💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-social-ecology-and-communalism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:33:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Social Ecology and Communalism
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 2006
Language: en
Topics: social ecology, communalism, libertarian municipalism, municipalism, post-anarchism, post-marxism
Source: http://new-compass.net/publications/social-ecology-and-communalism provided by New Compass.

Murray Bookchin

Social Ecology and Communalism

m-b-murray-bookchin-social-ecology-and-communalism-1.png Social Ecology

and Communalism Murray Bookchin social ecology, communalism, libertarian

municipalism, municipalism, post-anarchism, post-marxism 2006

PDF

provided by New Compass. en

An Introduction to Social Ecology and Communalism

We are standing at a crucial crossroads. Not only does the age-old

“social question” concerning the exploitation of human labor remain

unresolved, but the plundering of natural resources has reached a point

where humanity is also forced to politically deal with an “ecological

question.” Today, we have to make conscious choices about what direction

society should take, to properly meet these challenges.

At the same time, we see that our very ability to make the necessary

choices are being undermined by an incessant centralization of economic

and political power. Not only is there a process of centralization in

most modern nation states that divests humanity of any control over

social affairs, but power is also gradually being transferred to

transnational institutions.

Simultaneously, the elites governing the multinational corporations are

virtually given free rein to continue exploiting people as well as the

natural world, in a series of new “free trade” agreements that in turn

have provoked a range of popular protests. The last few years have also

witnessed, in the ongoing “War on Terror,” serious encroachments on a

range of civil rights that we, in the Western world, have come to take

for granted. So, at a time when the social and ecological crises are

intensified in breadth and scope, we find ourselves utterly

disempowered, and virtually stripped of possibilities to arrest and

reverse this destructive “development.”

None of the established political tendencies, no matter how “radical”

they claim to be, seem to be able to counter these processes.

One after another, the European Social Democratic parties, not to speak

of the once so promising Green tendencies, have all lowered their

banners and come to accept the most pernicious market forces. Their

participation in national parliaments continuously hollows out their

expressed ideals. Not only has the traditional Left crumbled

ideologically with the collapse of the Eastern Bloc — which indeed is a

tragic irony — but today, there exists no real extraparliamentary

movement, with the will and ability to foster and advance an alternative

politics. No left libertarian movement has yet emerged that could make

use of the vast opportunities that opened up as “Real Existing

Socialism” ceased to exist. The great hopes that were nurtured by the

many new social movements which emerged in the twentieth century have

all but faded away, and where the radical Left has not simply “melted

into air,” it has become highly confused. This is a trend that echoes

throughout the world, and, despite the recent resurgence of protest

movements, there are still no visible tendencies which advance practical

and credible alternative directions to the destructive tracks we are on.

If we are not able to intelligently respond to these challenges, it is

clear that popular discontents will be channeled through the Right

instead, as we indeed witness in many industrialized countries today —

notably the disconcerting growth of religious fundamentalisms. Inasmuch

as there exists no clear and principled Left radicalism, the

conservatives and the reactionaries can set the political agenda, and as

a result, the whole political spectrum has tilted markedly toward the

Right. The current political climate is itself a reason to be concerned,

as there is an urgent need to find political alternatives that can

seriously deal with the social and ecological crisis in which we find

ourselves. We have to open up a debate and clarify the basic theoretical

issues at stake, before we can carve out a possible Left agenda suited

for our time. It is in this quest for political alternatives that we

turn to the radical theorist Murray Bookchin.

This book is a collection of essays written by Bookchin, a man who

dedicated his whole life to seeking rational alternatives to capitalist

society. Bookchin was born in January 1921, in New York City to

Jewish-Russian immigrants. His grandparents had been members of the

Socialist Revolutionary Party of Russia, and fled the country in the

wake of the failed revolution of 1905. In the working class

neighborhoods of the Bronx, Bookchin’s childhood and youth were strongly

marked by the hopeful enthusiasm that followed in the aftermath of the

October revolution of 1917. As America entered headlong into the Great

Depression, Bookchin got in touch with the radical organizations

agitating in his New York neighborhood, and quickly he became very

politically active.

This marked the beginning of a long life dedicated to the cause of

social freedom.

Because of his family’s economic situation, Bookchin had to start

working at an early age, and got involved in the activities of the trade

union movement. In the thirties, he was a member of the various

organizations spawned by the Communist Party, acting as an agitator,

organizer and study leader, although he gradually became strongly

critical of many of its policies. Already by the outbreak of the Spanish

Revolution, he broke with the Communists, mainly because of their

Popular Front strategy (notoriously the Stalinist betrayal of the

Spanish working class). He then became involved in the Trotskyist

movement — while Trotsky was still alive — and wrote his first articles

for dissident Left groups. After the Second World War, he gravitated

more and more toward a libertarian socialism, and started reevaluating

the basic premises and the logical conclusions of conventional radical

theory.

Bookchin was an untiring activist and theorist in most of the

significant radical movements that emerged after the Second World War.

He was in the worker’s movement while it was still truly radical, and

was active as a shop steward and a strike leader. He was one of the

definitive pioneers of ecological thought, and participated in the

environmental movement from its tentative inception in the 1950s.

Bookchin was also a part of the Civil Rights Movement, the anti- nuclear

movement, involved with Students for a Democratic Society, and a series

of urban development projects. He was very engaged in efforts to develop

neo-anarchist ideas, groups and projects. Later on he became heavily

involved in the emergence of the Greens, and was active in local issues

and electoral campaigns in his home town, Burlington, Vermont. It was

only in the last few years that physical infirmities impeded him from

taking part in active politics, and relegated him to the writer’s desk.

Indeed, it is probably for his theoretical contributions Bookchin is

most well-known and valued.

Bookchin published more than twenty books, and a wide range of articles,

lectures and essays, and his work has been translated into many

different languages. His writings have encompassed a great variety of

subject matters, including history, anthropology, philosophy, science,

and technology, as well as culture and social organization. Still, it is

his treatment of ecological and political issues that has made Bookchin

known to most readers, and some of his older books, notably

Post-Scarcity Anarchism, Toward an Ecological Society, and The Ecology

of Freedom, have been sources of inspiration for several generations of

radicals.

Murray Bookchin experienced many radical movements in his lifetime, and

had a relationship to all the major radical ideological trends of the

last century. Still, he managed to hammer out a unique political

philosophy that attempts to build on the best in these traditions. The

purpose of his work was to renew radical theory so that it maintains its

best principles and draws lessons from a broad spectrum of historical

experiences, while being adapted to new issues and challenges.

Although by no means his first relevant work, it was with his 1964

essay, “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought” that Bookchin started to

define the outlines of the body of ideas he called social ecology — a

theory that was to be more fully developed in books like The Ecology of

Freedom, Remaking Society, The Philosophy of Social Ecology, and

Re-enchanting Humanity. In 1971, his “Spring Offensives and Summer

Vacations” was hinting at a libertarian municipalist approach, that

later was carved out in the pages of The Limits of the City, and

particularly in From Urbanization to Cities, as well as in a series of

shorter essays. His historical writings have recently culminated in his

massive history of revolutionary popular movements — the four-volume The

Third Revolution (1996–2005).

For more than four decades, the theory of social ecology has been

continually nuanced and developed. For a rounded introduction to his

body of ideas, readers should turn to Janet Biehl’s excellent

presentation in The Murray Bookchin Reader.

The basic promise of social ecology is to re-harmonize the relationship

between society and nature, and to create a rational, ecological

society. Here Bookchin suggests a dialectical interpretation of human

history, culture, and natural evolution. By looking at humanity’s

potentialities for freedom and cooperation he argues that history itself

suggests to us, if only in a fragmented and incomplete form, how such a

rational future can and ought to be formed.

While Bookchin relied partly on the the theories of Karl Marx

(particularly his critique of capitalism), he saw the need to distance

himself from the Marxist tradition, of which he had been a part, in

order to clarify the liberatory content of his ideas. As an

anti-authoritarian and a libertarian socialist, he tried to build upon

the viable fragments of anarchism to create a rounded libertarian

complement to Marx’s ideas on the radical Left. In order to create a new

ecological body of thought, as well as a new politics, he used the words

“post-scarcity anarchism” to express the new transcendence his

perspective reflected of both libertarian and Marxian views. Still, he

gradually felt that the traditional radical orthodoxies inhibited the

logic of his ideas. After making great efforts at defending (and trying

to fill with meaning) variably an “anarchist-communism,” an

“eco-anarchism,” and “social anarchism” that maintained a coherency and

political radicalism, he came to a point where this project no longer

seemed feasible. The inherent flaws of anarchism became all the more

apparent as Bookchin studied the historical emergence of its basic ideas

and its various organized expressions: Not only had anarchism been

infected by current trends of nihilism and lifestyle approaches, it was

indeed a product of individualist and anti-social attitudes from its

very inception. He openly broke with anarchism at the second

International Conference on Libertarian Municipalism, in Vermont, 1999 —

and made it clear that his theory of social ecology had to be embodied

in the ideology he called Communalism.

This is not to say that the anarchist tradition did not provide a set of

sound sentiments, namely anti-statism, federalism, and self- management

(however naïvely they were formulated), but that they never made up a

coherent theoretical framework for radical social action. Accordingly,

Bookchin urged serious libertarians to transcend anarchism, along with

Marxism and other radical ideologies. It is necessary, he contended, to

create a new body of thought based on a coherent and revolutionary

social approach that integrates and goes beyond all traditional forms of

socialist radicalism. Indeed, vague libertarian ideals of popular self-

management, mutual aid, and a stateless community, are through

Bookchin’s social ecology, developed into aspects of a coherent

political theory, marked by direct democracy, municipalization, and

confederalism. This constitutes the political alternative that Bookchin

argued could confront the market economy and powerful centralized

institutions.

These political ideas have been developed over many decades, and are

based on both concrete lessons as well as the creative formulations of a

man who passionately dedicated his life to the radical movement, a

glowing passion that is clearly expressed in the essays here presented.

The purpose of this small collection of essays is to give a general

overview of Murray Bookchin’s fundamental ideas on social ecology and

Communalism. Of course four essays cannot replace the many books and

polemical essays written by Bookchin on these subjects, and this

collection is not meant as a substitute for a more thorough study of his

ideas. Still, these essays can indeed serve as a decent introduction for

serious readers, and give a good sense of the theoretical outlines of

Bookchin’s theoretical corpus.

The first essay, “What is Social Ecology?,” gives an important overview

of the basic theoretical tenets of social ecology. Here Bookchin offers

a developmental perspective on society and nature, explaining how

“second nature” (human culture) has developed out of “first nature”

(biological evolution), and showing that the very “idea of dominating

nature” is connected to the historical emergence of hierarchies, and

later to the breakthrough of capitalism. In order to create an

ecological society, Bookchin claimed, we have to confront and challenge

all hierarchical relationships, and ultimately abolish hierarchy as such

from the human condition.

The essay was originally published in an anthology edited by Michael

Zimmerman, Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical

Ecology (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1993), although it was

revised both in 1996 and 2001.

The second essay, “Radical Politics in an Era of Advanced Capitalism,”

appeared in Green Perspectives (#18, November 1989). The essay begins

with a critique of Marxism and its economistic class orientation, urging

radicals to understand the changing nature of capitalism. Bookchin urges

us to clarify the relationship between “society,” “politics,” and “the

state,” in order to develop an new radical ecological politics, by

expanding on the historical advances made by the public domain and the

city. It is, in my view, one of the clearest expressions of his proposal

for a new libertarian politics, insisting on the centrality of the

municipality and of confederalism. This essay was revised by Murray

Bookchin in 2001.

The third essay, “The Role of Social Ecology in a Period of Reaction,”

was written in 1995, when Bookchin had just finished writing

Re-enchanting Humanity. It makes very clear distinctions between social

ecology, and contemporary trends like “deep ecology,” mysticism,

anti-humanism, as well as postmodernist eclecticism and relativism. It

was first sent to an International Gathering of social ecologists in

Dunoon, Scotland, in August of that year, and it was subsequently

published as “Theses on Social Ecology in a Period of Reaction” in Green

Perspectives (# 33, October 1995).

In addition to many interesting comments on current cultural and

philosophical trends, Bookchin here places social ecology unequivocally

in the trajectory of the Enlightenment and its revolutionary offshoots,

and for those reasons I consider this essay particularly appropriate to

include in this anthology.

The final essay, “The Communalist Project,” is in my view the most

significant essay in this anthology, binding the other essays together

by defining a new outlook. Although an earlier version (that was to be

significantly revised and expanded) was circulated as “The Communalist

Moment,” this essay was first published in the journal Communalism (#2,

November, 2002). Bookchin details the need to go beyond all the

ideologies of the traditional Left, such as Marxism, anarchism, and

syndicalism, and create a new, coherent libertarian radicalism. He

explains the relationship between Communalism and libertarian

municipalism. This essay constitutes the best exposition to the extent

that Bookchin had shaken off all the “anarchist” trappings that were

formerly identified with his theories of social ecology. In fact, this

essay was initially published with an appendix on “Anarchism and Power

in the Spanish Revolution,” that criticizes anarchism for not having any

theory of power, and for not being able to deal with this important

question in real life politics. This appendix has been left out of this

collection for one reason: in these pages, I wanted to present only

general essays — essays which were neither considered too polemical nor

too specific — which would constitute a short book properly expressing

the main ideological aspects of Bookchin’s theoretical writings. (The

appendix is available at

www.communalism.org

, and will be published, along with other critiques of anarchism and

Marxism, in a forthcoming anthology presenting Bookchin’s recent

writings on Libertarian Municipalism.)

The red thread running through all these essays is the drive to

understand and explain the struggle for a rational society, and to

understand the necessary ideological underpinnings of a contemporary

radical politics. Although the essays included are very different in

focus and emphasis, I think that taken together, they convey the

ideological foundations of this political project, and its roots in the

rich and fecund theory of social ecology.

This book gives a highly accessible introduction to social ecology and

Communalism, as it has been developed by one of the most exciting and

pioneering thinkers of the twentieth century. Its purpose is to give a

general overview of Murray Bookchin’s ideas, and convey a sense of his

originality, by presenting some of his most central contributions to

radical theory. Despite Bookchin’s insistence that the ideas he proposed

are a product of revolutionary movements of the past, and of the ideals

of the Enlightenment, he nevertheless created a new and unique

synthesis. This political philosophy suggests that the solution to the

enormous social and ecological problems we face today, fundamentally lie

in the formation of a new citizenry, its empowerment through new

political institutions, and a new political culture. It is my profound

belief that Communalism, as a coherent body of ideas — with a

dialectical philosophy of nature, a confederalist politics, a

non-hierarchical social analysis, and an ethics based on complementarity

— can be an inspiration for a new radical popular movement in the years

to come, indeed, for the resuscitation of the Left in a meaningful

sense.

At this crossroads, we now have to decide where we want to go, and how

we can get there. The current ecological crisis is also a social one,

and we must redefine humanity’s relationship to the natural world by

remaking the basic social institutions and advancing a new ecological

humanism, in order to make science, technology, and the human intellect

serve both social development and a natural evolution guided by reason.

To carve the outlines of a rational ecological future, and to initiate

the necessary steps in that direction, has now become not only a

desideratum, but a necessity. As Murray Bookchin so challengingly asks,

“humanity is too intelligent not to live in a rational society. It

remains to see whether it is intelligent enough to achieve one.”

Eirik Eiglad,

January 14^(th), 2006

What is Social Ecology?

Social ecology is based on the conviction that nearly all of our present

ecological problems originate in deep-seated social problems. It

follows, from this view, that these ecological problems cannot be

understood, let alone solved, without a careful understanding of our

existing society and the irrationalities that dominate it. To make this

point more concrete: economic, ethnic, cultural, and gender conflicts,

among many others, lie at the core of the most serious ecological

dislocations we face today — apart, to be sure, from those that are

produced by natural catastrophes.

If this approach seems a bit too sociological for those

environmentalists who identify the primary ecological problem as being

the preservation of wildlife or wilderness, or more broadly as attending

to “Gaia” to achieve planetary “oneness,” they might wish to consider

certain recent developments. The massive oil spills that have occurred

over the past two decades, the extensive deforestation of tropical

forest and magnificent ancient trees in temperate areas, and vast

hydroelectric projects that flood places where people live, to cite only

a few problems, are sobering reminders that the real battleground on

which the ecological future of the planet will be decided is clearly a

social one, particularly between corporate power and the long-range

interests of humanity as a whole.

Indeed, to separate ecological problems from social problems — or even

to play down or give only token recognition to their crucial

relationship — would be to grossly misconstrue the sources of the

growing environmental crisis. In effect, the way human beings deal with

each other as social beings is crucial to addressing the ecological

crisis. Unless we clearly recognize this, we will fail to see that the

hierarchical mentality and class relationships that so thoroughly

permeate society are what has given rise to the very idea of dominating

the natural world.

Unless we realize that the present market society, structured around the

brutally competitive imperative of “grow or die,” is a thoroughly

impersonal, self-operating mechanism, we will falsely tend to blame

other phenomena — such as technology or population growth — for growing

environmental dislocations. We will ignore their root causes, such as

trade for profit, industrial expansion for its own sake, and the

identification of progress with corporate self- interest. In short, we

will tend to focus on the symptoms of a grim social pathology rather

than on the pathology itself, and our efforts will be directed toward

limited goals whose attainment is more cosmetic than curative.

Some critics have recently questioned whether social ecology has treated

the issue of spirituality in ecological politics adequately. In fact,

social ecology was among the earliest of contemporary ecologies to call

for a sweeping change in existing spiritual values. Indeed, such a

change would involve a far-reaching transformation of our prevailing

mentality of domination into one of complementarity, one that sees our

role in the natural world as creative, supportive, and deeply

appreciative of the well-being of nonhuman life. In social ecology a

truly natural spirituality, free of mystical regressions, would center

on the ability of an emancipated humanity to function as ethical agents

for diminishing needless suffering, engaging in ecological restoration,

and fostering an aesthetic appreciation of natural evolution in all its

fecundity and diversity.

Thus, in its call for a collective effort to change society, social

ecology has never eschewed the need for a radically new spirituality or

mentality. As early as 1965, the first public statement to advance the

ideas of social ecology concluded with the injunction: “The cast of mind

that today organizes differences among human and other life-forms along

hierarchical lines of ‘supremacy or ‘inferiority’ will give way to an

outlook that deals with diversity in an ecological manner — that is,

according to an ethics of complementarity.”[1] In such an ethics, human

beings would complement nonhuman beings with their own capacities to

produce a richer, creative, and developmental whole — not as a“dominant”

species but as supportive one. Although this ethics, expressed at times

as an appeal for the “respiritization of the natural world,” recurs

throughout the literature of social ecology, it should not be mistaken

for a theology that raises a deity above the natural world or even that

seeks to discover one within it. The spirituality advanced by social

ecology is definitively naturalist (as one would expect, given its

relation to ecology itself, which stems from the biological sciences)

rather than supernaturalistic or pantheistic areas of speculation.

The effort in some quarters of the ecology movement to prioritize the

need to develop a pantheistic “eco-spirituality” over the need to

address social factors raises serious questions about their ability to

come to grips with reality. At a time when a blind social mechanism —

the market — is turning soil into sand, covering fertile land with

concrete, poisoning air and water, and producing sweeping climatic and

atmospheric changes, we cannot ignore the impact that an aggressive

hierarchical and exploitative class society has on the natural world. We

must face the fact that economic growth, gender oppressions, and ethnic

domination — not to speak of corporate, state, and bureaucratic

incursions on human well- being — are much more capable of shaping the

future of the natural world than are privatistic forms of spiritual

self-redemption. These forms of domination must be confronted by

collective action and by major social movements that challenge the

social sources of the ecological crisis, not simply by personalistic

forms of consumption and investment that often go under the oxymoronic

rubric of “green capitalism.” The present highly cooptative society is

only too eager to find new means of commercial aggrandizement and to add

ecological verbiage to its advertising and customer relations efforts.

Nature and Society

To escape from this profit-oriented image of ecology, let us begin with

some basics — namely, by asking what society and the natural world

actually are. Among the many definitions of nature that have been

formulated over time, the one that has the most affinity with social

ecology is rather elusive and often difficult to grasp because

understanding and articulating it requires a certain way of thinking —

one that stands at odds with what is popularly called “linear thinking.”

This “nonlinear” or organic way of thinking is developmental rather than

analytical, or in more technical terms, it is dialectical rather than

instrumental. It conceives the natural world as a developmental process

, rather than the beautiful vistas we see from a mountaintop or images

fixed on the backs of picture postcards. Such vistas and images of

nonhuman nature are basically static and immobile. As we gaze over a

landscape, to be sure, our attention may momentarily be arrested by the

soaring flight of a hawk, or the bolting leap of a deer, or the

low-slung shadowy lope of a coyote. But what we are really witnessing in

such cases is the mere kinetics of physical motion, caught in the frame

of an essentially static image of the scene before our eyes. Such static

images deceive us into believing in the “eternality” of single moments

in nature.

But nonhuman nature is more than a scenic view, and as we examine it

with some care, we begin to sense that it is basically an evolving and

unfolding phenomenon, a richly fecund, even dramatic development that is

forever changing. I mean to define nonhuman nature precisely as an

evolving process, as the totality, in fact, of its evolution. Nature, so

concerned, encompasses the development from the inorganic into the

organic, and from the less differentiated and relatively limited world

of unicellular organisms into that of multicellular ones equipped with

simple, then, complex, and in time fairly intelligent neural apparatuses

that allow them to make innovative choices. Finally, the acquisition of

warm-bloodedness gives to organisms the astonishing flexibility to exist

in the most demanding climatic environments.

This vast drama of nonhuman nature is in every respect stunning and

wondrous. Its evolution is marked by increasing subjectivity and

flexibility and by increasing differentiation that makes an organism

more adaptable to new environmental challenges and opportunities and

that better equips living beings (specifically human beings) to alter

their environment to meet their own needs rather than merely adapt to

environmental changes. One may speculate that the potentiality of matter

itself — the ceaseless interactivity of atoms in forming new chemical

combinations to produce ever more complex molecules, amino acids,

proteins, and under suitable conditions, elementary life-forms — is

inherent in inorganic nature. [2] Or one may decide quite

matter-of-factly that the “struggle for existence” or the “survival of

the fittest” explains why increasingly subjective and more flexible

beings are capable of addressing environmental change more effectively

that are less subjective and flexible beings. But the simple fact

remains that these evolutionary dramas did occur, indeed the evidence is

carved in stone in the fossil record. That nonhuman nature is this

record, this history, this developmental or evolutionary process, is a

very sobering fact that cannot be ignored without ignoring reality

itself.

Conceiving nonhuman nature as its own interactive evolution rather than

as a mere scenic vista has profound implications — ethical as well as

biological — for ecologically minded people. Human beings embody, at

least potentially, attributes of nonhuman development that place them

squarely within organic evolution. They are not “natural aliens,” to use

Neil Evernden’s phrase, strong exotics, phylogenetic deformities that,

owing to their tool-making capacities, “cannot evolve with an ecosystem

anywhere.” [3] Nor are they “intelligent fleas,” to use the language of

Gaian theorists who believe that the earth (“Gaia”) is one living

organism. [4] These untenable disjunctions between humanity and the

evolutionary process are as superficial as they are potentially

misanthropic. Humans are highly intelligent, indeed, very self-conscious

primates, which is to say that they have emerged — not diverged — from a

long evolution of vertebrate life-forms into mammalian and finally

primate life-forms. They are a product of a significant evolutionary

trend toward intellectuality, self-awareness, will, intentionality, and

expressiveness, be it in verbal or in body language.

Human beings belong to a natural continuum, no less than their primate

ancestors and mammals in general. To depict them as “aliens” that have

no place or pedigree in natural evolution, or to see them essentially as

an infestation that parasitizes the planet the way fleas parasitize dogs

and cats, is not only bad ecology but bad thinking. Lacking any sense of

process, this kind of thinking — regrettably so commonplace among

ethicists — radically divides the nonhuman from the human. Indeed, to

the degree environmental thinkers romanticize nonhuman nature as

wilderness and see it as more authentically “natural” than the works of

humans, they freeze nonhuman nature as a circumscribed domain in which

human innovation, foresight, and creativity have no place and offer no

possibilities.

The truth is that human beings not only belong in nature, they are

products of a long, natural evolutionary process. Their seemingly

“unnatural” activities — like the development of technology and science,

the formation of mutable social institutions, highly symbolic forms of

communication, and aesthetic sensibilities, and the creation of towns

and cities — all would have been impossible without the large array of

physical human attributes that have been aeons in the making, be they

the large human brain or the bipedal motion that frees human hands for

making tools and carrying food. In many respects, human traits are

enlargements of nonhuman traits that have been evolving over the ages.

Increasing care for the young, cooperation, the substitution of mentally

guided behavior for largely instinctive behavior — all are present more

keenly in human behavior. Among humans, as opposed to nonhuman beings,

these traits are developed sufficiently to reach a degree of elaboration

and integration that yields cultures, comprising institutions of

families, bands, tribes, hierarchies, economic classes, and the state —

in short, highly mutable societies for which there is no precedent in

the nonhuman world, unless the genetically programmed behavior of

insects is to be regarded as social. In fact, the emergence and

development of human society has been a continual process of shedding

instinctive behavioral traits and of clearing a new terrain for

potentially rational behavior.

Human beings always remain rooted in their biological evolutionary

history, which we may call “first nature,” but they produce a

characteristically human social nature of their own, which we may call

“second nature.” Far from being unnatural, human second nature is

eminently a creation of organic evolution’s first nature. To write

second nature out of nature as a whole, or indeed to minimize it, is to

ignore the creativity of natural evolution itself and to view it

one-sidedly. If “true” evolution embodies itself simply in creatures

like grizzly bears, wolves, and whales — generally, animals that people

find aesthetically pleasing or relatively intelligent — then human

beings are de-natured. Such views, whether they see human beings as

“aliens” or as “fleas,” essentially place them outside the

self-organizing thrust of natural evolution toward increasing

subjectivity and flexibility. The more enthusiastic proponents of this

de-naturing of humanity may see human beings as existing apart from

nonhuman evolution, as a “freaking,” as Paul Shepard put it, of the

evolutionary process. Others simply avoid the problem of clarifying

humanity’s unique place in natural evolution by promiscuously putting

human beings on a par with beetles in terms of their “intrinsic worth.”

The “either/ or” propositional thinking that produces such obfuscations

either separates the social from the organic altogether or flippantly

makes it disappear into the organic, resulting in an inexplicable

dualism at one extreme or a naive reductionism at the other. The

dualistic approach, with its quasi-theological premise that the world

was “made” for human use, is saddled with the name anthropocentrism,

while the reductionist approach, with its almost meaningless notion of a

“biocentric democracy,” is saddled with the name biocentrism.

The bifurcation of the human from the nonhuman reflects a failure to

think organically or to approach evolutionary phenomena with an

evolutionary way of thought. Needless to say, if nature were no more

than a scenic vista, then mere metaphoric and poetic descriptions of it

might suffice to replace systematic thinking about it. But nature is the

history of nature, an evolutionary process that is going on to one

degree or another under our very eyes, and as such, we dishonor it by

thinking of it in anything but a processual way. That is to say, we

require a way of thinking that recognizes that “what is,” as it seems to

lie before our eyes, is always developing into “what is not,” that it is

engaged in a continual self-organizing process in which past and

present, along a richly differentiated but shared continuum, give rise

to a new potentiality for an ever-richer degree of wholeness. Life,

clearly in its human form, becomes open- endedly innovative and

transcends its relatively narrow capacity to adapt only to a pregiven

set of environmental conditions. As V. Gordon Childe once put it, “Man

makes himself; he is not preset to survive by his genetic makeup.”

By the same token, a processual, organic, and dialectical way of

thinking has little difficulty in locating and explaining the emergence

of the social out of the biological, of second nature out of first

nature. It seems more fashionable these days to deal with ecologically

significant social issues like an accountant. Thus, one simply

juxtaposes two lists of cultural facts — one labeled “old paradigm” and

the other, “new paradigm” — as though they were columns of debits and

credits. Obviously distasteful items like centralization are listed

under “old paradigm,” while more appealing ones like decentralization

are regarded as “new paradigm.” The result is an inventory of

bumper-sticker slogans whose “bottom line” is patently absolute good

versus absolute evil. All of this may be deliciously synoptic and easy

on the eyes, but it is singularly lacking as food for the brain. To

truly know and be able to give interpretive meaning to the social issues

and ideas so arranged, we should want to know how each one derived from

the other and what its part is in an overall development. What, in fact,

is meant by “decentralization,” and how, in the history of human

society, does it derive from or give rise to centralization? Again, we

need processual thinking to comprehend processual realities, if we are

to gain some sense of direction — practical as well as theoretical — in

addressing our ecological problems.

Social ecology seems to stand alone, at present, in calling for an

organic, developmental way of thinking out problems that are basically

organic and developmental in character. The very definition of the

natural world as a development (albeit not any one) indicates the need

for organic thinking, as does the derivation of human from nonhuman

nature — a derivation from which we can draw far-reaching conclusions

for the development of an ecological ethics that in turn can provide

serious guidelines for the solution of our ecological problems.

Social ecology calls upon us to see that the natural world and the

social are interlinked by evolution into one nature that consists of two

differentiations: first or biotic nature, and second or social nature.

Social nature and biotic nature share an evolutionary potential for

greater subjectivity and flexibility. Second nature is the way in which

human beings, as flexible, highly intelligent primates, inhabit and

alter the natural world. That is to say, people create an environment

that is most suitable for their mode of existence. In this respect,

second nature is no different from the environment that every animal,

depending upon its abilities, partially creates as well as primarily

adapts to — the biophysical circumstances or ecocommunity in which it

must live. In principle, on this very simple level, human beings are

doing nothing that differs from the survival activities of nonhuman

beings, be it building beaver dams or digging gopher holes.

But the environmental changes that human beings produce are profoundly

different from those produced by nonhuman beings. Humans act upon their

environments with considerable technical foresight, however lacking that

foresight may be in ecological ideals. Animals adapt to the world around

them; human beings innovate through thought and social labor. For better

or worse, they alter the natural world to meet their needs and desires —

not because they are perverse, but because they have evolved quite

naturally over the ages to do so. Their cultures are rich in knowledge,

experience, cooperation, and conceptual intellectuality; however, they

have been sharply divided against themselves at many points of their

development, through conflicts between groups, classes, nation- states,

and even city-states. Nonhuman beings generally live in ecological

niches, their behavior guided primarily by instinctive drives and

conditioned reflexes. Human societies are “bonded” together by

institutions that change radically over centuries. Nonhuman communities

are notable for their general fixity, by their clearly preset, often

genetically imprinted rhythms. Human communities are guided in part by

ideological factors and are subject to changes conditioned by those

factors. Nonhuman communities are generally tied together by genetically

rooted instinctive factors — to the extent that these communities exist

at all.

Hence human beings, emerging from an organic evolutionary process,

initiate, by the sheer force of their biological and survival needs, a

social evolutionary development that clearly involves their organic

evolutionary process. Owing to their naturally endowed intelligence,

powers of communication, capacity for institutional organization, and

relative freedom from instinctive behavior, they refashion their

environment — as do nonhuman beings — to the full extent that their

biological equipment allows. This equipment makes it possible for them

to engage not only in social life but in social development. It is not

so much that human beings, in principle, behave differently from animals

or are inherently more problematical in a strictly ecological sense, as

it is that the social development by which they grade out of their

biological development often becomes more problematical for themselves

and nonhuman life. How these problems emerge, the ideologies they

produce, the extent to which they contribute to biotic evolution or

abort it, and the damage they inflict on the planet as a whole lie at

the very heart of the modern ecological crisis. Second nature as it

exists today, far from marking the fulfillment of human potentialities,

is riddled by contradictions, antagonisms, and conflicting interests

that have distorted humanity’s unique capacities for development. Its

future prospects encompass both the danger of tearing down the biosphere

and alas, given the struggle to achieve an ecological society, the

capacity to provide an entirely new ecological dispensation.

Social Hierarchy and Domination

How, then, did the social emerge from the biological? We have good

reason to believe that as biological facts such as kin lineage, gender

distinctions, and age differences were slowly institutionalized, their

uniquely social dimension was initially quite egalitarian. Later this

development acquired an oppressive hierarchical and then an exploitative

class form. The lineage or blood tie in early prehistory obviously

formed the organic basis of the family. Indeed, it joined together

groups of families into bands, clans, and tribes, through either

intermarriage or fictive forms of descent, thereby forming the earliest

social horizon of our ancestors. More than in other mammals, the simple

biological facts of human reproduction and the protracted maternal care

of the human infant tended to knit siblings together and produced a

strong sense of solidarity and group inwardness. Men, women, and their

children were socialize by means of a fairly stable family life, based

on mutual obligation and an expressed affinity that was often sanctified

by initiation ceremonies and marital vows of one kind or another.

Human beings who were outside the family and all its elaborations into

bands, clans, tribes, and the like, were regarded as “strangers” who

could alternatively be welcomed hospitably or enslaved or put to death.

What mores existed were based on unreflective customs that seemed to

have been inherited from time immemorial. What we call morality began as

the rules or commandments of a deity or various deities, in that moral

beliefs required some kind of supernatural or mystical reinforcement or

sanctification to be accepted by a community. Only later, beginning with

the ancient Greeks, did ethics emerge, based on rational discourse and

reflection. The shift from blind custom to a commanding morality and

finally to a rational ethics occurred with the rise of cities and urban

cosmopolitanism, although by no means did custom and morality diminish

in importance. Humanity, gradually disengaging its social organization

from the biological facts of blood ties, began to admit the “stranger”

and increasingly recognize itself as a shared community of human beings

(and ultimately a community of citizens) rather than an ethnic folk or

group of kinsmen.

In this primordial and socially formative world, other human biological

traits were also reworked from the strictly natural to the social. One

of these was the fact of age and its distinctions. In social groups

among early humans, the absence of a written language helped to confer

on the elderly a high degree of status, for it was they who possessed

the traditional wisdom of the community, including knowledge of the

traditional kinship lines that prescribed marital ties in obedience to

extensive incest taboos as well as survival techniques that had to be

acquired by both the young and the mature members of the group. In

addition, the biological fact of gender distinctions was slowly reworked

along social lines into what were initially complementary sororal and

fraternal groups. Women formed their own food-gathering and care-taking

groups with their own customs, belief systems, and values, while men

formed their own hunting and warrior groups with their own behavioral

characteristics, mores, and ideologies.

From everything we know about the socialization of the biological facts

of kinship, age, and gender groups — their elaboration into early

institutions — there is no reason to doubt that these groups existed

initially in complementary relationships with one another. Each, in

effect, needed the others to form a relatively stable whole. No one

group “dominated” the others or tried to privilege itself in the normal

course of things. Yet even as the biological underpinnings of

consociation were, over time, further reworked into social institutions,

so the social institutions were slowly reworked, at various periods and

in various degrees, into hierarchical structures based on command and

obedience. I speak here of a historical trend, in no way predetermined

by any mystical force or deity, and one that was often a very limited

development among many preliterate or aboriginal cultures and even in

certain fairly elaborate civilizations.

Hierarchy in its earliest forms was probably not marked by the harsh

qualities it has acquired over history. Elders, at the very beginnings

of gerontocracy, were not only respected for their wisdom but were often

beloved of the young, with affection that was often reciprocated in

kind. We can probably account for the increasing harshness of later

gerontocracies by supposing that the elderly, burdened by their failing

physical powers and dependent upon their community’s goodwill, were more

vulnerable to abandonment in periods of material want than any other

part of the population. “Even in simple food-gathering cultures,”

observed anthropologist Paul Radin, “individuals above fifty, let us

say, apparently arrogate to themselves certain powers and privileges

which benefited themselves specifically, and were not necessarily, if at

all, dictated by considerations either of the rights of others or the

welfare of the community.” [5] In any case, that gerontocracy was

probably the earliest form of hierarchy is corroborated by its existence

in communities as disparate as the Australian Aborigines, tribal

societies in East Africa, and Native communities in the Americas. Many

tribal councils throughout the world were really councils of elders, an

institution that never completely disappeared (as the word alderman

suggests), even after they were overlaid by warrior societies,

chiefdoms, and kingships.

Patricentricity, in which masculine values, institutions, and forms of

behavior prevail over feminine ones, seems to have developed in the wake

of gerontocracy. Initially, the emergence of patricentricity may have

been a useful adjunct to a life deeply rooted in the primordial natural

world; preliterate and early aboriginal societies were essentially small

domestic communities in which the authentic center of material life was

the home, not the “men’s house” so widely present in later, more

elaborate tribal societies. Male rule, if such it can strictly be

called, takes on its harshest and most coercive form in patriarchy, an

institution in which the eldest male of an extended family or clan has a

life-and-death command over all other members of the group. Women may be

ordered whom to marry, but they are by no means the exclusive or even

the principal object of a patriarch’s domination. Sons, like daughters,

may be ordered how to behave at the patriarch’s command or be killed at

his whim.

So far as patricentricity is concerned, however, the authority and

prerogative of the male are the product of a long, often subtly

negotiated development in which the male fraternity edges out the female

sorority by virtue of the former’s growing “civil” responsibilities.

Increasing population, marauding bands of outsiders whose migrations may

be induced by drought or other unfavorable conditions, and vendettas of

one kind or another, to cite common causes of hostility or war, create a

new “civil” sphere side by side with woman’s domestic sphere, and the

former gradually encroaches upon the latter. With the appearance of

cattle-drawn plow agriculture, the male, who is the “master of the

beasts,” begins to invade the horticultural sphere of woman, whose

primacy as the food cultivator and food gatherer gives her cultural

preeminence in the community’s internal life, slowly diluting her

preeminence. Warrior societies and chiefdoms carry the momentum of male

dominance to the level of a new material and cultural dispensation. Male

dominance becomes extremely active and ultimately yields a world in

which male elites dominate not only women but also, in the form of

classes, other men.

The causes of the emergence of hierarchy are transparent enough: the

infirmities of age, increasing population numbers, natural disasters,

technological changes that privileged activities of hunting and animal

husbandry over horticultural responsibilities, the growth of civil

society, and the spread of warfare. All served to enhance the male’s

standing at the expense of the female’s. It must be emphasized that

hierarchical domination, however coercive it may be, is not the same

thing as class exploitation. As I wrote in The Ecology of Freedom,

hierarchy

must be viewed as institutionalized relationships, relationships that

living beings literally institute or create but which are neither

ruthlessly fixed by instinct on the one hand nor idiosyncratic on the

other. By this, I mean that they must comprise a clearly social

structure of coercive and privileged ranks that exist apart from the

idiosyncratic individuals who seem to be dominant within a given

community, a hierarchy that is guided by a social logic that goes beyond

individual interactions or inborn patterns of behavior. [6]

They are not reducible to strictly economic relationships based on the

exploitation of labor. In fact, many chiefs earn their prestige, so

essential to their authority, by disposing of gifts, and even by a

considerable disaccumulation of their personal goods. The respect

accorded to many chiefs is earned, not by hoarding surpluses as a source

of power but by disposing of them as evidence of generosity.

By contrast, classes tend to operate along different lines. In class

societies power is usually gained by the acquisition of wealth, not by

its disposal; rulership is guaranteed by outright physical coercion, not

simply by persuasion; and the state is the ultimate guarantor of

authority. That hierarchy is historically more entrenched than class can

perhaps be verified by the fact that despite sweeping changes in class

societies, even of an economically egalitarian kind, women have still

been dominated beings for millennia. By the same token, the abolition of

class rule and economic exploitation offers no guarantee whatever that

elaborate hierarchies and systems of domination will also disappear.

In nonhierarchical societies, certain customs guide human behavior along

basically decent lines. Of primary importance among early customs was

the principle of the irreducible minimum (to use Paul Radin’s

expression), the shared notion that all members of the same community

are entitled to the means of life, irrespective of the amount of work

they perform. To deny anyone food, shelter, and the basic means of life

because of their infirmities or even their frivolous behavior would have

been seen as a heinous denial of the very right to live. Nor were the

basic resources needed to sustain the community ever permitted to be

privately owned; overriding individualistic control was the broader

principle of usufruct — the notion that the means of life that were not

being used by one group could be used, as needed, by another. Thus

unused land, orchards, and even tools and weapons, if left idle, were

often at the disposition of anyone in the community who needed them.

Lastly, custom fostered the practice of mutual aid, the rather sensible

cooperative sharing of things and labor, so that an individual or family

in straitened circumstances could expect to be helped by others. Taken

as whole, these customs became so sedimented into organic society that

they persisted long after hierarchy became oppressive and class society

became predominant.

The Idea of Dominating Nature

Nature, in the sense of the biotic environment from which humans take

the simple things they need for survival, often has no meaning to

preliterate peoples as a general concept. Immersed in it as they are,

even celebrating animistic rituals in an environment they view as a

nexus of life, often imputing their own social institutions to the

behavior of nonhuman species, as in the case of beaver “lodges” and

humanlike spirits, the concept of “nature” a such eludes them. Words

that express our conventional notions of nature are not easy to find, if

they exist at all, in the languages of aboriginal peoples.

With the rise of hierarchy and domination, however, the seeds were

planted for the belief that first nature not only exists as a world that

is increasingly distinguishable from the community but one that is

hierarchically organized and can be dominated by human beings. The

worldview of magic reveal this shift clearly. Here nature was not

conceived as a world apart; rather, a practitioner of magic essentially

pleaded with the “chief spirit” of a game animal (itself a puzzling

figure in the dream world) to coax it in the direction of an arrow or a

spear. Later, magic became almost entirely instrumental; the hunter used

magical techniques to “coerce” the game to become prey. While the

earliest forms of magic may be regarded as the practices of a generally

nonhierarchical and egalitarian community, the later kinds of animistic

beliefs betray a more or less hierarchical view of the natural world and

of latent human powers of domination over reality.

We must emphasize here that the idea of dominating nature has its

primary source in the domination of human by human and in the

structuring of the natural world into a hierarchical chain of being (a

static conception, incidentally, that has no relationship to the dynamic

evolution of life into increasingly advanced forms of subjectivity and

flexibility). The biblical injunction that gave command of the living

world to Adam and Noah was above all an expression of a social

dispensation. Its idea of dominating nature — so essential to the view

of the nonhuman world as an object of domination — can be overcome only

through the creation of a society without those class and hierarchical

structures that make for rule and obedience in private as well as public

life, and the objectifications of reality as mere materials for

exploitation. That this revolutionary dispensation would involve changes

in attitudes and values should go without saying. But new ecological

attitudes and values will remain vaporous if they are not given

substance and solidity through real and objective institutions (the

structures by which humans concretely interact with each other) and

through the tangible realities of everyday life from childrearing to

work and play. Until human beings cease to live in societies that are

structured around hierarchies as well as economic classes, we shall

never be free of domination, however much we try to dispel it with

rituals, incantations, ecotheologies, and the adoption of seemingly

“natural” lifeways.

The idea of dominating nature has a history that is almost as old as

that of hierarchy itself. Already in the Gilgamesh epic of Mesopotamia,

a drama whose written form dates back some four thousand years, the hero

defies the deities and cuts down their sacred trees in his quest for

immortality. The Odyssey is a vast travelogue of the Greek warrior, more

canny than heroic, who in his wanderings essentially subdues the nature

deities that the Hellenic world had inherited form its less well-known

precursors (ironically, the dark pre-Olympian world that has been

revived by purveyors of eco-mysticism and spiritualism). Long before the

emergence of modern science, “linear” rationality, and “industrial

society” (to cite causal factors that are invoked so flippantly in the

modern ecology movement), hierarchical and class societies laid waste to

much of the Mediterranean basin as well as the hillsides of China,

beginning a vast remaking and often despoliation of the planet.

To be sure, human second nature, in inflicting harm on first nature,

created no Garden of Eden. More often than not, it despoiled much that

was beautiful, creative, and dynamic in the biotic world, just as it

ravaged human life itself in murderous warfare, genocide, and acts of

heartless oppression. Social ecology maintains that the future of human

life goes hand in hand with the future of the nonhuman world, yet it

does not overlook the fact that the harm that hierarchical and class

society inflicted on the natural world was more than matched by the harm

it inflicted on much of humanity.

However troubling the ills produced by second nature, the customs of the

irreducible minimum, usufruct, and mutual aid cannot be ignored in any

account of anthropology and history. These customs persisted well into

historical times and surfaced sometimes explosively in massive popular

uprisings, from revolts in ancient Sumer to the present time. Many of

those revolts demanded the recovery of caring and communistic values, at

times when these were coming under the onslaught of elitist and class

oppression. Indeed, despite the armies that roamed the landscape of

warring areas, the tax-gatherers who plundered ordinary village peoples,

and the daily abuses that overseers inflicted on peasants and workers,

community life still persisted and retained many of the cherished values

of a more egalitarian past. Neither ancient despots nor feudal lords

could fully obliterate them in peasant villages and in the towns with

independent craft associations. In ancient Greece, a rational philosophy

that rejected the encumbering of thought and political life by

extravagant wants, as well as a religion based on austerity, tended to

scale down needs and delimit human appetites for material goods.

Together they served to slow the pace of technological innovation

sufficiently that when new means of production were developed, they

could be sensitively integrated into a balanced society. In medieval

times, markets were still modest, usually local affairs, in which guilds

exercised strict control over prices, competition, and the quality of

the goods produced by their members.

“Grow or Die”

But just as hierarchies and class structures had acquired momentum and

permeated much of society, so too the market began to acquire a life of

its own and extended its reach beyond a few limited regions into the

depths of vast continents. Where exchange had once been primarily a

means to provide for essential needs, limited by guilds or by moral and

religious restrictions, long-distance trade subverted those limits. Not

only did trade place a high premium on techniques for increasing

production; it also became the progenitor of new needs, many of them

wholly artificial, and gave a tremendous impetus to consumption and the

growth of capital. First in northern Italy and the European lowlands,

and later — and most decisively — in England during the seventeenth and

eighteenth centuries, the production of goods exclusively for sale and

profit (the production of the capitalistic commodity) rapidly swept

aside all cultural and social barriers to market growth.

By the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, the new

industrial capitalist class, with its factory system and commitment to

limitless expansion, had embarked on its colonization of the entire

world, including most aspects of personal life. Unlike the feudal

nobility, with its cherished lands and castles, the bourgeoisie had no

home but the marketplace and its bank vaults. As a class, it turned more

and more of the world into a domain of factories. In the ancient and

medieval worlds, entrepreneurs had normally invested profits in land and

lived like country gentry, given the prejudices of the times against

“ill-gotten” gains from trade. But the industrial capitalists of the

modern world spawned a bitterly competitive marketplace that placed a

high premium on industrial expansion and the commercial power it

conferred, functioning as though growth were an end in itself.

In social ecology it is crucially important to recognize that industrial

growth did not and does not result from changes in cultural outlook

alone — least of all from the impact of scientific and technological

rationality on society. Growth occurs above all from harshly objective

factors churned up by the expansion of the market itself, factors that

are largely impervious to moral considerations and efforts at ethical

persuasion. Indeed, despite the close association between capitalist

development and technological innovation, the most driving imperative of

any enterprise in the harshly capitalist marketplace, given the savagely

dehumanizing competition that prevails there, is the need of an

enterprise to grow in order to avoid perishing at the hands of its

savage rivals. Important as even greed may be as a motivating force,

sheer survival requires that the entrepreneur must expand his or her

productive apparatus in order to remain ahead of others. Each

capitalist, in short, must try to devour his or her rivals — or else be

devoured by them. The key to this law of life — to survival — is

expansion, and the quest for ever- greater profits, to be invested, in

turn, in still further expansion. Indeed, the notion of progress, once

regarded as faith in the evolution of greater human cooperation and

care, is now identified with ever greater competition and reckless

economic growth.

The effort by many well-intentioned ecology theorists and their admirers

to reduce the ecological crisis to a cultural crisis rather than a

social one becomes very obfuscatory and misleading. However ecologically

well-meaning an entrepreneur may be, the harsh fact is that his or her

very survival in the marketplace precludes the development of a

meaningful ecological orientation. The adoption of ecologically sound

practices places a morally concerned entrepreneur at a striking and

indeed fatal disadvantage in a competitive relationship with a rival —

who, operating without ecological guidelines and moral constraints,

produces cheap commodities at lower costs and reaps higher profits for

further capital expansion. The marketplace has its own law of survival:

only the most unscrupulous can rise to the top of that competitive

struggle.

Indeed, to the extent that environmental movements and ideologies merely

moralize about the wickedness of our anti- ecological society and call

for changes in personal lifestyles and attitudes, they obscure the need

for concerted social action and tend to deflect the struggle for

far-reaching social change. Meanwhile, corporations are skillfully

manipulating this popular desire for personal ecologically sound

practices by cultivating ecological mirages. Mercedes-Benz, for example,

declaims in a two-page magazine advertisement, decorated with a bison

painting from a Paleolithic cave wall, that “we must work to make

progress more environmentally sustainable by including environmental

themes in the planning of new products.” [7] Such messages are

commonplace in Germany, one of western Europe’s worst polluters. Such

advertising is equally manipulative in the United States, where leading

polluters piously declare that for them, “every day is Earth Day.”

The point social ecology emphasizes is not that moral and spiritual

persuasion and renewal are meaningless or unnecessary; they are

necessary and can be educational. But modern capitalism is structurally

amoral and hence impervious to moral appeals. The modern marketplace is

driven by imperatives of its own, irrespective of what kind of CEO sits

in a corporation’s driver’s seat or holds on to its handlebars. The

direction it follows depends not upon ethical prescriptions and personal

inclinations but upon objective laws of profit or loss, growth or death,

eat or be eaten, and the like. The maxim “Business is business”

explicitly tells us that ethical, religious, psychological, and

emotional factors have virtually no place in the predatory world of

production, profit, and growth. It is grossly misleading to think that

we can divest this harsh, indeed mechanistic world of its objective

characteristics by means of ethical appeals.

A society based on the law of “grow or die” as its all-pervasive

imperative must of necessity have a devastating impact on first nature.

Nor does “growth” here refer to population growth; the current wisdom of

population-boomers to the contrary, the most serious disruptors of

ecological cycles are found in the large industrial centers of the

world, which are not only poisoning water and air but producing the

greenhouse gases that threaten to melt the ice caps and flood vast areas

of the planet. Suppose we could somehow cut the world’s population in

half: would growth and the despoliation of the earth be reduced at all?

Capital would insist that it was “indispensable” to own two or three of

every appliance, motor vehicle, or electronic gadget, where one would

more than suffice if not be too many. In addition, the military would

continue to demand ever more lethal instruments of death and

devastation, of which new models would be provided annually.

Nor would “softer” technologies, if produced by a grow-or-die market,

fail to be used for destructive capitalistic ends. Two centuries ago,

large forested areas in England were hacked into fuel for iron forges

with axes that had not changed appreciably since the Bronze Age, and

ordinary sails guided ships laden with commodities to all parts of the

world well into the nineteenth century. Indeed, much of the United

States was cleared of its forests, wildlife, and aboriginal inhabitants

with tools and weapons that could have easily been recognized, however

much they were modified, by Renaissance people centuries earlier. What

modern technics did was accelerate a process that had been well under

way at the close of the Middle Ages. It cannot be held solely

responsible for endeavors that were under way for centuries; it

essentially abetted damage caused by the ever-expanding market system,

whose roots, in turn, lay in one of history’s most fundamental social

transformations: the elaboration of a system of production and

distribution based on exchange rather than complementarity and mutual

aid.

An Ecological Society

Social ecology is an appeal not only for moral regeneration but, and

above all, for social reconstruction along ecological lines. It

emphasizes that, taken by itself, an ethical appeal to the powers that

be, based on blind market forces and ruthless competition, is certain to

be futile. Indeed, taken by itself, such an appeal obscures the real

power relationships that prevail today by making the attainment of an

ecological society seem merely a matter of changing individual

attitudes, spiritual renewal, or quasi-religious redemption.

Although always mindful of the importance of a new ethical outlook,

social ecology seeks to redress the ecological abuses that the

prevailing society has inflicted on the natural world by going to the

structural as well as the subjective sources of notions like the

domination of first nature. That is, it challenges the entire system of

domination itself — its economy, its misuse of technics, its

administrative apparatus, its degradations of political life, its

destruction of the city as a center of cultural development, indeed the

entire panoply of its moral hypocrisies and defiling of the human spirit

— and seeks to eliminate the hierarchical and class edifices that have

imposed themselves on humanity and defined the relationship between

nonhuman and human nature. It advances an ethics of complementary in

which human beings play a supportive role in perpetuating the integrity

of the biosphere — the potentiality of human beings to be the most

conscious products of natural evolution. Indeed, humans have an ethical

responsibility to function creatively in the unfolding of that

evolution. Social ecology thus stresses the need to embody its ethics of

complementarity in palpable social institutions that will make human

beings conscious ethical agents in promoting the well-being of

themselves and the nonhuman world. It seeks the enrichment of the

evolutionary process by the diversification of life-forms and the

application of reason to a wondrous remaking of the planet along

ecological lines. Notwithstanding most romantic views, “Mother Nature”

does not necessarily “know best.” To oppose activities of the corporate

world does not require one to become naively biocentric. Indeed by the

same token, to applaud humanity’s potential for foresight, rationality,

and technological achievement does not make one anthropocentric. The

loose usage of such buzzwords, so commonplace in the ecology movement

today, must be brought to a definitive end by reflective discussion, not

by deprecating denunciations.

Social ecology, in effect, recognizes that — like it or not — the future

of life on this planet pivots on the future of society. It contends that

evolution, both in first nature and in second, is not yet complete. Nor

are the two realms so separated from each other that we must choose one

or the other — either national evolution, with its “biocentric” halo, or

social evolution, as we have known it up to now, with its

“anthropocentric” halo — as the basis for a creative biosphere. We must

go beyond both the natural and the social toward a new synthesis that

contains the best of both. Such a synthesis must transcend both first

and second nature in the form of a creative, self-conscious, and

therefore “free nature,” in which human beings intervene in natural

evolution with their best capacities — their ethical sense, their

unequaled capacity for conceptual thought, and their remarkable powers

and range of communication.

But such a goal remains mere rhetoric unless a movement gives it

logistical and social tangibility. How are we to organize such a

movement? Logistically, “free nature” is unattainable without the

decentralization of cities into confederally united communities

sensitively tailored to the natural areas in which they are located.

Ecotechnologies, and of solar, wind, methane, and other renewable

sources of energy; organic forms of agriculture; and the design of

humanly scaled, versatile industrial installations to meet the regional

needs of confederated municipalities — all must be brought into the

service of an ecologically sound world based on an ethics of

complementarity. It means too an emphasis not only on recycling but on

the production of high-quality goods that can, in many cases, last for

generations. It means the replacement of needlessly insensate labor with

creative work and an emphasis on artful craftspersonship in preference

to mechanized production. It means the free time to be artful and to

fully engage in public affairs. One would hope that the sheer

availability of goods, the mechanization of production, and the freedom

to choose one’s material lifestyle would sooner or later influence

people to practice moderation in all aspects of life as a response to

the consumerism promoted by the capitalist market. [8]

But no ethics or vision of an ecological society, however inspired, can

be meaningful unless it is embodied in a living politics. By politics, I

do not mean the statecraft practiced by what we call politicians —

namely, representatives elected or selected to manage public affairs and

formulate policies as guidelines for social life. To social ecology,

politics means what it meant in the democratic polis of classical Athens

some two thousand years ago: direct democracy, the formulation of

policies by directly democratic popular assemblies, and the

administration of those policies by mandated coordinators who can easily

be recalled if they fail to abide by the decision of the assembly’s

citizens. I am very mindful that Athenian politics, even in its most

democratic periods, was marred by the existence of slavery and

patriarchy, and by the exclusion of the stranger from public life. In

this respect, to be sure, it differed very little from most of the other

ancient Mediterranean civilizations — and certainly ancient Asian ones —

of the time. What made Athenian politics unique, however, was that it

produced institutions that were extraordinarily democratic — even

directly so — by comparison with the republican institutions of the

so-called “democracies” of today’s world. Either directly or indirectly,

the Athenian democracy inspired later, more all-encompassing direct

democracies, such as many medieval European towns, the little- known

Parisian “sections” (or neighborhood assemblies) of 1793 that propelled

the French Revolution in a highly radical direction, and more

indirectly, New England town meetings, and other, more recent attempts

at civic self-governance.[9]

Any self-managed community, however, that tries to live in isolation and

develop self-sufficiency risks the danger of becoming parochial, even

racist. Hence the need to extend the ecological politics of a direct

democracy into confederations of ecocommunities, and to foster a healthy

interdependence, rather than an introverted, stultifying independence.

Social ecology would be obliged to embody its ethics in a politics of

libertarian municipalism, in which municipalities conjointly gain rights

to self-governance through networks of confederal councils, to which

towns and cities would be expected to send their mandated, recallable

delegates to adjust differences. All decisions would have to be ratified

by a majority of the popular assemblies of the confederated towns and

cities. This institutional process could be initiated in the

neighborhoods of giant cities as well as in networks of small towns. In

fact, the formation of numerous “town halls” has already repeatedly been

proposed in cities as large as New York and Paris, only to be defeated

by well-organized elitist groups that sought to centralize power rather

than allow its decentralization.

Power will always belong to elite and commanding strata if it is not

institutionalized in face-to-face democracies, among people who are

fully empowered as social beings to make decisions in new communal

assemblies. Attempts to empower people in this manner and form

constitute an abiding challenge to the nation- state — that is, a dual

power in which the free municipality exists in open tension with the

nation-state. Power that does not belong to the people invariably

belongs to the state and the exploitative interests it represents. Which

is not to say that diversity is not a desideratum; to the contrary, it

is the source of cultural creativity. Still it never should be

celebrated in a nationalistic sense of “apartness” from the general

interests of humanity as a whole, or else it will regress into the

parochialism of folkdom and tribalism.

Should the full reality of citizenship in all its discursiveness and

political vitality begin to wane, its disappearance would mark an

unprecedented loss in human development. Citizenship, in the classical

sense of the term, which involved a lifelong, ethically oriented

education in the art of participation in public affairs (not the empty

form of national legitimation that it so often consists of today), would

disappear. Its loss would mean the atrophying of a communal life beyond

the limits of the family, the waning of a civic sensibility to the point

of the shriveled ego, the complete replacement of the public arena with

the private world and with private pursuits.

The failure of a rational, socially committed ecology movement would

yield a mechanized, aesthetically arid, and administered society,

composed of vacuous egos at best and totalitarian automata at worst.

Before the planet was rendered physically uninhabitable, there would be

few humans who would be able to inhabit it.

Alternatively, a truly ecological society would open the vista of a

“free nature” with a sophisticated eco-technology based on solar, wind,

and water; carefully treated fossil fuels would be sited to produce

power to meet rationally conceived needs. Production would occur

entirely for use, not for profit, and the distribution of goods would

occur entirely to meet human needs based on norms established by

citizens’ assemblies and confederations of assemblies. Decisions by the

community would be made according to direct, face-to-face procedures

with all the coordinative judgments mandated delegates. These judgments,

in turn, would be referred back for discussion, approval, modification,

or rejection by the assembly of assemblies (or Commune of communes) as a

whole, reflecting the wishes of the fully assembled majority.

We cannot tell how much technology will be expanded a few decades from

now, let alone a few generations. Its growth and the prospects it is

likely to open over the course of this century alone are too dazzling

even for the most imaginative utopian to envision. If nothing else, we

have been swept into a permanent technological and communications

revolution whose culmination it is impossible to foresee. This amassing

of power and knowledge opens two radically opposing prospects: either

humanity will truly destroy itself and its habitat, or it will create a

garden, a fruitful and benign world that not even the most fanciful

utopian, Charles Fourier, could have imagined.

It is fitting that such dire alternatives should appear now and in such

extreme forms. Unless social ecology — with its naturalistic outlook,

its developmental interpretations of natural and social phenomena, its

emphasis on discipline with freedom and responsibility with imagination

— can be brought to the service of such historic ends, humanity may well

prove to be incapable of changing the world. We cannot defer the need to

deal with these prospects indefinitely: either a movement will arise

that will bestir humanity into action, or the last great chance in

history for the complete emancipation of humanity will perish in

unrestrained self-destruction.

Radical Politics in an Era of Advanced Capitalism

Defying all the theoretical predictions of the 1930s, capitalism has

restabilized itself with a vengeance and acquired extraordinary

flexibility in the decades since World War II. In fact, we have yet to

clearly determine what constitutes capitalism in its most “mature” form,

not to speak of its social trajectory in the years to come. But what is

clear, I would argue, is that capitalism has transformed itself from an

economy surrounded by many precapitalist social and political formations

into a society that itself has become “economized.” Terms like

consumerism and industrialism are merely obscurantist euphemisms for an

all-pervasive embourgeoisement that involves not simply an appetite for

commodities and sophisticated technologies but the expansion of

commodity relationships — of market relationships — into areas of life

and social movements that once offered some degree of resistance to, if

not a refuge from, utterly amoral, accumulative, and competitive forms

of human interaction. Marketplace values have increasingly percolated

into familial, educational, personal, and even spiritual relationships

and have largely edged out the precapitalist traditions that made for

mutual aid, idealism, and moral responsibility in contrast to

businesslike norms of behavior.

There is a sense in which any new forms of resistance — be they by left

libertarians, or radicals generally — must open alternative areas of

life that can countervail and undo the embourgeoisement of society at

all its levels. The issue of the relationship of “society,” “politics,”

and “the state” becomes one of programmatic urgency. Can there be any

room for a radical public realm beyond the communes, cooperatives, and

neighborhood service organizations fostered by the 1960s counterculture

— structures that easily degenerated into boutique-type businesses when

they did not disappear completely? Is there, perhaps, a public realm

that can become an arena for the interplay of conflicting forces for

change, education, empowerment, and ultimately, confrontation with the

established way of life?

Marxism, Capitalism, and the Public Sphere

The very concept of a public realm stands at odds with traditional

radical notions of a class realm. Marxism, in particular, denied the

existence of a definable “public,” or what in the Age of Democratic

Revolutions of two centuries ago was called “the People,” because the

notion ostensibly obscured specific class interests — interests that

were ultimately supposed to bring the bourgeoisie into unrelenting

conflict with the proletariat. If “the People” meant anything, according

to Marxist theorists, it seemed to mean a waning, unformed, nondescript

petty bourgeoisie — a legacy of the past and of past revolutions — that

could be expected to side mainly with the capitalist class it aspired to

enter and ultimately with the working class it was forced to enter. The

proletariat, to the degree that it became class conscious, would

ultimately express the general interests of humanity once it absorbed

this vague middle class, particularly during a general economic or

“chronic” crisis within capitalism itself.

The 1930s, with its waves of strikes, its workers’ insurrections, its

street confrontations between revolutionary and fascist groups, and its

prospect of war and bloody social upheaval, seemed to confirm this

vision. But we cannot any longer ignore the fact that this traditional

radical vision has since been replaced by the present-day reality of a

managed capitalist system — managed culturally and ideologically as well

as economically. However much living standards have been eroded for

millions of people, the unprecedented fact remains that capitalism has

been free of a “chronic crisis” for a half-century. Nor are there any

signs that we are faced in the foreseeable future with a crisis

comparable to that of the Great Depression. Far from having an internal

source of long-term economic breakdown that will presumably create a

general interest for a new society, capitalism has been more successful

in crisis management in the last fifty years than it was in the previous

century and a half, the period of its so-called “historical ascendancy.”

The classical industrial proletariat, too, has waned in numbers in the

First World (the historical locus classicus of socialist confrontation

with capitalism), in class consciousness, and even in political

consciousness of itself as a historically unique class. Attempts to

rewrite Marxian theory to include salaried people in the proletariat are

not only nonsensical, they stand flatly at odds with how this vastly

differentiated middle-class population conceives itself and its

relationship to a market society. To live with the hope that capitalism

will “immanently” collapse from within as a result of its own

contradictory self-development is illusory as things stand today.

But there are dramatic signs that capitalism, as I have emphasized

elsewhere, is producing external conditions for a crisis an ecological

crisis — that may well generate a general human interest for radical

social change. Capitalism, organized around a “grow-or-die” market

system based on rivalry and expansion, must tear down the natural world

— turning soil into sand, polluting the atmosphere, changing the entire

climatic pattern of the planet, and possibly making the earth unsuitable

for complex forms of life. In effect, it is proving to be an ecological

cancer and may well simplify complex ecosystems that have been in the

making for countless aeons.

If mindless and unceasing growth as an end in itself — forced by

competition to accumulate and devour the organic world — creates

problems that cut across material, ethnic, and cultural differences, the

concept of “the People” and of a “public sphere” may become a living

reality in history. Some kind of radical ecology movement has yet to be

established that could acquire a unique, cohering, and political

significance to replace the influence of the traditional workers’

movement. If the locus of proletarian radicalism was the factory, the

locus of the ecology movement would be the community: the neighborhood,

the town, and the municipality. A new alternative, a political one,

would have to be developed that is neither parliamentary on the one hand

nor locked into direct action and countercultural activities on the

other. Indeed, direct action could mesh with this new politics in the

form of community assemblies oriented toward a fully participatory

democracy — in the highest form of direct action, the full empowerment

of the people in determining the destiny of society.

Society, Politics, and the State

If the 1960s gave rise to a counterculture to resist the prevailing

culture, the following decades have created the need for popular

counter-institutions to countervail the centralized state. Although the

specific form that such institutions could take may vary according to

the traditions, values, concerns, and culture of a given area, certain

basic theoretical premises must be clarified if one is to advance the

need for new institutions and, more broadly, for a new radical politics.

The need once again to define politics — indeed, to give it a broader

meaning than it has had in the past — becomes a practical imperative.

The ability and wilingness of radicals to meet this need may well

determine the future of movements like the Greens and the very

possibility of radicalism to exist as a coherent force for basic social

change.

The major institutional arenas — the social, the political, and the

statist — were once clearly distinguishable from each other. The social

arena could be clearly demarcated from the political, and the political,

in turn, from the state. But in our present, historically clouded world,

these have been blurred and mystified. Politics has been absorbed by the

state, just as society has increasingly been absorbed by the economy

today. If new, truly radical movements to deal with ecological breakdown

are to emerge and if an ecologically oriented society is to end attempts

to dominate nature as well as people, this process must be arrested and

reversed.

It easy to think of society, politics, and the state ahistorically, as

if they had always existed as we find them today. But the fact is that

each one of these has had a complex development, one that should be

understood if we are to gain a clear sense of their importance in social

theory and practice. Much of what we today call politics, for one, is

really statecraft, structured around staffing the state apparatus with

parliamentarians, judges, bureaucrats, police, the military, and the

like, a phenomenon often replicated from the summits of the state to the

smallest of communities. But the term politics, Greek etymologically,

once referred to a public arena peopled by conscious citizens who felt

competent to directly manage their own communities, or poleis.

Society, in turn, was the relatively private arena, the realm of

familial obligation, friendship, personal self-maintenance, production,

and reproduction. From its first emergence as merely human group

existence to its highly institutionalized forms, which we properly call

society, social life was structured around the family or oikos.

(Economy, in fact, once meant little more than the management of the

family.) Its core was the domestic world of woman, complemented by the

civil world of man.

In early human communities, the most important functions for survival,

care, and maintenance occurred in the domestic arena, to which the civil

arena, such as it was, largely existed in service. A tribe (to use this

term in a very broad sense to include bands and clans) was a truly

social entity, knitted together by blood, marital, and functional ties

based on age and work. These strong centripetal forces, rooted in the

biological facts of life, held these eminently social communities

together. They gave them a sense of internal solidarity so strong that

the tribes largely excluded the “stranger” or “outsider,” whose

acceptability usually depended upon canons of hospitality and the need

for new members to replenish warriors when warfare became increasingly

important.

A great part of recorded history is an account of the growth of the male

civil arena at the expense of this domestic or social one. Males gained

growing authority over the early community as a result of intertribal

warfare and clashes over territory in which to hunt. Perhaps more

important, agricultural peoples appropriated large areas of the land

that hunting peoples required to sustain themselves and their lifeways.

It was from this undifferentiated civil arena (again, to use the word

civil in a very broad sense) that politics and the state emerged. Which

is not to say that politics and statecraft were the same from the

beginning. Despite their common origins in the early civil arena, these

two were sharply opposed to each other. History’s garments are never

neat and unwrinkled. The evolution of society from small domestic social

groups into highly differentiated, hierarchical, and class systems whose

authority encompassed vast territorial empires is nothing if not complex

and irregular.

The domestic and familial arena itself — that is to say, the social

arena — helped to shape the formation of these states. Early despotic

kingdoms, such as those of Egypt and Persia, were seen not as clearly

civil entities but as the personal “households” or domestic domains of

monarchs. These vast palatial estates of “divine” kings and their

families were later carved up by lesser families into manorial or feudal

estates. The social values of present-day aristocracies are redolent of

a time when kinship and lineage, not citizenship or wealth, determined

one’s status and power.

The Rise of the Public Domain

It was the Bronze Age “urban revolution,” to use V. Gordon Childe’s

expression, that slowly eliminated the trappings of the social or

domestic arena from the state and created a new terrain for the

political arena. The rise of cities — largely around temples, military

fortresses, administrative centers, and interregional markets — created

the basis for a new, more secular and more universalistic form of

political space. Given time and development, this space slowly evolved

an unprecedented public domain.

Cities that are perfect models of such a public space do not exist in

either history or social theory. But some cities were neither

predominantly social (in the domestic sense) nor statist, but gave rise

to an entirely new societal dispensation. The most remarkable of these

were the seaports of ancient Hellas and the craft and commercial cities

of medieval Italy, Russia, and central Europe. Even modern cities of

newly forming nation- states like Spain, England, and France developed

identities of their own and relatively popular forms of citizen

participation. Their parochial, even patriarchal attributes should not

be permitted to overshadow their universal humanistic attributes. From

the Olympian standpoint of modernity, it would be as petty as it would

be ahistorical to highlight failings that cities shared with nearly all

“civilizations” over thousands of years.

What should stand out as a matter of vital importance is that these

cities created the public domain. There, in the agora of the Greek

democracies, the forum of the Roman republic, the town center of the

medieval commune, and the plaza of the Renaissance city, citizens could

congregate. To one degree or another in this public domain a radically

new arena — a political one — emerged, based on limited but often

participatory forms of democracy and a new concept of civic personhood,

the citizen.

Defined in terms of its etymological roots, politics means the mangement

of the community or polis by its members, the citizens. Politics also

meant the recognition of civic rights for strangers or “outsiders” who

were not linked to the population by blood ties. That is, it meant the

idea of a universal humanitas, as distinguished from the genealogically

related “folk.” Together with these fundamental developments, politics

was marked by the increasing secularization of societal affairs, a new

respect for the individual, and a growing regard for rational canons of

behavior over the unthinking imperatives of custom.

I do not wish to suggest that privilege, inequality of rights,

supernatural vagaries, custom, or even mistrust of the “stranger”

totally disappeared with the rise of cities and politics. During the

most radical and democratic periods of the French Revolution, for

example, Paris was rife with fears of “foreign conspiracies” and a

xenophobic mistrust of “outsiders. “ Nor did women ever fully share the

freedoms enjoyed by men. My point, however, is that something very new

was created by the city that cannot be buried in the folds of the social

or of the state: namely, a public domain. This domain narrowed and

expanded with time, but it never completely disappeared from history. It

stood very much at odds with the state, which tried in varying degrees

to professionalize and centralize power, often becoming an end in

itself, such as the state power that emerged in Ptolemaic Egypt, the

absolute monarchies of seventeenth-century Europe, and the totalitarian

systems of rule established in Russia and in China in the past century.

The Importance of the Municipality and the Confederation

The abiding physical arena of politics has almost always been the city

or town — more generically, the municipality. The size of a politically

viable city is not unimportant, to be sure. To the Greeks, notably

Aristotle, a city or polis should not be so large that it cannot deal

with its affairs on a face-to-face basis or eliminate a certain degree

of familiarity among its citizens. These standards, by no means fixed or

inviolable, were meant to foster urban development along lines that

directly countervailed the emerging state. Given a modest but by no

means small size, the polis could be arranged institutionally so that it

could conduct its affairs by rounded, publicly engaged men with a

minimal, carefully guarded degree of representation.

To be a political person, it was supposed, required certain material

preconditions. A modicum of free time was needed to participate in

political affairs, leisure that was probably supplied by slave labor,

although it is by no means true that all active Greek citizens were

slaveowners. Even more important than leisure time was the need for

personal training or character formation — the Greek notion of paidaeia

— which inculcated the reasoned restraint by which citizens maintained

the decorum needed to keep an assembly of the people viable. An ideal of

public service was necessary to outweigh narrow, egoistic impulses and

to develop the ideal of a general interest. This was achieved by

establishing a complex network of relationships, ranging from loyal

friendships — the Greek notion of philia — to shared experiences in

civic festivals and military service.

But politics in this sense was not a strictly Hellenic phenomenon.

Similar problems and needs arose and were solved in a variety of ways in

the free cities not only in the Mediterranean basin but in continental

Europe, England, and North America. Nearly all these free cities created

a public domain and a politics that were democratic to varying degrees

over long periods of time. Deeply hostile to centralized states, free

cities and their federations formed some of history’s crucial turning

points in which humanity was faced with the possibility of establishing

societies based on municipal confederations or on nation-states.

The state, too, had a historical development and cannot be reduced to a

simplistic ahistorical image. Ancient states were historically followed

by quasi- states, monarchical states, feudal states, and republican

states. The totalitarian states of this century beggar the harshest

tyrannies of the past. But essential to the rise of the nation-state was

the ability of centralized states to weaken the vitality of urban, town,

and village structures and replace their functions by bureaucracies,

police, and military forces. A subtle interplay between the municipality

and the state, often exploding in open conflict, has occurred throughout

history and has shaped the societal landscape of the present day.

Unfortunately, not enough attention has been given to the fact that the

capacity of states to exercise the full measure of their power has often

been limited by the municipal obstacles they encountered.

Nationalism, like statism, has so deeply imprinted itself on modern

thinking that the very idea of a municipalist politics as an option for

societal organization has virtually been written off. For one thing, as

I have already emphasized, politics these days has been identified

completely with statecraft, the professionalization of power. That the

political realm and the state have often been in sharp conflict with

each other — indeed, in conflicts that exploded in bloody civil wars —

has been almost completely overlooked.

The great revolutionary movements of the past, from the English

Revolution of the 1640s to those in our own century, have always been

marked by strong community upsurges and depended for their success on

strong community ties. That fears of municipal autonomy still haunt the

nation-state can be seen in the endless arguments that are brought

against it. Phenomena as “dead” as the free community and participatory

democracy should presumably arouse far fewer opponents than we continue

to encounter.

The rise of the great megalopolis has not ended the historic quest for

community and civic politics, any more than the rise of multinational

corporations has removed the issue of nationalism from the modern

agenda. Cities like New York, London, Frankfurt, Milan, and Madrid can

be politically decentralized institutionally, be they by neighborhood or

district networks, despite their large structural size and their

internal interdependence. Indeed, how well they can function if they do

not decentralize structurally is an ecological issue of paramount

importance, as problems of air pollution, adequate water supply, crime,

the quality of life, and transportation suggest.

History has shown very dramatically that major cities of Europe with

populations approaching a million and with primitive means of

communication functioned by means of well-coordinated decentralized

institutions of extraordinary political vitality. From the Castilian

cities that exploded in the Comuñero revolt in the early l500s through

the Parisian sections or assemblies of the early 1790s to the Madrid

Citizens’ Movement of the 1960s (to cite only a few), municipal

movements in large cities have posed crucial issues of where power

should be centered and how societal life should be managed

institutionally.

That a municipality can be as parochial as a tribe is fairly obvious —

and is no less true today than it has been in the past. Hence, any

municipal movement that is not confederal — that is to say, that does

not enter into a network of mutual obligations to towns and cities in

its own region — can no more be regarded as a truly political entity in

any traditional sense than a neighborhood that does not work with other

neighborhoods in the city in which it is located. Confederation, based

on shared responsibilities, full accountability of confederal delegates

to their communities, the right to recall, and firmly mandated

representative forms an indispensable part of a new politics. To demand

that existing towns and cities replicate the nation-state on a local

level is to surrender any commitment to social change as such.

What is of immense practical importance is that prestatist institutions,

traditions, and sentiments remain alive in varying degrees throughout

most of the world. Resistance to the encroachment of oppressive states

has been nourished by village, neighborhood, and town community

networks, as witness such struggles in South Africa, the Middle East,

and Latin America. To ignore the communal basis of this resistance would

be as myopic as to ignore the latent instability of every nation-state;

worse would be to take the nation-state as it is for granted and deal

with it merely on its own terms. Indeed, whether a state remains “more”

of a state or ”less” — no trifling matter to radical theorists as

disparate as Bakunin and Marx — depends heavily upon the power of local,

confederal, and community movements to countervail it and hopefully

establish a dual power that will replace it. The major role that the

Madrid Citizens’ Movement played nearly three decades ago in weakening

the Franco regime would require a major study to do it justice.

Notwithstanding Marxist visions of a largely economistic conflict

between “wage labor and capital,” the revolutionary working class

movements of the past were not simply industrial movements. The volatile

Parisian labor movement, largely artisanal in character, for example,

was also a community movement that was centered on quartiers and

nourished by a rich neighborhood life. From the Levellers of

seventeenth-century London to the anarcho-syndicalists of Barcelona in

the twentieth century, radical activity has been sustained by strong

community bonds, a public sphere provided by streets, squares, and

cafes.

The Need for a New Politics

This municipal life cannot be ignored in radical practice and must even

be recreated where it has been undermined by the modern state. A new

politics, rooted in towns, neighborhoods, cities, and regions, forms the

only viable alternative to the anemic parliamentarism that is

percolating through various Green parties today and similar social

movements — in short, their recourse to sheer and corruptive statecraft

in which the larger bourgeois parties can always be expected to

outmaneuver them and absorb them into coalitions. The duration of

strictly single-issue movements, too, is limited to the problems they

are opposing. Militant action around such issues should not be confused

with the long-range radicalism that is needed to change consciousness

and ultimately society itself. Such movements flare up and pass away,

even when they are successful. They lack the institutional underpinnings

that are so necessary to create lasting movements for social change and

the arena in which they can be a permanent presence in political

conflict.

Hence the enormous need for genuinely political grassroots movements,

united confederally, that are anchored in abiding and democratic

institutions that can be evolved into truly libertarian ones.

Life would indeed be marvelous, if not miraculous, if we were born with

all the training, literacy, skills, and mental equipment we need to

practice a profession or vocation. Alas, we must go though the toil of

acquiring these abilities, a toil that requires struggle, confrontation,

education, and development. It is very unlikely that a radical

municipalist approach, too, is meaningful at all merely as an easy means

for institutional change. It must be fought for if it is to be

cherished, just as the fight for a free society must itself be as

liberating and self-transforming as the existence of a free society.

The municipality is a potential time-bomb. To create local networks and

try to transform municipal institutions that replicate the state is to

pick up a historic challenge — a truly political one — that has existed

for centuries. New social movements are foundering today for want of a

political perspective that will bring them into the public arena, hence

the ease with which they slip into parliarnentarism. Historically,

libertarian theory has always focused on the free municipality that was

to provide the cellular tissue for a new society. To ignore the

potential of this free municipality because it is not yet free is to

bypass a slumbering domain of politics that could give lived meaning to

the great libertarian demand: a commune of communes. For in these

municipal institutions and the changes that we can make in their

structure — turning them more and more into a new public sphere — lies

the abiding institutional basis for a grassroots dual power, a

grassroots concept of citizenship, and municipalized economic systems

that can be counterposed to the growing power of the centralized

nation-state and centralized economic corporations.

The Role of Social Ecology in a Period of Reaction

Social ecology developed out of important social and theoretical

problems that faced the Left in the post-World War II period. The

historical realities of the 1940s and the 1950s completely invalidated

the perspectives of a proletarian revolution, of a “chronic economic

crisis” that would bring capitalism to its knees, and of commitment to a

centralistic workers’ party that would seize state power and, by

dictatorial means, initiate a transition to socialism and communism. It

became painfully evident in time that no such generalized crisis was in

the offing; indeed, that the proletariat and any party — or labor

confederation — that spoke in the name of the working class could not be

regarded as a hegemonic force in social transformation.

Quite to the contrary: capitalism emerged from the war stronger and more

stable than it had been at any time in its history. A generalized crisis

could be managed to one degree or another within a strictly bourgeois

framework, let alone the many limited and cyclical crises normal to

capitalism. The proletariat, in turn, ceased to play the hegemonic role

that the Left had assigned to it for more than a century, and Leninist

forms of organization were evidently vulnerable to bureaucratic

degeneration.

Moreover, capitalism, following the logic of its own nature as a

competitive market economy, was creating social and cultural issues that

had not been adequately encompassed by the traditional Left of the

interwar era (1917–39). To be sure, the traditional Left’s theoretical

cornerstone, notably, the class struggle between wage labor and capital,

had not disappeared; nor had economic exploitation ceased to exist. But

the issues that had defined the traditional Left — more precisely,

“proletarian socialism” in all its forms — had broadened immensely,

expanding both the nature of oppression and the meaning of freedom.

Hierarchy, while not supplanting the issue of class struggle, began to

move to the foreground of at least Euro-American radical concerns, in

the widespread challenges raised by the sixties “New Left” and youth

culture to authority as such, not only to the State. Domination, while

not supplanting exploitation, became the target of radical critique and

practice, in the early civil rights movement in the United States, in

attempts to remove conventional constraints on sexual behavior, dress,

lifestyle, and values, and later, in the rise of feminist movements,

ecological movements that challenged the myth of “dominating” the

natural world, and movements for gay and lesbian liberation.

It is unlikely that any of these movements would have emerged had

capitalism at midcentury not created all the indispensable technological

preconditions for a libertarian communist society — prospects that are

consistent with Enlightenment ideals and the progressive dimensions of

modernity. One must return to the great debates that began in the late

1950s over the prospects for free time and material abundance to

understand the ideological atmosphere that new technologies such as

automation created and the extent to which they were absorbed by the

“New Left” of the 1960s.

The prospect of a post-scarcity society, free of material want and

demanding toil, opened a new horizon of potentiality and hope —

ironically, reiterating the prescient demands of the Berlin Dadaists of

1919 for “universal unemployment,” which stood in marked contrast to the

traditional Left’s demand for “full employment.”

The Struggle for a Rational Society

Social ecology, as developed in the United States in the early sixties

(long after the expression had fallen into disuse as a variant of “human

ecology”), tried to advance a coherent, developmental, and socially

practical outlook to deal with the changes in radicalism and capitalism

that were in the offing. Indeed, in great part, it actually anticipated

them. Long before an ecology movement emerged, social ecology delineated

the scope of the ecological crisis that capitalism must necessarily

produce, tracing its roots back to hierarchical domination, and

emphasizing that a competitive capitalist economy must unavoidably give

rise to unprecendented contradictions with the nonhuman natural world.

None of these perspectives, it should be noted, were in the air in the

early sixties — Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring with its emphasis on

pesticides notwithstanding. Indeed, as early as 1962, social ecology

projected the alternative of solar energy, wind power, and water power,

among other new ecotechnologies, and alternatives to existing productive

facilities that were to become axiomatic to a later generation of

ecologists. It also advanced the vision of new ecocommunities based on

direct democracy and nonhierarchical forms of human relations. These

facts should be emphasized in view of deep ecology’s attempt to rewrite

the history of the ecology movement in terms of its own quasi-religious

and scarcity-oriented outlook. Nor should we overlook the fact that

social ecology’s antihierarchical analyses laid the theoretical basis

for early feminism, various community movements, the antinuclear

movement, and in varying degrees, Green movements, before they turned

from “nonparty parties” into conventional electoral machines.

Nonetheless, social ecology makes no claim that it emerged ab novo. It

was — and it remains — deeply rooted in Enlightenment ideals and the

revolutionary tradition of the past two centuries. Its analyses and

goals have never been detached from the understandably less developed

theoretical analyses of Karl Marx and classical radical thinkers (like

Peter Kropotkin), or from the great revolutions that culminated in the

Spanish Revolution of 1936–37. It eschews any attempt to defame the

historic traditions of the Left in favor a neo-liberal patchwork of

ideas or a queasy political centrism that parades as “postmodernism” and

“post- industrialism,” not to speak of the “post-materialist”

spiritualism fostered by eco-feminists, life-style anarchists, deep

ecologists, and so-called “social deep ecologists” or “deep social

ecologists.”

Quite to the contrary: social ecology functions to countervail attempts

to denature the Enlightenment and revolutionary project by emphasizing

the need for theoretical coherence, no less today than it did in the

1960s, when the “New Left” drifted from a healthy libertarian populism

into a quagmire of Leninist, Maoist, and Trotskyist tendencies. Social

ecology retains its filiations with the Enlightenment and the

revolutionary tradition all the more emphatically in opposition to the

quasi-mystical and expressly mystical trends that are thoroughly

sweeping up the privileged petty bourgeoisie of North America and

Europe, with their goulash of antirational, spiritualistic, and

atavastic ideologies. Social ecology is only too mindful that capitalism

today has a nearly infinite capacity to coopt, indeed commodify,

self-styled “oppositional trends” that remain as the detritus of the

“New Left” and the old counterculture. Today, anarchism comes packaged

by Hakim Bey, Bob Black, David Watson, and Jason McQuinn, and is little

more than a merchandisable boutique ideology that panders to petty-

bourgeois tastes for naughtiness and eccentricity.

Ecology, too, has been packaged and repackaged into a variety of “deep

ecologies” that generally emphasize an animalistic reductionism,

neo-Malthusian “hunger politics,” antihumanism, and bio- or

“eco-”centrism — in short, a pastiche that renders it equally palatable

to members of the British royal family at the summit of the social

hierarchy and to lumpenized anarchoids at its base. Feminism, initially

a universalized challenge to hierarchy as such, has devolved into

parochial, often self-serving, and even materially rewarding species of

eco-feminism and express theisms that pander to a myth of gender

superiority (no less ugly when it concerns women than when it concerns

men) in one form or another — not to speak of the outright

wealth-oriented “feminism” promoted by Naomi Wolf et al.

Capitalism, in effect, has not only rendered the human condition more

and more irrational, but it has absorbed into its orbit, to one degree

or another, the very consciousness that once professed to oppose it. If

Fourier insightfully declared that the way a society treats its women

can be regarded as a measure of its status as a civilization, so today

we can add that the extent to which a society devolves into mysticism

and eclecticism can be regarded as measure of its cultural decline. By

these standards, no society has more thoroughly denatured its

once-radical opponents than capitalism in the closing years of the

twentieth century.

The Relevance of Social Ecology

This devolution of consciousness is by no means solely the product of

our century’s new global media, as even radical theorists of popular

culture tend to believe. Absolutism and medievalism, no less than

capitalism, had its own “media,” the Church, that reached as

ubiquitously into every village as television reaches into the modern

living room. The roots of modern cultural devolution are as deep-seated

as the ecological crisis itself. Capitalism, today, is openly flaunted

not only as a system of social relationships but as the “end of

history,” indeed, as a natural society that expresses the most intrinsic

qualities of “human nature” — its ostensible “drive” to compete, win,

and grow. This transmutation of means into ends, vicious as the means

may be, is not merely “the American way”; it is the bourgeois way.

The commodity has now colonized every aspect of life, rendering what was

once a capitalist economy into a capitalist culture. It has produced

literally a “marketplace of ideas,” in which the coin for exchanging

inchoate notions and intuitions is validated by the academy, the

corrupter par excellence of the “best and brightest” in modern society

and the eviscerator of all that is coherent and clearly delineable.

Indeed, never has “high culture,” once guarded by academic mandarins,

been so scandalously debased by academic presses that have become the

pornographers of ideology.

Bourgeois society qua culture, particularly its academic purveyors,

abhors a principled stand, particularly a combative one that is prepared

to clearly articulate a body of coherent principles and thrust it into

opposition against the capitalist system as a whole. Theoretically and

practically, serious opposition takes its point of departure from the

need to understand the logic of an ideology, not its euphemistic

metaphors and drifting inconsistencies. Capitalism has nothing to fear

from an ecological, feminist, anarchist, or socialist hash of hazy ideas

(often fatuously justified as “pluralistic” or “relativistic”) that

leaves its social premises untouched. It is all the better for the

prevailing order that reason be denounced as “logocentrism,” that

bourgeois social relations be concealed under the rubric of “industrial

society,” that the social need for an oppositional movement be brushed

aside in favor of a personal need for spiritual redemption, that the

political be reduced to the personal, that the project of social

revolution be erased by hopeless communitarian endeavors to create

“alternative” enterprises.

Except where its profits and “growth opportunities” are concerned,

capitalism now delights in avowals of the need to “compromise,” to seek

a “common ground” — the language of its professoriat no less than its

political establishment — which invariably turns out to be its own

terrain in a mystified form.

Hence the popularity of “market socialism” in self-styled “leftist”

periodicals; or possibly “social deep ecology” in deep ecology

periodicals like The Trumpeter; or more brazenly, accolades to Gramsci

by the Nouvelle Droite in France, or to a “Green Adolf ” in Germany. A

Robin Eckersley has no difficulty juggling the ideas of the Frankfurt

School with deep ecology while comparing in truly biocentric fashion the

“navigational skills” of birds with the workings of the human mind. The

wisdom of making friends with everyone that underpins this academic

“discourse” can only lead to a blurring of latent and serious

differences — and ultimately to the compromise of all principles and the

loss of political direction.

The social and cultural decomposition produced by capitalism can be

resisted only by taking the most principled stand against the corrosion

of nearly all self-professed oppositional ideas. More than at any time

in the past, social ecologists should abandon the illusion that a shared

use of the word “social” renders all of us into socialists, or

“ecology,” into radical ecologists. The measure of social ecology’s

relevance and theoretical integrity consists of its ability to be

rational, ethical, coherent, and true to the ideal of the Enlightenment

and the revolutionary tradition — not of any ability to earn plaudits

from the Prince of Wales, Al Gore, or Gary Snyder, still less from

academics, spiritualists, and mystics. In this darkening age when

capitalism — the mystified social order par excellence — threatens to

globalize the world with capital, commodities, and a facile spirit of

“negotiation” and “compromise,” it is necessary to keep alive the very

idea of uncompromising critique. It is not dogmatic to insist on

consistency, to infer and contest the logic of a given body of premises,

to demand clarity in a time of cultural twilight. Indeed, quite to the

contrary, eclecticism and theoretical chaos, not to speak of practices

that are more theatrical than threatening and that consist more of

posturing than convincing, will only dim the light of truth and

critique. Until social forces emerge that can provide a voice for basic

social change rather than spiritual redemption, social ecology must take

upon itself the task of preserving and extending the great traditions

from which it has emerged.

Should the darkness of capitalist barbarism thicken to the point where

this enterprise is no longer possible, history as the rational

development of humanity’s potentialities for freedom and consciousness

will indeed reach its definitive end.

The Communalist Project

Whether the twenty-first century will be the most radical of times or

the most reactionary — or will simply lapse into a gray era of dismal

mediocrity — will depend overwhelmingly upon the kind of social movement

and program that social radicals create out of the theoretical,

organizational, and political wealth that has accumulated during the

past two centuries of the revolutionary era. The direction we select,

from among several intersecting roads of human development, may well

determine the future of our species for centuries to come. As long as

this irrational society endangers us with nuclear and biological

weapons, we cannot ignore the possibility that the entire human

enterprise may come to a devastating end. Given the exquisitely

elaborate technical plans that the military-industrial complex has

devised, the self- extermination of the human species must be included

in the futuristic scenarios that, at the turn of the millennium, the

mass media are projecting — the end of a human future as such.

Lest these remarks seem too apocalyptic, I should emphasize that we also

live in an era when human creativity, technology, and imagination have

the capability to produce extraordinary material achievements and to

endow us with societies that allow for a degree of freedom that far and

away exceeds the most dramatic and emancipatory visions projected by

social theorists such as Saint- Simon, Charles Fourier, Karl Marx, and

Peter Kropotkin.[10] Many thinkers of the postmodern age have obtusely

singled out science and technology as the principal threats to human

well-being, yet few disciplines have imparted to humanity such a

stupendous knowledge of the innermost secrets of matter and life, or

provided our species better with the ability to alter every important

feature of reality and to improve the well-being of human and nonhuman

life-forms.

We are thus in a position either to follow a path toward a grim “end of

history,” in which a banal succession of vacuous events replaces genuine

progress, or to move on to a path toward the true making of history, in

which humanity genuinely progresses toward a rational world. We are in a

position to choose between an ignominious finale, possibly including the

catastrophic nuclear oblivion of history itself, and history’s rational

fulfillment in a free, materially abundant society in an aesthetically

crafted environment.

Notwithstanding the technological marvels that competing enterprises of

the ruling class (that is, the bourgeoisie) are developing in order to

achieve hegemony over one another, little of a subjective nature that

exists in the existing society can redeem it. Precisely at a time when

we, as a species, are capable of producing the means for amazing

objective advances and improvements in the human condition and in the

nonhuman natural world — advances that could make for a free and

rational society — we stand almost naked morally before the onslaught of

social forces that may very well lead to our physical immolation.

Prognoses about the future are understandably very fragile and are

easily distrusted. Pessimism has become very widespread, as capitalist

social relations become more deeply entrenched in the human mind than

ever before, and as culture regresses appallingly, almost to a vanishing

point. To most people today, the hopeful and very radical certainties of

the twenty-year period between the Russian Revolution of 1917–18 and the

end of the Spanish Civil War in 1939 seem almost naïve.

Yet our decision to create a better society, and our choice of the way

to do it, must come from within ourselves, without the aid of a deity,

still less a mystical “force of nature” or a charismatic leader. If we

choose the road toward a better future, our choice must be the

consequence of our ability — and ours alone — to learn from the material

lessons of the past and to appreciate the real prospects of the future.

We will need to have recourse, not to ghostly vagaries conjured up from

the murky hell of superstition or, absurdly, from the couloirs of the

academy, but to the innovative attributes that make up our very humanity

and the essential features that account for natural and social

development, as opposed to the social pathologies and accidental events

that have sidetracked humanity from its self-fulfillment in

consciousness and reason. Having brought history to a point where nearly

everything is possible, at least of a material nature — and having left

behind a past that was permeated ideologically by mystical and religious

elements produced by the human imagination — we are faced with a new

challenge, one that has never before confronted humanity. We must

consciously create our own world, not according to demonic fantasies,

mindless customs, and destructive prejudices, but according to the

canons of reason, reflection, and discourse that uniquely belong to our

own species.

Capitalism, Classes, and Hierarchies

What factors should be decisive in making our choice? First, of great

significance is the immense accumulation of social and political

experience that is available to revolutionaries today, a storehouse of

knowledge that, properly conceived, could be used to avoid the terrible

errors that our predecessors made and to spare humanity the terrible

plagues of failed revolutions in the past. Of indispensable importance

is the potential for a new theoretical springboard that has been created

by the history of ideas, one that provides the means to catapult an

emerging radical movement beyond existing social conditions into a

future that fosters humanity’s emancipation.

But we must also be fully aware of the scope of the problems that we

face. We must understand with complete clarity where we stand in the

development of the prevailing capitalist order, and we have to grasp

emergent social problems and address them in the program of a new

movement. Capitalism is unquestionably the most dynamic society ever to

appear in history. By definition, to be sure, it always remains a system

of commodity exchange in which objects that are made for sale and profit

pervade and mediate most human relations. Yet capitalism is also a

highly mutable system, continually advancing the brutal maxim that

whatever enterprise does not grow at the expense of its rivals must die.

Hence “growth” and perpetual change become the very laws of life of

capitalist existence. This means that capitalism never remains

permanently in only one form; it must always transform the institutions

that arise from its basic social relations.

Although capitalism became a dominant society only in the past few

centuries, it long existed on the periphery of earlier societies: in a

largely commercial form, structured around trade between cities and

empires; in a craft form throughout the European Middle Ages; in a

hugely industrial form in our own time; and if we are to believe recent

seers, in an informational form in the coming period. It has created not

only new technologies but also a great variety of economic and social

structures, such as the small shop, the factory, the huge mill, and the

industrial and commercial complex. Certainly the capitalism of the

Industrial Revolution has not completely disappeared, any more than the

isolated peasant family and small craftsman of a still earlier period

have been consigned to complete oblivion. Much of the past is always

incorporated into the present; indeed, as Marx insistently warned, there

is no “pure capitalism,” and none of the earlier forms of capitalism

fade away until radically new social relations are established and

become overwhelmingly dominant. But today capitalism, even as it

coexists with and utilizes precapitalist institutions for its own ends

(see Marx’s Grundrisse for this dialectic), now reaches into the suburbs

and the countryside with its shopping malls and newly styled factories.

Indeed, it is by no means inconceivable that one day it will reach

beyond our planet. In any case, it has produced not only new commodities

to create and feed new wants but new social and cultural issues, which

in turn have given rise to new supporters and antagonists of the

existing system. The famous first part of Marx and Engels’s Communist

Manifesto, in which they celebrate capitalism’s wonders, would have to

be periodically rewritten to keep pace with the achievements — as well

as the horrors — produced by the bourgeoisie’s development.

One of the most striking features of capitalism today is that in the

Western world the highly simplified two-class structure- the bourgeoisie

and the proletariat-that Marx and Engels, in T he Communist Manifesto,

predicted would become dominant under “mature” capitalism (and we have

yet to determine what “mature,” still less “late” or “moribund”

capitalism actually is) has undergone a process of reconfiguration. The

conflict between wage labor and capital, while it has by no means

disappeared, nonetheless lacks the all-embracing importance that it

possessed in the past. Contrary to Marx’s expectations, the industrial

working class is now dwindling in numbers and is steadily losing its

traditional identity as a class — which by no means excludes it from a

potentially broader and perhaps more extensive conflict of society as a

whole against capitalist social relations. Present-day culture, social

relations, cityscapes, modes of production, agriculture, and

transportation have remade the traditional proletariat, upon which

syndicalists and Marxists were overwhelmingly, indeed almost mystically

focused, into a largely petty-bourgeois stratum whose mentality is

marked by its own bourgeois utopianism of “consumption for the sake of

consumption.” We can foresee a time when the proletarian, whatever the

color of his or her collar or place on the assembly line, will be

completely replaced by automated and even miniaturized means of

production that are operated by a few white-coated manipulators of

machines and by computers.

By the same token, the living standards of the traditional proletariat

and its material expectations (no small factor in the shaping of social

consciousness!) have changed enormously, soaring within only a

generation or two from near poverty to a comparatively high degree of

material affluence. Among the children and grandchildren of former steel

and automobile workers and coal miners, who have no proletarian class

identity, a college education has replaced the high school diploma as

emblematic of a new class status. In the United States once-opposing

class interests have converged to a point that almost 50 percent of

American households own stocks and bonds, while a huge number are

proprietors of one kind or another, possessing their own homes, gardens,

and rural summer retreats.

Given these changes, the stern working man or woman, portrayed in

radical posters of the past with a flexed, highly muscular arm holding a

bone-crushing hammer, has been replaced by the genteel and well-mannered

(so-called) “working middle class.” The traditional cry “Workers of the

world, unite!” in its old historical sense becomes ever more

meaningless. The class-consciousness of the proletariat, which Marx

tried to awaken in The Communist Manifesto, has been hemorrhaging

steadily and in many places has virtually disappeared. The more

existential class struggle has not been eliminated, to be sure, any more

than the bourgeoisie could eliminate gravity from the existing human

condition, but unless radicals today become aware of the fact that it

has been narrowed down largely to the individual factory or office, they

will fail to see that a new, perhaps more expansive form of social

consciousness can emerge in the generalized struggles that face us.

Indeed, this form of social consciousness can be given a refreshingly

new meaning as the concept of the rebirth of the citoyen — a concept so

important to the Great Revolution of 1789 and its more broadly

humanistic sentiment of sociality that it became the form of address

among later revolutionaries summoned to the barricades by the heraldic

crowing of the red French rooster.

Seen as a whole, the social condition that capitalism has produced today

stands very much at odds with the simplistic class prognoses advanced by

Marx and by the revolutionary French syndicalists. After the Second

World War, capitalism underwent an enormous transformation, creating

broad new social issues with extraordinary rapidity, issues that went

beyond traditional proletarian demands for improved wages, hours, and

working conditions: notably environmental, gender, hierarchical, civic,

and democratic issues. Capitalism, in effect, has generalized its

threats to humanity, particularly with climatic changes that may alter

the very face of the planet, oligarchical institutions of a global

scope, and rampant urbanization that radically corrodes the civic life

basic to grassroots politics.

Hierarchy, today, is becoming as pronounced an issue as class — as

witness the extent to which many social analyses have singled out

managers, bureaucrats, scientists, and the like as emerging, ostensibly

dominant groups. New and elaborate gradations of status and interests

count today to an extent that they did not in the recent past; they blur

the conflict between wage labor and capital that was once so central,

clearly defined, and militantly waged by traditional socialists. Class

categories are now intermingled with hierarchical categories based on

race, gender, sexual preference, and certainly national or regional

differences. Status differentiations, characteristic of hierarchy, tend

to converge with class differentiations, and a more all-inclusive

capitalistic world is emerging in which ethnic, national, and gender

differences often surpass the importance of class differences in the

public eye. This phenomenon is not entirely new: in the First World War

countless German socialist workers cast aside their earlier commitment

to the red flags of proletarian unity in favor of the national flags of

their well-fed and parasitic rulers and went on to plunge bayonets into

the bodies of French and Russian socialist workers — as they did, in

turn, under the national flags of their own oppressors.

At the same time capitalism has produced a new, perhaps paramount

contradiction: the clash between an economy based on unending growth and

the desiccation of the natural environment. [11] This issue and its vast

ramifications can no more be minimized, let alone dismissed, than the

need of human beings for food or air. At present the most promising

struggles in the West, where socialism was born, seem to be waged less

around income and working conditions than around nuclear power,

pollution, deforestation, urban blight, education, health care,

community life, and the oppression of people in underdeveloped

countries-as witness the (albeit sporadic) antiglobalization upsurges,

in which blue- and white-collar “workers” march in the same ranks with

middle-class humanitarians and are motivated by common social concerns.

Proletarian combatants become indistinguishable from middle- class ones.

Burly workers, whose hallmark is a combative militancy, now march behind

“bread and puppet” theater performers, often with a considerable measure

of shared playfulness. Members of the working and middle classes now

wear many different social hats, so to speak, challenging capitalism

obliquely as well as directly on cultural as well as economic grounds.

Nor can we ignore, in deciding what direction we are to follow, the fact

that capitalism, if it is not checked, will in the future-and not

necessarily the very distant future — differ appreciably from the system

we know today. Capitalist development can be expected to vastly alter

the social horizon in the years ahead. Can we suppose that factories,

offices, cities, residential areas, industry, commerce, and agriculture,

let alone moral values, aesthetics, media, popular desires, and the like

will not change immensely before the twenty-first century is out? In the

past century, capitalism, above all else, has broadened social issues —

indeed, the historical social question of how a humanity, divided by

classes and exploitation, will create a society based on equality, the

development of authentic harmony, and freedom — to include those whose

resolution was barely foreseen by the liberatory social theorists in the

nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Our age, with its endless

array of “bottom lines” and “investment choices,” now threatens to turn

society itself into a vast and exploitative marketplace. [12]

The public with which the progressive socialist had to deal is also

changing radically and will continue to do so in the coming decades. To

lag in understanding behind the changes that capitalism is introducing

and the new or broader contradictions it is producing would be to commit

the recurringly disastrous error that led to the defeat of nearly all

revolutionary upsurges in the past two centuries. Foremost among the

lessons that a new revolutionary movement must learn from the past is

that it must win over broad sectors of the middle class to its new

populist program. No attempt to replace capitalism with socialism ever

had or will have the remotest chance of success without the aid of the

discontented petty bourgeoisie, whether it was the intelligentsia and

peasantry-in-uniform of the Russian Revolution or the intellectuals,

farmers, shopkeepers, clerks, and managers in industry and even in

government in the German upheavals of 1918–21. Even during the most

promising periods of past revolutionary cycles, the Bolsheviks,

Mensheviks, the German Social Democrats, and Russian Communists never

acquired absolute majorities in their respective legislatives bodies.

So-called “proletarian revolutions” were invariably minority

revolutions, usually even within the proletariat itself, and those that

succeeded (often briefly, before they were subdued or drifted

historically out of the revolutionary movement) depended overwhelmingly

on the fact that the bourgeoisie lacked active support among its own

military forces or was simply socially demoralized.

Marxism, Anarchism and Syndicalism

Given the changes that we are witnessing and those that are still taking

form, social radicals can no longer oppose the predatory (as well as

immensely creative) capitalist system by using the ideologies and

methods that were born in the first Industrial Revolution, when a

factory proletarian seemed to be the principal antagonist of a textile

plant owner. (Nor can we use ideologies that were spawned by conflicts

that an impoverished peasantry used to oppose feudal and semifeudal

landowners.) None of the professedly anticapitalist ideologies of the

past — Marxism, anarchism, syndicalism, and more generic forms of

socialism — retain the same relevance that they had at an earlier stage

of capitalist development and in an earlier period of technological

advance. Nor can any of them hope to encompass the multitude of new

issues, opportunities, problems, and interests that capitalism has

repeatedly created over time.

Marxism was the most comprehensive and coherent effort to produce a

systematic form of socialism, emphasizing the material as well as the

subjective historical preconditions of a new society. This project, in

the present era of precapitalist economic decomposition and of

intellectual confusion, relativism, and subjectivism, must never

surrender to the new barbarians, many of whom find their home in what

was once a barrier to ideological regression-the academy. We owe much to

Marx’s attempt to provide us with a coherent and stimulating analysis of

the commodity and commodity relations, to an activist philosophy, a

systematic social theory, an objectively grounded or “scientific”

concept of historical development, and a flexible political strategy.

Marxist political ideas were eminently relevant to the needs of a

terribly disoriented proletariat and to the particular oppressions that

the industrial bourgeoisie inflicted upon it in England in the 1840s,

somewhat later in France, Italy, and Germany, and very presciently in

Russia in the last decade of Marx’s life. Until the rise of the populist

movement in Russia (most famously, the Narodnaya Volya), Marx expected

the emerging proletariat to become the great majority of the population

in Europe and North America, and to inevitably engage in revolutionary

class war as a result of capitalist exploitation and immiseration. And

especially between 1917 and 1939, long after Marx’s death, Europe was

indeed beleaguered by a mounting class war that reached the point of

outright workers’ insurrections. In 1917, owing to an extraordinary

confluence of circumstances — particularly with the outbreak of the

First World War, which rendered several quasi-feudal European social

systems terribly unstable — Lenin and the Bolsheviks tried to use (but

greatly altered) Marx’s writings in order to take power in an

economically backward empire, whose size spanned eleven time zones

across Europe and Asia. [13]

But for the most part, as we have seen, Marxism’s economic insights

belonged to an era of emerging factory capitalism in the nineteenth

century. Brilliant as a theory of the material preconditions for

socialism, it did not address the ecological, civic, and subjective

forces or the efficient causes that could impel humanity into a movement

for revolutionary social change. On the contrary, for nearly a century

Marxism stagnated theoretically. Its theorists were often puzzled by

developments that have passed it by and, since the 1960s, have

mechanically appended environmentalist and feminist ideas to its

formulaic ouvrierist outlook.

By the same token, anarchism — which, I believe, represents in its

authentic form a highly individualistic outlook that fosters a radically

unfettered lifestyle, often as a substitute for mass action-is far

better suited to articulate a Proudhonian single-family peasant and

craft world than a modern urban and industrial environment. I myself

once used this political label, but further thought has obliged me to

conclude that, its often-refreshing aphorisms and insights

notwithstanding, it is simply not a social theory. Its foremost

theorists celebrate its seeming openness to eclecticism and the

liberatory effects of “paradox” or even “contradiction,” to use

Proudhonian hyperbole. Accordingly, and without prejudice to the

earnestness of many anarchistic practices, a case can made that many of

the ideas of social and economic reconstruction that in the past have

been advanced in the name of “anarchy” were often drawn from Marxism

(including my own concept of “post-scarcity,” which understandably

infuriated many anarchists who read my essays on the subject).

Regrettably, the use of socialistic terms has often prevented anarchists

from telling us or even understanding clearly what they are:

individualists whose concepts of autonomy originate in a strong

commitment to personal liberty rather than to social freedom, or

socialists committed to a structured, institutionalized, and responsible

form of social organization. Indeed the history of this “ideology” is

peppered with idiosyncratic acts of defiance that verge on the

eccentric, which not surprisingly have attracted many young people and

aesthetes.

In fact anarchism represents the most extreme formulation of

liberalism’s ideology of unfettered autonomy, culminating in a

celebration of heroic acts of defiance of the state. Anarchism’s mythos

of self-regulation (auto nomos) — the radical assertion of the

individual over or even against society and the personalistic absence of

responsibility for the collective welfare — leads to a radical

affirmation of the all-powerful will so central to Nietzsche’s

ideological peregrinations. Some self-professed anarchists have even

denounced mass social action as futile and alien to their private

concerns and made a fetish of what the Spanish anarchists called

grupismo, a small-group mode of action that is highly personal rather

than social.

Anarchism has often been confused with revolutionary syndicalism, a

highly structured and well-developed mass form of libertarian trade

unionism that, unlike anarchism, was long committed to democratic

procedures,[14] to discipline in action, and to organized, long-range

revolutionary practice to eliminate capitalism. Its affinity with

anarchism stems from its strong libertarian bias, but bitter antagonisms

between anarchists and syndicalists have a long history in nearly every

country in Western Europe and North America, as witness the tensions

between the Spanish CNT and the anarchist groups associated with Tierra

y Libertad early in the twentieth century; between the revolutionary

syndicalist and anarchist groups in Russia during the 1917 revolution;

and between the IWW in the United States and the SAC in Sweden, to cite

the more illustrative cases in the history of the libertarian labor

movement. More than one American anarchist was affronted by Joe Hill’s

defiant maxim on the eve of his execution in Utah: “Don’t mourn —

Organize!” Alas, small groups were not quite the “organizations” that

Joe Hill, or the grossly misunderstood idol of the Spanish libertarian

movement, Salvador Seguí, had in mind. It was largely the shared word

libertarian that made it possible for somewhat confused anarchists to

coexist in the same organization with revolutionary syndicalists. It was

often verbal confusion rather than ideological clarity that made

possible the coexistence in Spain of the FAI, as represented by the

anarchist Federica Montseny, with the syndicalists, as represented by

Juan Prieto, in the CNT- FAI, a truly confused organization if ever

there was one.

Revolutionary syndicalism’s destiny has been tied in varying degrees to

a pathology called ouvrierisme, or “workerism,” and whatever philosophy,

theory of history, or political economy it possesses has been borrowed,

often piecemeal and indirectly, from Marx — indeed, Georges Sorel and

many other professed revolutionary syndicalists in the early twentieth

century expressly regarded themselves as Marxists and even more

expressly eschewed anarchism. Moreover, revolutionary syndicalism lacks

a strategy for social change beyond the general strike, which

revolutionary uprisings such as the famous October and November general

strikes in Russia during 1905 proved to be stirring but ultimately

ineffectual. Indeed, as invaluable as the general strike may be as a

prelude to direct confrontation with the state, they decidedly do not

have the mystical capacity that revolutionary syndicalists assigned to

them as means for social change. Their limitations are striking evidence

that, as episodic forms of direct action, general strikes are not

equatable with revolution nor even with profound social changes, which

presuppose a mass movement and require years of gestation and a clear

sense of direction. Indeed, revolutionary syndicalism exudes a typical

ouvrierist anti-intellectualism that disdains attempts to formulate a

purposive revolutionary direction and a reverence for proletarian

“spontaneity” that, at times, has led it into highly self-destructive

situations. Lacking the means for an analysis of their situation, the

Spanish syndicalists (and anarchists) revealed only a minimal capacity

to understand the situation in which they found themselves after their

victory over Franco’s forces in the summer of 1936 and no capacity to

take “the next step” to institutionalize a workers’ and peasants’ form

of government.

What these observations add up to is that Marxists, revolutionary

syndicalists, and authentic anarchists all have a fallacious

understanding of politics, which should be conceived as the civic arena

and the institutions by which people democratically and directly manage

their community affairs. Indeed the Left has repeatedly mistaken

statecraft for politics by its persistent failure to understand that the

two are not only radically different but exist in radical tension — in

fact, opposition — to each other.[15] As I have written elsewhere,

historically politics did not emerge from the state — an apparatus whose

professional machinery is designed to dominate and facilitate the

exploitation of the citizenry in the interests of a privileged class.

Rather, politics, almost by definition, is the active engagement of free

citizens in the handling their municipal affairs and in their defense of

its freedom. One can almost say that politics is the “embodiment” of

what the French revolutionaries of the 1790s called civicisme. Quite

properly, in fact, the word politics itself contains the Greek word for

“city” or polis, and its use in classical Athens, together with

democracy, connoted the direct governing of the city by its citizens.

Centuries of civic degradation, marked particularly by the formation of

classes, were necessary to produce the state and its corrosive

absorption of the political realm.

A defining feature of the Left is precisely the Marxist, anarchist, and

revolutionary syndicalist belief that no distinction exists, in

principle, between the political realm and the statist realm.

By emphasizing the nation-state — including a “workers’ state”- as the

locus of economic as well as political power, Marx (as well as

libertarians) notoriously failed to demonstrate how workers could fully

and directly control such a state without the mediation of an empowered

bureaucracy and essentially statist (or equivalently, in the case of

libertarians, governmental) institutions. As a result, the Marxists

unavoidably saw the political realm, which it designated a “workers’

state,” as a repressive entity, ostensibly based on the interests of a

single class, the proletariat.

Revolutionary syndicalism, for its part, emphasized factory control by

workers’ committees and confederal economic councils as the locus of

social authority, thereby simply bypassing any popular institutions that

existed outside the economy. Oddly, this was economic determinism with a

vengeance, which, tested by the experiences of the Spanish revolution of

1936, proved completely ineffectual. A vast domain of real governmental

power, from military affairs to the administration of justice, fell to

the Stalinists and the liberals of Spain, who used their authority to

subvert the libertarian movement — and with it, the revolutionary

achievements of the syndicalist workers in July 1936, or what was dourly

called by one novelist “The Brief Summer of Spanish Anarchism.”

As for anarchism, Bakunin expressed the typical view of its adherents in

1871 when he wrote that the new social order could be created “only

through the development and organization of the nonpolitical or

antipolitical social power of the working class in city and country,”

thereby rejecting with characteristic inconsistency the very municipal

politics which he sanctioned in Italy around the same year. Accordingly,

anarchists have long regarded every government as a state and condemned

it accordingly — a view that is a recipe for the elimination of any

organized social life whatever. While the state is the instrument by

which an oppressive and exploitative class regulates and coercively

controls the behavior of an exploited class by a ruling class, a

government — or better still, a polity — is an ensemble of institutions

designed to deal with the problems of consociational life in an orderly

and hopefully fair manner. Every institutionalized association that

constitutes a system for handling public affairs — with or without the

presence of a state — is necessarily a government. By contrast, every

state, although necessarily a form of government, is a force for class

repression and control. Annoying as it must seem to Marxists and

anarchist alike, the cry for a constitution, for a responsible and a

responsive government, and even for law or nomos has been clearly

articulated — and committed to print! — by the oppressed for centuries

against the capricious rule exercised by monarchs, nobles, and

bureaucrats. The libertarian opposition to law, not to speak of

government as such, has been as silly as the image of a snake swallowing

its tail. What remains in the end is nothing but a retinal afterimage

that has no existential reality.

The issues raised in the preceding pages are of more than academic

interest. As we enter the twenty-first century, social radicals need a

socialism — libertarian and revolutionary — that is neither an extension

of the peasant-craft “associationism” that lies at the core of anarchism

nor the proletarianism that lies at the core of revolutionary

syndicalism and Marxism. However fashionable the traditional ideologies

(particularly anarchism) may be among young people today, a truly

progressive socialism that is informed by libertarian as well as Marxian

ideas but transcends these older ideologies must provide intellectual

leadership. For political radicals today to simply resuscitate Marxism,

anarchism, or revolutionary syndicalism and endow them with ideological

immortality would be obstructive to the development of a relevant

radical movement. A new and comprehensive revolutionary outlook is

needed, one that is capable of systematically addressing the generalized

issues that may potentially bring most of society into opposition to an

ever-evolving and changing capitalist system.

The clash between a predatory society based on indefinite expansion and

nonhuman nature has given rise to an ensemble of ideas that has emerged

as the explication of the present social crisis and meaningful radical

change. Social ecology, a coherent vision of social development that

intertwines the mutual impact of hierarchy and class on the civilizing

of humanity, has for decades argued that we must reorder social

relations so that humanity can live in a protective balance with the

natural world.

Contrary to the simplistic ideology of “eco-anarchism,” social ecology

maintains that an ecologically oriented society can be progressive

rather than regressive, placing a strong emphasis not on primitivism,

austerity, and denial but on material pleasure and ease. If a society is

to be capable of making life not only vastly enjoyable for its members

but also leisurely enough that they can engage in the intellectual and

cultural self-cultivation that is necessary for creating civilization

and a vibrant political life, it must not denigrate technics and science

but bring them into accord with visions of human happiness and leisure.

Social ecology is an ecology not of hunger and material deprivation but

of plenty; it seeks the creation of a rational society in which waste,

indeed excess, will be controlled by a new system of values; and when or

if shortages arise as a result of irrational behavior, popular

assemblies will establish rational standards of consumption by

democratic processes. In short, social ecology favors management, plans,

and regulations formulated democratically by popular assemblies, not

freewheeling forms of behavior that have their origin in individual

eccentricities.

Communalism and Libertarian Municipalism

It is my contention that Communalism is the overarching political

category most suitable to encompass the fully thought out and systematic

views of social ecology, including libertarian municipalism and

dialectical naturalism.[16] As an ideology, Communalism draws on the

best of the older Left ideologies-Marxism and anarchism, more properly

the libertarian socialist tradition-while offering a wider and more

relevant scope for our time. From Marxism, it draws the basic project of

formulating a rationally systematic and coherent socialism that

integrates philosophy, history, economics, and politics. Avowedly

dialectical, it attempts to infuse theory with practice. From anarchism,

it draws its commitment to antistatism and confederalism, as well as its

recognition that hierarchy is a basic problem that can be overcome only

by a libertarian socialist society.[17]

The choice of the term Communalism to encompass the philosophical,

historical, political, and organizational components of a socialism for

the twenty-first century has not been a flippant one. The word

originated in the Paris Commune of 1871, when the armed people of the

French capital raised barricades not only to defend the city council of

Paris and its administrative substructures but also to create a

nationwide confederation of cities and towns to replace the republican

nation-state. Communalism as an ideology is not sullied by the

individualism and the often explicit antirationalism of anarchism; nor

does it carry the historical burden of Marxism’s authoritarianism as

embodied in Bolshevism.

It does not focus on the factory as its principal social arena or on the

industrial proletariat as its main historical agent; and it does not

reduce the free community of the future to a fanciful medieval village.

Its most important goal is clearly spelled out in a conventional

dictionary definition: Communalism, according to The American Heritage

Dictionary of the English Language, is ”a theory or system of government

in which virtually autonomous local communities are loosely bound in a

federation.”[18]

Communalism seeks to recapture the meaning of politics in its broadest,

most emancipatory sense, indeed, to fulfill the historic potential of

the municipality as the developmental arena of mind and discourse. It

conceptualizes the municipality, potentially at least, as a

transformative development beyond organic evolution into the domain of

social evolution. The city is the domain where the archaic blood-tie

that was once limited to the unification of families and tribes, to the

exclusion of outsiders, was-juridically, at least-dissolved. It became

the domain where hierarchies based on parochial and sociobiological

attributes of kinship, gender, and age could be eliminated and replaced

by a free society based on a shared common humanity. Potentially, it

remains the domain where the once-feared stranger can be fully absorbed

into the community-initially as a protected resident of a common

territory and eventually as a citizen, engaged in making policy

decisions in the public arena. It is above all the domain where

institutions and values have their roots not in zoology but in civil

human activity.

Looking beyond these historical functions, the municipality constitutes

the only domain for an association based on the free exchange of ideas

and a creative endeavor to bring the capacities of consciousness to the

service of freedom. It is the domain where a mere animalistic adaptation

to an existing and pregiven environment can be radically supplanted by

proactive, rational intervention into the world — indeed, a world yet to

be made and molded by reason- with a view toward ending the

environmental, social, and political insults to which humanity and the

biosphere have been subjected by classes and hierarchies. Freed of

domination as well as material exploitation-indeed, recreated as a

rational arena for human creativity in all spheres of life — the

municipality becomes the ethical space for the good life. Communalism is

thus no contrived product of mere fancy: it expresses an abiding concept

and practice of political life, formed by a dialectic of social

development and reason.

As a explicitly political body of ideas, Communalism seeks to recover

and advance the development of the city (or commune) in a form that

accords with its greatest potentialities and historical traditions. This

is not to say that Communalism accepts the municipality as it is today.

Quite to the contrary, the modern municipality is infused with many

statist features and often functions as an agent of the bourgeois

nation-state. Today, when the nation-state still seems supreme, the

rights that modern municipalities possess cannot be dismissed as the

epiphenomena of more basic economic relations. Indeed, to a great

degree, they are the hard-won gains of commoners, who long defended them

against assaults by ruling classes over the course of history — even

against the bourgeoisie itself.

The concrete political dimension of Communalism is known as libertarian

municipalism, about which I have previously written extensively. [19] In

its libertarian municipalist program, Communalism resolutely seeks to

eliminate statist municipal structures and replace them with the

institutions of a libertarian polity. It seeks to radically restructure

cities’ governing institutions into popular democratic assemblies based

on neighborhoods, towns, and villages. In these popular assemblies,

citizens — including the middle classes as well as the working

classes-deal with community affairs on a face- to-face basis, making

policy decisions in a direct democracy, and giving reality to the ideal

of a humanistic, rational society.

Minimally, if we are to have the kind of free social life to which we

aspire, democracy should be our form of a shared political life. To

address problems and issues that transcend the boundaries of a single

municipality, in turn, the democratized municipalities should join

together to form a broader confederation. These assemblies and

confederations, by their very existence, could then challenge the

legitimacy of the state and statist forms of power. They could expressly

be aimed at replacing state power and statecraft with popular power and

a socially rational transformative politics. And they would become

arenas where class conflicts could be played out and where classes could

be eliminated.

Libertarian municipalists do not delude themselves that the state will

view with equanimity their attempts to replace professionalized power

with popular power. They harbor no illusions that the ruling classes

will indifferently allow a Communalist movement to demand rights that

infringe on the state’s sovereignty over towns and cities. Historically,

regions, localities, and above all towns and cities have desperately

struggled to reclaim their local sovereignty from the state (albeit not

always for high-minded purposes). Communalists’ attempt to restore the

powers of towns and cities and to knit them together into confederations

can be expected to evoke increasing resistance from national

institutions. That the new popular-assemblyist municipal confederations

will embody a dual power against the state that becomes a source of

growing political tension is obvious. Either a Communalist movement will

be radicalized by this tension and will resolutely face all its

consequences, or it will surely sink into a morass of compromises that

absorb it back into the social order that it once sought to change. How

the movement meets this challenge is a clear measure of its seriousness

in seeking to change the existing political system and the social

consciousness it develops as a source of public education and

leadership.

Communalism constitutes a critique of hierarchical and capitalist

society as a whole. It seeks to alter not only the political life of

society but also its economic life. On this score, its aim is not to

nationalize the economy or retain private ownership of the means of

production but to municipalize the economy. It seeks to integrate the

means of production into the existential life of the municipality, such

that every productive enterprise falls under the purview of the local

assembly, which decides how it will function to meet the interests of

the community as a whole. The separation between life and work, so

prevalent in the modern capitalist economy, must be overcome so that

citizens’ desires and needs, the artful challenges of creation in the

course of production, and role of production in fashioning thought and

self-definition are not lost. “Humanity makes itself,” to cite the title

of V. Gordon Childe’s book on the urban revolution at the end of the

Neolithic age and the rise of cities, and it does so not only

intellectually and esthetically, but by expanding human needs as well as

the productive methods for satisfying them. We discover ourselves — our

potentialities and their actualization — through creative and useful

work that not only transforms the natural world but leads to our

self-formation and self-definition.

We must also avoid the parochialism and ultimately the desires for

proprietorship that have afflicted so many self-managed enterprises,

such as the “collectives” in the Russian and Spanish revolutions. Not

enough has been written about the drift among many “socialistic”

self-managed enterprises, even under the red and red-and-black flags,

respectively, of revolutionary Russia and revolutionary Spain, toward

forms of collective capitalism that ultimately led many of these

concerns to compete with one another for raw materials and markets. [20]

Most importantly, in Communalist political life, workers of different

occupations would take their seats in popular assemblies not as workers

— printers, plumbers, foundry workers and the like, with special

occupational interests to advance — but as citizens, whose overriding

concern should be the general interest of the society in which they

live. Citizens should be freed of their particularistic identity as

workers, specialists, and individuals concerned primarily with their own

particularistic interests. Municipal life should become a school for the

formation of citizens, both by absorbing new citizens and by educating

the young, while the assemblies themselves should function not only as

permanent decision-making institutions but as arenas for educating the

people in handling complex civic and regional affairs. [21]

In a Communalist way of life, conventional economics, with its focus on

prices and scarce resources, would be replaced by ethics, with its

concern for human needs and the good life. Human solidarity — or philia,

as the Greeks called it — would replace material gain and egotism.

Municipal assemblies would become not only vital arenas for civic life

and decision-making but centers where the shadowy world of economic

logistics, properly coordinated production, and civic operations would

be demystified and opened to the scrutiny and participation of the

citizenry as a whole. The emergence of the new citizen would mark a

transcendence of the particularistic class being of traditional

socialism and the formation of the “new man” which the Russian

revolutionaries hoped they could eventually achieve. Humanity would now

be able to rise to the universal state of consciousness and rationality

that the great utopians of the nineteenth century and the Marxists hoped

their efforts would create, opening the way to humanity’s fulfillment as

a species that embodies reason rather than material interest and that

affords material post-scarcity rather than an austere harmony enforced

by a morality of scarcity and material deprivation.[22]

Classical Athenian democracy of the fifth century B.C.E., the source of

the Western democratic tradition, was based on face-to-face

decision-making in communal assemblies of the people and confederations

of those municipal assemblies. For more than two millennia, the

political writings of Aristotle recurrently served to heighten our

awareness of the city as the arena for the fulfillment of human

potentialities for reason, self-consciousness, and the good life.

Appropriately, Aristotle traced the emergence of the polis from the

family or oikos — i.e., the realm of necessity, where human beings

satisfied their basically animalistic needs, and where authority rested

with the eldest male. But the association of several families, he

observed, “aim[ed] at something more than the supply of daily

needs”[23]; this aim initiated the earliest political formation, the

village. Aristotle famously described man (by which he meant the adult

Greek male [24]) as a “political animal” (politikon zoon) who presided

over family members not only to meet their material needs but as the

material precondition for his participation in political life, in which

discourse and reason replaced mindless deeds, custom, and violence.

Thus, “[w]hen several villages are united in a single complete community

(koinonan), large enough to be nearly or quite self-sufficing,” he

continued, “the polis comes into existence, originating in the bare

needs of life, and continuing in existence for the sake of a good

life.”[25]

For Aristotle, and we may assume also for the ancient Athenians, the

municipality’s proper functions were thus not strictly instrumental or

even economic. As the locale of human consociation, the municipality,

and the social and political arrangements that people living there

constructed, was humanity’s telos, the arena par excellence where human

beings, over the course of history, could actualize their potentiality

for reason, self-consciousness, and creativity. Thus for the ancient

Athenians, politics denoted not only the handling of the practical

affairs of a polity but civic activities that were charged with moral

obligation to one’s community. All citizens of a city were expected to

participate in civic activities as ethical beings.

Examples of municipal democracy were not limited to ancient Athens.

Quite to the contrary, long before class differentiations gave rise to

the state, many relatively secular towns produced the earliest

institutional structures of local democracy. Assemblies of the people

may have existed in ancient Sumer, at the very beginning of the

so-called “urban revolution” some seven or eight thousand years ago.

They clearly appeared among the Greeks, and until the defeat of the

Gracchus brothers, they were popular centers of power in republican

Rome. They were nearly ubiquitous in the medieval towns of Europe and

even in Russia, notably in Novgorod and Pskov, which, for a time, were

among the most democratic cities in the Slavic world. The assembly, it

should be emphasized, began to approximate its truly modern form in the

neighborhood Parisian sections of 1793, when they became the authentic

motive forces of the Great Revolution and conscious agents for the

making of a new body politic. That they were never given the

consideration they deserve in the literature on democracy, particularly

democratic Marxist tendencies and revolutionary syndicalists, is

dramatic evidence of the flaws that existed in the revolutionary

tradition.

These democratic municipal institutions normally existed in combative

tension with grasping monarchs, feudal lords, wealthy families, and

freebooting invaders until they were crushed, frequently in bloody

struggles. It cannot be emphasized too strongly that every great

revolution in modern history had a civic dimension that has been

smothered in radical histories by an emphasis on class antagonisms,

however important these antagonisms have been. Thus it is unthinkable

that the English Revolution of the 1640s can be understood without

singling out London as its terrain; or, by the same token, any

discussions of the various French Revolutions without focusing on Paris,

or the Russian Revolutions without dwelling on Petrograd, or the Spanish

Revolution of 1936 without citing Barcelona as its most advanced social

center. This centrality of the city is not a mere geographic fact; it

is, above all, a profoundly political one, which involved the ways in

which revolutionary masses aggregated and debated, the civic traditions

that nourished them, and the environment that fostered their

revolutionary views.

Libertarian municipalism is an integral part of the Communalist

framework, indeed its praxis, just as Communalism as a systematic body

of revolutionary thought is meaningless without libertarian

municipalism. The differences between Communalism and authentic or

“pure” anarchism, let alone Marxism, are much too great to be spanned by

a prefix such as anarcho-, social-, neo-, or even libertarian. Any

attempt to reduce Communalism to a mere variant of anarchism would be to

deny the integrity of both ideas — indeed, to ignore their conflicting

concepts of democracy, organization, elections, government, and the

like. Gustave Lefrancais, the Paris Communard who may have coined this

political term, adamantly declared that he was “a Communalist, not an

anarchist.”[26]

Above all, Communalism is engaged with the problem of power.[27] In

marked contrast to the various kinds of communitarian enterprises

favored by many self-designated anarchists, such as “people’s” garages,

print shops, food coops, and backyard gardens, adherents of Communalism

mobilize themselves to electorally engage in a potentially important

center of power — the municipal council — and try to compel it to create

legislatively potent neighborhood assemblies. These assemblies, it

should be emphasized, would make every effort to delegitimate and depose

the statist organs that currently control their villages, towns, or

cities and thereafter act as the real engines in the exercise of power.

Once a number of municipalities are democratized along communalist

lines, they would methodically confederate into municipal leagues and

challenge the role of the nation-state and, through popular assemblies

and confederal councils, try to acquire control over economic and

political life.

Finally, Communalism, in contrast to anarchism, decidedly calls for

decision-making by majority voting as the only equitable way for a large

number of people to make decisions. Authentic anarchists claim that this

principle — the “rule” of the minority by the majority — is

authoritarian and propose instead to make decisions by consensus.

Consensus, in which single individuals can veto majority decisions,

threatens to abolish society as such. A free society is not one in which

its members, like Homer’s lotus-eaters, live in a state of bliss without

memory, temptation, or knowledge. Like it or not, humanity has eaten of

the fruit of knowledge, and its memories are laden with history and

experience. In a lived mode of freedom — contrary to mere café chatter —

the rights of minorities to express their dissenting views will always

be protected as fully as the rights of majorities. Any abridgements of

those rights would be instantly corrected by the community — hopefully

gently, but if unavoidable, forcefully — lest social life collapse into

sheer chaos. Indeed, the views of a minority would be treasured as

potential source of new insights and nascent truths that, if abridged,

would deny society the sources of creativity and developmental advances

— for new ideas generally emerge from inspired minorities that gradually

gain the centrality they deserve at a given time and place — until,

again, they too are challenged as the conventional wisdom of a period

that is beginning to pass away and requires new (minority) views to

replace frozen orthodoxies.

The Need for Organization and Education

It remains to ask: how are we to achieve this rational society? One

anarchist writer would have it that the good society (or a true

“natural” disposition of affairs, including a “natural man”) exists

beneath the oppressive burdens of civilization like fertile soil beneath

the snow. It follows from this mentality that all we are obliged to do

to achieve the good society is to somehow eliminate the snow, which is

to say capitalism, nation-states, churches, conventional schools, and

other almost endless types of institutions that perversely embody

domination in one form or another. Presumably an anarchist society —

once state, governmental, and cultural institutions are merely

removed-would emerge intact, ready to function and thrive as a free

society. Such a “society,” if one can even call it such, would not

require that we proactively create it: we would simply let the snow

above it melt away. The process of rationally creating a free

Communalist society, alas, will require substantially more thought and

work than embracing a mystified concept of aboriginal innocence and

bliss.

A Communalist society should rest, above all, on the efforts of a new

radical organization to change the world, one that has a new political

vocabulary to explain its goals, and a new program and theoretical

framework to make those goals coherent. It would, above all, require

dedicated individuals who are willing to take on the responsibilities of

education and, yes, leadership. Unless words are not to become

completely mystified and obscure a reality that exists before our very

eyes, it should minimally be acknowledged that leadership always exists

and does not disappear because it is clouded by euphemisms such as

“militants” or, as in Spain, “influential militants.” It must also be

acknowledge that many individuals in earlier groups like the CNT were

not just “influential militants” but outright leaders, whose views were

given more consideration — and deservedly so! — than those of others

because they were based on more experience, knowledge, and wisdom, as

well as the psychological traits that were needed to provide effective

guidance. A serious libertarian approach to leadership would indeed

acknowledge the reality and crucial importance of leaders — all the more

to establish the greatly needed formal structures and regulations that

can effectively control and modify the activities of leaders and recall

them when the membership decides their respect is being misused or when

leadership becomes an exercise in the abusive exercise of power.

A libertarian municipalist movement should function, not with the

adherence of flippant and tentative members, but with people who have

been schooled in the movement’s ideas, procedures and activities. They

should, in effect, demonstrate a serious commitment to their

organization — an organization whose structure is laid out explicitly in

a formal constitution and appropriate bylaws. Without a democratically

formulated and approved institutional framework whose members and

leaders can be held accountable, clearly articulated standards of

responsibility cease to exist. Indeed, it is precisely when a membership

is no longer responsible to its constitutional and regulatory provisions

that authoritarianism develops and eventually leads to the movement’s

immolation. Freedom from authoritarianism can best be assured only by

the clear, concise, and detailed allocation of power, not by pretensions

that power and leadership are forms of “rule” or by libertarian

metaphors that conceal their reality. It has been precisely when an

organization fails to articulate these regulatory details that the

conditions emerge for its degeneration and decay.

Ironically, no stratum has been more insistent in demanding its freedom

to exercise its will against regulation than chiefs, monarchs, nobles,

and the bourgeoisie; similarly even well- meaning anarchists have seen

individual autonomy as the true expression of freedom from the

“artificialities” of civilization. In the realm of true freedom — that

is, freedom that has been actualized as the result of consciousness,

knowledge, and necessity — to know what we can and cannot do is more

cleanly honest and true to reality than to avert the responsibility of

knowing the limits of the lived world. Said a very wise man more than a

century and a half ago: “Men make their own history, but they do not

make it just as they please.”

Creating a New Left

The need for the international Left to advance courageously beyond a

Marxist, anarchist, syndicalist, or vague socialist framework toward a

Communalist framework is particularly compelling today. Rarely in the

history of leftist political ideas have ideologies been so wildly and

irresponsibly muddled; rarely has ideology itself been so disparaged;

rarely has the cry for “Unity!” on any terms been heard with such

desperation. To be sure, the various tendencies that oppose capitalism

should indeed unite around efforts to discredit and ultimately efface

the market system. To such ends, unity is an invaluable desideratum: a

united front of the entire Left is needed in order to counter the

entrenched system-indeed, culture-of commodity production and exchange,

and to defend the residual rights that the masses have won in earlier

struggles against oppressive governments and social systems.

The urgency of this need, however, does not require movement

participants to abandon mutual criticism, or to stifle their criticism

of the authoritarian traits present in anticapitalist organizations.

Least of all does it require them to compromise the integrity and

identity of their various programs. Th vast majority of participants in

today’s movement are inexperienced young radicals who have come of age

in an era of postmodernist relativism. As a consequence, the movement is

marked by a chilling eclecticism, in which tentative opinions are

chaotically mismarried to ideals that should rest on soundly objective

premises.[28] In a milieu where the clear expression of ideas is not

valued and terms are inappropriately used, and where argumentation is

disparaged as “aggressive” and, worse, “divisive,” it becomes difficult

to formulate ideas in the crucible of debate. Ideas grow and mature

best, in fact, not in the silence and controlled humidity of an

ideological nursery, but in the tumult of dispute and mutual criticism.

Following revolutionary socialist practices of the past, Communalists

would try to formulate a minimum program that calls for satisfaction of

the immediate concerns of the masses, such as improved wages and shelter

or adequate park space and transportation. This minimum program would

aim to satisfy the most elemental needs of the masses, to improve their

access to the resources that make daily life tolerable. The maximum

program, by contrast, would present an image of what human life could be

like under libertarian socialism, at least as far as such a society is

foreseeable in a world that is continually changing under the impact of

seemingly unending industrial revolutions.

Even more, however, Communalists would see their program and practice as

a process. Indeed, a transitional program in which each new demand

provides the springboard for escalating demands that lead toward more

radical and eventually revolutionary demands. One of the most striking

examples of a transitional demand was the programmatic call in the late

nineteenth century by the Second International for a popular militia to

replace a professional army. In still other cases, revolutionary

socialists demanded that railroads be publicly owned (or, as

revolutionary syndicalists might have demanded, be controlled by

railroad workers) rather than privately owned and operated. None of

these demands were in themselves revolutionary, but they opened

pathways, politically, to revolutionary forms of ownership and operation

— which, in turn, could be escalated to achieve the movement’s maximum

program. Others might criticize such step-by-step endeavors as

“reformist,” but Communalists do not contend that a Communalist society

can be legislated into existence. What these demands try to achieve, in

the short term, are new rules of engagement between the people and

capital — rules that are all the more needed at a time when “direct

action” is being confused with protests of mere events whose agenda is

set entirely by the ruling classes.

On the whole, Communalism is trying to rescue a realm of public action

and discourse that is either disappearing or that is being be reduced to

often-meaningless engagements with the police, or to street theater

that, however artfully, reduces serious issues to simplistic

performances that have no instructive influence. By contrast,

Communalists try to build lasting organizations and institutions that

can play a socially transformative role in the real world.

Significantly, Communalists do not hesitate to run candidates in

municipal elections who, if elected, would use what real power their

offices confer to legislate popular assemblies into existence. These

assemblies, in turn, would have the power ultimately to create effective

forms of town-meeting government. Inasmuch as the emergence of the city

— and city councils — long preceded the emergence of class society,

councils based on popular assemblies are not inherently statist organs,

and to participate seriously in municipal elections countervails

reformist socialist attempts to elect statist delegates by offering the

historic libertarian vision of municipal confederations as a practical,

combative, and politically credible popular alternative to state power.

Indeed, Communalist candidacies, which explicitly denounce parliamentary

candidacies as opportunist, keep alive the debate over how libertarian

socialism can be achieved — a debate that has been languishing for

years.

There should be no self-deception about the opportunities that exist as

a means of transforming our existing irrational society into a rational

one. Our choices on how to transform the existing society are still on

the table of history and are faced with immense problems. But unless

present and future generations are beaten into complete submission by a

culture based on queasy calculation as well as by police with tear gas

and water cannons, we cannot desist from fighting for what freedoms we

have and try to expand them into a free society wherever the opportunity

to do so emerges. At any rate we now know, in the light of all the

weaponry and means of ecological destruction that are at hand, that the

need for radical change cannot be indefinitely deferred. What is clear

is that human beings are much too intelligent not to have a rational

society; the most serious question we face is whether they are rational

enough to achieve one.

After Murray Bookchin

Murray Bookchin unfortunately did not live to see the publication of

Social Ecology and Communalism. July 30^(th), 2006, he died peacefully

in his home, surrounded by family and friends.

Until his very last breath, Bookchin never abandoned his commitment to

humanism and Enlightenment, and he was always a forceful representative

of the great radical traditions he strove to nurture and develop.

Although his impact on the ecology movement and on grassroots activism

is recognized and appreciated, Bookchin’s real importance and

originality has yet to be asserted. Fortunately Bookchin was not only a

lifelong activist but also a prolific writer, leaving behind numerous

books, essays, lectures, and interviews. Bookchin was a real thinker —

controversial and stimulating — and he maintained a consistent social

focus all his life. Without doubt, the loss of this great revolutionary

will be felt for many years to come.

The publication of these essays seems particularly appropriate now, as

they can help us understand how Bookchin has left us a comprehensive and

coherent corpus. This book is important for two reasons. First, it

provides a decent and accessible introduction to Bookchin’s basic ideas,

and it is my sincere hope that this book will encourage the reader to

take a closer look at his rich theoretical works. Second, it provides a

very definable and ideological focus by which we can evaluate his older

works and his many polemics. Indeed, “The Communalist Project” was the

last proper essay Bookchin ever wrote, and the oldest essays were

revised quite recently. (It could also be noted that I presented my

editorial choices to him while working on this project, and he even read

and commented on the introduction I have written for this book.)

Bookchin was enthusiastic about this specific collection of essays, and

thought that they represented the most recent and, in many ways,

clearest expression of his ideological stance. In that respect, they can

be considered a political testament.

I believe that social ecology and Communalism, and the whole body of

ideas that Bookchin created, has left us with a tremendous legacy that

will continue to challenge us and inspire us in the struggle for a new

libertarian and ecological society. Let us make sure these ideas get the

attention they deserve, and help create the free society that Bookchin

never had the privilege to see come into being. Creating a new radical

movement, and indeed a new society, is an immense project that can not

be taken lightly. As Bookchin himself wrote in Re-enchanting Humanity:

“The achievement of freedom must be a free act on the highest level of

intellectual and moral probity, for if we cannot act vigorously to free

ourselves, we will not deserve to be free.”

Murray Bookchin threw down the gauntlet.

The future is our responsibility.

Eirik Eiglad,

October 30^(th), 2006

[1] Murray Bookchin, “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought,” originally

published in the libertarian socialist periodical Comment (September

1965) and collected, together with all my major essays of the 1960s, in

Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Berkeley: Ramparts Press, 1972; reprinted

Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1977). The expression “ethics of

complementarity” is from my The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and

Dissolution of Hierarchy (San Francisco: Cheshire Books, 1982; revised

edition Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1991; reprinted with a new

introduction by AK Press, 2005).

[2] I am not saying that complexity necessarily yields subjectivity,

merely that it is difficult to conceive of subjectivity without

complexity, specifically the nervous system. Human beings, as active

agents in changing their environments to suit their needs, could not

have achieved their present level of control over their environments

without their extraordinary complex brains and nervous systems – a

remarkable example of the specialization of an organ system that had

highly general functions.

[3] Neil Evernden, The Natural Alien (Toronto: University of Toronto

Press, 1986), p. 109.

[4] Quoted in Alan Wolfe, “Up from Humanism,” American Prospect (Winter

1991), p. 125.

[5] Paul Radin, The World of Primitive Man (New York: Grove Press,

1960), p. 211.

[6] Murray Bookchin, The Ecology of Freedom (Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire

Books, 1982), p. 29.

[7] Der Spiegel (Sept. 16, 1991), pp. 144–45.

[8] I spelled out all these views in my 1964–65 essay “Ecology and

Revolutionary Thought,” and they were assimilated over time by

subsequent ecology movements. Many of the technological views advanced

in my 1965 essay “Toward a Liberatory Technology” were also assimilated

and renamed “appropriate technology,” a rather socially neutral

expression in comparison with my original term ecotechnology. Both of

these essays can be found in Post-Scarcity Anarchism.

[9] See “The Forms of Freedom” in Post Scarcity-Anarchism; “The Legacy

of Freedom” in The Ecology of Freedom ; and “Patterns of Civic Freedom “

in From Urbanization to Cities: Towards a New Politics of Citizenship

(1982, 1992; rev. ed. London: Cassell, 1995).

[10] Many less-well-known names could be added to this list, but one

that in particular I would like very much to single out is the gallant

leader of the Left Socialist Revolutionary Party, Maria Spiridonova,

whose supporters were virtually alone in proposing a workable

revolutionary program for the Russian people in 1917–18. Their failure

to implement their political insights and replace the Bolsheviks (with

whom they initially joined in forming the first Soviet government) not

only led to their defeat but contributed to the disastrous failure of

revolutionary movements in the century that followed.

[11] I frankly regard this contradiction as more fundamental than the

often-indiscernible tendency of the rate of profit to decline and

thereby to render capitalist exchange inoperable – a contradiction to

which Marxists assigned a decisive role in the nineteenth and early

twentieth centuries.

[12] Contrary to Marx’s assertion that a society disappears only when it

has exhausted its capacity for new technological developments,

capitalism is in a state of permanent technological revolution – at

times, frighteningly so. Marx erred on this score: it will take more

than technological stagnation to terminate this system of social

relations. As new issues challenge the validity of the entire system,

the political and ecological domains will become all the more important.

Alternatively, we are faced with the prospect that capitalism may pull

down the entire world and leave behind little more than ashes and ruin –

achieving, in short, the “capitalist barbarism” of which Rosa Luxemburg

warned in her “Junius” essay.

[13] I use the word extraordinary because, by Marxist standards, Europe

was still objectively unprepared for a socialist revolution in 1914.

Much of the continent, in fact, had yet to be colonized by the

capitalist market or bourgeois social relations. The proletariat – still

a very conspicuous minority of the population in a sea of peasants and

small producers – had yet to mature as a class into a significant force.

Despite the opprobrium that has been heaped on Plekhanov, Kautsky,

Bernstein et al., they had a better understanding of the failure of

Marxist socialism to embed itself in proletarian consciousness than did

Lenin. Luxemburg, in any case, straddled the so-called

“social-patriotic” and “internationalist” camps in her image of a

Marxist party’s function, in contrast to Lenin, her principal opponent

in the so-called “organizational question” in the Left of the wartime

socialists, who was prepared to establish a “proletarian dictatorship”

under all and any circumstances. The First World War was by no means

inevitable, and it generated democratic and nationalist revolutions

rather than proletarian ones. (Russia, in this respect, was no more a

“workers’ state” under Bolshevik rule than were the Hungarian and

Bavarian “soviet” republics.) Not until 1939 was Europe placed in a

position where a world war was inevitable. The revolutionary Left (to

which I belonged at the time) frankly erred profoundly when it took a

so-called “internationalist” position and refused to support the Allies

(their imperialist pathologies notwithstanding) against the vanguard of

world fascism, the Third Reich.

[14] Kropotkin, for example, rejected democratic decision-making

procedures: “Majority rule is as defective as any other kind of rule,”

he asserted. See Peter Kropotkin, “Anarchist Communism: Its Basis and

Principles,” in Kropotkin’s Revolutionary Pamphlets, edited by Roger N.

Baldwin (1927; reprinted by New York: Dover, 1970), p. 68.

[15] I have made the distinction between politics and statecraft in, for

example, Murray Bookchin, From Urbanization to Cities: Toward a New

Politics of Citizenship (1987; reprinted by London: Cassell, 1992), pp.

41–3, 59–61.

[16] Several years ago, while I still identified myself as an anarchist,

I attempted to formulate a distinction between “social” and “lifestyle”

anarchism, and I wrote an article that identified Communalism as “the

democratic dimension of anarchism” (see Left Green Perspectives, no. 31,

October 1994). I no longer believe that Communalism is a mere

“dimension” of anarchism, democratic or otherwise; rather, it is a

distinct ideology with a revolutionary tradition that has yet to be

explored.

[17] To be sure, these points undergo modification in Communalism: for

example, Marxism’s historical materialism, explaining the rise of class

societies, is expanded by social ecology’s explanation of the

anthropological and historical rise of hierarchy. Marxian dialectical

materialism, in turn, is transcended by dialectical naturalism; and the

anarcho-communist notion of a very loose “federation of autonomous

communes” is replaced with a confederation from which its components,

functioning in a democratic manner through citizens’ assemblies, may

withdraw only with the approval of the confederation as a whole.

[18] What is so surprising about this minimalist dictionary definition

is its overall accuracy: I would take issue only with its formulations

“virtually autonomous” and “loosely bound,” which suggest a parochial

and particularistic, even irresponsible relationship of the components

of a confederation.

[19] My writings on libertarian municipalism date back to the early

1970s, with “Spring Offensives and Summer Vacations,” Anarchos, no. 4

(1972). The more significant works include the books From Urbanization

to Cities (1987; reprinted by London: Cassell, 1992) and The Limits of

the City (New York: Harper Colophon, 1974), as well as the articles

“Theses on Libertarian Municipalism,” Our Generation [Montreal], vol.

16, nos. 3–4 (Spring/Summer 1985); “Radical Politics in an Era of

Advanced Capitalism,” (included herein); “The Meaning of Confederalism,”

Green Perspectives, no. 20 (November 1990); and “Libertarian

Municipalism: An Overview,” Green Perspectives, no. 24 (October 1991).

For a concise summary, see Janet Biehl, The Politics of Social Ecology:

Libertarian Municipalism (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1998).

[20] For one such discussion, see Murray Bookchin, “The Ghost of

Anarchosyndicalism,” Anarchist Studies, vol. 1, no. 1 (Spring 1993).

[21] One of the great tragedies of the Russian Revolution of 1917 and

the Spanish Revolution of 1936 was the failure of the masses to acquire

more than the scantiest knowledge of social logistics and the complex

interlinkages involved in providing for the necessities of life in a

modern society. Inasmuch as those who had the expertise involved in

managing productive enterprises and in making cities functional were

supporters of the old regime, workers were in fact unable to actually

take over the full control of factories. They were obliged instead to

depend on “bourgeois specialists” to operate them, individuals who

steadily made them the victims of a technocratic elite.

[22] I have previously discussed this transformation of workers from

mere class beings into citizens, among other places, in From

Urbanization to Cities (1987; reprinted by London: Cassell, 1995), and

in “Workers and the Peace Movement” (1983), published in The Modern

Crisis (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1987).

[23] Aristotle, Politics (1252 [b] 16), trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The

Complete Works of Aristotle , Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan

Barnes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984), vol. 2, p.

1987.

[24] As a libertarian ideal for the future of humanity and a genuine

domain of freedom, the Athenian polis falls far short of the city’s

ultimate promise. Its population included slaves, subordinated women,

and franchiseless resident aliens. Only a minority of male citizens

possessed civic rights, and they ran the city without consulting a

larger population. Materially, the stability of the polis depended upon

the labor of its noncitizens. These are among the several monumental

failings that later municipalities would have to correct. The polis is

significant, however, not an example of an emancipated community but for

the successful functioning of its free institutions.

[25] Aristotle, Politics (1252 [b] 29–30), trans. Jowett; emphasis

added. The words from the original Greek text may be found in the Loeb

Classical Library edition: Aristotle, Politics, trans. H. Rackham

(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972).

[26] Lefrancais is quoted in Peter Kropotkin, Memoirs of a Revolutionist

(New York: Horizon Press, 1968), p. 393. I too would be obliged today to

make the same statement. In the late 1950s, when anarchism in the United

States was a barely discernible presence, it seemed like a sufficiently

clear field in which I could develop social ecology, as well as the

philosophical and political ideas that would eventually become

dialectical naturalism and libertarian municipalism. I well knew that

these views were not consistent with traditional anarchist ideas, least

of all post-scarcity, which implied that a modern libertarian society

rested on advanced material preconditions. Today I find that anarchism

remains the very simplistic individualistic and antirationalist

psychology it has always been. My attempt to retain anarchism under the

name of “social anarchism” has largely been a failure, and I now find

that the term I have used to denote my views must be replaced with

Communalism, which coherently integrates and goes beyond the most viable

features of the anarchist and Marxist traditions. Recent attempts to use

the word anarchism as a leveler to minimize the abundant and

contradictory differences that are grouped under that term and even

celebrate its openness to “differences” make it a diffuse catch-all for

tendencies that properly should be in sharp conflict with one another.

[27] For a discussion of the very real problems created by anarchists’

disdain for power during the Spanish Revolution, see the appendix

originally written to this article, “Anarchism and Power in the Spanish

Revolution.” (Available at

www.communalism.org

.)

[28] I should note that by objective I do not refer merely to

existential entities and events but also to potentialities that can be

rationally conceived, nurtured, and in time actualized into what we

would narrowly call realities. If mere substantiality were all that the

term objective meant, no ideal or promise of freedom would be an

objectively valid goal unless it existed under our very noses.