đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș alex-comfort-art-and-social-responsibility.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:35:06. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Art and Social Responsibility Author: Alex Comfort Date: 1946 (reprinted 1994) Language: en Topics: art, poetry, music, anarchist analysis Source: Selection 6, pp. 52â78 in *Writings Against Power and Death: The Anarchist Articles and Pamphlets of Alex Comfort*, Edited with an Introduction by David Goodway. Freedom Press, London 1994. ISBN 0 900384 71 9
âHe [Josef Kramer] wasnât a bad chap really... He simply couldnât see
what he had done wrong in obeying orders...â
âPRESS REPORT
âLe regne de la poesie est peut-ĂȘtre plus proche que je nâose le penser.
Que restera-t-il aux vivants de demain? Leurs yeux pour pleurer, des
mauvaises herbes et des fleurs des champs, une terre ravagée, des
cabanes aufond des bois, un carré de ciel, et des sentiments violents.
Pour un poete, les conditions necessaires et suffisantes.â
âRAYMOND DUMAY
Partisan Review, published in New York, advertised this year a number to
be devoted to exposing the âNew Failure of Nerveâ in Western
liberalism.[1] The advertisement catalogued a series of the tendencies
which the editors regarded as retrograde, obscurantist, reactionary.
They included the abandonment of the historical for the metaphysical
approach to politics and ethics, a return to the idea of Original Sin,
and the appearance once again of the semi-deterministic conception of
sociology. It struck me that so many of these concepts were, in fact,
the principles of thought and art which are tending more and more to
guide the artists who have begin to appear publicly since the war broke
out; belonging to that generation, I am perfectly aware of the influence
of such ideas on myself. I have examined them fairly often, and whether
out of personal prejudice or out of conviction I must refuse to admit
that they are in essence obscurantist principles. We have just passed
through a period of classicism in English poetry which has no parallel
in American work, and we have seen a few of its limitations. History has
driven us from classicism to romanticism, and the migration has been
almost universal among sensitive writers.
I do not believe that the conflict between human beings and society is
the product of the Industrial Revolution, socialism, fascism, or any
other contemporary causeâit is as old as the hills, and the common man
knows it well enough. He has not been bludgeoned into the armies of
eight or nine millennia for nothing. The reason that the existence of
such a conflict requires mention in this essay is that for the first
time in a good many years the creative artist, who has previously, by
reason of his occupation, contrived to dodge the issue and claim special
privileges, is finding himself involved. The end of regionalism
liberated him from it; the collapse of urban centralisation confronts
him with it again. Just as friars contrived to escape being impressed to
fight at Crecy, artists have contrived, and still are contriving, if
they are prepared to sell their humanity, to avoid the issue of
accepting society or rejecting it. To the peasants of Alsace or China
none of this would need sayingâthey know armies and causes for what they
areâbut to a great many writers, those of Partisan Review included,
brought up in an essentially urban culture, who have no such timeless,
hereditary awareness of disobedience, it badly needs saying. In England,
at any rate, the realisation of the active irresponsibility of society
has come as such a thunderbolt to writers reared in an atmosphere of
socialism (as we were) that they have had no time to make up their
minds. Caught on the wrong foot, they have postponed the decision,
either by preparing âto defend the bad against the worseâ, or, far less
creditably, by using their status as artists to detach themselves from
general conscription, which is somewhat comparable with the action of
the doctor who claims priority air transport away from a cholera
epidemic, because he is an important asset to society.
These terms, classic and romantic, stand for more than differences of
style. The classic sees man as master, the romantic sees him as victim
of his environment. That seems to me to be the real difference. I regard
the periods of English literature as an alternation between these two
concepts. It is as if the awareness of death, the factor which, at root,
determines the degree to which we feel masters of our circumstances,
ebbed and flowed, alternately emphasised and obscured as a factor in
interpretative art. The classical periods are periods of economic and
mental security, when the drive is towards action and where the majority
of the people is in possession of a satisfactory interpretation of the
universe and of themselves, religious or political (it can be either).
They are periods during which the burdens of realising and interpreting
the most ghastly of all conflicts, between the manâs and the artistâs
desperate desire for permanence, and factual death which he discovers,
fall upon individual shoulders. These artists, standing in a period of
general complacency, are the major poetsâfrequently psychopathic, since
their insecurity is endogenous. The Victorian period was one such, and
it produced its Arnolds and Mark Rutherfords who agonised as much
quantitatively if not qualitatively within the structure of the times as
did Rilke or Thompson, or Unamuno and Lorca in contemporary Europe.
The active periods with their extroverted public alternate with ages
when the realisation of the Tragic Sense becomes general, spreads over
continents, reaches men who are conscious only of being afraid. There
are no major poets, because what they have to say, everybody already
knows. The times need not revealers but concealers, a hierarchy of men
who will hide the truth of death from humanity, or life becomes empty. I
am convinced that a large part of cultural barbarism arises from this
source. Perhaps this is the true failure of nerve. Major poetry is the
vicarious function of the single artistâhe takes the weight of tragic
awareness to shield the rest of humanity from it. I rather doubt if ever
in history there have been so many who realised the emotional fact of
death. Megalopolitan civilisation is living under a death sentence. That
has become a personal realisation over great areas of the world. We are
at the turn of a major period of classicism (Victorian) which produced
major romantic poets, and finally classical poets using the husk of
romantic technique. Slack water was at about 1900, and suddenly the face
of social disintegration and personal death began to be seen by more and
more people. The private knowledge of the Dostoievskys and Unamunos of
the past was becoming general. A numb silence fell on everyone, except
Monro and his Georgians, who could not understand what was happening and
shouted to fill the gap. There were few attempts to reinstate a
classical, secure approach. The Imagists wrote, with increasing tragic
awareness. The socialist poets attempted to deny the awareness and to
turn to society, but in Spain the face of the unpleasant black figure
was unveiled. The poets went out to fight, taking Marx with them, and
came back with Unamuno and Lorca. It was then that the
dialectical-historical approach became hollow. In some strange fashion
the same knowledge, unconditioned by history, was growing up in
innumerable childhoodsâDylan Thomas knew it early in life, long before
the Spanish defeat. Art does not move always by sudden
transitionâSteinerâs concept of the Zeitgeist is truer than it looks.
The transition is a matter of relative numbers who reach a viewpoint
together, independently. Artists reflect it now only because it is the
general temper of the public.
The awareness of death, the quasi-priestly but secular attitude, are
omnipresent for anyone who knows contemporary English art and letters.
No artist of my generation is uninfluenced by them. I should make it
clear that I do not wish to argue for them, only to state that they are
here. The new climate is a thing into which we grew up. The ideas that
lie behind it are the obscurantist ideas of the Editor of Partisan
Review, and analysis of what has been written suggests that they are
these.
universe and the psychological and so-called âspiritualâ aspirations of
manâthat no human activity can be said to have âpermanentâ or âabsoluteâ
significance, and that ethics and aesthetics exist because we make them
and assert them, not in conformity with Platonic absolutes but in the
teeth of material reality. That the common enemy of man is Death, that
the common tie of man is ultimate victimhood, and that anyone who, in
attempting to escape the realisation of that victimhood in himself,
increases its incidence upon others, is a traitor to humanity and an
ally of death.
regarded as a steady progress in any direction, whether moral or
political, e.g. towards civilisation, goodness, socialism, but as an
oscillation about a fixed point, a series of self-limiting ecological
changes, an ebb and flow between certain fixed limits which have not
within human record been exceeded. We see it as a fluctuating conflict
between biological freedom and power. One cannot suggest on the recorded
evidence that man is either âmorally betterâ (however that be defined)
or politically more capable of forming a society which does not involve
the abuse of power. His achievement fluctuates sufficiently for one to
be able to say that democracy is âbetterââi.e. more humane or less
exactingâthan fascism, or that the Greece of 450 BC was preferable to
the Rome of AD 50, but the statement that absolute qualitative charge
has taken place between 500 BC and AD 1943 is without meaning for us.
Such comparisons are in themselves historically meaningless. We do not
believe that irresponsible society is any less of an evil than
irresponsible society then, or society when Godwin saw it. Every society
based upon power is, to us, vitiated by the fact, whoever the rulers may
be, and where free communities have come into existence their freedom
has to be constantly asserted, or they degenerate slowly or rapidly into
the adoption of power. In other words, the recurrent tendency of society
is to degenerate into barbarism. We accept this hypothesis for the same
reason that we call the tendency to live between fifty and eighty years
a human propertyâevidence tends to suggest that in a majority of cases
it is factually true. One does not detect the tendency so freely in
individuals as the Adlerians would lead us to believeâit is not a
question of individual lust-for-power, but a different property,
belonging to masses, and able to vitiate the most enlightened decisions.
It seems that in any society, acting as a society, once responsibility
and mutual aid are submerged, the constructive impulses tend to cancel
out, and the negative and destructive summate. This is as true of the
Communist Party as it is of feudal Poland or the Roman Empire. It is as
though we were to have a boat full of blindfold rowers. They pull in
different directions and no progress is made, but the weights of the
crew add up and she sinks. There is a good deal of argument possible
whether education can in any degree remedy this tendency. One can call
it original sin if one wishes. I do not care what name I give itâfor me
as an artist it is real, the most real feature of society in all ages.
It is possible that, in reality, it is a feature of the collapse-phase
onlyâcertainly its recognition isâyet all ages speak of deterioration as
a journey down hill. Social conduct is described as harder than its
opposite. It is no new idea. But the state of irresponsibility once
reached, the viciousness of an organisation tends to be proportional to
its size. Democracy in a barbarian state is a priori impossible, because
it involves the refusal to admit that the majority is never right.
Fascism is the attempt to summate the destructive influences and to use
them as a basis for a society. It teaches that the individual is unreal,
and therefore death, the termination of the individual, is unreal also.
If this does not explain the genuine satisfaction which all
authoritarian societies give to their adherents, then I have
misunderstood society. But I have no use for a Swedenborgian Hell by
common consent. One cannot propel the boat by the weight of its rowers.â
Romanticism is our ideology. It is based upon a metaphysical theory. The
most serious difficulty in the discussion of romanticism and its place
in sociological and literary criticism is the progressive loss of
meaning which critical illiteracy has inflicted on the name itself.
Romanticism is not a stylistic term, and the criterion of its
application is not how the subject writes, but what he
believesâotherwise we might find it difficult to explain the clarity and
definition with which we can speak of romantic painting, romantic
poetry, romantic sculpture and romantic music, with equal readiness and
an exact correspondence in the quality described. It has become
fashionable to deride any attempt to relate artistic criticism to
cosmological theory, except among those who confuse mystical speculation
with metaphysics. To attempt such a relation is one of the stigmata
which characterises âloss of nerveâ in the eyes of the neo-classicists.
But without coherent metaphysics art is no more a comprehensible
activity than travel without a sense of direction. The nature of reality
is the first concern not only of poetry but of intelligent biology or
political ethics, and the only claim of romanticism to the status of an
ideology, and a historically valid ideology, lies in the coherence of
its metaphysics, and its root in observed fact.
The romantic believes that the particular qualities which make up
humannessâmind, purpose, consciousness, will, personalityâare unique in
known phylogeny, and are so far at variance with the physical conditions
in which man exists that they are irrelevant to the general structure of
physical reality. Christian and pagan metaphysicians of opposing
ideologies (including the Marxists, who believe in historical
inevitability) have contended either that Man was made in Godâs image,
in which case ethical obligation corresponded with the nature of a
Creator, or that the Universe was made in Manâs image, and that some of
the values to which human individuals tend to aspire (beauty, goodness
or order) were incorporated in the physical universe itself. The
distinguishing feature of the metaphysical theory which underlies
romanticism is that it rejects the ideals themselves. They exist only so
long as Man himself exists and fights for them. The entire romantic
ethic and body of art rests upon this assumption of insecurity, an
insecurity which begins at the personal level of mortality, and extends
into all the intellectual fields where insecurity is least tolerable. It
is comical that such a view should be characterised as wish-fulfilment.
The romantic has only two basic certaintiesâthe certainty of irresoluble
conflict which cannot be won but must be continued, and the certainty
that there exists between all human beings who are involved in this
conflict an indefeasible responsibility to one another. The romantic has
two enemies, Death, and the obedient who, by conformity to power and
irresponsibility, ally themselves with Death. There is no hint of
mysticism in thisâromanticism is the ideology of a whole human being
looking at the whole universe.
Romanticism, the belief in the human conflict against the Universe and
against power, seems to me to be the driving force in all art and
science which deserves the name. In Western civilisation today there are
only two recognisable elements which can be said to differentiate it
from total barbarism, our art and our medical science, and both are
based upon this romantic ideology. The ethical content of romanticism
has always been the same. The romantic bases his ethic upon his belief
in the hostility or the neutrality of the Universe. He does not deny the
existence of absolute standards, but he denies their existence apart
from Man. The conceptions of artistic beauty or moral goodness did not
exist before the emergence of consciousness, and they will return to
oblivion with its extinction, but they are none the less good for their
impermanence. And because of this one-sided battle which the romantic
believes himself to be fighting, he recognises an absolute and
imperative responsibility to his fellow men as individualsâboth because
he, unlike the Christian, is defending standards in which he believes
but which are not by nature assured of triumph, which he feels will only
exist so long as they are defended, and because his pessimistic
interpretation of philosophy makes him feel towards his fellow men much
as you might feel towards fellow survivors on a raft.
It is from this metaphysical idea of conflict, of principles which are
maintained only by struggle, that romanticism draws the tremendous force
of its social and philosophical criticism, and the equally tremendous
emotional and intellectual appeal of its artistic statements. It is a
force which alone among artistic forces seems to preserve perpetual
virility and perpetual youth. Compare the Enthronement of Our Lady,
which Ruskin called the most outstanding work of art in the world, with
the works of Brueghel and see which seems to you to be the more trueâthe
order and peace of the first, or the tumult of the second. The ideal of
beauty and order is the same in each case, but for the Italian master
the battle is already won, God is on His throne. For Brueghel, in the
world, in society, in his own body, the battle continued as bloody and
as fierce as ever.
The romantic recognises a perpetual struggle upon two levels, the fight
against Death which I have described, and the struggle against those men
and institutions who ally themselves with Death against humanity, the
struggle against barbarism. These are the two subjects of the Brueghel
paintings, The Triumph of Death and The Massacre of the Holy Innocents.
In the first, a gigantic host of skeletons is riding down mankind. In
the second, the Duke of Alvaâs soldiery are butchering Flemish peasants
and their children. I regard these paintings as the highest level which
the expression of the romantic ideology has ever reachedâand Brueghel is
not in any lecture catalogue of romantic painters. These are the enemies
of humanity, and of the standards of beauty and of truth which exist
only for and in humanityâDeath and Deathâs ally, irresponsibility. The
relevance of romanticism today lies in the fact that of all ideologies
it alone declares this basic antagonism and moulds its course
accordingly.
I suppose that I would summarise the social conclusions of contemporary
romantics in some such form as this:
possesses a conscious sense of personality which, as far as one can
reasonably guess, is not shared by other organisms, and which renders
the emotional realisation of death intolerable and incompatible with
continued enjoyment of existence. He therefore attempts universally to
deny either that death is real or that his personality is really
personal.[2]
negation of death) is apparently sealed by scientific research. I say
apparently, because the important factor from the viewpoint of social
psychology is not the actual evidence but the acceptance of death as
real and final by a high proportion of the populations which have so far
evaded the realisation.[3] This acceptance, coming upon people whose
humanity has been undermined by social organisation, is a root cause of
the flight into barbarism.
negation of individual personality and responsibility, since to admit
that I am an individual I must also admit that I shall cease to exist.
The negation takes the form of a growing belief in the conception of an
immortal, invisible and only wise society, which can exact
responsibilities and demand allegiances. The concept is as old as human
thought, but its acceptance is becoming more and more a refuge from the
reality of self. Society is not only a form of abrogating moral
responsibility, it is a womb into which one can crawl back and become
immortal because unborn.
they submerge constructive impulses and summate destructive ones, so
that the product of any group[4] action is by tendency destructive and
irrational. The courses of action which the group mode of thought
imposes upon the individual members are so grotesque and so wildly at
variance with reason and with normal constructive activity that by
reference to individual standards of human responsibility they are
clinically insane. The consciousness of personal responsibility is the
factor which differentiates human relationships from superficially
similar animal societies: and contemporary irresponsibility has thrown
it overboard.
The barbarian revolution occurs without external change at the point
where mutual aid becomes detached from political organisation, civic
delegation passes out of the control of the delegators, at the
transition between a community of responsible individuals and a society
of irresponsible citizens. At a definite point in the history of every
civilisation, and shortly before its economic peak, there occurs a
transfer of civic obligation, from the community based on mutual aid to
the society based upon common irresponsibility. It may manifest itself
as an industrial revolution, a megalopolitan development of the city, or
as a change in national attitude from community to communal aggression.
Every society has its Melian Dialogues, and thereafter the barbarian
revolution has taken place, and the actions of that society are
irresponsible, and its members insane.
The most terrible feature of this insanity is that it can be recognised
in ourselves, in our friends. The man whom one knowsâa good fellow, able
to live as an individual a life which is free from any conscious
assaults on the rights of others, who does not make a practice of
beating his own head or the heads of others against the walls, who is
sane, with whom one eats or drinks... this same man can very well return
one evening to talk or drink with you again and catalogue the most
grotesque and contemptible actions which he has performed, or which he
supports, with full approval and a fixed delusional sense of their
rightness, solely because he is now acting as a member of some organised
and irresponsible group. He will pay any price to rid himself of the
selfhood which, subconsciously, he knows must die. It is this frantic
prostration before society/this masochistic attitude which permits
aggregate lunacy to torture him, kill him, or drive him to actions of
unspeakable idiocy, which explains the obedience of so many populations
to rogues and brutes who pull the strings and make Leviathan walk. Yet
this fellow you eat and drink with is still a good fellow. If all those
who supported tyranny, butchered each other, and generally raised hell
and high-water, were personal blackguards, film Nazis, one could be
happy. But I sat smoking last week with a great personal friend of mine
who has just helped to exterminate, under orders, the population of a
city where he has a good many acquaintances. He is filled with a sense
of the rightness of his action, and he was willing to perform it at
great personal risk. By participating in a human society, he had bought
the abrogation of the fear of death at the price of his personality. He
is not a fool nor a sadistâhe is your friend or your son. His contact
with society has made him perform an action which, a year ago, or if it
had been performed yesterday by a society of which he was not a member,
he would have called bestial and contemptible. He looks back on it with
pride, because he has accepted it as an action on behalf of humanity.
Jailers, firing squads, thugsâthe horror of it is that in many cases
they owe the criminality of their acts not to themselves but to the fact
that they are members of a society and possess no insight into its
corporate actions. To call them insane, over the range of those actions,
is not a figure of speech but a clinical fact. If insanity is a divorce
between reality and perception which, by depriving a man of insight,
renders him a peril to himself and others, then these menâmy friend, all
of themâare insane, over the whole section of their activity which is
involved with the madhouse group. What else does the tag concerning
Salus Populi mean, save the society abrogates rational conduct? What
else is the contemporary phrase Military Necessity but a prelude to some
grotesque piece of bestiality which we are being asked to accept? We are
living in a madhouse whenever society is allowed to become personalised
and regarded as a super-individual. We are living in a madhouse now.
What will the artist, as an individual, have to say for himself when he
looks at the results of this process in the present time? He will lay
down, and I believe he is laying down, a set of cynical but reliable
guides to conduct.
In a barbarian society, we are forced to live in an asylum, where we are
both patients and explorers. Certain rules, arrived at empirically, will
govern our conduct in terms of that analogy.
First, I recognise the seeds of madness in myself. I know that if ever,
for any purpose, I allow myself to act as a member of such a group and
to forfeit my responsibility to my fellows, from that moment I am a
madman, and the degree of my insanity will be purely fortuitous.
Second, I must suspect all bodies, groups, teams, gangs, based on power,
for where two or three hundred are gathered together, there is the
potentiality of lunacy in the midst of them, whether lunacy that kills
Jews, lunacy that flogs Indians, lunacy that believes Lord George Gordon
or the Ku Klux Klan, or lunacy that bombs Berlin. Yet I shall not hate
or distrust any of my fellow patients singly. They are exactly as I am.
I can see how dangerous they are, but I can be as dangerous to them if I
allow myself to become involved. It will be said that I deny social
responsibility. I do notâI believe that responsibility is boundless. We
have boundless responsibility to every person we meet. The foreman owes
it to his men not to persecute themâhe owes it as a man, not because
there is an abstract power vested in the TUC which demands it. Barbarism
is a flight from responsibility, an attempt to exercise it towards a
non-existent scarecrow rather than to real people. Each sincere citizen
feels responsibility to society in the abstract, and none to the people
he kills. The furious obedience of the Good Citizens is basically
irresponsible. âThe simple love of country and home and soil, a love
that needs neither reasons nor justifications, is turned by the official
apologists of the state into the demented cult of âpatriotismâ: coercive
group unanimity: blind support of the rulers of the state: maudlin
national egoism: an imbecile willingness to commit collective atrocities
for the sake of ânational glory.ââ[5] We have no responsibility whatever
to a barbarian society (we recognise no moral duties towards a gang of
madmen): our responsibilities to each other I believe to be boundless.
Third, one must aim at concealment. When lunacy is a norm, cynicism is a
duty. The chief task will be to remain unnoticed by these ranging gangs
of fellow patients. Their main duty falls on anybody who, by remaining a
person, reminds them of personality and death. One lives in perpetual
danger from the hatred or the equally destructive desire of the Good
Citizens, and we shall need to humour, to cajole, to deceive, to
appease, to compromise, to run at the right moments. When two of these
squealing packs are murdering each other we shall be denounced by both
as traitors for failing to join in. The most we can do is to attempt to
snatch out of the mob one or two of the pathetic figures, urged on by
scamps, who compose such mobs. They are our friends.
The positive expression of such ideas is not in the ballot box but in
the individual restoration of responsible citizenship, the practice of
recalcitrant mutual aid, not in political organisation but in the
fostering of individual disobedience, individual thought, small
responsible mutual aid bodies which can survive the collapse and
concentrate their efforts upon the practice of civilisation. It is the
philosophy of direct action, of the deserter and the maquis, the two
most significant and human figures of every barbarian age.
In future, our responsibilities are to our fellow men, not to a society.
The point at which responsibility becomes finally submerged is the point
at which we no longer have common ground with society. Once the choice
of barbarism has been made, the only remedy is in direct action. We now
accept no responsibility to any group, only to individuals. This
repudiation is not confined to âartistsâââartistsâ have made it because
they happen to be human beings. They enjoy no rights that shoemakers,
doctors or housewives are not equally entitled to demand. The claim of
society on bakers is just as much vitiated by irresponsibility as its
claim on poets. There are no corporate allegiances. All our politics are
atomised.
It is not that as artists we have deserted society. It has deserted or
ejected us, and we live on in contact with it as tenants whom the
landlord has not troubled to have thrown out. We have not seceded, but
in clinging to personality we sling to something which everyone knows is
the harbinger of death. They hate us for reminding them of it. They
burrow deeper into society to lose sight of the fact which towers over
them. Rather than face it, they become insane. Fascism is a refuge from
Death in death. And fascism epitomises the historical tendency of
barbarian society.
These are the necessary conclusions of an age in which a concept of
society and of the universeâI mean the Victorian-Liberal-bourgeois
concept, has collapsed. To describe them as obscurantist or a âfailure
of nerveâ contributes little to their discussion. They are the almost
inevitable product of the time, and in practice they exercise everybody,
even Marxist writers who repudiate them and find it hard to sympathise
with âromanticsâ who express them. They are far more a fact of social
history than a result of conscious thought.
Further, they represent the conscious or unconscious state of mind of an
entire generation of writers, both those who profess individualism and
those who reject it. They are manifestly not identical with the ideas
behind âArt for Artâs sakeââit would be far fairer to regard them as art
for responsibilityâs sake. The generation which is influenced by such
ideas is certainly making no special claims for itself, either of
privilege or of insight. This set of ideas, this metaphysical and
political attitude, is an ideology, and that ideology is correctly
termed romanticism.
If this seems a cynical or a hysterical estimate of human society and of
an artistâs attitude to it, I feel that there is evidence, from what we
have seen of history in some ten years of increasing political
degeneration throughout societies whose barbarian revolution has taken
place, that it may be true. Perhaps the environment was a very
unfavourable one. I have lived only in a social system generally
admitted to be at the end of its tether. I belong to a generation
brought up in the certainty that it would be killed in action on behalf
of an unreality against an insanity. But war is not a special case. The
English public is madder now than in 1938âit kills and tortures with as
little scruple as its enemies did themâbut war is only an aggravation of
barbarism. The shock effect of such ideas as I have expressed is present
only to people who, like the American and Fjiglish artists of the
present day, are politically and humanly semi-adult. The Chinese, the
peasants of Europe, the peasants of sixteenth-century England, artists
like Brueghel and Shelley, would not require their formulation. They
would find them too obvious to require stating. Of course the artist is
a responsible individual. It is only the artist who is recovering from a
period of dehumanised Victorianism or industrialism who needs to be
reminded of them. Brueghel, unlike the intellectuals of classicism,
would not have been surprised and disoriented because obedient citizens
massacred Jews or Germans, because the Japanese raided Pearl Harbour.
These ideas are part of the humanity which we re-learn in becoming
romantics. However, the romantic is certainly obliged to face the
criticism that he denounces other peopleâs doings when he cannot say
what principles guide his own actions. I say emphatically that war is
wrong, and do not know why I say it. The position is illogical, but I
see no way out. I cannot give so many reasons for believing any one
action to be wrong as I can give for believing a work of art to be bad.
Yet as I am confident that aesthetics are real, and find myself obliged
to act accordingly, so in the field of ethics I must act on some of the
convictions that compose humanity. The only coherent ethic is that of
responsible humaneness. I believe, therefore, in reason against
insanity, in responsibility against barbarism. A society of
irresponsible, obedient citizens to my mind is as morally null as it is
historically doomed. The ethic of romanticism is an ethic derived
entirely from man, and for the artist and the scientist, concerned with
humanity and nothing else, it is true and coherent. Apart from human
beings, neither âgoodnessâ nor âbeautyâ have any absolute significance.
They are human things and the seeking of them is a human obligation. The
romantic launches his protest and bases his conduct upon an ethic, an
agathistic utilitarianism, which he finds in the alliance for mutual aid
of all human beings against a universe which does not exist for their
comfort nor share their aspirations.
Perhaps the most important factor which has led to the widespread
acceptance of romanticism today is that it offers an adequate
explanation of contemporary Western society and has shown itself capable
of predicting accurately the future course of that society. Manâs only
weapon against the anarchy of the universe is his civilisation, the
responsible adoption of each individual of his social rights and duties.
The growth of Western society has been coterminous with the gradual
passage of these functions of justice, law, mutual aid and creative work
out of the hands of individuals and into the hands of professional
exponents, but never until the total unhinging of the whole system of
individual civilisation by the Industrial Revolution had the ascendancy
of barbarism been absolute, and the existence of a public possessing no
single element of normal human activity or culture become widespread.
The megalopolitan pattern is irreversible, if any historical process is
irreversible, and it was possible to predict with accuracy the total
collapse of the megalopolitan communities and the survival only of such
groups as were able or could become able to revert to the practice of
mutual aid, as early as the beginning of the twentieth century. The only
persons from whom this process was concealed were the inevitable
progress party, who required yet another demonstration of the
inevitability of post-revolutionary tyranny inherent in any revolution
which retains the concept of centralised power. They have had that
demonstration in France, in Russia, in Germany. Romanticism is fully
vindicated as a theory of life, and its offspring anarchism as a theory
of politics, by the only valid arbiter, the historical event.
Romanticism postulates the alliance of all human beings against the
hostility of the universe, and against power, which is the attempt to
push off the burden of personal responsibility on to other shoulders.
Both biologically and historically, it is a wholly realistic view. It
comprises no conclusion which is reached by any process save the
examination of human experience and observation, and the anger of the
classicists against it is based entirely upon the romantic rejection
both of the wholly illusory ideas of historical and inevitable progress
and of the implicit metaphysical assumption that human ideals have some
unexplained entity, in a psychological vacuum called âultimate
realityââthe ideals to which the most hardened dialectical materialist
unconsciously appeal when he talks about âsocial justiceâ.
Even more urgently romanticism rejects the form of social order in which
human responsibilities are curtailed, to a point at which none of the
conceptions which constitute justice or freedom retain any meaning save
that which the stateholders confer on them, the condition of society in
which we now live, and which is correctly termed barbarism. With the
moral extinction of Christianity, romanticism remains the only ideology
which has a coherent system of moral judgments on which it can rely, and
because its morals and its sociology, its conception of human need and
of human duty, coincide and have a common historic and scientific
origin, it can confidently predict the self-destruction of every
barbarian order.
The failure of nerve which the writers of Partisan Review deplore on
ideological grounds is no more a failure of nerve on the part of the
artist than a bad prognosis is a failure of nerve on the part of the
doctor. Western civilisation is not moribund as a result of the failure
of its social organisation; it is far more probably moribund through the
failure of the individual to assert his resistance to organisation of an
irresponsible kind, and through a sort of natural decay which seems to
afflict civilisations much as mortality afflicts individuals. I find it
difficult to decide what it is that makes a âcivilisationâ, but one
anthropological essential is a group ethic in which the individual
retains his responsibility. Renan, a cynic would say, may well have been
right in doubting whether, in the absence of some form of theocratic
supernaturalism, however untrue, civilisations can remain coherent at
all. Marxist historians point to the decay of the medieval theology and
its successor, Victorian evangelicalism, as symptoms of the dialectical
decay of medieval feudalism and Victorian capitalismâit is probably more
true to say that the collapse of economic organisation and the collapse
of bodies of belief and thought were parallel phenomena, determined by
some third factor, the semi-organic process, through its rise and decay,
of a complete civilisation.
Because romanticism has always been aware of the tragic aspects of human
life, it has always tended to preach personalism, to base its ideology
on direct responsibility and upon political anarchism. The romantic
awareness of Death and the romantic awareness of personal human
responsibility are indissolubly united. The political component results
from the metaphysical. Because we are all in the same boat, therefore we
are inevitably responsible to one another, as if we were afloat on the
same raft. In those same periods of social expansion when the
âprogressiveâ aspects of society are uppermost, it is hard enough for
the artist to recognise that he is ultimately the enemy of society, but
in a disintegrative phase such as the present the necessity for
accepting the role of masterless men, in the face of âtotal warâ and
total society, has been sprung on writers totally unprepared to grapple
with it. The technical complexity of contemporary barbarism has produced
a genuine loss of nerve among ex-classicists who have become dependent
on it, and argue that while totalitarianism is manifestly loathsome,
society is the giver of town-drainage and safe appendectomy as well as
of mass raids on Hamburg and massacres in Poland. The romantic view is
now what it has always beenâthat in dealing with acephalous societies
one is perpetually at sea with Captain Blighâwhen he orders the taking
in of sail, he is obeyed with perfect discipline; when he orders us to
flog a man, not a soul stirs. That is the lesson of responsibility which
the peasant and the experienced human being know. The industrial
abolition of humanity only obscured a conception which would have a
universal assent in any responsible community. It is the rediscovery of
the beastliness of which obedient citizens, educated in the Western
virtues of citizenship, are capable, which has so utterly overturned
this generation. The Victorians had forgotten Deathâit was swallowed up
in Victoryâand their excesses were removed to parts of the globe where
they were inconspicuous to the artist. The lunacy of obedience played
itself out on distant frontiers under the anaesthetic of an evangelical
Christianity.
It was upon our generation that the decision was forced. Either we had
to evade it by pleading some sort of artistic immunity (and thereby
cease to be human beings), with the likelihood that even such a plea
would not go down with the total society (I can see somebody getting his
ticket from the German Army because he was an artist), or by cynical
co-operation of the Ehrenburg-McLeish-Suarez brand, which might at least
save our skins; or, we must face the choice between becoming good
citizens and accepting our role as human beings and masterless men.
I say that to the Chinese or to the peasants of Europe or of Ireland,
more adult in humanity than most American or English artists, these
things would have been obvious, and no such choice would have presented
itself. But when the acceptance of the romantic attitude is
characterised as a failure of nerve, it means that to apologise for it I
must return to first principles. The romantic ideology of responsible
disobedience is as much the logical produce of this age as responsible
Christianity was the product of praetorian Imperial Rome. We are
romantics because we have grown up romantics, and because we are human
beings. In romanticism, art and science join hands, because both take
the side of man against the compulsions of his environment, against
Death, against power.
I have described romanticism sympathetically, but not because I fail to
see its fallacies. The classicist is running the perpetual risk of
forfeiting his responsibilityâthe romantic of forfeiting his sanity. He
is performing a continual tightrope walk over a series of intellectual
abysses, of self-pity, self-dramatisation, mysticism, conversion to
Roman Catholicism, acquiescence in political reaction, or pathological
despair. The danger of such a collapse is greatest when the romantic
ideology is thrown up half-consciously by a semi-emotional sense of
impending social disaster, just as revolutionary classicism is at its
most irresponsible when it comes into violent conflict with historical
and sociological fact. But we are no more entitled to denounce
romanticism in terms of romantics who have lost their nerve than we are
entitled to abolish coal gas because some persons use it as a means of
suicide. Every idea and every ideology carries in itself the potential
destruction of its adherents. The prediction that a social order is
bound to destroy itself, while it is an unnerving conclusion, is no more
a loss of nerve in itself than the conclusion upon scientific
observation or common experience that a man is likely to die or a
volcano to erupt. It is in the consciousness of common humanity and the
retention of this wholly scientific conception of history that the
validity of romanticism persists.
Because of these two provisos, romanticism today is not a destructive or
a defeatist force. Its adherents in the sociological field predict the
destruction of megalopolitan societies as a historical probability, and
for that reason they tend to concentrate their practical activity in the
cultivation of mutual aid, direct action, and the other communal
activities which are the basis of culture, and in terms of which human
life will survive. Such activity is essential, whether the destruction
of barbarism occurs violently in mass air raids or by consentâthose who
predict violent disintegration on historical grounds have to remember
that there is no such thing as inevitability in any historical process:
they are dealing with probabilities, nothing more. Other factors than
war or civil violence may operate to terminate the barbarian phase, and
the resuscitation of mutual aid, personal responsibility and direct
action, the three criteria of a civilised community, may occur by some
form of political consent. There are also a good many historical
examples of barbarian states surviving in an extended form, in which
culture passes into a state of suspended animation: Rome underwent such
a period between AD 70 and the final and gradual disintegration of
Imperial barbarism: this alternative, the prolongation of servile
barbarism by consent in the Western and American states, is a more
menacing one for human culture than the prospect of the breakdown of
megalopolitanisms by direct violence. It can be combated only by the
encouragement of autonomous civilised activities from withinâactivities
which deny the validity of the barbarian political system.
A few years ago, my immediate predecessors were chiefly influenced by
the concept of the class war. I believe that the concept, as a force for
progress, has outlived its truth (not because it was, in the first
place, falseânobody in his senses could deny that it was and is an
historical event) and become a partial truth only. We are beginning to
see that âclasslessâ societies can be as preposterous in their demands
on the individual conscience as any others, and as heavily impregnated
with barbarism. Where they have succeeded, it is because they have
permitted the fragmentation of the state into individuals, civilised by
mutual aid. Where they have not permitted it, they have become more
tyrannical than the manifestly unjust societies that went before. The
war is not between classes. The war is at root between individuals and
barbarian society. The beginnings of every revolutionary movement show
stagesâthe first, when it moves forward to overthrow a society whose
demands on the individual are insane, being itself a free association of
individuals; the second, when it stands still, and a Leviathan acquires
a body; the third, when Leviathan becomes Frankenstein and the fitting
object for a fresh revolution. Revolution is not a single act, it is an
unending process based upon civil disobedience. The demands become
increasingly exorbitant, abstract notions of solidarity are made
concrete, a state is invested with powers and properties, centralisation
inflates the vices of individual leaders to titanic proportions, and
once again it preys on its individual members, with or without their
consent. It is with this whole idea of society as a super-person that
responsibility is at war, and class struggles are superseded by this
struggle.
Certainly, this struggle, the relevant struggle, is overlapped by
othersâthe class war, the European war. Many participants in fact remain
participants through confusion of the two struggles. A good many of the
dynamitards and secret journalists of Europe will resume their weapons
against whatever carpet-bag state the Allies install. A good many
communistsâlike the Old Guardâwill be forced to continue their war
against the classless state if they get it. The most discouraging thing
is to see sincere people who appreciate the nature of society mistaking
one struggle for the other. The war for freedom is the war against
society. There is no other enemy.
And for those who can see the present war as a struggle for human
freedom, I can only say that that is what they are fighting for but not
what they will get. In a rigged society the scenery can be so skilfully
changed. The obviously right course of action can be doggedly pursued
until with the collapse of the stage scenery its true enormity appears.
The people are the only victims and the only losers. Whoever wins it
will not be they, and whatever results it will not be freedom. We are
sitting now and awaiting the swindle.
What are we to teach the people? As writers and artists we cannot avoid
teaching them. In all wars we are neutral, not because we ignore
wrongdoing, but because as individuals we must apply identical standards
to the actions of both sides. Acquiescence in the murder of the
population of Lidice is as evil as acquiescence in the murder of the
population of Hamburg. We cannot be bothered with the interminable
nonsense of causes and nations, because we know it to be fraudulent. It
is a waste of breath to argue the intentions of the Allies or the
Germans, the superiority of one set of professions over another, because
both are fictitiousâthe electric hares that neither we, nor any other
people that follow them, will ever be permitted to catch. Military
action is a part of barbarism, and as such it cannot salvage
civilisation. The âobviously righf cause is so only because of the stage
scenery which has been set up by society. Only people matter to us. When
Diamond was fighting Capone, he missed a golden chance. He should have
raised a citizen army to support him, on the ground that he only robbed
while Capone cut throats: he should have denounced non-participants for
acquiescing in murder. Our pity extents to every individual who is the
victim of historyâthe persecuted Jews, the persecuted Indians. Stripes
are red whatever back they are upon. We are neutral not because we feel
too little of evil, but because we feel too much. At every move we make
to assist a sufferer, crash goes our foot in an equally innocent face.
To say âall peoples are our friends, all societies are our enemiesâ is
not as foolish as it sounds. We will say it.
As we look at Europe today, we cannot see it as writers of the thirties
saw it. We do not see it as a clear-cut issue between progress and
reaction. We see defrauded and deluded peoples engaged in utterly
purposeless destruction, because the objects for which they fight are
unreal hopes dangled in front of their noses by the respective
governments of their countries. Because these peoples have abrogated
their right to employ their intelligence and have agreed to act as Good
Citizens, their sincerity and self-sacrifice count for absolutely
nothing. (There is an equal sincerity and an equal self-sacrifice on
both sides, exploited for diametrically opposite but equally fraudulent
objects.)
The barbarian citizen, fascist or democratic, has delegated his culture
to professional artists, his coition to professional film stars, his
juridical duties to professional policemen, his civic rights to
professional politicians. He remains alone with idleness, and the last
human attribute, Death. For him all wars are irrelevant unless they
destroy the mechanism of delegation and leave him a human being again,
faced with the necessity for mutual aid.
I have referred to stage scenery. The young man of my own generation was
pushed by society on to a stage where certain events were being enacted,
shown the villain, and instructed to choose between shooting him and
being shot. Now in the circumstances of the play, and assuming all the
conventions of melodrama, there was only one right course of action, but
no sooner has one pursued it, for a year or a scene, than down comes the
scenery and a fresh set-up, a fresh set of conventions appears, and one
is told, ânow do your obvious dutyâ (which has become the direct
opposite of what it was in Scene I, because the villain has been altered
and several of the heroes have gone to the bad). And some of us have
made up our minds that we will no longer be party to a bloodstained and
fraudulent charade in which the weapons are loaded and the helpless
audience are the only victims. We reject the dramatic conventions. From
now on we will be concerned with people, not conjuring tricks.
But what are we to make of our subject? Europe stinks of blood and
groans with separation. What are we to make of a world where disablement
and sickness are priceless possessions, as sort of passport to life? How
many wives would buy a game leg or a hunchback for their husbandsâhow
many mothers for their sons? I was present at a strange celebration. We
sat round a table drinking to a young manâs future. A week before the
house had been in mourning as if he were already dead. He was reaching
his eighteenth birthday, when one chooses between a butcherâs life and a
sheepâs death. The papers had come. During the day he fell into his
machine at work. One of his legs became shorter than the other. It was
as though he had been given a paper certifying: âThis man is out of the
hands of the Lunatics. If he looks sharp and is lucky, he may form a
cell for himself into which the gangs of Good Citizens, who patrol the
world looking for people to educate by cutting their windpipes, may fail
to breakâ.
That, until the fall of barbarism at its own hands, is how Freedom
comes.
I say all this, because I believe that in essence art is the act of
standing aside from society, with certain important qualifications. (I
ask my critics to abstain from quoting this until they have heard the
rest of the story.) Herbert Read has pointed out that in truly free
communities art is a general activity, far more cognate with craft than
it can ever be in contemporary organised life, and he consigns the
professional artist to his father the devil. I accept the proposition:
it seems to be merely another statement of the hostility between
barbarism and humanity which I have described. A state of affairs in
which art could become a part of all daily activity, and in which all
activity was potentially creative, would be a free community, and not a
societyâthat is, a personified body treated as though it were an entity
in itselfâof the kind I have attacked. Art, when it is professionalised,
consists in standing aside.
But it is essential that there should be no bitterness in the action. It
may take any form, from the pure escape of decoration to the analysis of
dreams and impulses in the myth, and to the most savage denunciation.
But there must be no bitterness against humanity, or the artist defeats
his own end. Neither must there be an attitude of superiority. He has
absolutely no right to claim exemptions or privileges except in his
capacity as a human being. The artist employs his form as the voice of a
great multitude. It is only through the vicarious activity of creation
that the great multitude ever finds a voice. Every creative activity
speaks on behalf of utterly voiceless victims of society and
circumstance, of everyone, finally, since man is always at some time the
victim of his environment: and since they have undergone the supreme
indignity, on behalf of the dead. The artist in barbarian society is the
only true representative of the people.
That is what I mean by saying that the essence of romanticism is the
acceptance of a sense of tragedy. All creative work speaks on behalf of
somebody who would otherwise be voiceless, even the decoration of the
potter who protests against the monotony of his work. I am always
conscious of these submerged voices, as much in the tentative and
nervous forms of early expressionâsavage and childhood productions, bad
derivative art produced, under civilised conditions, by people striving
to express themselvesâas in the technically professional work of the
great ages of painting. No creative activity is free from the sense of
protest. It is the sole way open to man of protesting against his
destiny.
In the actual circumstances of contemporary writing, the standing aside
must take different forms, though if it involves bitterness, hatred, a
sense of moral and aesthetic superiority, or any form of ivory-towerism,
it defeats itself. On the one hand, one can and must stand aside, though
one can at the same time admire the scale and tragic quality of an
event, or the courage which has gone to make an achievement. Anyone who
is not deeply moved by events is probably not capable of creation. There
is not the smallest reason why a poet should not write odes to the
Russian Revolution or the Dneiper Dam if these subjects move him, and
represent the message which, on behalf of some of the submerged voices,
he is attempting to interpret, any more than there is a reason why he
should not hate a tyrant or drive a concrete-mixer. But the poetry is
subsequent to the fact that whoever writes it has already stood far
enough away from his subject to be able to see it in reasonable and
historical proportion. It is the right to do this, even in a community
whose ideals inspire sympathy, that is utterly fundamental to good
writing, and it is precisely this right which contemporary society is
unanimous in denying. When it comes to the interpretation of the war,
both publics and their leaders realise, consciously or unconsciously,
that there is no more serious threat to the will to continue fighting
than the existence of a body of objective art. It requires to be
explained away, blackguarded into silence, conscripted, or ignored,
according to the methods in vogue in the society concerned. But it
continues to exist. The right to stand aside is contested everywhere.
Leaders who have acclaimed the work of a particular artist because he
denounced their opponents are exasperated to find that the denunciatory
criticism extends to themselves.
And on the other hand there is the essential prerequisite on which all
romantic theory is foundedâthe community of the artist with his fellow
men: in other words, his humanity. He must cater for the need to stand
aside by regarding all movements and societies neutrally, not in that he
refuses to judge them at all, but that he judges them on the same basis.
He cannot afford to have in his bag divers weightsâthat is one of the
traits of civic lunacy. The artistâs isolation and humanity are no
different from the isolation and humanity of other responsible
peopleâisolation from barbarism, solidarity with other human beings. It
is a tribute to English letters that in a period of almost unparalleled
national insanity England should have produced Trevelyanâs Social
History. This is the history of the relationships and the experience
from which there is no standing aside, the story of humanity in its
incessant war with society. If the artist is to take the side of man, he
is fulfilling both his duties of isolation and humanity.
I disagree with the idea that the artist is primarily the interpreter of
the symptoms and processes of economic changeâto follow Caudwellâs
conception is to limit the number of levels on which art could or should
exist. The unit with which the artist is concerned is first of all the
individual human being. The romantic artist sees him exactly as the
physician sees himâan individual who shares his organs and a high
proportion of his psychological make-up with every individual who has
existed within historical time, and with the artist himself. Like the
physician, the artist is one of humanity, subject to every branch of
human experience, from politics to death, but possessing by virtue of
his talent the faculty which the physician acquires through training, of
elucidating, interpreting, assisting. His sensibility corresponds to the
physicianâs medical trainingâconsciously or unconsciously he is aware of
the individualâs position and of the roots in anthropology, psychology
and evolution which make up humanness. He is neither a superman nor a
privileged person, any more than the physician is. It is with this
quality of humanness that the romantic is primarily concernedâit is the
origin of the romantic sympathy, the concept of shared, responsible
experience, and of man as the product and victim of environment, which
makes romanticism and defines it. In addition to this prerequisite
consciousness, there is the technical mastery, learned or acquired,
which is needed to express it. One might almost continue the analogy and
say that classicism bears some resemblance to operative surgeryâthere is
the same emphasis on technical virtuosity and the same preoccupation
with intervention rather than with organic process. To the artist as a
human being, and to the physician in his practice, the sense of
continuity of circumstances and difference of environment are
perpetually present the human being and the patient, for the purposes of
art and medicine, are fundamental constants. There is no difference
between Hagesichora and any other young girl dancing, between the
Homeric warriors and any other soldierâyou cannot tell whether the man
under the theatre towels is a Nazi or an anarchist; that aspect of his
existence concerns you very littleâyou are interested in him as a man.
The neutrality of medicine has survived this war well. The neutrality of
romantic art will also survive it, because it is based on the far larger
community of man, which society tends to destroy, which one finds only
in Londonâs slums or Americaâs prisons. It seems to me that it is this
university in art which Marxist classicism misses, just as in the
political sphere it does not extend âworking class solidarityâ into the
responsible and anti-authoritarian conception of human solidarity. It is
the extension of this evaluation of man into politics which makes up
anarchism, and the common foundation of anarchism and romanticism
renders them inseparable in the evolution of art, just as medicine as a
practice, if we are to oppose it to the technical vetinary surgery of
such people as army psychologists, whose aim is something other than
plain human welfare, is inseparable from a similar human neutrality.
The value of Marxist criticism has lain, however, in its perpetual
emphasis on the environmental concern of the artist. Once fortified with
this conception of humanity and his knowledge that he is a part of it,
not an observer, the artist is under obligation to concern himself with
the entire environment of the times, both by interpreting it and by
modifying it. Writers who are afraid to throw their weight into the
cause of the humanity they recognise will find little in the tradition
of romanticism to support their abstention. This criticism is valuable
in itself, but at present is pretty consistently directed against the
wrong people. It is the concept of irresponsible society, whatever its
social organisation, that is now and always has been the enemy of the
romantic conception of man, and in a period of disintegration, with
irresponsibility at a premium, the artist who reflects and interprets is
accused of decadence, and the artist who advocates responsibility is
accused of disruption. I cannot see an iota of difference between the
attacks of sycophants and clowns who propagate a theory of cultural
bolshevism (that Joyce and Proust were responsible for the fall of
France, for instance) and those of the political actives who charge
romantic individualism with losing its nerve. They are both imitating
the man who smashes the barometer because it points to rain.
This characteristic phase of a collapsing culture is very obvious in
England and America at present. It merits further discussion. The stupid
and illiterate attacks of Alfred Noyes on Proust, the venom with which
bourgeois formalism has been denounced by the communists, and the
suppression of the work of Klee by the Nazis, had this in common they
were all attacks upon images of disintegration by people who feared the
disintegration itself and could not see its cause. Some of them were the
product of mere personal or political malice. Yet there remains a valid
ground for attack, upon purely disintegrative and analytic forms such as
surrealismâthey are not fully human. The real treason lies not in
reflecting disintegration but in failing to reflect anything else.
There is still confusion of mind among the enemies of disintegration who
have rather more grasp on its causes than the dealers in cultural
bolshevism. Perhaps the most striking instance of this confusion is to
be found in their attempts to defend art. I have in mind the pamphlets
and counter-pamphlets of 1943â44: it is the nearness of the
disintegration which upsets them, precisely as it has upset and unnerved
the poets.
The right-wing critic can see that the pretensions of artists of the
disintegrative school to be immune from the collapse by virtue of their
function as artists are preposterous: he can see that the common
individual, who retains his humanity in the face of everything, is
sound, but he rushes to identify the Cause of Man with the Cause of
Humanity sponsored by the Daily Telegraph. The aristocrat can see that
the war is a fraud, but pins the blame on the anti-cultural bias of the
masses. This controversy is conducted in the same historical Wonderland
as that of A.L. Rowse, who prophesies a ânew Elizabethan ageââa remark
historically equivalent to predicting a new Secession of the Plebs in
the reign of Nero, or a new set of milk-teeth in a centenarian.
Yet there is a real failure of nerve in the manuscripts which 1944
brought in to every English poetry magazine, in which the sole images
present are images of disintegrationâone reads of nothing else: it is
the schizophrenia of writers who are unable to cut themselves off from
the collapse of society, because to do so would involve them in an adult
awareness of humanity, including an awareness of death. Partisan Review
and Horizon are full of the praises of schizophrenia. The failure of
nerve is common to the people who attack it, if one excludes the
sycophants and the congenital idiots, and a great many of the people
they are attacking. The romantic wholeness involves a good deal more
than the passive acceptance of collapseâthere is also the assertion of
responsibility to oneâs fellows, and the exhortation to disobey the
irresponsible directives of barbarism. I think that the best example of
this wholeness in the face of barbarism is Brueghel. The disquietening
images of disintegration are thereâMumford selects him as the symbolic
exponent of the medieval collapseâbut one feels that the artist has no
share in them. It is not he who is disintegrating but the society whose
irresponsibility he hatesâthe society of expressionless unanimous
skeletons, the forest of lances that supports Herod. The humanity of
Herodâs soldiers is stressed as much as their unanimity. These are the
lunatics, but at home they are also peasants. The victims and killers
are interchangeable. The subject of each of these masterpieces is an
aspect of the romantic struggle of Man against his environmental
enemies, the fully human Man who is shown us with his physical and
mental equipment of faults and virtues in the âpeasantâ pictures. The
Triumph of Death, the Massacre of the Innocents, Man against Obedience,
Man against Death. If we cannot win the second battle we can at least
win the first.
Accordingly, we apply the same standards to every cause or body which
presents itself, without owing allegiance to any of them. We recognise
boundless responsibility to men, especially to all those who are
deprived of their voices, but ultimately to all men, since they will in
time become silent. We must demand the right to secession as the one
square foot of ground which is solid and from which we can look and
interpret the gigantic chaos of human existence. We are learning
ourselves to live in the structure of insane societies while defying
them, practising to retain our lives as if we were really sane men in an
asylum where all individuals were allies and all bodies were bent on
killing us, and we teach others, as far as we can, to do likewise.
The weak are inheriting the earth, though we are forced to fight, plot,
deceive for every inch of the legacy. They are taxed, killed,
frightened, conscripted, swindled, interned, collectively; the gangs of
good citizens drive them like sheep, they are dragged from their
standing ground by the innumerable pressure of the flood around them,
and the ranks of Bedlamite citizenship are recruited from them. They
inherit by default, like small animals inhabiting the floor of a forest,
and dying off like flies, but they strike back ineffectually and, by
sheer weight of numbers, invincibly. Their aggregate intervals of sanity
suffice to overthrow the entire edifice of society which has been built
on their backs and out of their flesh. Their sane moments are ultimately
decisive. Their clinging among the wreckage to mutual aid perpetuates
civilisation. In the ultimate explosion of the barbarism structure,
islets of true civilisation, the nuclei of future cultures which have
still their upward cycle to run, persist and grow. Then in a decade or
two they begin like coral insects to construct a new load for their
backs. But all of them are ready now and again, in the time of
barbarism, to assert their personality from time to time. The woman who
fails to fuse a shell securely, the clerk who does not look a second
time at a pass, the girl who hides a deserter and the idiot who
misdirects an escort, whatever their nationality, are acting as members
and soldiers of the community of the weak, the greatest conspiracy in
history, which is ceaseless. It is quite irrelevant that at the next
moment they are killing Jews, bombing cities, supporting Jacks-in office
and believing lies. At times every one of them has struck a minor blow
for personality. It is to these people that art owes a responsibility
which is hard to measure. Among modern writers one feels that only
Arnold Zweig and Giono have achieved it continuously, and some reports
suggest that the German occupation has disorientated even Giono.
It is rare that a free community of such people can come into existence.
One finds islands of community which have escaped the curse of
personified societies scattered everywhereâthe shelters during the air
raids, the Cossack villages, some primitive tribes, prisoners in Dachau
or Huyton, the Russian collective farms. These are the largest
communities in which anarchism is real and the standing aside
preliminary to creation is not resented to the same degree as in the
societies of clockfaces, whose sole virtue is their unanimity in error.
This virtue is a virtue of death. They do not escape death by evading it
in the renunciation of life. It is not for nothing that Brueghelâs
skeletons have all the same faces. And artistic responsibility consists
in taking all this upon our shouldersâin providing voices for all those
who have not voices. The romantic ideology of art is the ideology of
that responsibility, a responsibility borne out of a sense of
victimhood, of community in a hostile universe, and destined like
Prometheus, its central creation, to be the perpetual advocate and
defender of Man against Barbarism, community against irresponsibility,
life against homicidal and suicidal obedience.
---
(Art and Social Responsibility: Lectures on the Ideology of Romanticism,
Falcon Press, 1946)
[1]
1942.
[2] I am surprised that Fromm (The Fear of Freedom) and other
psychologists do not make more of this. The fear of death is probably at
root the fear of isolation, rather than of a cessation of experience.
Total isolation is reached only in âdeterioratedâ schizophrenia and in
death, but one of the chief artistic grounds for attacking contemporary
societies is that they produce a false sense of community while, in
reality, they destroy the individualâs true relation with his fellows
and substitute a relationship to a fictitious dummy, the Group.
[3] Singularly enough, some critics again attempt to depict this view as
a form of religious mysticism, largely because it uses the term âhuman
natureâ and discusses the relationship of man to the Universe. Except in
so far as philosophical pessimism is a âreligionâ, it is difficult to
see in what way a romantic interpretation of history is any more
âreligiousâ than a marxist of physiochemical interpretation. It
certainly rejects every form of supernaturalism. As to Whiteheadâs
conception of romanticism as a revolt against science, the romantic
conception of metaphysics and politics is constituted in the same way as
any scientific hypothesisâby reference to the observed facts of history
or of psychology. Its interpretation may be fallible, but its method is
surely above reproach, even from the rationalists, whose notion of the
economic reform of society has no historical evidence to support it. I
would have placed the romantic awareness high in the list of causes of
scientific progress.
[4] In view of criticisms which have been made of this remark, it needs
qualifying. I do not say that all groups are bad, any more than I say
that because all men have stomachs they are dyspeptics. The tendency to
degenerate into irresponsibility is inherent in every group, once its
members cease to act as individuals, and transfer their responsibility
from their fellow men to the group. Where I use the word âsocietyâ in a
derogatory sense, I mean a society in which this change for the worse
has taken place.
[5] Lewis Mumford, Culture of Cities, IV, 9, page 256.