created among the workers.â[19] His election manifesto of the same
year saw him proclaim that âunder universal association, ownership of
the land and of the instruments of labour is social ownershipâ to be
operated by âdemocratically organised workersâ associationsâ.[20] He
empathetically denied in 1849 that he argued that the âownership of the
instruments of labour must forever stay vested in the individual and
remain unorganisedâ, stating he had ânever penned nor uttered any such
thingâ, had âargued the opposite a hundred times overâ and he wished for
âan order wherein the instruments of labour will cease to be
appropriated and instead become sharedâ. He then sketched how
âtransferring ownershipâ would be achieved by the organisation of credit
that would produce âworkersâ associationsâ before forming âthe
over-arching group, comprising the nation in its entiretyâ.[20]
A few years later, Proudhon talks of a âdouble contractâ between the
members of the co-operative and between it and society. While its
members have âan undivided share in the property of the companyâ, the
company itself was âa creation and a dependenceâ of society and âholds
its books and records at the disposition of Society, which⊠reserves the
power of dissolving the workers company, as the sanction of its right of
control.â The company was to be run democratically and âmay take in new
members at any timeâ so producing an institution which âhas no precedent
and no model.â[21] The change in terminology does not obscure that the
company was to be run (used) by its workers â who automatically become
members of the association upon entry â under the control (ownership) of
society.
On his deathbed he stressed that mutualism would not be âcommunityâ but
rather an association âwhich must embrace the whole of Society, and
nevertheless preserve all the rights of individual and corporate [i.e.,
self-managed industry] freedomâ. While both capitalist firms and
communist associations show âtheir narrowness of spiritâ and âare
composed by a determinate number of people, to the exclusion of all
othersâ, the âmutualist association⊠admits⊠everyone in the world, and
tends towards universalityâ. Thus âthe labouring masses are actually,
positively and effectively sovereignâ because âthe economic organism â
labour, capital, property and assets â belongs to them entirelyâ.[22]
Proudhonâs objection to community was that while the âmembers of a
community⊠have no private propertyâ the community âis proprietor, and
proprietor not only of the goods, but of the persons and wills.â[23]
Workers did not control their own labour (âpersons and willsâ) nor its
product (âgoodsâ) â use was, in other words, as undivided as ownership.
The âentire animus of [Proudhonâs] opposition to what he termed
âcommunityâ was to avoid the central ownership of property and the
central control of economic and social decision-makingâ.[24]
While his critique of property as theft and despotism is well known,
Proudhon also suggested the âmost delightful feature of propertyâ was
âthe free disposition of oneâs goodsâ[25] and so desired âproperty
restored to its proper limits, that is to say, free disposition of the
fruits of labour, property MINUS USURY!â[26] Proudhon wished to âretain
the private possession of the land, dwelling, and tools which a worker
needed⊠a social arrangement which would allow the worker to make the
decisions relevant to the conduct and operation of his trade, either
alone or with cooperation of his immediate associations.â[27]
Anarchists are well aware that âprivate property in capital goods is
possible without exploitationâ (58) but only when it involves workers
using the tools they own as in artisan and peasant production.[28]
Unlike artisan and peasant production, capitalism divorces ownership and
use: âwhen the usufructuary converted his right to personally use the
thing into the right to use it by his neighbourâs labour â then property
changed its nature, and its idea became complex.â[29] Would ownership by
co-operatives end this complexity? No, for, as indicated above,
co-operatives can be as exclusive as capitalist companies. Proudhon
recognised the economic transformation produced by the industrial
revolution and his arguments for workersâ associations and social
ownership of capital reflect this.[30]
So in capitalism ownership and use are divided while in community they
are undivided. A synthesis that produced liberty meant that ownership
had to be undivided while use was divided. Social property ensured
workers would become associates not wage-workers when they join a
workplace and so receive the full product of their labour. This would
allow the benefits desired by both property and community to be achieved
without their negative consequences.
Strong is wrong: Proudhon did argue for the social ownership of land and
capital, using the word indivise (âjointâ or âundividedâ) to describe
it. Such âundividedâ ownership by all was the framework within which
possession (use) was exercised.[31] As Jack Hayward notes, it was âthe
community which alone owns property, although its use is accorded to
individual and associated producers linked by free contractâ and while
âthe means of production should be publicly owned, production itself
should be organised by workers companies.â[33] Other commentators on
Proudhon â Max Stirner[32] Daniel GuĂ©rin[33], Georges Gurvitch[34] and
Robert L. Hoffman[35] â concur.
Proudhon rejected communism as well as community and did not extend the
socialisation from the means of production to the goods created by them:
workers would sell the product of their labour in markets.[38] Those who
did move from the critique of wage-labour to the wage-system like
Proudhonâs contemporary Joseph DĂ©jacque and later communist-anarchists
based their ideas on Proudhonâs and retained the same commitment to
undivided ownership and divided use: the same usufructuary position is
common to both.[36]
There is a clear link between mutualism and libertarian communism and we
discover Kropotkin arguing for distribution according to need by
pointing to the contradiction between usufructuary use of commonly held
means of production and the private ownership of the products created by
them.[37] However, the use of both means and goods would remain
âdividedâ and, as such, libertarian communism avoids the problems of
âcommunity.â Indeed, Kropotkin explicitly argues that
anarchist-communism would not sacrifice the individual on the âaltarâ of
âthe communityâ by ensuring use rights to all socialised goods.[38]
Strong is incorrect to suggest a fundamental difference in perspective
between mutualism and communism. This is not to suggest that Proudhon
would have embraced libertarian communism simply that his ideas on
possession are at the heart of it.[39]
For Proudhon, then, it was not the case that â[e]nsuring access to
capital goods need not imply common ownership of physical capitalâ (60),
he did not âmean two different thingsâ when he advocated social
ownership and so did not argue for workplaces being âowned collectively
by the workers in a particular firm, but not society as a whole.â (59)
Only social ownership/property meant new entrants to a workplace become
associates and not wage-workers. Strong fails to grasp how Proudhonâs
theory of âcollective forceâ shows how exploitation happens within
production and why socialisation of âcapitalâ was necessary.
Yet while land, raw materials and instruments of labour (âcapital
goodsâ) must be socially owned to end exploitation their use must be
divided to ensure freedom. Social property was the foundation which
ensured the collective use of a workplace by its associated workforce.
Strong confuses use (which is divided) with ownership (which is not).
If, as he (rightly) argues, Proudhonâs position on land use âis best
described as usufruct, or private use of common property, rather than a
type of private propertyâ (59) then this also applies to the means of
production. The notion of Proudhon advocating âmutualist private
propertyâ (63) is incorrect and it would be better to use his term:
possession.
[20]Election Manifesto of Le Peupleâ, 377
[33]Jack Hayward, After the French Revolution: Six Critics of Democracy
and Nationalism (Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1991), 181, 201
[38]This explains how âsome of the items Proudhon lists, such as a
plough, are capital goodsâ (62) for he is talking of the plough as a
âproduct of labourâ and, as such, the workers should be paid for that
labour. The paid for good would then be used by the worker who bought it
and who would, in turn, be paid for the goods they create using it. This
would be possession and not property.
[1] Property is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology (Iain McKay
(Editor), Edinburgh/Oakland/Baltimore: AK Press, 2011), 202. All quotes
from Proudhonâs works are from this anthology.
[2]
K. Steven Vincent, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French
Republican Socialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984)
[3] While The Poverty of Philosophy (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books,
1995) is best known, Marx repeatedly commented on Proudhon throughout
his life. I discuss this in my introduction to Property is Theft!
(64â79) as well as indicating on how Marx distorts Proudhonâs System of
Economic Contradictions within The Poverty of Philosophy by comparing
what Marx claims Proudhon wrote with the actual text.
[4] Most obviously, J. Salwyn Schapiroâs attempt to portray Proudhon as
a fascist cannot withstand even a causal familiarity with Proudhonâs
ideas nor an investigation of the material he selectively quotes from
(âPierre Joseph Proudhon, Harbinger of Fascismâ, The American Historical
Review, 50: 4, 714â737).
[5] For example, his discussion of association within mutualism in âThe
Political Capacity of the Working Classesâ (744â753) is identical to
that made nearly 20 years previously within âSystem of Economic
Contradictionsâ (213â215).
[6] Anarchist Studies 22: 1, 52â65
[7] I address these issues in âIntroduction: General Idea of the
Revolution in the 21^(st) Centuryâ (Property is Theft!, 30â1, 37â8,
47â9) and âLaying the Foundations: Proudhonâs Contribution to Anarchist
Economicsâ (Accumulation of Freedom: Writings on Anarchist Economics
[Anthony J. Nocella, Deric Shannon and John Asimakopoulos (Editors),
Oakland/Edinburgh/Baltimore: AK Press, 2012], 64â78)
[8] As Proudhon suggested, they are related: âHere [economist] M.
Wolowski pretends to think that the opponents of property refer only to
property in land, while they merely take it as a term of comparisonâ
(âLetter to M. Blanqui on Propertyâ, 147)
[9] Benjamin Tucker translated this passage as âall accumulated capital
being social property, no one can be its exclusive proprietor.â (âWhat
is Property?â, 118)
[10] âWhat is Property?â, 117â8
[11] âWhat is Property?â, 137
[12] See Proudhonâs discussion of association in âSystem of Economic
Contradictionsâ (213â5) and Vincentâs excellent discussion (154â160)
[13] âSystem of Economic Contradictionsâ, 212, 192, 253. Labour renting
capital does not end exploitation and so it is not âdifficult to say
whether or not Proudhon [like Ellerman] would have supportedâ a
situation of âlabour-managed firmsâ in which âlabour hires in capital to
produce goodsâ and so âdivorces the ownership and usage of those goods
while maintaining workersâ control of productionâ. (58) Proudhon was
clear: âif labour is the sole basis of property, I cease to be
proprietor of my field as soon as I receive rent for it from another⊠It
is the same with all capitalâ. Rent âreceived by the proprietorâ means
âto be rewarded for the use of a toolâ and so he âliterally receives
something for nothing.â (âWhat is Property?â, 119, 123)
[14] âWhat is Property?â, 109, 136; âLetter to M. Blanqui on Propertyâ,
143, 148; âSystem of Economic Contradictionsâ, 179, 255; âElection
Manifesto of Le Peupleâ, 377. Other equivalent terms include
âagricultural-industrial federationâ (âThe Federative Principleâ, 709)
and âGuaranteeismâ (âThe Federative Principleâ, 718; âThe Political
Capacity of the Working Classesâ, 750)
[15] âWhat is Property?â, 136. An added confusion is the translation of
âcommunityâ as âcommunismâ by Benjamin Tucker and others. I did not
clarify the issue in Property is Theft! by consistently correcting
Tuckerâs translations by replacing âcommunismâ by the more accurate
âcommunity.â If a second edition is produced, this error will be
rectified. In addition, âcommunityâ would not be considered as communism
by the likes of Kropotkin for it retained payment to members related to
the amount of work done, skill expressed and money invested.
[16] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon: A Biography 3^(rd) edition (Montréal: Black
Rose, 1987), 45. Woodcockâs account of many of Proudhonâs ideas (such as
on possession as property, small-scale production, late acceptance of
workersâ associations) seem more driven by his own rejection of
revolutionary anarchism (âA Personal Preface to the Third Editionâ,
xiii-xx) than an objective summary.
[17] âWhat is Property?â, 100
[18] âLetter to M. Blanqui on Propertyâ, 153, 149
[19] âLetter to Louis Blancâ, 296â7
[20] Letter to Pierre Lerouxâ, 498â500
[21] âGeneral Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth Centuryâ, 585â6.
This socialisation of property included more than capital, with Proudhon
indicating community ownership of housing: âall payments made as rental
shall be carried over to the account of the purchase of the propertyâŠ
such payment shall purchase for the tenant a proportional undivided
share in the house he lives in, and in all buildings erected for rental,
and serving as a habitation for citizens ... [housing] thus paid for
shall pass under the control of the communal administration⊠in the name
of all the tenants, and shall guarantee them all a domicile, in
perpetuity⊠For repairs, management, and upkeep of buildings, as well as
for new constructions, the communes shall deal with⊠building workersâ
associationsâ. This also applied to land and once âthe property has been
entirely paid for, it shall revert immediately to the commune, which
shall take the place of the former proprietorâ. (576, 578)
[22] âThe Political Capacity of the Working Classesâ, 750, 746, 752,
761.
[23] âWhat is Property?â, 131.
[24] Vincent, 141
[25] âLetter to M. Blanqui on propertyâ, 155
[26] âElection Manifesto of Le Peupleâ, 379
[27] Vincent, 141
[28] An artisan worker would not fear expropriation because he âexploits
nobody, and nobody would have the right to interfere with his workâ and
so âwe see no use in taking the tools⊠to give to another worker.â
(Peter Kropotkin, âCommunism and the Wage System: Expropriation,â Act
For Yourselves: Articles from FREEDOM 1886â1907 (London: Freedom Press,
1988), 104â5.
[29] âLetter to M. Blanqui on propertyâ, 155
[30] Given that many secondary sources assert â following Marx â that
Proudhon wished to return to a pre-industrial economy, it must be
stressed that he explicitly rejected such a position: âM. de Sismondi,
like all men of patriarchal ideas, would like the division of labour,
with machinery and manufactures, to be abandoned, and each family to
return to the system of primitive indivision, that is, to each one by
himself, each one for himself, in the most literal meaning of the words.
That would be to retrograde; it is impossible.â (âSystem of Economic
Contradictionsâ, 194) Compare Marxâs almost identical comments
suggesting Proudhon held the opposite viewpoint (The Poverty of
Philosophy, 73)
[31] There is a parallel here with Proudhonâs position on democracy
within unitarian and federalist regime, for example his comments on
decentralisation in âGeneral Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth
Centuryâ (595) and elsewhere.
[32] Proudhon âtries to get us to believe that society is the original
possessor and the sole proprietor⊠against it the so-called proprietors
have become thievesâ. (The Ego and Its Own [London: Rebel Press, 1993],
250)
[33] Proudhon âdistinguished between possession and ownershipâ and so
workers âshould hold their means of production in alleu ... but would
not be the outright owners. Property would be replaced by federal,
cooperative ownership vested not in the State but in the producers as a
whole, united in a vast agricultural and industrial federation.â (Daniel
Guérin, Anarchism: From Theory to Practice [New York/London: Monthly
Review Press, 1970], 48)
[34] Rob Knowles quotes approvingly Georges Gurvitchâs summary that âthe
attribution of the means of production all at once to the whole of
economic society, to each region, to each group of labourers, and to
each individual worker and peasant. Individuals and groups could demand
the redemption of their share [of the means of production], but not the
division of federative property, which remains one and indivisible.â The
means of production was âco-property in communal handsâ and so
âeffectively socialisedâ and thereby change ânot only its subjects, but
its nature.â (quoted in Rob Knowles, Political Economy From Below:
Economic Thought in Communitarian Anarchism, 1840â1914 [Oxon: Routledge,
2004], 150)
[35] âBy labour man creates products; by this he has right to the
products, but not to the land or to any other instrument of productionâŠ
Everyone had a right to possession of the means of production⊠Proudhon
would abolish property right altogether⊠possession⊠would be granted
and withdrawn by societyâŠâ (Revolutionary Justice: The Social and
Political Ideas of P-J Proudhon [Urbana: University of Illinois Press,
1972], 58â9)
[36] Emma Goldman, âThere is No Communism in Russiaâ, Red Emma Speaks:
An Emma Goldman Reader (3^(rd) Edition, Alix Kates Shulman (ed.), New
York: Humanity Books, 1998), 406; Alexander Berkman, What is Anarchism?
(Edinburgh/London/Oakland: AK Press, 2003), 217
[37] Peter Kropotkin, âThe Wages Systemâ, Direct Struggle Against
Capital: A Peter Kropotkin Anthology (Iain McKay (Editor),
Edinburgh/Oakland/Baltimore: AK Press, 2014) 617â629
[38] âThe Place of Anarchism in Socialistic Evolutionâ, Direct Struggle
Against Capital, 125â6
[39] See his rejection of the idea of production according to ability
and distribution according to need in âGeneral Idea of the Revolution in
the Nineteenth Centuryâ (555â7)