💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › john-zerzan-tonality-and-totality.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:40:38. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Tonality and Totality
Author: John Zerzan
Date: 1994
Language: en
Topics: music, primitivist
Source: Retrieved on May 18, 2013 from http://www.t0.or.at/zerzan/politon.htm

John Zerzan

Tonality and Totality

The defining of sentiments has always been a preoccupation of religions

and governments. But for quite some time music, with its apparent

indifference to external reality, has been developing an ideological

power of expression hitherto unknown. Originally music was a utility to

establish the rhythms of work, the rhythms of dances which were ritual

observances. And we know that it was treated as a vital symbolic

reinforcement of the “harmony” of ancient Chinese hierarchical society,

just as to Plato and Aristotle it embodied key moral functions in the

social order. The pythagorean belief that “the whole cosmos is a harmony

and a number” leapt from the fact of natural sonic phenomena to an

all-encompassing philosophical idealism, and was echoed about a thousand

years later by the seventh century encyclopedist lsadore of Seville, who

asserted that the universe “is held together by a certain harmony of

sounds, and the heavens themselves are made to revolve” by its

modulations. As Sancho Panza said to the duchess (another thousand years

down the road), who was distressed at hearing the distant sound of an

orchestra in the forest, “Where there is music, Madam, there could be no

mischief.”

Indeed, many things have been said to characterize the elusive element

we know as music. Stravinsky, for example, was quite serious in denying

its expressive, emotional aspect: “The phenomenon of music is given to

us for the sole purpose of establishing order in things, and chiefly

between man and time.” It does seem clear that music calms the sense of

time’s oppressiveness, by offering, in its patterns of tensions and

resolutions, a temporal counterworld. As Lévi-Strauss put it, “Because

of the internal organization of the musical work, the act of listening

to it immobilizes passing time; it catches and enfolds it as one catches

and enfolds a cloth flapping in the wind.”

But, contra Stravinsky, there is clearly more to music, more to its

compelling appeal, of which Homer said, “We only hear, we know nothing.”

Part of its mysterious resonance, if you will, is its simultaneous

universality and immediacy. Herein lies also its ambiguity, a cardinal

feature of all art. An Eisenstadt photograph of 1934, entitled “The Room

in which Beethoven was Born,” testifies to the latter point; just as he

was about to take the picture, a party of Nazis arrived and placed a

commemorative wreath — shown in the foreground — before the room’s bust

of Beethoven.

So the great genre of inwardness that is music has been appropriated to

many purposes and philosophies. To the Marxist Bloch, it is a realm

where the utopian horizon already “begins at our feet.” It lets us hear

what we do not have, as in Marcuse’s poetic formulation that music is “a

remembrance of what could be.” Although representation is already

reconciliation with society, there is always a moment of longing in

music. “Something is lacking, and sound at least states this lack

clearly. Sound has itself something dark and thirsty about it and blows

about instead of stopping in one place, like paint,” to quote Bloch once

more. Adorno insisted that the truth of music is “guaranteed more by its

denial of any meaning in organized society,” consonant with a retreat

into aesthetics as his choice for the last repository of negation in an

administered world.

Music, however, like all art, owes its existence to the division of

labor in society. Although it is still generally seen in isolation, as

personal creation and autonomous sphere, social meaning and values are

always encoded in music. This truth coexists with the fact that music

refers to nothing other than itself as is often said, and that what it

signifies is, at base, always determined solely by its inner

relationships. It is valid to point out, after Adorno, that music can be

understood as “a kind of analogue to that of social theory.” If it keeps

open “the irrational doorways” through which we glimpse “the wildness

and the pang of life,” according to Aaron Copland, its ideological

component must also be recognized, especially when it claims to

transcend social reality and its antagonisms.

In “The Rational and Social Foundations of Music” Weber (as elsewhere)

concerned himself with the disenchantment of the world, in this case

searching out the irrational musical elements (e.g. the 7^(th) chord)

which seemed to him to have escaped the rationalistic equalization that

characterizes the development of modern bureaucratic society. But if

non-rationalized nature is a rebuke to equivalence, a reminder and

remainder of non-identity, music, with its obsessive rules, is not such

a reminder.

Research carried out at the University of Chicago demonstrated that

there are more than thirteen hundred discernible pitches available to

melodic consciousness, yet only a very small fraction of them are

allowed. Not even the eighty-eight tones of the piano really come into

play, considering the repetition of the octave structure — another

aspect of the absence of free or natural music.

Not reducible to words, at once intelligible and untranslatable, music

continues to refuse us complete access. Lévi-Strauss, introducing The

Raw and the Cooked, even went so far as to isolate it as “the supreme

mystery of the science of man (sic), a mystery that all the various

disciplines come up against and which holds the key to their progress.”

This essay locates the fundamentals rather more simply, namely in the

question of music’s perennial combination of free expression with social

regulation; more precisely in this case, with an historical treatment of

that which is our sense of music, Western tonality. Put in context, its

standardized grammar to a large extent answers the question of what it

is that music says. And the depth of its authority may be understood as

applicable to Nietzsche’s fear that “We shall never be rid of God so

long as we still believe in grammar.”

But before situating tonality historically, a few words are in order

toward defining this basic musical syntax, a cultural practice which has

been termed one of the greatest intellectual achievements of Western

civilization. First, it must be stressed that, contrary to the assertion

of major theorists of tonal harmonics from Rameau to Schenker, tonality

was not destined by the physical order of sounds. Tone, almost never

found fixed at the same pitch in nature, is divested of any natural

quality and shaped according to arbitrary laws; this standardization and

strict distancing are elementary to harmonic progress, and tend toward

an instrumental or mechanical expression and away from the human voice.

As a result of the selection made in the sound continuum by an

arbitrarily imposed scale, hierarchical relations are established among

the notes.

Since the Renaissance (and until Schoenberg), Western music has been

conceived on the basis of the diatonic scale, whose central element is

the tonic triad, or defined key, which subordinates the other notes to

it. Tonality actually means the state of having a pitch — the tonic, as

it is most simply called — that has authority over all the other tones;

the systematics of this leading-note quality has been the preoccupation

of our music. Schenker wrote of the tonic’s “desire to dominate its

fellow tones”: in his choice of words we can already begin to see a

connection between tonality and modern class society. The leading

theorist of tonal authority, he referred to it in 1906 as “a sort of

higher collective order, similar to a state, based on its own social

contracts by which the individual tones are bound to abide.”

There are many who still hold that the emergence of a tonal center in a

work is an inevitable product of natural harmonic function and cannot be

suppressed. Here we have an exact parallel to ideology, where the

hegemony of the frame of reference that is tonality is treated as merely

self-evident. The ideological miasma which helps make other social

constructs seem natural and objective also hides the ruling prejudices

that are embedded in the essence of tonality. It is, nonetheless, as

Arnold Schoenberg suggested, a ‘device’ to produce unity. In fact, tonal

music is full of illusion, such as that of false community, in which the

whole is portrayed as being made up of autonomous voices; this

impression transcends music to provide a legitimizing reflection of the

general division of labor in divided society.

Dynamically speaking, tonality creates a sense of tension and release,

of motion and repose, through the use of chordal dissonance and

consonance. Movement away from the tonic is experienced as tension,

returning as a homecoming, a resolution. All tonal music moves toward

resolution in the cadence or close, with the tonic chord ruling all

other harmonic combinations, drawing them to itself, and embodying

authority, stability, repose. Supramusically, a nostalgically painful

attitude of wandering and returning runs through the whole course of

bourgeois culture, and is ably expressed by the very movement basic to

tonality.

This periodic convergence toward a point of repose enabled increasingly

extended musical structures, and the areas of tonal expectation and

fulfillment came to be placed further apart. It is not surprising that

as the dominant society must strive for agreement, assent — harmony —

from its subjects through greater distances of alienation, tonality

develops more distant departures from the certainty and repose of the

tonic and thus lengthier delays in gratification. The forced march of

progress finds its correspondence in the rationalized

direction-compulsion of tonic-dominant harmony, complete with a

persistent patriarchal character.

Three centuries of tonality also tend to bury awareness of its

suppression of earlier rhythmic possibilities, its narrowing of the

great inner variety of the rhythm to a schematic alternation of

‘stressed’ and ‘unstressed’. The rise of tonality similarly coincided

with the coming to power of symmetrical thinking and the recapitulating

musical structure, the possibility of attaining a certain closure by

means of a certain uniformity. Chenneviére, in discussing tonality’s

newly simplified and intellectualized system of notation, discerned “a

most radical impoverishment of occidental music,” referring mainly to

the symmetrical balancing of clause against clause and the emphasis on

chordal repetition.

In the early nineteenth century, William Chappell published a collection

of “national English airs” (popular songs) in which academic harmonic

patterns were imposed on surviving folk melodies, older melodies

suppressed and “irregular tunes squared off.” The binarism of the basic

major key-minor key had come to prevail and, as Busoni concluded, “The

harmonic symbols have fenced in the expression of music.” The emergence

of tonality corresponded to that of nationalized and centralized

hierarchy which came to pervade economic, political and cultural life.

Ready-made structures of expressivity monopolize musical subjectivity

and patterns of desire. Clifford Geertz makes this pertinent judgment:

“One of the most significant facts about us may finally be that we all

begin with the natural equipment to live a thousand lives but end in the

end having lived only one.”

Tonality in music may be likened to realism in literature and

perspective in painting, but it is more deeply ingrained than either.

This facilitates a would-be transcendence of class distinctions and

social differences under the sign of a ‘universal’ key-centered music,

triumphant since tonality defined the realm of mass musical appreciation

and consumption. There is no spoken language on the planet which even

begins to compete with the accessibility tonality has provided as a

means of human expression.

Any historical study that omits music risks a diminished understanding

of society. Consider, for example, the ninth-century efforts of

Charlemagne to establish uniformity in liturgical music throughout his

empire for political reasons, or the tenth-century organ in Winchester

Cathedral with its four hundred pipes: the height of Western technology

to that time. It is at least arguable that music, in fact, provides a

better key’ than any other to the understanding of the changing spirit

of this civilization. To refocus on tonality, one can, using

conventional periodization, locate perhaps its earliest roots in the

transition between the Middle Ages and the Renaissance era.

If the eminent medievalist Bloch is correct in characterizing medieval

society as unequal rather than hierarchical, there is a definite cogency

to John Shepherd’s interpretation of the faint beginnings of the tonal

system as the encoding of a new hierarchical musical ideology out of a

more mutual one which idealized its own, earlier society. The medieval

outlook, based on its decentralized and localized character, was

relatively tolerant of varying world views and musical forms, and did

not consider them as basically destructive of its feudal ideological

foundation. The emerging modern world, however, was typified by greater

division of labor, abstraction, and an intolerant, totalizing character.

Uniform printing, and a print literacy corrosive of oral, face-to-face

traditions, explains some of the shift, as movable type provided a model

for the proto-industrial use of individuals as mechanically interacting

parts of a machine. Indeed the invention of printing at about 1500 gave

musical notation great scope, which made possible the role of composer,

by the separation of creator and performer and the downgrading of the

latter. Western culture thus soon produced the completely notated

musical work, facilitating a formal theory of composition at the expense

of an earlier predominance of improvisation along certain guidelines. In

this way print literacy and its dynamic uniformity led to a growing

harmonic explicitness.

Some musicologists have even located a recurrent urge to curb the

“recalcitrant independence” of the individual parts of polyphonic

multi-voiced music in the interests of harmony and order, dating back to

the late thirteenth century. Ars nova, the principal musical form of the

fourteenth century, illustrates some of the tendencies at work in this

long transitional period of pre-harmonic polyphony. Early on, and

especially in France, Ars nova reached a stunning degree of rhythmic

complexity that European music would not achieve again until

Stravinsky’s Rite of Spring five centuries later. But this very

complexity, increasingly based on an abstract conception of time, led to

an extraordinary refinement of notation, and hence pointed away from a

music based on the singing voice and away from melodic subtlety and

rhythmic flexibility. Formalization seems always to imply reduction, and

in turn a nascent feeling for tonic-dominant relationships was manifest

by the mid fifteenth century.

The considerable loss of a spontaneous rhythmic sense after the Middle

Ages is evidence of increased domestication, just as two basic

Renaissance characteristics, specialization of and within the orchestra

and the formation of a class of narrowly focused virtuosi, also bespoke

a greater division of labor at large. Similarly, new emphasis had been

placed on the spectator, and by the late 1500s, music involving no

spectacle other than that of men at work, not intended for provoking

movement or for singing but made only for being passively consumed,

first appeared.

Renaissance music remained for the most part and most importantly vocal,

but during this period instrumental music became independent and first

developed a number of autonomous forms known collectively as “absolute

music.” More and more secularized as well, European music under the

unquestioned leadership of the Netherlands between 1400 and 1600 took on

a mathematicized aspect quite compatible with the Dutch ascendancy

within the rise of early mercantile capitalism. The power of sound

achieved an intoxication born of the choral mass effects that are made

possible when the many, formerly independent voices of a composition

join into one body of harmony.

But a tonal harmonics present in some places was not yet a tonality

present throughout. The modal scales, sufficient from the early Middle

Ages to the latter part of the sixteenth century, expanded from eight to

twelve modes and then began to break down and yield to two less fluid

modes, major/minor scale binarism. “The restlessness and disenchantment

of the late Renaissance,” in Edward Lowinsky’s words, called forth the

coherence and unity of tonic-dominant structure as music’s contribution

to class society’s cultural hegemony. Our modern harmonic sense, the

conception of tone as the sum of many vertically grouped tones, is an

idealization of hierarchized social harmony.

Peter Clark’s The European Crisis of the 1590s quotes a Spanish writer

of 1592: “England without God, Germany in schism, Flanders in rebellion,

France with all these together.” As the century drew to a close,

surveyed Henry Karmen, “Probably never before in European history had so

many popular uprisings coincided in time.” Tonality was not yet

victorious but would, fairly soon, come to reign among the dominant

ideas of society, playing its part to channel and thereby pacify desire.

As polyphony faded, the modern key system began to emerge more

distinctly in a new form in the opening years of the 1600s; namely,

opera, first brought forth in Italy by Monteverdi. The conscious

rhetorical presentation of emotion, it was the first secular musical

structure in the West conceived on a scale sufficiently grand to rival

that of religious music. With opera and elsewhere, the early phases of

“the developing feeling for tonality,” according to H.C. Colles,

“already gave the new works an appearance of orderliness and stability

which marked the inauguration of a new era in art.”

The growing concern for a central tonality in the seventeenth century

thrived on Descartes. With his mathematized, mechanistic rationalism and

his specific attention to musical structure, Descartes advanced the new

tonal system in the same spirit as he consciously put his scientific

philosophy in the service of strong central government. To Adorno,

polyphonic music contained nonreified, autonomous elements which made it

perhaps best suited to express the ‘otherness’ Cartesian consciousness

was designed to eliminate.

The background to this development was a marked renewal of the social

strife of the very late 1500s. Hobsbawm found in the 1600s the crisis

par excellence; Parker and Smith (The General Crisis of the Seventeenth

Century) saw this “explosion of political instability” in Europe as

“directed overwhelmingly against the State, particularly during the

period 1625–1675.” The previous century had been largely the golden age

of counterpoint, reaching its apogee with Palestrina and Lassus, its

ideal a static social harmony to be imitated in music. The Baroque

aesthetic corresponded to the crises beginning in the 1590s, and

resuming in earnest with the general economic breakdown of 1620; it’s

nothing if not a rejection of classical calm and its polyphonic

refinements. The essence of Baroque is to move with the turbulence so as

to control it; hence it combines restless movement with formalism. Here

the concerto comes of age, linked by more than etymology to consent,

consensus. Derived from the Latin concertare, agreement reached with

dissonant elements, it reflected, as a well-harmonized ensemble, the

great demand of the system for authority equal to the social struggles.

Harmony is homophony not polyphony; polyphony and harmony are in

themselves irreconcilable. Instead of a form in which many voices are

combined so that each retains its own character, with harmony we really

hear only one tone. In the Baroque age of conflict homophony overtakes

and supplants polyphony, with obvious ideological ‘overtones’.

Independent sounds merge to form a united block, whose function is

background for the melody and also to register the tune in motion in its

place within the tonal system. At this time harmony first established

itself as essential to music, even changing the nature of melody in the

process. Rhythm too was affected by harmony; indeed the division of

music into bars was dictated by the new, ever-present harmonic rhythm.

Spengler judged that music overtook painting as the chief European art

at about 1670. It prevailed at the very time when tonality was

definitively realized; music was henceforth to be written in the idiom

of fully established tonality, without challenge, for about two and a

half centuries. The externalization of immediate subjective interests

according to tonality’s generalizing code corresponds, from this time as

weil, to the legal conception of the “reasonable man,” Dunwell informs

us, though one is tempted to rephrase it as “modern, domesticated,”

rather than “reasonable.”

There are other striking temporal coincidences. John Wolf’s The

Emergence of the Great Powers, 1685–1715, among other historical

studies, sets the moment of ascendant state power as paralleling that of

central tonality. And as Bukhofzer wrote, “Both tonality and gravitation

were discoveries of the baroque period made at exactly the same time.”

The significance of Newtonian physics is that universal gravitation

offered a model emphasizing immutable law and resistance to change; its

universally prevailing, ordered motions provided a unified cosmological

exemplar for political and economic order — as did tonality. In the new

harmonic system the principal tone, the one strongest and most dominant,

gravitates downward and through, and becomes the bass, the fundamental

tone of the chord; the laws of tonality can be read almost

interchangeably, incredible as it may sound, with those of gravitation.

Mid to late seventeenth century England exemplified more general social

trends in music. The critics North and Mace wrote of the decline of the

amateur viol player, and the tendency in composition wherein “Part

writing gave way to fireworks and pattern making,” to cite Peter

Warlock. Family chamber music decreased; the habit of passive listening

increased, against the breakup of village communalism with its songs and

dances. Victorious tonality was a very important part of a major social

and symbolic restructuring, and certainly not just in England.

Beginning in the Baroque era, the main vehicle of tonality was the

sonata (i.e. ‘played’ as opposed to the earlier, single movement canzona

or ‘sung’), which came to cover virtually any instrumental,

multimovement composition that proceeds according to a formal plan. The

sonata form was an organic outgrowth of harmonic tonality in that its

symmetrics were basically related to the internal symmetrical

organization of the grammar of tonality; its fundamental structure

requires that music which appears first as a move away from the tonic

toward a newly polarized key be reinterpreted finally with the original

tonic area in order to restore the balance. Even the challenging finales

of Mozart’s operas, Rosen reminds us, have the symmetrical tonal

structure of a sonata. By the end of the Baroque in the late eighteenth

century, symmetry withheld and then finally granted had become one of

music’s cardinal satisfactions.

With its conflict of two themes, its keynote, development and reprise,

the sonata form presupposes a capitalist dynamics; the

equilibrium-oriented and totally undramatic fugue, high water mark of an

earlier counterpoint, reflected a more static hierarchical society.

Fugal style was fulfilled just as tonality came to complete predominance

and its movement is largely one of sequence. A classical sonata, on the

other hand, is self-generating, moving forward as a revelation of its

initially unseen inner potential. The fugue goes on obeying its initial

law, like a calculation, as befits rationalist Enlightenment, whereas

sonata themes exhibit a dynamic condition announcing the qualitative

leap in domination of nature inaugurated by industrial capitalism.

In the early 17^(th) century Rubens’ studio became a factory; his output

of over 1200 paintings was unprecedented in the history of art. One

hundred fifty years later’ utilizing the preordained sonata form, Haydn

and Mozart could turn out 150 symphonies between them. Perhaps it is not

suggesting too much, or denying the genius of some creators, to see in

this mechanism a cultural prefiguring of mass production. A further

characteristic is that sonata music, unlike the complicated late fugal

style, had to be predictable, pleasing. Reminding one of tonality

itself, “The sonata cycle affirms the happy ending, lends itself to

reconciliation, to salvation from first and second movement strivings,

torments, inner doubts” before it concludes, in the words of Robert

Solomon.

The sonata-form principle also involves the idea of gradually increasing

activity, a cumulative dynamism that reaches out to exclude specificity,

to dominate via generalization. It is for this effect that it embodies

the crowning achievement of the emergence of generalizing forms in

bourgeois evolution and so well expresses the drive toward ‘universal’

values and world hegemony of European culture and capital.

In the eighteenth century the modern notion of music’s autonomy began to

form, with the claim (persisting today) to transcendental truth that

attaches to Bach and Mozart especially. The proud solemnity of Handel’s

oratorios speaks of the rise of imperialist England and a desire to

lezitimate that rise, but Bach in particular most effectively

articulated the social values of the emerging bourgeoisie as universal

rationality, objectivity, truth.

The precursors of Bach had made evident a structuration proper to

tonality, but it was he who brought that structuration to a precise

perfection, combining the drama and goal orientation of the late Baroque

with aspects of the earlier, soberer contrapuntal ideal. It is worth

noting that the older, more statically mathematized forms survive in the

eighteenth century, though they do not reign; this survival accounts for

those sequential developments which Constant Lambert disrespectfully

speaks of as the Bach “sewing machine,” just as Wagner referred to

Mozart as possessed of “sometimes an almost trivial regularity”

But if Bach represents the virtual apotheosis of harmonically based

tonality there were some doubts expressed regarding this whole thrust.

Rousseau for example, saw harmony as only another symptom of Europe’s

cultural decay indeed as the death of music. He based this extreme view

on harmony’s depreciation of melody its delimitation of the perception

of musical sounds to the internal structuring of its elements and hence

its truncation of the listener’s experience. Goethe too had misgivings

in terms of the artificiality and reification of fully developed

tonality, but they were less clearly stated than Rousseau´s.

By about 1800, tonal instrumental music reached the full command of its

powers, a point that painting had arrived at almost three hundred years

earlier. The greatest change in eighteenth century tonality in part

influenced by the establishment of equal temperament (the division of

the octave into twelve precisely equal semitones) was an even more

emphatic polarity between tonic and dominant and an enlargement of the

range over which the key modulation obtains. At the beginning of the

century the key relationship could already hold up over periods of eight

or more bars without being sounded again, whereas Mozart, Haydn and

Beethoven had, by the end of the century, extended the authority of

harmonic relations to five or even ten minutes.

The widening of the tonal orbit, however, meant a consequent weakening

in the gravitational pull of the tonic; with Beethoven, in the early

Romantic era, some undermining of structural tonality can already be

seen. What is new thematically in Beethoven is a climax of emotional

expression as well as a greater range of emotions expressed, plus the

centrality of the motif of the struggle for individual freedom,

precisely as the defeat of the Luddites in England presaged the

suppression of emotional expressivity and individual freedom in society

at large. Much unlike say, Bach, he began from the fact of alienation

and ultimately refused to reconcile in his music that which is

unreconciled in society; this can be seen most clearly in his last

quartets, which recall the incompleteness and anguish of the late music

of Mozart.

The Romantic art par excellence, music came to be thought of as a

uniquely privileged medium. Indeed, it was in the Beethovenian period,

or shortly thereafter, that the composer was ceded the status of

philosopher, contrasting sharply with the role of virtual servant that

Haydn and Mozart had occupied. Perhaps the so-called “redemptive force”

of music, to cross over to the social terrain, was nowhere more in

evidence than with a performance of Auber’s opera, La Muette de Portici,

which provoked the out break of revolution in Brussels in 1830. Later in

the century, Walter Pater’s assessment that “All art constantly aspires

towards the condition of music” bespoke not only music as the

culmination of the arts but reflected its forcefulness at the height of

tonality. It is also in this latter sense, as appreciation of tonality,

that Schopenhauer celebrated music in a way unrivaled in philosophical

writing, as more powerful than words and the direct expression of inner

consciousness. Adorno spoke of the “bursting longing of Romanticism” and

Marothy discussed its frequented themes of loneliness and nostalgia, the

effort to capture the sense of something that is irretrievably lost.

Along these lines, the drama of rescue was not only the literary fashion

of the day but is often found in music, such as Beethoven’s Fidelio.

Schubert could ask whether there was such a thing as joyous music, as if

in response to an industrializing Europe, and was answered by the

elegiac, resigned Brahms and the pessimist Mahler in the later Romantic

era.

Harmony was the special realm of the period; orchestral groupings

favored the massed and unified deployment of each instrumental family to

stretch and intensify the central concern with pitch relationships to

convey meaning, over the other aspects of music. It was the age of great

orchestral forces designed to exploit the compulsive powers of tone,

proceeding via the coordination of diverse specialist function. In this

manner, and with an increasingly systematic conception of musical

structure, Romantic music paralleled the perfection of industrial

method. As the nineteenth century progressed, a growing number of

composers felt that musical language was becoming trapped under the

syntactical and formal constraints of tonality, an overly standardized

harmonic vocabulary bound to empty symmetrical regularities. Flattening

out under the weight of its own habits, music seemed to be losing its

former expressive power.

Like capital, then at the height of its initial expansiveness, the

modern orchestra pursued the illusion of indefinite growth. But Romantic

overstatement and giganticism (i.e. Mahler’s Symphony of a Thousand)

were used, more often than not, to create a limited range of homogenized

sounds, a uniformity of timbre.

To speak of expansion calls to mind Wagner’s attempt at a simple,

economical repertoire opera — the resultant work was the five-hour,

gorgeous agony of Tristan and Isolde. Or Wagner’s Ring series, based on

the Nibelungen myth, that epic of perpetual lust and death by which he

desired to outdo all conceivable spectacles, and which most likely

prompted Nietzsche to judge, “There is a deep significance in the fact

that the rise of Wagner coincides with the rise of empire.” An operatic

portrait of Kaiser Wilhelm I beside a swan and wearing a Lohengrin

helmet suggests the debt owed him for celebrating and reconsecrating the

social order of the second German Reich. If Tristan was the prelude to

the political development of Bismarckian Germany, the latter found its

authoritarian and mystical justification in Parsifal’s pseudo-erotic

religiosity.

Wagner intended a merger of all the arts into a higher form of opera and

in this project it seemed to him that he had superseded dogmatic

religion. Such an aim projected the complete domination of the spectator

by mean’s of the grandeur and pomposity of his musical productions,

their perfumed sultriness and bombardment of the senses. His boast was

no less than that, owing to his neopagan, neonationalist achievement,

“Church and state will be abolished,” having outlived their usefulness.

Thus his aims for art were more grandiose than those of industrial

capitalism itself and spoke its language of power.

And yet Wagner also, and more importantly, represents the full decay of

the classic harmonic system. Despite all the bombast and striving for a

maximum of authority, his is the music of doubt. His music remained

faithful to at least a latent foundation of tonality but, especially

with Tristan, the enduring validity of tonal harmony was already

disproved. Wagner had extended it to its ultimate limits and exhausted

its last resources.

Part of Mahler’s Song of the Earth is marked “without expression.” It

seems that romanticism after Wagner was turning to ashes, though at the

same time something new was being foreshadowed. Harmony continued to

show signs of collapse from within and increasing liberties were taken

with the previously unlimited sovereignty of the major/minor tonal

system (e.g. Debussy). Meanwhile, as capital required more “Third World”

resources for its stability, music too turned imperialist in the sense

of much needed folk transfusions (e.g. Bartok).

In 1908 Arnold Schoenberg’s Second Quartet in F Sharp Minor attained the

decisive break with harmonic development: it was the first atonal

composition. Fittingly, the movement in question is begun by the soprano

with the words: “Ich fühle Luft von anderen Planeten” (“I feel air from

other planets”).

Adorno saw the radical openness of atonal music as an “expression of

unmitigated suffering, bound by no convention whatsoever” and as such

“often hostile to culture” and “containing elements of barbarism.” The

rejection of tonality indeed enabled expression of the most intense

subjectivity, the loneliness of the subject under technological

domination. Nonetheless, the equivalences by which human emotion is

universalized and objectified are still present, if released from the

centralized control of the “laws of harmony”. Schoenberg’s “emancipation

of the dissonance” allowed for the presentation of human passions with

unprecedented immediacy via dissonant harmonies that have little or no

tendency to resolve. The avoidance of tonal suggestion and resolution

provides the listener with precious little support or security:

Schoenberg’s atonal work often seems almost hysterically emotional due

to the absence of points of real repose. “It is driven frantically

toward the unattainable,” noted Leonard Meyer.

In this sense, atonality proved to be the most extreme manifestation of

the general anti-authoritarian upheaval in society of the five or so

years preceding World War I Schoenberg’s abandonment of tonality

coincides with the abandonment of perspective in painting by Picasso and

Kandinsky (in 1908). But with these “two great negative gestures” in

culture, as they have been termed, it was the composer who found himself

propelled into a public void. In his steadfast affirmation of

alienation, his unwillingness to present any scene of human realization

that was not feral, difficult, wild, Schoenberg’s atonality was too much

of a threat and challenge to find much acceptance. The expressionist

painter August Macke wrote to his colleague Franz Marc following an

evening of Schoenberg’s chamber music in 1911: “Can you imagine music in

which tonality has been completely abandoned? I was reminded constantly

of Kandinsky’s large compositions which are written, as it were, in no

single key...this music which lets every tone stand by itself.”

Unfortunately, their feeling for such a radically libertarian approach

was not shared by many, not exposed to many.

As Macke’s letter implies, before the atonal breakout, music had

achieved meaning through the defined relations of chords to a tonal

center. Schoenberg’s Theory of Harmony summed up the old system well:

“It has always been the referring of all results to a center, to an

emanating point... Tonality does not serve: on the contrary it demands

to be served.”

Some defenders of tonality, on the other hand, have adopted a frankly

socially authoritarian point of view, feeling that more than just

changes in music were at stake. Levarie and Levy’s Musical Morphology

(1983), for example, proceeded from the philosophical thesis that “Chaos

is nonbeing” to the political stance that “The revolt against

tonality... is an egalitarian revolution.” They further pronounced

atonality to be “a general contemporary phenomenon,” noting with

displeasure how “Obsessive fear of tonality reveals a deep aversion to

the concept of hierarchy and rank.” This stance is reminiscent of

Hindemith’s conclusion that it is impossible to deny the validity of

hierarchical tone relationships and that there is therefore “no such

thing as atonal music.” Such comments obviously seek to defend more than

the dominant musical form: they would preserve authority,

standardization, hierarchy and whatever cultural grammar guarantees a

world defined by such values.

Schoenberg’s atonal experiment suffered as part of the defeat that World

War I and its aftermath meted out for social dissonance. By the early

1920s he had given up the systemless radicalism of atonality. not a

single ‘free’ note survived. In the absence of a tonal center he

inserted the totally rule-governed 32-tone set, which, as Adorno judged,

“virtually extinguishes the subject.” Dodecaphony, or serialism as it is

also called, constituted a new compliance in the place of tonality,

corresponding to a new phase of increasingly systematized industrialism

introduced with World War I. Schoenberg forged new laws to control what

was liberated by the destruction of the old tonal rules of resolution,

new laws that guarantee a more complete circulation among all twelve

pitches and may be said to speak to capital’s growing need for improved

recirculation. Serial technique is a kind of total integration in which

movement is strictly controlled, as in a bureaucratically enforced mode.

Its conceptual drawback for the dominant order is that while greater

circulation is achieved via its new standardized demands (none of the

tones is to be repeated before the other eleven have been heard), the

concentrated control actually allows for very little production. This is

seen most clearly in the extreme understatement and brevity in much of

the work of Webern, Schoenberg’s most successful disciple; at times

there are as many pauses as notes, while the second of Webern’s early

Three Pieces for Cello and Piano, for example, lasts only thirteen

seconds.

The old harmonic system and its major/minor key points of reference

provided easily understood places of departure and destination.

Serialism accords equal use to each note, making any chord feasible:

this conveys a somewhat homeless, fragmentary sense, suitable to an age

of more diffuse, traditionless domination.

As of World War 1, art music in general began to fragment. Stravinsky

led the neoclassicist tendency, which reaffirmed a tonal center despite

the prevailing winds of change. Grounded firmly in the 18^(th) century,

it seemed to increasing numbers of composers, especially after World War

1l, to be no solution to music’s theoretical problems. Serialist figure

Pierre Boulez termed its rather flagrantly anachronistic character and

refusal of development a ‘mockery’. Neoclassical music seemed to share

at least something with the new serialist movement, however, an often

stark, austere character, in line with the general trend toward

contraction and pessimism. Benjamin Britten seemed preoccupied with the

problem of suffering, while many of Aaron Copland’s works evoke the

loneliness of industrial cities, whose very energy is bereft of real

vitality. Another major traditionalist, Vaughan Williams, ended his

masterful Sixth Symphony with what can only be described as an objective

statement of utter nihilism.

Meanwhile, by the 1950s, serialism came to be regarded as

overdetermined, its discipline too severe, so much so that it occasioned

‘chance’ music (also called aleatory music or indeterminacy). Closely

identified popularly with John Cage, chance seemed another part of the

larger swing away from the subject — which electronic or

computer-generated composition would take even further — whereby the

human voice disappears and even the performer is often eliminated.

Paradoxically, the aesthetic effects produced by random methods are the

same as those realized by totally ordered music. The minimalism of

Reich, Glass and others seems a mass-marketed neoconservatism in its

pleasant, repetitious poverty of ideas. Iannis Xenakis, imitating the

brutalism of his teacher Le Corbusier, may be said to stand for the

height of the cybernetizing, computer-worshipping approach: he has

sought an “alloy of music and technology” based on his research into

“logico-mathematical invariants.”

Art music is today bewildered by a scattering influence, the absence of

any unifying, common-practice language. And yet the main thrust of all

of it — if one can use the word thrust in such an enervated context — is

a cold expressionlessness wholly befitting the enormous increase in

alienation, objectification and reification of worldwide late

capitalism. A divided society must finally make do with a divided art:

the landscape does not ‘harmonize’. It is an era that perhaps cannot

even be given a musical ending any more; it has certainly become both

too unruly and too bleak to be composed and brought to any tonal,

cadenced close. When art and even symbolization itself seem false to

many, the question occurs, where do the forces lie by which music can be

kept alive, where is the enchantment?

“All art is mortal, not merely the individual artifacts but the arts

themselves,” wrote Spengler. Art — with music in the forefront — may, as

Hegel speculated it would, be already well within the age of its demise.

Samuel Lipman’s Music after Modernism (1979) pronounced music’s terminal

illness, its status as “living on the capital of the explosion of

creativity which lasted from before Bach to World War I.” The failure of

tonality’s ‘creativity’ is of course part of an overall entropy in which

capital, in Lipman’s accidental accuracy of words, turns toxic and

unmistakably self-destructive. Adorno saw that “There are fewer and

fewer works from the past that continue to be any good. It is as if the

entire supply of culture is dwindling.” Some would merely hold on to the

museum pieces of tonality at all costs and deplore the lack of their

resupply. This is the meaning of virtually all the standard laments on

the subject, such as Constant Lambert’s Music Ho! A Study of Music in

Decline (1934) or The Agony of Modern Music (1955) in which Henry

Pleasants told us that “The vein which for three hundred years offered a

seemingly inexhaustible yield of beautiful music has run out,” or Roland

Stromberg in After Everything (1975): “It is hard ...not to think that

serious music has reached the state of total decay.” But the same death

verdict also comes from non-antiquarians: a 1983 lecture by noted

serialist composer Milton Babbitt was called “The Unlikely Survival of

Serious Music.” Earlier, Babbitt, in the face of the unpopularity of

contemporary art music posed, defiantly and unrealistically, the

“complete elimination of the public and social aspects of musical

composition” and penned an article entitled “Who Cares If You Listen?”

The lack of a public for ‘difficult’ music is obvious and noteworthy. If

Bloch was correct to judge “All we hear is ourselves,” it may also be

correct to conclude that the listener does not want that element in

music that is a confrontation with our age. Adorno referred to

Schoenberg’s music as the reflection of a broken and empty world,

evoking a reply from Milan Rankovic that “Such a reflection cannot be

loved because it reproduces the same emptiness in the spirit of the

listener.” A further question, relating to the limits of art itself, is

whether estrangement in music could ever prove effective in the struggle

against the estrangement of society.

Modern music, however splintered and removed from the old tonal

paradigm, has obviously not effaced the popularity of the Baroque,

Classical and Romantic masters. And in the area of music education

tonality continues to prevail at all levels; undergraduates in

composition classes are instructed that the dominant ‘demands’

resolution, that it “must resolve” to the tonic, etc., and the students’

musical sense itself is appraised in terms of the once-unchallenged

harmonic categories and rules. Tonality, as should be clear by now, is

an ideology in purely musical terms, and one that perseveres.

One wonders, in fact, why art music, where traditions are revered,

should have made the break that it has, while all of pop music (and

almost all jazz, which inherited its harmonic system from classic

European tonality), where traditions are often despised, has held back.

There is no form of popular music in the industrial world that exists

outside the province of mass tonal consciousness. As Richard Norton said

so well: “It is the tonality of the church, school, office, parade,

convention, cafeteria, workplace, airport, airplane, automobile, truck,

tractor, lounge, lobby, bar, gym, brothel, bank, and elevator. Afraid of

being without it on foot, humans are presently strapping it to their

bodies in order to walk to it, run to it, work to it, and relax to it.

It is everywhere. It is music and it writes the songs.”

It is also as totally integrated into commercialized mass production as

any product of the assembly line. The music never changes from the

seemingly eternal formula, despite superficial variations; the ‘good’

song, the harmonically marketable song, is one that contains fewer

different chords than a 14^(th) century ballad. Its expressive potential

exists solely within the limited confines of consumer choice, wherein,

according to Horkheimer and Adorno, “Something is provided for everyone

so that none shall escape.” As a one-dimensional code of consumer

society, it is a training course in passivity.

Music, reduced to background noise which no longer takes itself

seriously, is at the same time a central, omnipresent element of

environment, more so than ever before. The immersion in tonality is at

once distraction and pervasive control, as the silence of isolation and

boredom must be filled in. It comforts us, denying that the world is as

reified as it is, reduced to making believe that — as Beckett put it in

Endgame — anything is happening, that anything changes. Pop music also

provides a pleasure of identification, the immediate experience of

collective identity that only massified culture, unconscious of the

authoritarian ideology which is tonality, can provide.

Rock music was a ‘revolution’ compared with earlier pop music only in

the sense of lyrics and tempo (and volume) — no tonal revolution had

even been dimly conceived. Studies have shown that all types of (tonal)

music calm the unruly. consider how punk has standardized and clichéd

the musical sneer. It is not only the music of overt pacification, like

New Age composition, which denies the negative as dangerous and evil in

the same way that Socialist Realism did, and likewise aids and abets the

daily oppression. Just as surely it will take more than rockers smashing

their guitars on stage, even though the limits of tonality may be behind

such acts, to signal a new age.

Like language, tonality is historically characterized by its unfreedom.

We are made tonal by society: only in the elimination of that society

will occur the superseding of all grammars of domination.