đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș alex-comfort-art-and-social-responsibility.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:35:06. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Art and Social Responsibility
Author: Alex Comfort
Date: 1946 (reprinted 1994)
Language: en
Topics: art, poetry, music, anarchist analysis
Source: Selection 6, pp. 52–78 in *Writings Against Power and Death: The Anarchist Articles and Pamphlets of Alex Comfort*, Edited with an Introduction by David Goodway. Freedom Press, London 1994. ISBN 0 900384 71 9

Alex Comfort

Art and Social Responsibility

“He [Josef Kramer] wasn’t a bad chap really... He simply couldn’t see

what he had done wrong in obeying orders...”

—PRESS REPORT

“Le regne de la poesie est peut-ĂȘtre plus proche que je n’ose le penser.

Que restera-t-il aux vivants de demain? Leurs yeux pour pleurer, des

mauvaises herbes et des fleurs des champs, une terre ravagée, des

cabanes aufond des bois, un carré de ciel, et des sentiments violents.

Pour un poete, les conditions necessaires et suffisantes.”

—RAYMOND DUMAY

I

Partisan Review, published in New York, advertised this year a number to

be devoted to exposing the ‘New Failure of Nerve’ in Western

liberalism.[1] The advertisement catalogued a series of the tendencies

which the editors regarded as retrograde, obscurantist, reactionary.

They included the abandonment of the historical for the metaphysical

approach to politics and ethics, a return to the idea of Original Sin,

and the appearance once again of the semi-deterministic conception of

sociology. It struck me that so many of these concepts were, in fact,

the principles of thought and art which are tending more and more to

guide the artists who have begin to appear publicly since the war broke

out; belonging to that generation, I am perfectly aware of the influence

of such ideas on myself. I have examined them fairly often, and whether

out of personal prejudice or out of conviction I must refuse to admit

that they are in essence obscurantist principles. We have just passed

through a period of classicism in English poetry which has no parallel

in American work, and we have seen a few of its limitations. History has

driven us from classicism to romanticism, and the migration has been

almost universal among sensitive writers.

I do not believe that the conflict between human beings and society is

the product of the Industrial Revolution, socialism, fascism, or any

other contemporary cause—it is as old as the hills, and the common man

knows it well enough. He has not been bludgeoned into the armies of

eight or nine millennia for nothing. The reason that the existence of

such a conflict requires mention in this essay is that for the first

time in a good many years the creative artist, who has previously, by

reason of his occupation, contrived to dodge the issue and claim special

privileges, is finding himself involved. The end of regionalism

liberated him from it; the collapse of urban centralisation confronts

him with it again. Just as friars contrived to escape being impressed to

fight at Crecy, artists have contrived, and still are contriving, if

they are prepared to sell their humanity, to avoid the issue of

accepting society or rejecting it. To the peasants of Alsace or China

none of this would need saying—they know armies and causes for what they

are—but to a great many writers, those of Partisan Review included,

brought up in an essentially urban culture, who have no such timeless,

hereditary awareness of disobedience, it badly needs saying. In England,

at any rate, the realisation of the active irresponsibility of society

has come as such a thunderbolt to writers reared in an atmosphere of

socialism (as we were) that they have had no time to make up their

minds. Caught on the wrong foot, they have postponed the decision,

either by preparing ‘to defend the bad against the worse’, or, far less

creditably, by using their status as artists to detach themselves from

general conscription, which is somewhat comparable with the action of

the doctor who claims priority air transport away from a cholera

epidemic, because he is an important asset to society.

These terms, classic and romantic, stand for more than differences of

style. The classic sees man as master, the romantic sees him as victim

of his environment. That seems to me to be the real difference. I regard

the periods of English literature as an alternation between these two

concepts. It is as if the awareness of death, the factor which, at root,

determines the degree to which we feel masters of our circumstances,

ebbed and flowed, alternately emphasised and obscured as a factor in

interpretative art. The classical periods are periods of economic and

mental security, when the drive is towards action and where the majority

of the people is in possession of a satisfactory interpretation of the

universe and of themselves, religious or political (it can be either).

They are periods during which the burdens of realising and interpreting

the most ghastly of all conflicts, between the man’s and the artist’s

desperate desire for permanence, and factual death which he discovers,

fall upon individual shoulders. These artists, standing in a period of

general complacency, are the major poets—frequently psychopathic, since

their insecurity is endogenous. The Victorian period was one such, and

it produced its Arnolds and Mark Rutherfords who agonised as much

quantitatively if not qualitatively within the structure of the times as

did Rilke or Thompson, or Unamuno and Lorca in contemporary Europe.

The active periods with their extroverted public alternate with ages

when the realisation of the Tragic Sense becomes general, spreads over

continents, reaches men who are conscious only of being afraid. There

are no major poets, because what they have to say, everybody already

knows. The times need not revealers but concealers, a hierarchy of men

who will hide the truth of death from humanity, or life becomes empty. I

am convinced that a large part of cultural barbarism arises from this

source. Perhaps this is the true failure of nerve. Major poetry is the

vicarious function of the single artist—he takes the weight of tragic

awareness to shield the rest of humanity from it. I rather doubt if ever

in history there have been so many who realised the emotional fact of

death. Megalopolitan civilisation is living under a death sentence. That

has become a personal realisation over great areas of the world. We are

at the turn of a major period of classicism (Victorian) which produced

major romantic poets, and finally classical poets using the husk of

romantic technique. Slack water was at about 1900, and suddenly the face

of social disintegration and personal death began to be seen by more and

more people. The private knowledge of the Dostoievskys and Unamunos of

the past was becoming general. A numb silence fell on everyone, except

Monro and his Georgians, who could not understand what was happening and

shouted to fill the gap. There were few attempts to reinstate a

classical, secure approach. The Imagists wrote, with increasing tragic

awareness. The socialist poets attempted to deny the awareness and to

turn to society, but in Spain the face of the unpleasant black figure

was unveiled. The poets went out to fight, taking Marx with them, and

came back with Unamuno and Lorca. It was then that the

dialectical-historical approach became hollow. In some strange fashion

the same knowledge, unconditioned by history, was growing up in

innumerable childhoods—Dylan Thomas knew it early in life, long before

the Spanish defeat. Art does not move always by sudden

transition—Steiner’s concept of the Zeitgeist is truer than it looks.

The transition is a matter of relative numbers who reach a viewpoint

together, independently. Artists reflect it now only because it is the

general temper of the public.

II

The awareness of death, the quasi-priestly but secular attitude, are

omnipresent for anyone who knows contemporary English art and letters.

No artist of my generation is uninfluenced by them. I should make it

clear that I do not wish to argue for them, only to state that they are

here. The new climate is a thing into which we grew up. The ideas that

lie behind it are the obscurantist ideas of the Editor of Partisan

Review, and analysis of what has been written suggests that they are

these.

universe and the psychological and so-called ‘spiritual’ aspirations of

man—that no human activity can be said to have ‘permanent’ or ‘absolute’

significance, and that ethics and aesthetics exist because we make them

and assert them, not in conformity with Platonic absolutes but in the

teeth of material reality. That the common enemy of man is Death, that

the common tie of man is ultimate victimhood, and that anyone who, in

attempting to escape the realisation of that victimhood in himself,

increases its incidence upon others, is a traitor to humanity and an

ally of death.

regarded as a steady progress in any direction, whether moral or

political, e.g. towards civilisation, goodness, socialism, but as an

oscillation about a fixed point, a series of self-limiting ecological

changes, an ebb and flow between certain fixed limits which have not

within human record been exceeded. We see it as a fluctuating conflict

between biological freedom and power. One cannot suggest on the recorded

evidence that man is either ‘morally better’ (however that be defined)

or politically more capable of forming a society which does not involve

the abuse of power. His achievement fluctuates sufficiently for one to

be able to say that democracy is ‘better’—i.e. more humane or less

exacting—than fascism, or that the Greece of 450 BC was preferable to

the Rome of AD 50, but the statement that absolute qualitative charge

has taken place between 500 BC and AD 1943 is without meaning for us.

Such comparisons are in themselves historically meaningless. We do not

believe that irresponsible society is any less of an evil than

irresponsible society then, or society when Godwin saw it. Every society

based upon power is, to us, vitiated by the fact, whoever the rulers may

be, and where free communities have come into existence their freedom

has to be constantly asserted, or they degenerate slowly or rapidly into

the adoption of power. In other words, the recurrent tendency of society

is to degenerate into barbarism. We accept this hypothesis for the same

reason that we call the tendency to live between fifty and eighty years

a human property—evidence tends to suggest that in a majority of cases

it is factually true. One does not detect the tendency so freely in

individuals as the Adlerians would lead us to believe—it is not a

question of individual lust-for-power, but a different property,

belonging to masses, and able to vitiate the most enlightened decisions.

It seems that in any society, acting as a society, once responsibility

and mutual aid are submerged, the constructive impulses tend to cancel

out, and the negative and destructive summate. This is as true of the

Communist Party as it is of feudal Poland or the Roman Empire. It is as

though we were to have a boat full of blindfold rowers. They pull in

different directions and no progress is made, but the weights of the

crew add up and she sinks. There is a good deal of argument possible

whether education can in any degree remedy this tendency. One can call

it original sin if one wishes. I do not care what name I give it—for me

as an artist it is real, the most real feature of society in all ages.

It is possible that, in reality, it is a feature of the collapse-phase

only—certainly its recognition is—yet all ages speak of deterioration as

a journey down hill. Social conduct is described as harder than its

opposite. It is no new idea. But the state of irresponsibility once

reached, the viciousness of an organisation tends to be proportional to

its size. Democracy in a barbarian state is a priori impossible, because

it involves the refusal to admit that the majority is never right.

Fascism is the attempt to summate the destructive influences and to use

them as a basis for a society. It teaches that the individual is unreal,

and therefore death, the termination of the individual, is unreal also.

If this does not explain the genuine satisfaction which all

authoritarian societies give to their adherents, then I have

misunderstood society. But I have no use for a Swedenborgian Hell by

common consent. One cannot propel the boat by the weight of its rowers.”

Romanticism is our ideology. It is based upon a metaphysical theory. The

most serious difficulty in the discussion of romanticism and its place

in sociological and literary criticism is the progressive loss of

meaning which critical illiteracy has inflicted on the name itself.

Romanticism is not a stylistic term, and the criterion of its

application is not how the subject writes, but what he

believes—otherwise we might find it difficult to explain the clarity and

definition with which we can speak of romantic painting, romantic

poetry, romantic sculpture and romantic music, with equal readiness and

an exact correspondence in the quality described. It has become

fashionable to deride any attempt to relate artistic criticism to

cosmological theory, except among those who confuse mystical speculation

with metaphysics. To attempt such a relation is one of the stigmata

which characterises ‘loss of nerve’ in the eyes of the neo-classicists.

But without coherent metaphysics art is no more a comprehensible

activity than travel without a sense of direction. The nature of reality

is the first concern not only of poetry but of intelligent biology or

political ethics, and the only claim of romanticism to the status of an

ideology, and a historically valid ideology, lies in the coherence of

its metaphysics, and its root in observed fact.

The romantic believes that the particular qualities which make up

humanness—mind, purpose, consciousness, will, personality—are unique in

known phylogeny, and are so far at variance with the physical conditions

in which man exists that they are irrelevant to the general structure of

physical reality. Christian and pagan metaphysicians of opposing

ideologies (including the Marxists, who believe in historical

inevitability) have contended either that Man was made in God’s image,

in which case ethical obligation corresponded with the nature of a

Creator, or that the Universe was made in Man’s image, and that some of

the values to which human individuals tend to aspire (beauty, goodness

or order) were incorporated in the physical universe itself. The

distinguishing feature of the metaphysical theory which underlies

romanticism is that it rejects the ideals themselves. They exist only so

long as Man himself exists and fights for them. The entire romantic

ethic and body of art rests upon this assumption of insecurity, an

insecurity which begins at the personal level of mortality, and extends

into all the intellectual fields where insecurity is least tolerable. It

is comical that such a view should be characterised as wish-fulfilment.

The romantic has only two basic certainties—the certainty of irresoluble

conflict which cannot be won but must be continued, and the certainty

that there exists between all human beings who are involved in this

conflict an indefeasible responsibility to one another. The romantic has

two enemies, Death, and the obedient who, by conformity to power and

irresponsibility, ally themselves with Death. There is no hint of

mysticism in this—romanticism is the ideology of a whole human being

looking at the whole universe.

Romanticism, the belief in the human conflict against the Universe and

against power, seems to me to be the driving force in all art and

science which deserves the name. In Western civilisation today there are

only two recognisable elements which can be said to differentiate it

from total barbarism, our art and our medical science, and both are

based upon this romantic ideology. The ethical content of romanticism

has always been the same. The romantic bases his ethic upon his belief

in the hostility or the neutrality of the Universe. He does not deny the

existence of absolute standards, but he denies their existence apart

from Man. The conceptions of artistic beauty or moral goodness did not

exist before the emergence of consciousness, and they will return to

oblivion with its extinction, but they are none the less good for their

impermanence. And because of this one-sided battle which the romantic

believes himself to be fighting, he recognises an absolute and

imperative responsibility to his fellow men as individuals—both because

he, unlike the Christian, is defending standards in which he believes

but which are not by nature assured of triumph, which he feels will only

exist so long as they are defended, and because his pessimistic

interpretation of philosophy makes him feel towards his fellow men much

as you might feel towards fellow survivors on a raft.

It is from this metaphysical idea of conflict, of principles which are

maintained only by struggle, that romanticism draws the tremendous force

of its social and philosophical criticism, and the equally tremendous

emotional and intellectual appeal of its artistic statements. It is a

force which alone among artistic forces seems to preserve perpetual

virility and perpetual youth. Compare the Enthronement of Our Lady,

which Ruskin called the most outstanding work of art in the world, with

the works of Brueghel and see which seems to you to be the more true—the

order and peace of the first, or the tumult of the second. The ideal of

beauty and order is the same in each case, but for the Italian master

the battle is already won, God is on His throne. For Brueghel, in the

world, in society, in his own body, the battle continued as bloody and

as fierce as ever.

The romantic recognises a perpetual struggle upon two levels, the fight

against Death which I have described, and the struggle against those men

and institutions who ally themselves with Death against humanity, the

struggle against barbarism. These are the two subjects of the Brueghel

paintings, The Triumph of Death and The Massacre of the Holy Innocents.

In the first, a gigantic host of skeletons is riding down mankind. In

the second, the Duke of Alva’s soldiery are butchering Flemish peasants

and their children. I regard these paintings as the highest level which

the expression of the romantic ideology has ever reached—and Brueghel is

not in any lecture catalogue of romantic painters. These are the enemies

of humanity, and of the standards of beauty and of truth which exist

only for and in humanity—Death and Death’s ally, irresponsibility. The

relevance of romanticism today lies in the fact that of all ideologies

it alone declares this basic antagonism and moulds its course

accordingly.

I suppose that I would summarise the social conclusions of contemporary

romantics in some such form as this:

possesses a conscious sense of personality which, as far as one can

reasonably guess, is not shared by other organisms, and which renders

the emotional realisation of death intolerable and incompatible with

continued enjoyment of existence. He therefore attempts universally to

deny either that death is real or that his personality is really

personal.[2]

negation of death) is apparently sealed by scientific research. I say

apparently, because the important factor from the viewpoint of social

psychology is not the actual evidence but the acceptance of death as

real and final by a high proportion of the populations which have so far

evaded the realisation.[3] This acceptance, coming upon people whose

humanity has been undermined by social organisation, is a root cause of

the flight into barbarism.

negation of individual personality and responsibility, since to admit

that I am an individual I must also admit that I shall cease to exist.

The negation takes the form of a growing belief in the conception of an

immortal, invisible and only wise society, which can exact

responsibilities and demand allegiances. The concept is as old as human

thought, but its acceptance is becoming more and more a refuge from the

reality of self. Society is not only a form of abrogating moral

responsibility, it is a womb into which one can crawl back and become

immortal because unborn.

they submerge constructive impulses and summate destructive ones, so

that the product of any group[4] action is by tendency destructive and

irrational. The courses of action which the group mode of thought

imposes upon the individual members are so grotesque and so wildly at

variance with reason and with normal constructive activity that by

reference to individual standards of human responsibility they are

clinically insane. The consciousness of personal responsibility is the

factor which differentiates human relationships from superficially

similar animal societies: and contemporary irresponsibility has thrown

it overboard.

The barbarian revolution occurs without external change at the point

where mutual aid becomes detached from political organisation, civic

delegation passes out of the control of the delegators, at the

transition between a community of responsible individuals and a society

of irresponsible citizens. At a definite point in the history of every

civilisation, and shortly before its economic peak, there occurs a

transfer of civic obligation, from the community based on mutual aid to

the society based upon common irresponsibility. It may manifest itself

as an industrial revolution, a megalopolitan development of the city, or

as a change in national attitude from community to communal aggression.

Every society has its Melian Dialogues, and thereafter the barbarian

revolution has taken place, and the actions of that society are

irresponsible, and its members insane.

The most terrible feature of this insanity is that it can be recognised

in ourselves, in our friends. The man whom one knows—a good fellow, able

to live as an individual a life which is free from any conscious

assaults on the rights of others, who does not make a practice of

beating his own head or the heads of others against the walls, who is

sane, with whom one eats or drinks... this same man can very well return

one evening to talk or drink with you again and catalogue the most

grotesque and contemptible actions which he has performed, or which he

supports, with full approval and a fixed delusional sense of their

rightness, solely because he is now acting as a member of some organised

and irresponsible group. He will pay any price to rid himself of the

selfhood which, subconsciously, he knows must die. It is this frantic

prostration before society/this masochistic attitude which permits

aggregate lunacy to torture him, kill him, or drive him to actions of

unspeakable idiocy, which explains the obedience of so many populations

to rogues and brutes who pull the strings and make Leviathan walk. Yet

this fellow you eat and drink with is still a good fellow. If all those

who supported tyranny, butchered each other, and generally raised hell

and high-water, were personal blackguards, film Nazis, one could be

happy. But I sat smoking last week with a great personal friend of mine

who has just helped to exterminate, under orders, the population of a

city where he has a good many acquaintances. He is filled with a sense

of the rightness of his action, and he was willing to perform it at

great personal risk. By participating in a human society, he had bought

the abrogation of the fear of death at the price of his personality. He

is not a fool nor a sadist—he is your friend or your son. His contact

with society has made him perform an action which, a year ago, or if it

had been performed yesterday by a society of which he was not a member,

he would have called bestial and contemptible. He looks back on it with

pride, because he has accepted it as an action on behalf of humanity.

Jailers, firing squads, thugs—the horror of it is that in many cases

they owe the criminality of their acts not to themselves but to the fact

that they are members of a society and possess no insight into its

corporate actions. To call them insane, over the range of those actions,

is not a figure of speech but a clinical fact. If insanity is a divorce

between reality and perception which, by depriving a man of insight,

renders him a peril to himself and others, then these men—my friend, all

of them—are insane, over the whole section of their activity which is

involved with the madhouse group. What else does the tag concerning

Salus Populi mean, save the society abrogates rational conduct? What

else is the contemporary phrase Military Necessity but a prelude to some

grotesque piece of bestiality which we are being asked to accept? We are

living in a madhouse whenever society is allowed to become personalised

and regarded as a super-individual. We are living in a madhouse now.

What will the artist, as an individual, have to say for himself when he

looks at the results of this process in the present time? He will lay

down, and I believe he is laying down, a set of cynical but reliable

guides to conduct.

In a barbarian society, we are forced to live in an asylum, where we are

both patients and explorers. Certain rules, arrived at empirically, will

govern our conduct in terms of that analogy.

First, I recognise the seeds of madness in myself. I know that if ever,

for any purpose, I allow myself to act as a member of such a group and

to forfeit my responsibility to my fellows, from that moment I am a

madman, and the degree of my insanity will be purely fortuitous.

Second, I must suspect all bodies, groups, teams, gangs, based on power,

for where two or three hundred are gathered together, there is the

potentiality of lunacy in the midst of them, whether lunacy that kills

Jews, lunacy that flogs Indians, lunacy that believes Lord George Gordon

or the Ku Klux Klan, or lunacy that bombs Berlin. Yet I shall not hate

or distrust any of my fellow patients singly. They are exactly as I am.

I can see how dangerous they are, but I can be as dangerous to them if I

allow myself to become involved. It will be said that I deny social

responsibility. I do not—I believe that responsibility is boundless. We

have boundless responsibility to every person we meet. The foreman owes

it to his men not to persecute them—he owes it as a man, not because

there is an abstract power vested in the TUC which demands it. Barbarism

is a flight from responsibility, an attempt to exercise it towards a

non-existent scarecrow rather than to real people. Each sincere citizen

feels responsibility to society in the abstract, and none to the people

he kills. The furious obedience of the Good Citizens is basically

irresponsible. ‘The simple love of country and home and soil, a love

that needs neither reasons nor justifications, is turned by the official

apologists of the state into the demented cult of “patriotism”: coercive

group unanimity: blind support of the rulers of the state: maudlin

national egoism: an imbecile willingness to commit collective atrocities

for the sake of “national glory.”’[5] We have no responsibility whatever

to a barbarian society (we recognise no moral duties towards a gang of

madmen): our responsibilities to each other I believe to be boundless.

Third, one must aim at concealment. When lunacy is a norm, cynicism is a

duty. The chief task will be to remain unnoticed by these ranging gangs

of fellow patients. Their main duty falls on anybody who, by remaining a

person, reminds them of personality and death. One lives in perpetual

danger from the hatred or the equally destructive desire of the Good

Citizens, and we shall need to humour, to cajole, to deceive, to

appease, to compromise, to run at the right moments. When two of these

squealing packs are murdering each other we shall be denounced by both

as traitors for failing to join in. The most we can do is to attempt to

snatch out of the mob one or two of the pathetic figures, urged on by

scamps, who compose such mobs. They are our friends.

The positive expression of such ideas is not in the ballot box but in

the individual restoration of responsible citizenship, the practice of

recalcitrant mutual aid, not in political organisation but in the

fostering of individual disobedience, individual thought, small

responsible mutual aid bodies which can survive the collapse and

concentrate their efforts upon the practice of civilisation. It is the

philosophy of direct action, of the deserter and the maquis, the two

most significant and human figures of every barbarian age.

In future, our responsibilities are to our fellow men, not to a society.

The point at which responsibility becomes finally submerged is the point

at which we no longer have common ground with society. Once the choice

of barbarism has been made, the only remedy is in direct action. We now

accept no responsibility to any group, only to individuals. This

repudiation is not confined to ‘artists’—‘artists’ have made it because

they happen to be human beings. They enjoy no rights that shoemakers,

doctors or housewives are not equally entitled to demand. The claim of

society on bakers is just as much vitiated by irresponsibility as its

claim on poets. There are no corporate allegiances. All our politics are

atomised.

It is not that as artists we have deserted society. It has deserted or

ejected us, and we live on in contact with it as tenants whom the

landlord has not troubled to have thrown out. We have not seceded, but

in clinging to personality we sling to something which everyone knows is

the harbinger of death. They hate us for reminding them of it. They

burrow deeper into society to lose sight of the fact which towers over

them. Rather than face it, they become insane. Fascism is a refuge from

Death in death. And fascism epitomises the historical tendency of

barbarian society.

These are the necessary conclusions of an age in which a concept of

society and of the universe—I mean the Victorian-Liberal-bourgeois

concept, has collapsed. To describe them as obscurantist or a ‘failure

of nerve’ contributes little to their discussion. They are the almost

inevitable product of the time, and in practice they exercise everybody,

even Marxist writers who repudiate them and find it hard to sympathise

with ‘romantics’ who express them. They are far more a fact of social

history than a result of conscious thought.

Further, they represent the conscious or unconscious state of mind of an

entire generation of writers, both those who profess individualism and

those who reject it. They are manifestly not identical with the ideas

behind ‘Art for Art’s sake’—it would be far fairer to regard them as art

for responsibility’s sake. The generation which is influenced by such

ideas is certainly making no special claims for itself, either of

privilege or of insight. This set of ideas, this metaphysical and

political attitude, is an ideology, and that ideology is correctly

termed romanticism.

III

If this seems a cynical or a hysterical estimate of human society and of

an artist’s attitude to it, I feel that there is evidence, from what we

have seen of history in some ten years of increasing political

degeneration throughout societies whose barbarian revolution has taken

place, that it may be true. Perhaps the environment was a very

unfavourable one. I have lived only in a social system generally

admitted to be at the end of its tether. I belong to a generation

brought up in the certainty that it would be killed in action on behalf

of an unreality against an insanity. But war is not a special case. The

English public is madder now than in 1938—it kills and tortures with as

little scruple as its enemies did them—but war is only an aggravation of

barbarism. The shock effect of such ideas as I have expressed is present

only to people who, like the American and Fjiglish artists of the

present day, are politically and humanly semi-adult. The Chinese, the

peasants of Europe, the peasants of sixteenth-century England, artists

like Brueghel and Shelley, would not require their formulation. They

would find them too obvious to require stating. Of course the artist is

a responsible individual. It is only the artist who is recovering from a

period of dehumanised Victorianism or industrialism who needs to be

reminded of them. Brueghel, unlike the intellectuals of classicism,

would not have been surprised and disoriented because obedient citizens

massacred Jews or Germans, because the Japanese raided Pearl Harbour.

These ideas are part of the humanity which we re-learn in becoming

romantics. However, the romantic is certainly obliged to face the

criticism that he denounces other people’s doings when he cannot say

what principles guide his own actions. I say emphatically that war is

wrong, and do not know why I say it. The position is illogical, but I

see no way out. I cannot give so many reasons for believing any one

action to be wrong as I can give for believing a work of art to be bad.

Yet as I am confident that aesthetics are real, and find myself obliged

to act accordingly, so in the field of ethics I must act on some of the

convictions that compose humanity. The only coherent ethic is that of

responsible humaneness. I believe, therefore, in reason against

insanity, in responsibility against barbarism. A society of

irresponsible, obedient citizens to my mind is as morally null as it is

historically doomed. The ethic of romanticism is an ethic derived

entirely from man, and for the artist and the scientist, concerned with

humanity and nothing else, it is true and coherent. Apart from human

beings, neither ‘goodness’ nor ‘beauty’ have any absolute significance.

They are human things and the seeking of them is a human obligation. The

romantic launches his protest and bases his conduct upon an ethic, an

agathistic utilitarianism, which he finds in the alliance for mutual aid

of all human beings against a universe which does not exist for their

comfort nor share their aspirations.

Perhaps the most important factor which has led to the widespread

acceptance of romanticism today is that it offers an adequate

explanation of contemporary Western society and has shown itself capable

of predicting accurately the future course of that society. Man’s only

weapon against the anarchy of the universe is his civilisation, the

responsible adoption of each individual of his social rights and duties.

The growth of Western society has been coterminous with the gradual

passage of these functions of justice, law, mutual aid and creative work

out of the hands of individuals and into the hands of professional

exponents, but never until the total unhinging of the whole system of

individual civilisation by the Industrial Revolution had the ascendancy

of barbarism been absolute, and the existence of a public possessing no

single element of normal human activity or culture become widespread.

The megalopolitan pattern is irreversible, if any historical process is

irreversible, and it was possible to predict with accuracy the total

collapse of the megalopolitan communities and the survival only of such

groups as were able or could become able to revert to the practice of

mutual aid, as early as the beginning of the twentieth century. The only

persons from whom this process was concealed were the inevitable

progress party, who required yet another demonstration of the

inevitability of post-revolutionary tyranny inherent in any revolution

which retains the concept of centralised power. They have had that

demonstration in France, in Russia, in Germany. Romanticism is fully

vindicated as a theory of life, and its offspring anarchism as a theory

of politics, by the only valid arbiter, the historical event.

Romanticism postulates the alliance of all human beings against the

hostility of the universe, and against power, which is the attempt to

push off the burden of personal responsibility on to other shoulders.

Both biologically and historically, it is a wholly realistic view. It

comprises no conclusion which is reached by any process save the

examination of human experience and observation, and the anger of the

classicists against it is based entirely upon the romantic rejection

both of the wholly illusory ideas of historical and inevitable progress

and of the implicit metaphysical assumption that human ideals have some

unexplained entity, in a psychological vacuum called ‘ultimate

reality’—the ideals to which the most hardened dialectical materialist

unconsciously appeal when he talks about ‘social justice’.

Even more urgently romanticism rejects the form of social order in which

human responsibilities are curtailed, to a point at which none of the

conceptions which constitute justice or freedom retain any meaning save

that which the stateholders confer on them, the condition of society in

which we now live, and which is correctly termed barbarism. With the

moral extinction of Christianity, romanticism remains the only ideology

which has a coherent system of moral judgments on which it can rely, and

because its morals and its sociology, its conception of human need and

of human duty, coincide and have a common historic and scientific

origin, it can confidently predict the self-destruction of every

barbarian order.

The failure of nerve which the writers of Partisan Review deplore on

ideological grounds is no more a failure of nerve on the part of the

artist than a bad prognosis is a failure of nerve on the part of the

doctor. Western civilisation is not moribund as a result of the failure

of its social organisation; it is far more probably moribund through the

failure of the individual to assert his resistance to organisation of an

irresponsible kind, and through a sort of natural decay which seems to

afflict civilisations much as mortality afflicts individuals. I find it

difficult to decide what it is that makes a ‘civilisation’, but one

anthropological essential is a group ethic in which the individual

retains his responsibility. Renan, a cynic would say, may well have been

right in doubting whether, in the absence of some form of theocratic

supernaturalism, however untrue, civilisations can remain coherent at

all. Marxist historians point to the decay of the medieval theology and

its successor, Victorian evangelicalism, as symptoms of the dialectical

decay of medieval feudalism and Victorian capitalism—it is probably more

true to say that the collapse of economic organisation and the collapse

of bodies of belief and thought were parallel phenomena, determined by

some third factor, the semi-organic process, through its rise and decay,

of a complete civilisation.

Because romanticism has always been aware of the tragic aspects of human

life, it has always tended to preach personalism, to base its ideology

on direct responsibility and upon political anarchism. The romantic

awareness of Death and the romantic awareness of personal human

responsibility are indissolubly united. The political component results

from the metaphysical. Because we are all in the same boat, therefore we

are inevitably responsible to one another, as if we were afloat on the

same raft. In those same periods of social expansion when the

‘progressive’ aspects of society are uppermost, it is hard enough for

the artist to recognise that he is ultimately the enemy of society, but

in a disintegrative phase such as the present the necessity for

accepting the role of masterless men, in the face of ‘total war’ and

total society, has been sprung on writers totally unprepared to grapple

with it. The technical complexity of contemporary barbarism has produced

a genuine loss of nerve among ex-classicists who have become dependent

on it, and argue that while totalitarianism is manifestly loathsome,

society is the giver of town-drainage and safe appendectomy as well as

of mass raids on Hamburg and massacres in Poland. The romantic view is

now what it has always been—that in dealing with acephalous societies

one is perpetually at sea with Captain Bligh—when he orders the taking

in of sail, he is obeyed with perfect discipline; when he orders us to

flog a man, not a soul stirs. That is the lesson of responsibility which

the peasant and the experienced human being know. The industrial

abolition of humanity only obscured a conception which would have a

universal assent in any responsible community. It is the rediscovery of

the beastliness of which obedient citizens, educated in the Western

virtues of citizenship, are capable, which has so utterly overturned

this generation. The Victorians had forgotten Death—it was swallowed up

in Victory—and their excesses were removed to parts of the globe where

they were inconspicuous to the artist. The lunacy of obedience played

itself out on distant frontiers under the anaesthetic of an evangelical

Christianity.

It was upon our generation that the decision was forced. Either we had

to evade it by pleading some sort of artistic immunity (and thereby

cease to be human beings), with the likelihood that even such a plea

would not go down with the total society (I can see somebody getting his

ticket from the German Army because he was an artist), or by cynical

co-operation of the Ehrenburg-McLeish-Suarez brand, which might at least

save our skins; or, we must face the choice between becoming good

citizens and accepting our role as human beings and masterless men.

I say that to the Chinese or to the peasants of Europe or of Ireland,

more adult in humanity than most American or English artists, these

things would have been obvious, and no such choice would have presented

itself. But when the acceptance of the romantic attitude is

characterised as a failure of nerve, it means that to apologise for it I

must return to first principles. The romantic ideology of responsible

disobedience is as much the logical produce of this age as responsible

Christianity was the product of praetorian Imperial Rome. We are

romantics because we have grown up romantics, and because we are human

beings. In romanticism, art and science join hands, because both take

the side of man against the compulsions of his environment, against

Death, against power.

IV

I have described romanticism sympathetically, but not because I fail to

see its fallacies. The classicist is running the perpetual risk of

forfeiting his responsibility—the romantic of forfeiting his sanity. He

is performing a continual tightrope walk over a series of intellectual

abysses, of self-pity, self-dramatisation, mysticism, conversion to

Roman Catholicism, acquiescence in political reaction, or pathological

despair. The danger of such a collapse is greatest when the romantic

ideology is thrown up half-consciously by a semi-emotional sense of

impending social disaster, just as revolutionary classicism is at its

most irresponsible when it comes into violent conflict with historical

and sociological fact. But we are no more entitled to denounce

romanticism in terms of romantics who have lost their nerve than we are

entitled to abolish coal gas because some persons use it as a means of

suicide. Every idea and every ideology carries in itself the potential

destruction of its adherents. The prediction that a social order is

bound to destroy itself, while it is an unnerving conclusion, is no more

a loss of nerve in itself than the conclusion upon scientific

observation or common experience that a man is likely to die or a

volcano to erupt. It is in the consciousness of common humanity and the

retention of this wholly scientific conception of history that the

validity of romanticism persists.

Because of these two provisos, romanticism today is not a destructive or

a defeatist force. Its adherents in the sociological field predict the

destruction of megalopolitan societies as a historical probability, and

for that reason they tend to concentrate their practical activity in the

cultivation of mutual aid, direct action, and the other communal

activities which are the basis of culture, and in terms of which human

life will survive. Such activity is essential, whether the destruction

of barbarism occurs violently in mass air raids or by consent—those who

predict violent disintegration on historical grounds have to remember

that there is no such thing as inevitability in any historical process:

they are dealing with probabilities, nothing more. Other factors than

war or civil violence may operate to terminate the barbarian phase, and

the resuscitation of mutual aid, personal responsibility and direct

action, the three criteria of a civilised community, may occur by some

form of political consent. There are also a good many historical

examples of barbarian states surviving in an extended form, in which

culture passes into a state of suspended animation: Rome underwent such

a period between AD 70 and the final and gradual disintegration of

Imperial barbarism: this alternative, the prolongation of servile

barbarism by consent in the Western and American states, is a more

menacing one for human culture than the prospect of the breakdown of

megalopolitanisms by direct violence. It can be combated only by the

encouragement of autonomous civilised activities from within—activities

which deny the validity of the barbarian political system.

A few years ago, my immediate predecessors were chiefly influenced by

the concept of the class war. I believe that the concept, as a force for

progress, has outlived its truth (not because it was, in the first

place, false—nobody in his senses could deny that it was and is an

historical event) and become a partial truth only. We are beginning to

see that ‘classless’ societies can be as preposterous in their demands

on the individual conscience as any others, and as heavily impregnated

with barbarism. Where they have succeeded, it is because they have

permitted the fragmentation of the state into individuals, civilised by

mutual aid. Where they have not permitted it, they have become more

tyrannical than the manifestly unjust societies that went before. The

war is not between classes. The war is at root between individuals and

barbarian society. The beginnings of every revolutionary movement show

stages—the first, when it moves forward to overthrow a society whose

demands on the individual are insane, being itself a free association of

individuals; the second, when it stands still, and a Leviathan acquires

a body; the third, when Leviathan becomes Frankenstein and the fitting

object for a fresh revolution. Revolution is not a single act, it is an

unending process based upon civil disobedience. The demands become

increasingly exorbitant, abstract notions of solidarity are made

concrete, a state is invested with powers and properties, centralisation

inflates the vices of individual leaders to titanic proportions, and

once again it preys on its individual members, with or without their

consent. It is with this whole idea of society as a super-person that

responsibility is at war, and class struggles are superseded by this

struggle.

Certainly, this struggle, the relevant struggle, is overlapped by

others—the class war, the European war. Many participants in fact remain

participants through confusion of the two struggles. A good many of the

dynamitards and secret journalists of Europe will resume their weapons

against whatever carpet-bag state the Allies install. A good many

communists—like the Old Guard—will be forced to continue their war

against the classless state if they get it. The most discouraging thing

is to see sincere people who appreciate the nature of society mistaking

one struggle for the other. The war for freedom is the war against

society. There is no other enemy.

And for those who can see the present war as a struggle for human

freedom, I can only say that that is what they are fighting for but not

what they will get. In a rigged society the scenery can be so skilfully

changed. The obviously right course of action can be doggedly pursued

until with the collapse of the stage scenery its true enormity appears.

The people are the only victims and the only losers. Whoever wins it

will not be they, and whatever results it will not be freedom. We are

sitting now and awaiting the swindle.

What are we to teach the people? As writers and artists we cannot avoid

teaching them. In all wars we are neutral, not because we ignore

wrongdoing, but because as individuals we must apply identical standards

to the actions of both sides. Acquiescence in the murder of the

population of Lidice is as evil as acquiescence in the murder of the

population of Hamburg. We cannot be bothered with the interminable

nonsense of causes and nations, because we know it to be fraudulent. It

is a waste of breath to argue the intentions of the Allies or the

Germans, the superiority of one set of professions over another, because

both are fictitious—the electric hares that neither we, nor any other

people that follow them, will ever be permitted to catch. Military

action is a part of barbarism, and as such it cannot salvage

civilisation. The ‘obviously righf cause is so only because of the stage

scenery which has been set up by society. Only people matter to us. When

Diamond was fighting Capone, he missed a golden chance. He should have

raised a citizen army to support him, on the ground that he only robbed

while Capone cut throats: he should have denounced non-participants for

acquiescing in murder. Our pity extents to every individual who is the

victim of history—the persecuted Jews, the persecuted Indians. Stripes

are red whatever back they are upon. We are neutral not because we feel

too little of evil, but because we feel too much. At every move we make

to assist a sufferer, crash goes our foot in an equally innocent face.

To say ‘all peoples are our friends, all societies are our enemies’ is

not as foolish as it sounds. We will say it.

As we look at Europe today, we cannot see it as writers of the thirties

saw it. We do not see it as a clear-cut issue between progress and

reaction. We see defrauded and deluded peoples engaged in utterly

purposeless destruction, because the objects for which they fight are

unreal hopes dangled in front of their noses by the respective

governments of their countries. Because these peoples have abrogated

their right to employ their intelligence and have agreed to act as Good

Citizens, their sincerity and self-sacrifice count for absolutely

nothing. (There is an equal sincerity and an equal self-sacrifice on

both sides, exploited for diametrically opposite but equally fraudulent

objects.)

The barbarian citizen, fascist or democratic, has delegated his culture

to professional artists, his coition to professional film stars, his

juridical duties to professional policemen, his civic rights to

professional politicians. He remains alone with idleness, and the last

human attribute, Death. For him all wars are irrelevant unless they

destroy the mechanism of delegation and leave him a human being again,

faced with the necessity for mutual aid.

I have referred to stage scenery. The young man of my own generation was

pushed by society on to a stage where certain events were being enacted,

shown the villain, and instructed to choose between shooting him and

being shot. Now in the circumstances of the play, and assuming all the

conventions of melodrama, there was only one right course of action, but

no sooner has one pursued it, for a year or a scene, than down comes the

scenery and a fresh set-up, a fresh set of conventions appears, and one

is told, ‘now do your obvious duty’ (which has become the direct

opposite of what it was in Scene I, because the villain has been altered

and several of the heroes have gone to the bad). And some of us have

made up our minds that we will no longer be party to a bloodstained and

fraudulent charade in which the weapons are loaded and the helpless

audience are the only victims. We reject the dramatic conventions. From

now on we will be concerned with people, not conjuring tricks.

But what are we to make of our subject? Europe stinks of blood and

groans with separation. What are we to make of a world where disablement

and sickness are priceless possessions, as sort of passport to life? How

many wives would buy a game leg or a hunchback for their husbands—how

many mothers for their sons? I was present at a strange celebration. We

sat round a table drinking to a young man’s future. A week before the

house had been in mourning as if he were already dead. He was reaching

his eighteenth birthday, when one chooses between a butcher’s life and a

sheep’s death. The papers had come. During the day he fell into his

machine at work. One of his legs became shorter than the other. It was

as though he had been given a paper certifying: ‘This man is out of the

hands of the Lunatics. If he looks sharp and is lucky, he may form a

cell for himself into which the gangs of Good Citizens, who patrol the

world looking for people to educate by cutting their windpipes, may fail

to break’.

That, until the fall of barbarism at its own hands, is how Freedom

comes.

I say all this, because I believe that in essence art is the act of

standing aside from society, with certain important qualifications. (I

ask my critics to abstain from quoting this until they have heard the

rest of the story.) Herbert Read has pointed out that in truly free

communities art is a general activity, far more cognate with craft than

it can ever be in contemporary organised life, and he consigns the

professional artist to his father the devil. I accept the proposition:

it seems to be merely another statement of the hostility between

barbarism and humanity which I have described. A state of affairs in

which art could become a part of all daily activity, and in which all

activity was potentially creative, would be a free community, and not a

society—that is, a personified body treated as though it were an entity

in itself—of the kind I have attacked. Art, when it is professionalised,

consists in standing aside.

But it is essential that there should be no bitterness in the action. It

may take any form, from the pure escape of decoration to the analysis of

dreams and impulses in the myth, and to the most savage denunciation.

But there must be no bitterness against humanity, or the artist defeats

his own end. Neither must there be an attitude of superiority. He has

absolutely no right to claim exemptions or privileges except in his

capacity as a human being. The artist employs his form as the voice of a

great multitude. It is only through the vicarious activity of creation

that the great multitude ever finds a voice. Every creative activity

speaks on behalf of utterly voiceless victims of society and

circumstance, of everyone, finally, since man is always at some time the

victim of his environment: and since they have undergone the supreme

indignity, on behalf of the dead. The artist in barbarian society is the

only true representative of the people.

That is what I mean by saying that the essence of romanticism is the

acceptance of a sense of tragedy. All creative work speaks on behalf of

somebody who would otherwise be voiceless, even the decoration of the

potter who protests against the monotony of his work. I am always

conscious of these submerged voices, as much in the tentative and

nervous forms of early expression—savage and childhood productions, bad

derivative art produced, under civilised conditions, by people striving

to express themselves—as in the technically professional work of the

great ages of painting. No creative activity is free from the sense of

protest. It is the sole way open to man of protesting against his

destiny.

In the actual circumstances of contemporary writing, the standing aside

must take different forms, though if it involves bitterness, hatred, a

sense of moral and aesthetic superiority, or any form of ivory-towerism,

it defeats itself. On the one hand, one can and must stand aside, though

one can at the same time admire the scale and tragic quality of an

event, or the courage which has gone to make an achievement. Anyone who

is not deeply moved by events is probably not capable of creation. There

is not the smallest reason why a poet should not write odes to the

Russian Revolution or the Dneiper Dam if these subjects move him, and

represent the message which, on behalf of some of the submerged voices,

he is attempting to interpret, any more than there is a reason why he

should not hate a tyrant or drive a concrete-mixer. But the poetry is

subsequent to the fact that whoever writes it has already stood far

enough away from his subject to be able to see it in reasonable and

historical proportion. It is the right to do this, even in a community

whose ideals inspire sympathy, that is utterly fundamental to good

writing, and it is precisely this right which contemporary society is

unanimous in denying. When it comes to the interpretation of the war,

both publics and their leaders realise, consciously or unconsciously,

that there is no more serious threat to the will to continue fighting

than the existence of a body of objective art. It requires to be

explained away, blackguarded into silence, conscripted, or ignored,

according to the methods in vogue in the society concerned. But it

continues to exist. The right to stand aside is contested everywhere.

Leaders who have acclaimed the work of a particular artist because he

denounced their opponents are exasperated to find that the denunciatory

criticism extends to themselves.

And on the other hand there is the essential prerequisite on which all

romantic theory is founded—the community of the artist with his fellow

men: in other words, his humanity. He must cater for the need to stand

aside by regarding all movements and societies neutrally, not in that he

refuses to judge them at all, but that he judges them on the same basis.

He cannot afford to have in his bag divers weights—that is one of the

traits of civic lunacy. The artist’s isolation and humanity are no

different from the isolation and humanity of other responsible

people—isolation from barbarism, solidarity with other human beings. It

is a tribute to English letters that in a period of almost unparalleled

national insanity England should have produced Trevelyan’s Social

History. This is the history of the relationships and the experience

from which there is no standing aside, the story of humanity in its

incessant war with society. If the artist is to take the side of man, he

is fulfilling both his duties of isolation and humanity.

I disagree with the idea that the artist is primarily the interpreter of

the symptoms and processes of economic change—to follow Caudwell’s

conception is to limit the number of levels on which art could or should

exist. The unit with which the artist is concerned is first of all the

individual human being. The romantic artist sees him exactly as the

physician sees him—an individual who shares his organs and a high

proportion of his psychological make-up with every individual who has

existed within historical time, and with the artist himself. Like the

physician, the artist is one of humanity, subject to every branch of

human experience, from politics to death, but possessing by virtue of

his talent the faculty which the physician acquires through training, of

elucidating, interpreting, assisting. His sensibility corresponds to the

physician’s medical training—consciously or unconsciously he is aware of

the individual’s position and of the roots in anthropology, psychology

and evolution which make up humanness. He is neither a superman nor a

privileged person, any more than the physician is. It is with this

quality of humanness that the romantic is primarily concerned—it is the

origin of the romantic sympathy, the concept of shared, responsible

experience, and of man as the product and victim of environment, which

makes romanticism and defines it. In addition to this prerequisite

consciousness, there is the technical mastery, learned or acquired,

which is needed to express it. One might almost continue the analogy and

say that classicism bears some resemblance to operative surgery—there is

the same emphasis on technical virtuosity and the same preoccupation

with intervention rather than with organic process. To the artist as a

human being, and to the physician in his practice, the sense of

continuity of circumstances and difference of environment are

perpetually present the human being and the patient, for the purposes of

art and medicine, are fundamental constants. There is no difference

between Hagesichora and any other young girl dancing, between the

Homeric warriors and any other soldier—you cannot tell whether the man

under the theatre towels is a Nazi or an anarchist; that aspect of his

existence concerns you very little—you are interested in him as a man.

The neutrality of medicine has survived this war well. The neutrality of

romantic art will also survive it, because it is based on the far larger

community of man, which society tends to destroy, which one finds only

in London’s slums or America’s prisons. It seems to me that it is this

university in art which Marxist classicism misses, just as in the

political sphere it does not extend ‘working class solidarity’ into the

responsible and anti-authoritarian conception of human solidarity. It is

the extension of this evaluation of man into politics which makes up

anarchism, and the common foundation of anarchism and romanticism

renders them inseparable in the evolution of art, just as medicine as a

practice, if we are to oppose it to the technical vetinary surgery of

such people as army psychologists, whose aim is something other than

plain human welfare, is inseparable from a similar human neutrality.

The value of Marxist criticism has lain, however, in its perpetual

emphasis on the environmental concern of the artist. Once fortified with

this conception of humanity and his knowledge that he is a part of it,

not an observer, the artist is under obligation to concern himself with

the entire environment of the times, both by interpreting it and by

modifying it. Writers who are afraid to throw their weight into the

cause of the humanity they recognise will find little in the tradition

of romanticism to support their abstention. This criticism is valuable

in itself, but at present is pretty consistently directed against the

wrong people. It is the concept of irresponsible society, whatever its

social organisation, that is now and always has been the enemy of the

romantic conception of man, and in a period of disintegration, with

irresponsibility at a premium, the artist who reflects and interprets is

accused of decadence, and the artist who advocates responsibility is

accused of disruption. I cannot see an iota of difference between the

attacks of sycophants and clowns who propagate a theory of cultural

bolshevism (that Joyce and Proust were responsible for the fall of

France, for instance) and those of the political actives who charge

romantic individualism with losing its nerve. They are both imitating

the man who smashes the barometer because it points to rain.

VI

This characteristic phase of a collapsing culture is very obvious in

England and America at present. It merits further discussion. The stupid

and illiterate attacks of Alfred Noyes on Proust, the venom with which

bourgeois formalism has been denounced by the communists, and the

suppression of the work of Klee by the Nazis, had this in common they

were all attacks upon images of disintegration by people who feared the

disintegration itself and could not see its cause. Some of them were the

product of mere personal or political malice. Yet there remains a valid

ground for attack, upon purely disintegrative and analytic forms such as

surrealism—they are not fully human. The real treason lies not in

reflecting disintegration but in failing to reflect anything else.

There is still confusion of mind among the enemies of disintegration who

have rather more grasp on its causes than the dealers in cultural

bolshevism. Perhaps the most striking instance of this confusion is to

be found in their attempts to defend art. I have in mind the pamphlets

and counter-pamphlets of 1943–44: it is the nearness of the

disintegration which upsets them, precisely as it has upset and unnerved

the poets.

The right-wing critic can see that the pretensions of artists of the

disintegrative school to be immune from the collapse by virtue of their

function as artists are preposterous: he can see that the common

individual, who retains his humanity in the face of everything, is

sound, but he rushes to identify the Cause of Man with the Cause of

Humanity sponsored by the Daily Telegraph. The aristocrat can see that

the war is a fraud, but pins the blame on the anti-cultural bias of the

masses. This controversy is conducted in the same historical Wonderland

as that of A.L. Rowse, who prophesies a ‘new Elizabethan age’—a remark

historically equivalent to predicting a new Secession of the Plebs in

the reign of Nero, or a new set of milk-teeth in a centenarian.

Yet there is a real failure of nerve in the manuscripts which 1944

brought in to every English poetry magazine, in which the sole images

present are images of disintegration—one reads of nothing else: it is

the schizophrenia of writers who are unable to cut themselves off from

the collapse of society, because to do so would involve them in an adult

awareness of humanity, including an awareness of death. Partisan Review

and Horizon are full of the praises of schizophrenia. The failure of

nerve is common to the people who attack it, if one excludes the

sycophants and the congenital idiots, and a great many of the people

they are attacking. The romantic wholeness involves a good deal more

than the passive acceptance of collapse—there is also the assertion of

responsibility to one’s fellows, and the exhortation to disobey the

irresponsible directives of barbarism. I think that the best example of

this wholeness in the face of barbarism is Brueghel. The disquietening

images of disintegration are there—Mumford selects him as the symbolic

exponent of the medieval collapse—but one feels that the artist has no

share in them. It is not he who is disintegrating but the society whose

irresponsibility he hates—the society of expressionless unanimous

skeletons, the forest of lances that supports Herod. The humanity of

Herod’s soldiers is stressed as much as their unanimity. These are the

lunatics, but at home they are also peasants. The victims and killers

are interchangeable. The subject of each of these masterpieces is an

aspect of the romantic struggle of Man against his environmental

enemies, the fully human Man who is shown us with his physical and

mental equipment of faults and virtues in the ‘peasant’ pictures. The

Triumph of Death, the Massacre of the Innocents, Man against Obedience,

Man against Death. If we cannot win the second battle we can at least

win the first.

Accordingly, we apply the same standards to every cause or body which

presents itself, without owing allegiance to any of them. We recognise

boundless responsibility to men, especially to all those who are

deprived of their voices, but ultimately to all men, since they will in

time become silent. We must demand the right to secession as the one

square foot of ground which is solid and from which we can look and

interpret the gigantic chaos of human existence. We are learning

ourselves to live in the structure of insane societies while defying

them, practising to retain our lives as if we were really sane men in an

asylum where all individuals were allies and all bodies were bent on

killing us, and we teach others, as far as we can, to do likewise.

The weak are inheriting the earth, though we are forced to fight, plot,

deceive for every inch of the legacy. They are taxed, killed,

frightened, conscripted, swindled, interned, collectively; the gangs of

good citizens drive them like sheep, they are dragged from their

standing ground by the innumerable pressure of the flood around them,

and the ranks of Bedlamite citizenship are recruited from them. They

inherit by default, like small animals inhabiting the floor of a forest,

and dying off like flies, but they strike back ineffectually and, by

sheer weight of numbers, invincibly. Their aggregate intervals of sanity

suffice to overthrow the entire edifice of society which has been built

on their backs and out of their flesh. Their sane moments are ultimately

decisive. Their clinging among the wreckage to mutual aid perpetuates

civilisation. In the ultimate explosion of the barbarism structure,

islets of true civilisation, the nuclei of future cultures which have

still their upward cycle to run, persist and grow. Then in a decade or

two they begin like coral insects to construct a new load for their

backs. But all of them are ready now and again, in the time of

barbarism, to assert their personality from time to time. The woman who

fails to fuse a shell securely, the clerk who does not look a second

time at a pass, the girl who hides a deserter and the idiot who

misdirects an escort, whatever their nationality, are acting as members

and soldiers of the community of the weak, the greatest conspiracy in

history, which is ceaseless. It is quite irrelevant that at the next

moment they are killing Jews, bombing cities, supporting Jacks-in office

and believing lies. At times every one of them has struck a minor blow

for personality. It is to these people that art owes a responsibility

which is hard to measure. Among modern writers one feels that only

Arnold Zweig and Giono have achieved it continuously, and some reports

suggest that the German occupation has disorientated even Giono.

It is rare that a free community of such people can come into existence.

One finds islands of community which have escaped the curse of

personified societies scattered everywhere—the shelters during the air

raids, the Cossack villages, some primitive tribes, prisoners in Dachau

or Huyton, the Russian collective farms. These are the largest

communities in which anarchism is real and the standing aside

preliminary to creation is not resented to the same degree as in the

societies of clockfaces, whose sole virtue is their unanimity in error.

This virtue is a virtue of death. They do not escape death by evading it

in the renunciation of life. It is not for nothing that Brueghel’s

skeletons have all the same faces. And artistic responsibility consists

in taking all this upon our shoulders—in providing voices for all those

who have not voices. The romantic ideology of art is the ideology of

that responsibility, a responsibility borne out of a sense of

victimhood, of community in a hostile universe, and destined like

Prometheus, its central creation, to be the perpetual advocate and

defender of Man against Barbarism, community against irresponsibility,

life against homicidal and suicidal obedience.

---

(Art and Social Responsibility: Lectures on the Ideology of Romanticism,

Falcon Press, 1946)

[1]

1942.

[2] I am surprised that Fromm (The Fear of Freedom) and other

psychologists do not make more of this. The fear of death is probably at

root the fear of isolation, rather than of a cessation of experience.

Total isolation is reached only in ‘deteriorated’ schizophrenia and in

death, but one of the chief artistic grounds for attacking contemporary

societies is that they produce a false sense of community while, in

reality, they destroy the individual’s true relation with his fellows

and substitute a relationship to a fictitious dummy, the Group.

[3] Singularly enough, some critics again attempt to depict this view as

a form of religious mysticism, largely because it uses the term ‘human

nature’ and discusses the relationship of man to the Universe. Except in

so far as philosophical pessimism is a ‘religion’, it is difficult to

see in what way a romantic interpretation of history is any more

‘religious’ than a marxist of physiochemical interpretation. It

certainly rejects every form of supernaturalism. As to Whitehead’s

conception of romanticism as a revolt against science, the romantic

conception of metaphysics and politics is constituted in the same way as

any scientific hypothesis—by reference to the observed facts of history

or of psychology. Its interpretation may be fallible, but its method is

surely above reproach, even from the rationalists, whose notion of the

economic reform of society has no historical evidence to support it. I

would have placed the romantic awareness high in the list of causes of

scientific progress.

[4] In view of criticisms which have been made of this remark, it needs

qualifying. I do not say that all groups are bad, any more than I say

that because all men have stomachs they are dyspeptics. The tendency to

degenerate into irresponsibility is inherent in every group, once its

members cease to act as individuals, and transfer their responsibility

from their fellow men to the group. Where I use the word ‘society’ in a

derogatory sense, I mean a society in which this change for the worse

has taken place.

[5] Lewis Mumford, Culture of Cities, IV, 9, page 256.