💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-eirik-eiglad-free-cities.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:30:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Free Cities
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 2008
Language: en
Topics: communalism, social ecology, theory, municipalism, libertarian municipalism, municipal government, post-anarchism, post-marxism, nationalism, anti-nationalism, cities
Source: https://aaaaarg.fail/thing/5c9ac9ff9ff37c58f2622beb

Murray Bookchin

Free Cities

Creating Free Cities

What would a free municipality look like? What would its basic

institutions be? What material, political, and cultural preconditions

must be met before we can arrive at them, and who will be the agents for

social change? What kinds of movements and political efforts are

required to create them? These questions strike to the core of Murray

Bookchin’s political project, particularly as he refined it during the

1980s and 1990s. The immediate and ultimate aim of the political

approach he advanced is to create free cities or municipalities, and as

such it is meant to provide both a clear social ideal as well as a

concrete political praxis.

By advancing libertarian municipalism, Bookchin hoped to see new civic

movements emerge and claim control over their communities. Political

involvement at the local level is necessary, he insisted, to guide and

inspire a process of municipal empowerment. This process and the

institutions it entails, he hoped, may provide a focal point for

rallying progressive social movements to the common cause of political

freedom in its most expansive sense. To a very large extent, creating

free cities is about developing free citizens, in whose hands power over

society should be squarely placed: it must reside in popular assemblies

and not in bureaucracies, parliaments, or corporate boards. Libertarian

municipalism is an attempt to create the political structures necessary

for this shift in power. Democratized and radicalized, municipal

confederations would emerge, it is hoped, as a dual power to challenge

and ultimately replace the nation state and the market.

A lifelong radical and a fertile thinker, Murray Bookchin had been

politically active since the 1930s; first in Communist parties, trade

unions, and Trotskyist groups, then during the 1960s in the civil rights

movement, urban ecology projects, anarchist groups, the radical student

movement, and community groups; and later in the 1970s and 1980s in

anti-nuclear movements and the early Green movement. Only in the early

1990s did his health preclude further involvement in practical political

affairs, but he continued to write until the last years of his life.

Bookchin’s works spanned a broad range of issues, including ecology,

anthropology, technology, history, politics, and philosophy. He started

to write about ecology and urban issues in the 1950s, and in 1964 wrote

his seminal “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought,” the first definitive

essay on radical social ecology. Later he was to refine his theories –

through a corpus of more than 20 books – into a coherent body of ideas.

Murray Bookchin died at the age of 85, on July 30, 2006. With his

passing we lost one of the most challenging and innovative radical

thinkers of the twentieth century.

Bookchin expressed his ideas on libertarian municipalism in a number of

essays and articles, and advocated it in his lectures and talks. But no

book has yet appeared that collects his essays on the subject. This

collection of his late political essays, I am proud to say, helps fill

that gap.[1] It should be seen, however, in relation to Bookchin’s

full-length book on civic development, citizenship, and politics; From

Urbanization to Cities.[2] When he republished this monumental work in

1992 he added the essay “The Meaning of Confederalism,” and in a later

edition, in 1995, further added “Confederal Municipalism: An Overview”

as well as a new prologue. Bookchin was no academic, and he did not

write for purely scholarly purposes; his aim with this work “was to

formulate a new politics” and by appending these essays he showed how he

meant to inspire a movement to give his ideas concrete reality.

In light of this, I initially intended this book to be an expanded

appendix to From Urbanization to Cities, so that both together would

constitute an overview of his political thinking. In my view his late

essays, collected here, make his earlier works on urbanization, ecology,

and revolutionary history even more relevant and tangible. Bookchin’s

essays from the 1980s and 1990s had tried to advance libertarian

municipalism as an anarchist alternative, an effort that turned out to

be problematical. Although for many years Bookchin called himself an

anarchist, pioneering its concerns with ecology and with hierarchy, he

had long had a troubled relationship with the anarchist tradition. After

a bitter polemical struggle to defend what he considered to be its

highest social ideals against individualists, workerists, mystics,

primitivists, and autonomists, he got tired of “defending anarchism

against anarchists,” as he put it, and publicly disassociated himself

from anarchism as such. He had spent much time and effort formulating

and presenting libertarian municipalism as an anarchist politics, but

anarchists, it turned out, were not interested in these ideas, and in

fact the political idea of democracy is actually alien to anarchism.

Several notions in anarchism inspired Bookchin, but his ideas about

municipal government, direct democracy, and confederation could not be

contained within an anarchist framework. Breaking with anarchism, he

urged left libertarian radicals to embrace a new set of ideas, indeed a

new ideology – he called it communalism – that could transcend all

classical radical theories, both Marxist and anarchist. As an attempt to

revive Enlightenment radicalism, Bookchin intended communalism to be a

coherent ideological platform upon which we might develop libertarian

ideas today and provide the Left with a politics.

For these reasons, I realized very soon that these essays expanded the

purpose of the anthology; they gave a remarkably consistent overview of

Bookchin’s perspectives on communalism and its relationship to the Left

in general. Taken together these essays not only provide an overview of

Bookchin’s political ideas but explain how his political ideas stem from

his broader historical, philosophical, and theoretical perspectives.

Although the subject matter may be libertarian municipalism and

practical politics, their foundational analyses are profoundly social

ecological, and their ideological perspective is basically communalist.

I chose the title Free Cities for this anthology because I think it

stimulates our understanding of the historical impetus behind Bookchin’s

political project. In order to achieve its ideal of a rational and

ecological society, libertarian municipalism is an effort to create free

cities, with an emphasis on both these words. Bookchin would have

insisted that we interpret free not simply as “independent,” or

“autonomous.” Rather, we should understand freedom in its expansive

political sense, as the collective expression of human self-recognition

and consciousness. Similarly, cities should not be interpreted merely as

spatial centers of population or trade. For Bookchin, the historic rise

of cities brought humanity the kind of social framework needed to break

out of the rigid tribal world and develop into truly social beings; such

citification is a historical precondition for our notion of citizenship.

The ideal of the free cities was a subject not only of great historical

interest but one that gave meaning to the project for social and

political emancipation. The question that occupied Bookchin was to what

extent municipalities could become genuine arenas for political

creativity, universalism, and freedom and thus give human society its

most rational expression.

I also hope that the title Free Cities stimulates the reader to

conceptualize the political ideas of social ecology in a tangible

manner. How can we empower our communities and recreate them along

libertarian lines? How can we democratically transform the political,

cultural, and material conditions of our own towns, villages, and

cities? Social ecology proposes a politics of remaking daily life not

only by creating nonhierarchical social relationships but also by

institutionally restructuring neighborhoods and cities. The solemn

theoretical adherence of these essays to “civilizatory advances” and a

“rational society” should not frighten the reader; libertarian

municipalism is a concrete political practice. It is my genuine hope

that this book encourages readers to consider how to revitalize their

own communities, how we may remake our municipalities as great places to

live – for all their citizens – and render them politically and socially

free.

My choice of subtitle, Communalism and the Left, expresses Bookchin’s

wish to frame his theories in a communalist framework and to define

their relationship to the Left. Bookchin explains in these essays the

major achievements as well as the serious deficiencies of various

traditional radical Left ideologies, such as Marxism, anarchism, and

syndicalism. For one thing, both socialism and anarchism have ignored

the need to develop a political approach in the classical sense of the

term, a politics distinct from the State on the one hand and from the

social sphere on the other. Communalism was for Bookchin an attempt to

provide the ideological framework to resuscitate the greatest Left

traditions and to formulate a libertarian politics.

---

The idea for this book germinated when I last saw Murray, a few months

before his death. At the end of November 2005 Sveinung Legard and I

visited Murray and Janet Biehl, his long-time partner and collaborator,

in Burlington. During our stay we had lengthy political discussions and

undertook a substantial interview with Murray, which turned out to be

the last one he ever gave. At one point in our discussions, Bookchin

mentioned that he hoped to see his writings on libertarian municipalism

collected and published. I had already given this possibility some

serious thought and had specific ideas about how to put together

anthologies of his writings. For some time I had been translating his

works into Norwegian, and had edited, anthologized, and published his

political writings here in Scandinavia. But I had hesitated to suggest

an English-language anthology, since English is my second language – an

obvious shortcoming. Moreover, Murray had long benefited from the

support of Janet’s superior editing skills; for many years, she had

carefully helped prepare his manuscripts for publication. Hence I was

reluctant to offer my assistance. But at that time Janet was exhausted

from the intense work of editing The Third Revolution and was in no

position to undertake any new obligation of the sort proposed. I

fervently wanted to see the anthologies materialize, and, emboldened by

Murray’s expressed wish, I offered to assist.

My specific suggestions were twofold. First, I would put together a

small book consisting of some four essays that gave a rounded yet

accessible presentation of social ecology, to be called Social Ecology

and Communalism.[3] Then I would collect the more directly political

essays in a second book that would comprise a comprehensive overview.

Murray and I discussed these book projects in detail, and he gave me

some manuscripts and notes for my work.[4] I assured him that I would do

my very best to see that these books were edited according to his

wishes, and he expressed his confidence by putting me in charge of their

publication. As soon as I returned to Norway, I began to work on the

books.

My own qualifications for preparing these books may not be obvious to

the reader, as I not only live on the other side of the Atlantic from

Murray but am not a native English speaker. But I have been involved

with the ideas of social ecology and libertarian municipalism since the

early 1990s. I first met Murray in 1996 and visited him many times

thereafter, staying in Burlington for weeks and months, experiencing

both his generosity and that of his family. Murray and I regularly had

long telephone conversations throughout our ten years of friendship and

cooperation. Whenever I made a decision to translate his works into

Norwegian for publication, I always informed him of my choices, and I

consulted him when I encountered problems. He thus became familiar with

my editorial approach and abilities. When I started writing my own

essays, he always read them carefully and gave me his comments. He was

sometimes a stern critic, sometimes encouraging, but always his

perspectives were challenging. Over the years we grew ever closer. After

the Second International Conference on Libertarian Municipalism (held in

Plainfield, Vermont, in 1999), I suggested the creation of an

international journal to express a consistent communalist perspective.

Murray eagerly joined the journal’s editorial board, the last political

group to which he belonged.[5] For its launch I wrote “Communalism as

Alternative,” a manifesto-like essay presenting the basic ideological

views Murray had developed.

Editing the two anthologies was a way for me to continue our

cooperation, as well as a way to show my gratitude for his intellectual

generosity. Unfortunately Murray died only seven months after our

meeting on the books, and he never had the chance to see either of them

published. I nonetheless feel confident that Free Cities: Communalism

and the Left has become what he wanted it to be. The essays gathered

here are among Bookchin’s last, and they give a good overview of his

ideas at the end of his life. I genuinely hope that the reader will get

as much intellectual stimulation and political inspiration from reading

these essays as I have done from preparing them for publication.

---

Some of the essays in this anthology may already be familiar to readers

who have followed Bookchin’s work closely, but most of them are

previously unpublished; they have been collected from letters, lectures,

unfinished drafts, and manuscripts. I have tried to order them in a

flowing presentation to give an overview of Bookchin’s late political

outlook. Since he died before witnessing the completion of this project,

I think it is only decent to explain as fully as possible my editorial

choices in creating Free Cities.

Generally speaking, in addition to doing regular editorial work, such as

adding titles and subheadings, or doublechecking references, dates and

names, I have tried to create a common style of presentation by making

the notes, letters and unfinished manuscripts into proper essays. The

book consists both of independent essays on specific political issues

and of more general essays in which Bookchin often gives brief synopses

of his basic political ideas. As a consequence, there is inevitably some

overlap between the chapters, though I have tried to keep this to a

minimum. In these essays Murray made recurring references to his basic

works, From Urbanization to Cities, The Ecology of Freedom, and Remaking

Society, and though I have trimmed down the number of references here, I

would strongly advise the reader unfamiliar with these works to consult

them. Sometimes Bookchin would discuss the same idea in several places,

such as the distinction between politics and statecraft, or his

tripartite distinction between the political sphere, the social sphere,

and the State. Suffice to say, again, readers will deepen their

understanding of these ideas by exploring them further in Bookchin’s

larger works.

I have also cut out some of the conceptual discussions Bookchin repeated

over several of these essays: in particular his often-mentioned

explanation that he is using the term politics in its classical Greek

meaning, as the self-management of the polis, and his frequently

repeated caveat that he is well aware of the historical shortcomings of

ancient Athenian democracy in regard to slavery, xenophobia, and

patriarchy. When Bookchin raises similar themes in different essays –

say, on the issues of consensus, confederation, or government – I have

tried to limit the repetition, either by removing sections or

consolidating the discussion in one place, particularly in the

previously unpublished writings. Generally I have omitted repetitions of

similar arguments in different essays, but have left them intact when

they approach an issue from a distinctive angle and thus serve to nuance

his views. Here Bookchin was well aware of my general intention.

Whenever possible I have accommodated Bookchin’s wish to update his

essays according to the communalist perspective. This issue is of course

most significantly related to his break with anarchism, a matter he

explains in some detail in several of the essays.[6] To the extent that

was appropriate, I have also updated some of the older essays.

Similarly, when he appeals to a specific group (say, the Greens, with

whom he worked with for a while) in a way that seemed outdated, I have

tried to make the appeal more general (changing it to, say, “radical

ecologists”). I thoroughly discussed all these changes with Bookchin and

am making them here at his explicit request.

Whenever linking one paragraph to another required the addition of a

transitional sentence, I have tried to make use of concrete expressions

that Bookchin used elsewhere. To the best of my abilities, whenever I

have had to revise paragraphs or move phrases, I have tried to preserve

Bookchin’s tone. If readers sometimes miss the characteristic musicality

of his writings, it is not for lack of trying on my part.

The hardest part of putting together such an anthology, however, lies in

deciding which essays to include and how to organize them. I can only

hope that more of Bookchin’s essays, lectures and interviews will be

made available in the years to come, to shed further light on his

intellectual development, particularly during the last decades. Still,

based as it is on my understanding of what Bookchin wanted to see

published from the last years of his life, this book presents that work

as honestly as possible.

---

The “Introduction” is cobbled together from notes that Bookchin gave me

November 2005. When we were discussing this project, I told him that I

would love to have him write an introduction to this book, as his

earlier essays on libertarian municipalism needed contextualization in

light of his recent break with anarchism. He then revealed that he had

already started drafting such an introduction, and passed along to me

his draft, along with a draft for a separate essay he had recently

started writing. Both these drafts were in a woefully unfinished state,

almost notes, and we agreed that they had to be focused to fit this

specific anthology. To ease my work, I suggested we use the drafts in

combination with a short piece Bookchin had written to introduce a

recent Swedish anthology of his writings – a suggestion he approved.[7]

I have thus extracted the core message of his drafts and spun them

around the existing Swedish introduction. By further distinguishing his

communalist approach from Marxism and anarchism, and by emphasizing the

profound historicism of these ideas, I think this piece constitutes an

appropriate introduction to the present anthology.

The next essay, “The Ecological Crisis and the Need to Remake Society,”

brings us directly to some social ecological conclusions on political

radicalism, and situates the remaining essays in the context of social

ecology. I chose this essay because I find it to be an accessible leadin

to libertarian municipalism as a social ecological politics, in relation

to the impending ecological crisis that besets us. I also like the fact

that it briefly touches on Bookchin’s criticisms of other radical

tendencies in the ecology movement, criticisms that have made for

defining debates. This essay was originally published as “The Ecological

Crisis, Socialism, and the Need to Remake Society,” in Society and

Nature 2, no. 3 (1994), and has been edited only slightly to fit this

anthology.

“Nationalism and the ‘National Question,’” written in March 1993, was

first published in Society and Nature 2, no. 2 (1994). It has long been

one of my personal favorites among Bookchin’s essays, and I am happy to

include it here as it gives a solid historical argument not only against

statism but also against nationalism. In this essay Bookchin explores

the Left’s historically ambivalent relationship to the “national

question,” and contrasts his ideas of municipalism and confederation to

those of nations and states, precisely by the universal principles of

democracy and human solidarity. The succinct “Nationalism and the Great

Revolutions” was originally published as an addendum to the preceding

essay, highlighting the universalistic spirit of the Enlightenme

Bookchin’s arguments against nationalism and statism are taken further

in the next piece, which I have called “The Historical Importance of the

City,” and which consists of excerpts from a longer polemical essay

“Comments on the International Social Ecology Network Gathering and the

‘Deep Social Ecology’ of John Clark,” written in September 1995 and

published in Democracy and Nature 3, no. 3 (1997). Here we are given

forceful arguments for the civilizatory and humanizing aspects of the

emergence of the cities – the tendencies that libertarian municipalism

ultimately wants to recover and expand. I told Bookchin that I had long

wanted to highlight some of the main issues in his polemics with John

Clark, and I specifically suggested these excerpts. Frustratingly, many

of his political adversaries have tended to deflect attention from the

real ideological questions at stake; by including these excerpts, I hope

to offer the basic yet crucial arguments. I suggested to Bookchin that I

include this abridged version, but would not want to suggest that this

version is better than the original, only that it better serves our

purpose here. Neither would I want readers to ignore the fact that every

sentence in this essay is meant as a direct or indirect criticism of

Clark’s position. Readers are strongly encouraged to read the polemic in

full, which relates more directly to the actual points of contention and

contains other important discussions as well.[8] Other essays from

Bookchin’s 1990s debates with anarchists are certainly also of interest,

as they often give different emphases and nuances to his political

ideas.

The 1990s debates over the nature of anarchism alienated Bookchin from

the contemporary anarchist movement. Unfortunately he wrote no

fundamental essays that explained his conclusions in great detail,

although in retrospect we can see how Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism initiated his break with this ideology.[9] Many of the

features of “lifestyle anarchism” that he criticized were ones that he

later concluded were symptomatic of anarchism as such. Murray explained

his reasoning in a letter to Peter Zegers and the editorial board of

Communalism (in November 2001), in which he considers even the more

social forms of anarchism to be basically egoist. He also developed some

of these ideas in a letter to Hamish Alcorn, written on July 30, 1999,

just before his public break with anarchism. With Bookchin’s permission

I have structured the essay “Anarchism as Individualism” around these

two letters, incorporating as well some unpublished material from

“Toward a Communalist Approach” and an early version of “The Communalist

Project.” Despite its brevity, I think this essay may shed light on

Bookchin’s reasons for breaking with anarchism – the political ideology

with which he had been associated, and of which he had been a major

representative, for four decades.

The next essay, “Anarchism, Power, and Government,” is based on the

appendix Murray wrote to “The Communalist Project,” which he called

“Anarchism and Power in the Spanish Revolution,” published in

Communalism, no. 2 (November 2002). I have expanded it with excerpts on

the same subject originally from “The Future of the Left” and “Toward a

Communalist Approach.” As these essays were written around the same time

and brought up very similar issues, I have knitted similar passages

together. As such, I think this short essay contains one of his

weightiest arguments against anarchism, focusing particularly on its

inability to deal with real-life problems in periods of social change

and revolution.

The two preceding essays make an interesting contrast with “The

Revolutionary Politics of Libertarian Municipalism.” Written as a

video-transmitted speech that Bookchin presented to the First

International Conference on Libertarian Municipalism, held in Lisbon in

1998, it was one of his last attempts to present his political ideas as

a direct extension of the anarchist-communist tradition. Here he tries

to uphold the classical anarchist preference for communes,

revolutionism, and federations, in order to rework and refine these

ideals for changed social conditions: The speech was titled “A Politics

for the 21^(st) Century.” I have removed dated references and some parts

that overlap with the other essays included herein. I have also tried to

update the essay according to Bookchin’s expressed wishes, making minor

changes concerning his ideological drift from anarchism to communalism,

without changing any of its basic content. After this speech Bookchin

gave up on his attempts to influence the anarchist movement from within,

and, at the Second International Conference in Vermont the following

year, he broke openly with anarchism as a theory and a movement. This

essay contains his last important evaluation of the anarchist tradition

from within, trying to emphasize its revolutionary, democratic, and

socialist character. He later considered his efforts to have been an

utter failure. Where he had earlier attempted to expand the federalist,

cooperative, and municipalist trends within the anarchist tradition, he

now tried to bring those valuable contributions into a new theoretical

framework unburdened by the anti-social, anti-intellectual, and

antiorganizational tendencies with which anarchism has always struggled.

The next essay, “The Future of the Left,” is in my view the jewel of

this collection, tying all the other pieces together and giving this

anthology its necessary coherence and breadth. Here Bookchin assesses of

the state of radicalism at the turn of the twenty-first century – not

only the radicalism of the contemporary resistance against

“globalization,” but radicalism going back to the interwar period and

twentieth-century revolutionary experiences. He takes a remarkably

detached, yet engaged, look at traditional radicalism and its basic

premises, specifically analyzing trends in Marxism and anarchism.

Bookchin often spoke of this essay and finally showed it to me at our

November 2005 meeting. The manuscript he handed over to me to edit had

been written in December 2002. It was still unfinished (it actually

ended mid-sentence) but was remarkably consistent in its reasoning.

Although I have edited the essay, nothing of substance has been omitted,

and though it broadens the focus of this anthology far beyond the

collection of “strictly political” writings I had intended, it is this

piece that contains Bookchin’s most mature ideas. It is fully

communalist, posing a set of challenging questions for our generation of

radicals to consider, and even as a stand-alone essay it gives this book

a scope that stretches far into the future.

We close with an essay that Bookchin wrote for Communalism. Originally

written in July 2000 as “Communalism: An Overview,” it was supposed to

be revised for publication, but instead Bookchin wrote a completely new

essay that ended up as the masterfully composed and theoretically

challenging “The Communalist Project.”[10] Even though the “Overview”

essay was thus superseded, it contained so many interesting aspects that

I always felt it deserved to be published in its own right. As a matter

of fact, Bookchin himself returned to it in June 2003 and made some

significant updates, and I have since taken out all the parts that

overlap with “The Communalist Project.” I think it is of great interest,

not because it is a definitive exposition of communalism – it is not –

but rather because it is so suggestive of such an exposition. In this

essay we see Bookchin still struggling with his ideological break with

anarchism, framing his presentation almost entirely as a polemic against

prevalent anarchist notions – unlike “The Communalist Project” and “The

Future of the Left,” which stand out independently as a challenging

ideological testament.

Taken together, the essays in Free Cities represent Bookchin’s most

recent ideas, particularly on political and ideological issues. In my

view this anthology offers both a good introduction to his political

ideas as well as solid overview of his communalist approach. Not only

does it contain much previously unpublished material, it helps explain

ideological issues that remained unresolved at his death, particularly

concerning his ideological break with anarchism. It will be easy for

readers familiar with Bookchin’s writings to see how his distinct

political ideas are educed from his broader theory of social ecology.

For Bookchin, to advance libertarian municipalism meant to defend and

build upon the ideals of the Enlightenment, which he considered the

greatest tradition of social development. Based on communalism and

social ecology, libertarian municipalism is a fundamental attempt to

define a political humanism and to formulate and create a rational

society.

---

I confess that preparing this manuscript for publication has not been

easy, particularly since Bookchin passed away before seeing its

completion. Despite the arduous task, I have nevertheless found it a

pleasure to work with these wonderful ideas.

I would particularly like to thank Janet Biehl, who meticulously edited

all of Murray’s work in his last two decades before it saw publication.

I would also like to express my gratitude to my close comrades Yngvild

Hasvik and Sveinung Legard, since their support, patience, and advice

have been indispensable in finishing this project.

At the end of this preface I would also like to properly thank Murray

Bookchin for allowing me to work on these ideas, and for our ten years

of cooperation and friendship. It has been a privilege to be associated

with him; his intellectual vigor was always a source of great

inspiration, and I have gained much from his genuinely sharing

personality. However much I have enjoyed his warmth and generosity on a

personal level, my gratitude above all is for his achievement in

providing a future movement with such challenging ideas.

If this collection of essays contributes to contemporary discussions on

what kind of political institutions and radical organizations we need

today, it will have served its purpose. It is my genuine hope that

readers will seek to familiarize themselves with Bookchin’s ideas, here

and in his other works, not as an academic exercise but as a way of

preparing to change the world.

Eirik Eiglad

March 30, 2008

Introduction

These essays are my final assessment of some 80 years of social

reflections on the twentieth century. In a very real sense, they are the

product of a lifetime of study and political work, distilled from a

remarkable era of revolutionary history that spanned decades of social

upheaval, from the 1917 Russian Revolution to the closing years of the

twentieth century.

I make no pretense to claiming that these essays resolve any of the

crises that beset the people who lived out the century. It would be

remarkable indeed to know even how to properly define these crises,

still less to be capable of solving them. I do not claim to be able to

answer all of the questions we face, but they must be considered –

hopefully as a basis for future and creative discourse. The questions we

ask and the answers we give are socially and politically defining. Taken

together, they actually form the battleground for the future of social

life, and our responses are the basis for how we constitute ourselves as

social beings.

I would like to suggest that these essays be seen as the political

conclusions I have drawn from my historical and philosophical work in

The Ecology of Freedom, The Philosophy of Social Ecology, Re-Enchanting

Humanity, From Urbanization to Cities and last but not in the least The

Third Revolution. Throughout these works I have tried to meld together

the most challenging historical ideals into a body of theory that

generally went by the name “social ecology”. These ideas combine as

strands in a common thread: a search to understand the place of humanity

in the natural world and the social factors that must be present if we

are to actualize our ability (as yet incomplete) to bring to bear, in

all the affairs of “raw” or first nature, a “sophisticated” or second

nature informed by reason. By combining the words “ecology” and

“freedom” I tried to show that neither nature nor reason could be

properly conceptualized independently of the other; that the natural

world could not be given any meaning without the social world or the

human mind, that is, without the ability to abstract experience and

generalize facts into far-reaching insights.

---

For most of human history, society, in effect, was familial, not civic;

it was organized around blood ties (real or fictive), not legal tenets.

Allocation of the means of life fulfilled necessities – especially

rights and duties – among literal and figurative relatives in a nexus of

shared, unquestioned responsibilities. Things were brought together in

an indisputably “natural” manner, such that the “people” were unified –

even more compellingly than by custom – by an inborn scheme of reality.

They could not act otherwise, and their life-ways allowed for no

discretion to follow any path other than what was given by the “eternal”

nature of things.

The rise of organized communities – ultimately cities, civilization, and

citizenship, as distinguished from habitats, customs, and folk –

radically changed this state of affairs. Indeed, it marked the great

rupture of Homo sapiens from merely a creative kind of animal into

humans as such. The most powerful medium for achieving this radical new

dispensation was a process of alienation called trade, a process that

drastically remade the apprehension of reality from imagery into

objectivity. The traditional world of imagination and analogical

thinking gave way to a new world of systematic analysis and disciplined

thought, engendered by commerce, efficient production, and careful

calculation. Trade rewarded predictability based on objectivity, and

knowledge based on reality, with power and wealth. To know meant to live

in palpable touch with reality.

Knowledge ceased to be an end in itself; it became a tool, an instrument

of control and manipulation. Yet ultimately it created a new world of

thoughts and things, a new universe that redefined what it meant to be

alive – generating an appetite for wealth, for competition, for growth

for its own sake, for private ownership, and for power over men. What

humans could imagine, they brought into existence. Even the

transformation of human beings from earth-bound to flying creatures

constituted a remarkable advance in the conversion of image into object

– and no less significantly, it reduced a frightening mystery to a

prosaic problem of engineering. Nuclear physics transformed vast,

ineffable legends into problems of ordinary mathematics, no less

unsolvable than the questions posed by Euclidean geometry.

But how was this even possible? The people who now grappled with the

fantastic problems that had occupied human beings even several millennia

earlier were, in fact, no longer the same people. Their outlook was no

longer animistic, and they no longer lived in organic societies. Owing

to their habitation in villages and cities, to their written literature

and systematic modes of thought, to their careful retrospection and

introspection, to their substitution of mythopoeic fantasy with rational

thought, they were becoming humanized, rationalized, and civilized –

veritably a new species.

Social theory could not ignore the extent to which mythopoesis, fantasy,

and unbridled subjectivity yielded to humanization, rationalization and

civilization, and it did not do so. This new world, particularly its

emergence, was most brilliantly elucidated in the economic works of Karl

Marx and his disciples. Despite their historical limitations, they still

stand as a monument to the power of thought to rise above fantasy.

---

Bolstered by three massive volumes of closely reasoned economic

analysis, considerable mathematical formulations, and highly persuasive

historical data, Marxism emerged after World War One as the dominant

ideology of the Western European radical intelligentsia and affected the

thinking of great masses of literate working people. Despite many

variations in Marxist tenets, Marx was seen as the man who provided the

labor movement of the West with the basic ideas of socialism.

Treated like a new gospel, this “scientific” socialism was regarded as

evidence, not of dogmatism, but of learning and of modern intellectual

certainty. Marxist doctrine, in effect, was regarded as objective truth,

which qualified its expositors to speak authoritatively on any subject

as the peers of informed scientists, not only in economics but also in

the life sciences and mathematics, not to speak of literature and

ethics. In history, social development, and, needless to emphasize, with

regard to current events, its acolytes persuasively claimed to enjoy a

special knowledge of the course of events and their meaning. Owing to

their adoption of Hegel’s notion of the “cunning of reason,” Marxists

professed to understand the “hidden hand” of social development, as it

were, looking beyond cultural, political, religious, mystical, and even

artistic claims to the “underlying” class interests.

In the hands of Marxian acolytes like Georg Plekhanov and Karl Kautsky,

who essentially substituted dialectics for mechanics, social theory

became the deadening scientism of a new “social physics.” The interwar

generation, the product of the mechanics of the class struggle, the

dogma of social reductionism, and the hard-nosed idea of social dynamics

rather than social dialectics, emerged as true class beings – Homo

economicus. Marxism’s greatest claim to superiority over the so-called

“utopian” socialists was its contention that it had prospectively

established the hegemonic role of the proletariat over all other classes

in achieving a socialist society. Of all classes, the proletariat, Marx

expressly maintained, had nothing to sell but its abstract “labor power”

(that is, its biological capacity to produce commodities in quantities

beyond what was necessary for the satisfaction of its needs), and for

that reason its historical destiny was to be driven to overthrow the

capitalist system and replace it with a planned, nationalized economy.

This seminal, forcibly driven act made Marx’s work distinctive among

theories of socialism.

But the greatest shortcoming of Marxism was its celebrated claim to

finality. Capital asserted that capitalism appears as the dissection of

the bourgeois economy in all its “wholeness,” encapsulated as a

“science,” a notion that presupposes (like Quesnay’s Tableau Economique)

a social stability that would have credibility only in the finitude or

static perfection of Aristotle’s stars. Of course, nowhere in Being is

such immobility possible, and no concept could be more nonsensical.

Indeed, as the ancient Greeks emphasized, all that exists is

development, elaboration, and increasing (but always incomplete)

“fullness.” Thought and life are unending innovation. In a Being that is

necessarily paradoxical, we strive not only for a “whole,” not only for

a “totality” that is complete, but for one whose “final” contours always

elude us.

---

These essays, then, do not work from the notion that there can be an

“end to history.” Defining history as having an ultimate end would

dissolve it into a meaningless conundrum, bereft of experience and

development. Yet the word history is one of the few that alternately

denotes both completeness and dynamism. Within a given “stage” history

has a completeness to itself, but in history as a “process” a given

period “flows” into the next with no terminus, so to speak. We thus find

ourselves faced with a conundrum, more like a Kantian syllogism that has

to be accepted as a given, or what Hegel would call a contradiction.

Not only do the grand works of philosophy have intrinsic dual meanings,

they also reflect significant institutional changes that societies have

undergone with the passage of time, from eras of obeisance to kings and

nobles to our own. Sweeping social changes in a surprisingly brief

period of time have created a need for profoundly new social terms,

indeed for a dictionary more inclusionary than we have today. Such a

compilation of terms, or expansions in meaning of words in common use

today, amounts to the formulation of a new system of ideas. As we educe

one idea from the others, we can derive from every one the

potentialities of less inclusive but profoundly meaningful offspring,

with a variety of divergent developments.

From this perspective, history becomes an open prospect that suggests

the potentiality for a multitude of radically new forms. I presented one

of a number of courses that this approach to a social dialectic might

take in my book The Ecology of Freedom; alternative courses were put

forward by non-European societies, particularly in the pre-Columbian

Americas. It is not an idle endeavor to try to imagine what a handicraft

society, whose economy was deliberately mixed and small-scale in

character, might have looked like – as a “rational” society – in

contrast to the medieval world that actually preceded urban society in

Western Europe. It is not accidental that William Morris’s News from

Nowhere, which describes such a society, has attracted so many admirers

in our own time as a “model” utopia, especially among libertarian

socialists and syndicalists.

---

What concerns us here, however, is the ossification of these libertarian

and organic traditions during the period that spanned the two world

wars. The “Great War” was fought largely by means of brutal trench

warfare; backing out of that slaughter, the world entered the “Roaring

Twenties,” then the “Great Depression” and the tumultuous 1930s, with

socialist insurrections, the fascist coups of Mussolini and Hitler, the

Spanish Civil War, and Stalin’s massive purges. The period that thus

closed with the genocidal World War Two cannot be mechanically locked

into a historical box. The years from 1914 to 1950 constitute one of the

most eventful periods of true history, wherein people’s actions surmount

the quantitative stuff from which mere calendars are made.

The Euro-American generation of young radicals that emerged after World

War One and that tried to resolve the revolutionary era of the interwar

era was perhaps the most perplexing in modern history. It was certainly

the most embattled and, ideologically, the most insurrectionary toward

the deeply entrenched exploitative social order, notably capitalism.

After World War Two astonishing technological changes, soaring

production figures, major advances in the living standards of Western

workers, and broadly rightward shifts in popular political sentiments

all made it evident that capitalism had more life remaining to it than

the Bolsheviks and the anarcho-syndicalists had foreseen decades

earlier. After the short-lived New Left of the 1960s, revolutionary

movements waned steadily in numbers and purpose, while erstwhile radical

social theorists immersed themselves in academic esoterica such as the

peregrinations of the various Frankfurt School theorists, of Georg

Lukács and Antonio Gramsci, and finally in postmodernism, the expression

par excellence of the “virtues” of ideological disorder and social

nihilism.

---

As someone who lived out this era, I was variously regarded – or

regarded myself – as a communist (including one who adhered to

successive views held by Trotsky), a libertarian socialist, and in a

rather spotty fashion, an anarchist. In the 1970s and 1980s I expressed

my ideas forcefully in a rather romantic anarchist framework. Later,

however, I found it increasingly difficult to reconcile anarchism with

my basic views. In the 1990s it was gradually becoming clear to me that

an ideology that does little more than hail the “autonomy of the ego,”

and that conceives of “liberty” in extremely individualistic terms, can

never produce basic social change. A lifestyle rather than an ideology,

anarchism, I came to realize, is concerned more with individual behavior

than with political change and allows little room for a creative

political practice.

My own experiences in the labor movement (as a foundryman and later as

an autoworker) in the 1930s and 1940s had long ago convinced me that

making basic and lasting change requires organization (as the IWW martyr

Joe Hill voiced just before his execution). But most of the anarchists I

encountered resisted organization, sometimes vehemently. And when I

tried to properly define politics (as the directly democratic

organization of the free municipality by popular assemblies) as the very

opposite of statecraft (rule by professional bureaucrats, ultimately

through a monopoly of the means of violence), my once-close anarchist

associates assailed me as “statist.” Democracy, they asserted, is itself

a form of “rule,” by the majority over the minority. A preposterous

rejection of majority voting in favor of consensus decision-making

played a major role in ruining the huge American anti-nuclear movement

in the 1980s and potentially makes any movement organization and

institution (beyond a small group) dysfunctional. In the end I found

that I had either to close my eyes to the compelling need for

organization in praxis, and for democratic institutions in public

affairs in a future libertarian society, or else completely recast my

views. I chose to do the latter.

Reflecting as they do my most recent and, having passed the age of 80,

my most mature ideas, these essays try to explain why social ecology can

no longer be seen as a mere extension of traditional radical ideologies,

either Marxist or anarchist. It is now my conviction that the ensemble

of views that I call social ecology, libertarian municipalism, and

dialectical naturalism should properly form the basis for a new

libertarian ideology and politics – communalism – that takes full

account of the sweeping changes that have occurred in capitalism since

the failure of proletarian socialism in the second half of the twentieth

century and that suggests the new methods that are needed to transform a

market-based society into a truly libertarian socialist one.

The reader alone will decide whether these essays are correct or

erroneous and whether my expectations for communalism are sound or

fanciful, but their most essential purpose is to create a new departure

from ideologies that were inspired by the problems of the Industrial

Revolution of two centuries ago, a departure that takes full account of

changing class relations and hierarchical forms, of demographical

transformations and ecological dislocations, and of urbanization, to

cite the most important factors. Few of these issues had an important

place in the writings of Marx, Bakunin, and their successors. Without

ignoring the vital contributions that the ablest Marxists and left

libertarians have made to social theory, I would ask the reader to

recognize the centrality of these more recent issues in the essays that

follow.

---

Only time will tell how capitalism will undermine itself, as Marx long

ago expected it would, and to what degree the public – middle class and

working class alike – will acquire those mutualistic impulses that the

followers of Kropotkin impute to human nature. It will not be my

privilege to see in my lifetime the achievement of a rational,

ecological, and humanistic society in which people will finally be

natural and social evolution rendered self-conscious – the great hope of

Western philosophy and social progress for two thousand years. What I

hold to, and what I try to impart through these essays, is my belief

that the noblest role conscious human beings can play today is not only

to seek the emancipation of people from the irrationalities of

capitalist and hierarchical society but also to defend the Enlightenment

and its message of reason in public affairs against the dark forces of

irrationality, nihilism, and ultimately barbarism that stand at the

gates of civilization. My own generation fought off Nazism and

superstition with some success. The present and coming generations must

have as their task to oppose the “dumbing down” of the human mind, its

growing trivialization and juvenilization, and its appalling ignorance

even of the recent past. They must oppose the new gospel of

self-absorption at the expense of public affairs. They may have once

again to deal with ghosts of the past – fascism and Stalinism – as well.

In the meantime, we still have time to build a coherent theoretical

framework for our practice and to prepare for the “final conflict” that

may yet come at some point in the present century.

Murray Bookchin

Burlington, Vermont

November, 2005

The Ecological Crisis and the Need to Remake Society

In addressing the sources of our present ecological and social problems,

perhaps the most fundamental message that social ecology advances is

that the very idea of dominating nature stems from the domination of

human by human. The primary implication of this most basic message is a

call for a politics and even an economics that offer a democratic

alternative to the nation-state and the market society. I would like to

offer a broad sketch of these issues to lay the groundwork for the

changes necessary in moving toward a free and ecological society.

The Social Roots of the Ecological Crisis

First, the most fundamental route to a resolution of our ecological

problems is social in character. That is to say, if we are faced with

the prospect of outright ecological catastrophe, toward which so many

knowledgeable people and institutions claim we are headed today, it is

because the historical domination of human by human has been extended

outward from society into the natural world. Until domination as such is

removed from social life and replaced by a truly egalitarian and sharing

society, powerful ideological, technological, and systemic forces will

be used by the existing society to degrade the environment, indeed the

entire biosphere. Hence, more than ever today, it is imperative that we

develop the consciousness and the movement to remove domination from

society, indeed from our everyday lives – in relationships between the

young and the elderly, between women and men, in educational

institutions and workplaces, and in our attitude toward the natural

world. To permit the poison of domination – and a domineering

sensibility – to persist is, at this time, to ignore the most basic

roots of our ecological as well as social problems – problems whose

sources can be traced back to the very roots of our civilization.

Second, and more specifically, the modern market society that we call

capitalism, and its alter ego, “state socialism,” have brought all the

historic problems of domination to a head. The consequences of this

“grow or die” market economy must inexorably lead to the destruction of

the natural basis for complex life-forms, including humanity. It is,

however, all too common these days to single out either population

growth or technology – or both – to blame for the ecological

dislocations that beset us. But we cannot single out either of these as

“causes” of problems whose most deep-seated roots actually lie in the

market economy. Attempts to focus on these alleged “causes” are

scandalously deceptive and shift our focus from the social issues we

must resolve.

In the American experience, people only a generation or two removed from

my own generation slashed their way through the vast forests of the

West, nearly exterminated millions of bison, plowed fertile grasslands,

and laid waste to a large part of the continent – all using only hand

axes, simple plows, horse-drawn vehicles, and simple hand tools. It

required no technological revolution to create the present devastation

of what had once been a vast and fecund region capable, with rational

management, of sustaining both human and non-human life. What brought so

much ruin to the land was not the technological implements that those

earlier generations of Americans used but the insane drive of

entrepreneurs to succeed in the bitter struggle of the marketplace, to

expand and devour the riches of their competitors lest they be devoured

in turn by their rivals. In my own lifetime, millions of small American

farmers were driven from their homes not only by natural disasters but

by giant agricultural corporations that turned so much of the landscape

into a huge industrial system for cultivating food.

Not only has a society based on endless wasteful growth devastated

entire regions, indeed a continent, with only simple technology; the

ecological crisis it has produced is systemic – and not a matter of

misinformation, spiritual insensitivity, or lack of moral integrity. The

present social illness lies not only in the outlook that pervades the

present society; it lies above all in the very structure and law of life

in the system itself, in its imperative, which no entrepreneur or

corporation can ignore without facing destruction: growth, more growth,

and still more growth. Blaming technology for the ecological crisis

serves, however unintentionally, to blind us to the ways technology

could in fact play a creative role in a rational, ecological society. In

such a society, the intelligent use of sophisticated technology would be

direly needed to restore the vast ecological damage that has already

been inflicted on the biosphere, much of which will not repair itself

without creative human intervention.

Along with technology, population is commonly singled out for blame as

an alleged “cause” of the ecological crisis. But population is by no

means the overwhelming threat that some disciples of Malthus in today’s

ecology movements would have us believe. People do not reproduce like

the fruit flies that are so often cited as examples of mindless

reproductive growth. They are products of culture as well as of

biological nature. Given decent living standards, reasonably educated

families often have fewer children in order to improve the quality of

their lives. Given education, moreover, and a consciousness of gender

oppression, women no longer allow themselves to be reduced to mere

reproductive factories. Instead, they stake out claims as humans with

all the rights to meaningful and creative lives. Ironically, technology

has played a major role in eliminating the domestic drudgery that for

centuries culturally stupefied women and reduced them to mere servants

of men and men’s desire to have children – preferably sons, to be sure.

In any case, even if population were to decline for some unspecified

reason, the large corporations would try to make people buy more and

still more in order to render economic expansion possible. Failing to

attain a large enough domestic consumers’ market in which to expand,

corporate minds would turn to international markets – or to that the

most lucrative of markets, the military.

Finally, well-meaning people who regard New Age moralism,

psychotherapeutic approaches, or personal lifestyle changes as the key

to resolving the present ecological crisis are destined to be tragically

disappointed. No matter how much this society paints itself green or

orates the need for an ecological outlook, the way society literally

breathes cannot be undone unless it undergoes profound structural

changes: namely by replacing competition with cooperation, and profit

seeking with relationships based on sharing and mutual concern. Given

the present market economy, a corporation or entrepreneur who tried to

produce goods in accordance with even a minimally decent ecological

outlook would rapidly be devoured by a rival in a marketplace whose

selective process of competition rewards the most villainous at the

expense of the most virtuous. After all, “business is business,” as the

maxim has it. And business allows no room for people who are restrained

by conscience or moral qualms, as the many scandals in the “business

community” attest. Attempting to win over the “business community” to an

ecological sensibility, let alone to ecologically beneficial practices,

would be like asking predatory sharks to live on grass or “persuading”

lions to lovingly lie down beside lambs.

The fact is that we are confronted by a thoroughly irrational social

system, not simply by predatory individuals who can be won over to

ecological ideas by moral arguments, psychotherapy, or even the

challenges of a troubled public to their products and behavior. It is

less that these entrepreneurs control the present system of savage

competition and endless growth than that the system of savage

competition and growth controls them. The stagnation of New Age ideology

today in the United States attests to its tragic failure to “improve” a

social system that must be completely replaced if we are to resolve the

ecological crisis. One can only commend the individuals who by virtue of

their consumption habits, recycling activities, and appeals for a new

sensibility undertake public activities to stop ecological degradation.

Each surely does his or her part. But it will require a much greater

effort – an organized, clearly conscious, and forward-looking political

movement – to meet the basic challenges posed by our aggressively

anti-ecological society.

Class, Hierarchies, and Politics

Yes, we as individuals should change our lifestyles as much as possible,

but it is the utmost shortsightedness to believe that that is all or

even primarily what we have to do. We need to restructure the entire

society, even as we engage in lifestyle changes and single-issue

struggles against pollution, nuclear power plants, the excessive use of

fossil fuels, the destruction of soil, and so forth. We must have a

coherent analysis of the deep-seated hierarchical relationships and

systems of domination, as well as of class relationships and economic

exploitation, that degrade people as well as the environment. Here, we

must move beyond the insights provided by the Marxists, syndicalists,

and even many liberal economists, who for years reduced most social

antagonisms and problems to class analysis. Class struggle and economic

exploitation still exist, and the classical – and still perceptive –

class analysis reveals iniquities about the present social order that

are intolerable.

But the Marxian and liberal belief that capitalism has played a

“revolutionary” role in destroying traditional communities, and that

technological advances seeking to “conquer” nature are a precondition

for freedom, rings terribly hollow today, when many of these very

advances are being used to make the most formidable weapons and means of

surveillance the world has ever seen. Nor could the Marxian socialists

of my day, 60 years ago, have anticipated how successfully capitalism

would use its technological prowess to co-opt the working class and even

diminish its numbers in relation to the rest of the population.

Yes, class struggles still exist – but they occur further and further

below the threshold of class war. Workers, as I can attest from my own

experience as a foundryman and autoworker for General Motors, do not

regard themselves as mindless adjuncts to machines, or as factory

dwellers, or as “instruments of history,” as Marxists might put it. They

regard themselves as living human beings: as fathers and mothers, as

sons and daughters, as people with dreams and visions, as members of

communities – not only of trade unions. Living in towns and cities,

their eminently human aspirations go well beyond their “historic role”

as class agents of “history.” They suffer from the pollution of their

communities as well as from their factories, and they are as concerned

about the welfare of their children, companions, neighbors, and

communities, as they are about their jobs and wage scales.

The overly economistic focus of traditional socialism and syndicalism

has in recent years caused these movements to lag behind emerging

ecological issues and visions – as they lagged, I may add, behind

feminist concerns, cultural issues, and urban issues, all of which often

cut across class lines to include middle-class people, intellectuals,

small proprietors, and even some bourgeois. Their failure to confront

hierarchy – not only class and domination, not only economic

exploitation – has often alienated women from socialism and syndicalism

to the extent that they awakened to the age-old reality that they have

been oppressed irrespective of their class status. Similarly, broad

community concerns like pollution afflict people as such, whatever the

class to which they belong. Disasters like the meltdown of the Chernobyl

reactor in the Ukraine justly panicked everyone who was exposed to

radiation from the plant, not simply workers and peasants.

Indeed, even if we were to achieve a classless society free of economic

exploitation, would we readily achieve a rational society? Would women,

young people, the infirm, the elderly, people of color, various

oppressed ethnic groups – the list is, in fact, enormous – be free of

domination? The answer is a categorical no – a fact to which women can

certainly attest, even within the socialist and syndicalist movements

themselves. Without eliminating the ancient hierarchical and domineering

structures from which classes and the state actually emerged, we would

have made only a part of the changes needed to achieve a rational

society. There would still be a historical intoxicant in a socialist or

syndicalist society – hierarchy – that would continually erode its

highest ideals, namely the achievement of a truly free and ecological

society.

The Myth of a “Minimal State”

Perhaps the most disquieting feature of many radical groups today,

particularly socialists who may accept the foregoing observation, is

their commitment to at least a minimal state that would coordinate and

administer a classless and egalitarian society – a non-hierarchical one,

no less! One hears this argument from André Gorz and many others, who,

presumably because of the many “complexities” of modern society, cannot

conceive of the administration of economic affairs without some kind of

coercive mechanism, albeit one with a “human face.”

This logistical and in some cases frankly authoritarian view of the

human condition (as expressed in the writings of Arne Næss, the father

of “deep ecology”) reminds one of a dog chasing its tail. Simply because

the “tail” is there – a metaphor for economic “complexity” or market

systems of distribution – does not mean that the metaphorical dog must

chase it in circles that lead nowhere. The “tail” we have to worry about

can be rationally simplified by reducing or eliminating commercial

bureaucracies and the needless reliance on goods from abroad that can be

produced by recycling at home, and by increasing the use of local

resources that are now ignored because they are not “competitively”

priced: in short, reducing the vast paraphernalia of goods and services

that may be indispensable to profit making and competition, but not to

the rational distribution of goods in a cooperative society. The painful

reality is that most excuses in radical theory for preserving a “minimal

state” stem from the myopic visions of eco-socialists like Gorz, who can

accept the present system of production and distribution as it is to one

degree or another – not as it should be in a moral economy. So

conceived, production and distribution seem more formidable – together

with their bureaucratic machinery, irrational division of labor, and

“global” nature – than they actually need to be. It would take no great

wisdom or array of computers to show with even a grain of imagination

how the present “global” system of production can be simplified and

still provide a decent standard of living for everyone. Indeed, it took

only some five years or so to rebuild a ruined Germany after World War

Two, far longer than it will require thinking people today to remove the

statist and bureaucratic apparatus for administering the global

distribution of goods and resources.

What is even more disquieting is the naive belief that a “minimal state”

could indeed remain “minimal.” If history – in fact, the events of the

past few years – has shown anything, it is that the state, far from

being only an instrument of a ruling elite, becomes an organism in its

own right that grows as unrelentingly as a cancer. Anarchism, in this

respect, has exhibited a prescience that discloses the terrible weakness

of the traditional socialist commitment to a state – proletarian, social

democratic, or “minimal.” To create a state is to institutionalize power

in the form of a machine that exists apart from the people. It is to

professionalize rule and policymaking, to create a distinct interest (be

it of bureaucrats, deputies, commissars, legislators, the military, the

police, ad nauseam) that, however weak, or however well-intentioned it

may be at first, eventually takes on a corruptive power of its own. When

over the course of history have states – however “minimal” – ever

dissolved themselves or constrained their growth into massive

malignancies? When have they ever remained “minimal”?

The recent deterioration of the German Greens – the so-called “non-party

party” that, after its acquisition of a place in the Bundestag, has now

become a crude political machine – is dramatic evidence that

parliamentary power corrupts with a vengeance. The idealists who helped

found the organization and sought to use the Bundestag merely as a

“platform” for their radical message have by now either left in disgust

or have themselves become rather unsavory examples of wanton political

careerism. One would have to be either utterly naive or simply blind to

the lessons of history to ignore the fact that the state, “minimal” or

not, absorbs and ultimately digests even the most well-meaning critics

once they enter it. It is not that statists use the state to abolish it

or “minimalize” its effects; it is, rather, the state that corrupts even

the most idealistic anti-statists who flirt with it.

Finally, the most disturbing feature of statism – even “minimal statism”

– is that it completely undermines a politics based on confederalism.

One of the most unfortunate features of traditional socialist history,

Marxian and otherwise, is that it emerged in an era of nation-state

building. The Jacobin model of a centralized revolutionary state was

accepted almost uncritically by nineteenth-century socialists and became

an integral part of the revolutionary tradition – a tradition, I may

add, that mistakenly associated itself with the nationalistic emphasis

of the French Revolution, as seen in the “Marseillaise” and its

adulation of la patrie. Marx’s view that the French Revolution was

basically to be a model for formulating a revolutionary strategy – he

mistakenly claimed that in its Jacobin form it was the most “classical”

of the “bourgeois” revolutions – had disastrous effects upon the

revolutionary tradition. Lenin adopted this vision so completely that

the Bolsheviks were rightly considered the “Jacobins” of the Russian

socialist movement, and, of course, Stalin used techniques such as

purges, show trials, and brute force with lethal effects for the

socialist project as a whole.

Beyond Statism and Privatism

The notion that human freedom can be achieved, much less perpetuated,

through a state of any kind is monstrously oxymoronic – a contradiction

in terms. Attempts to justify the existence of a cancerous phenomenon

like the state, and the use of statist measures or “statecraft,” exclude

a radically different form of social management, namely confederalism.

For centuries, in fact, democratic forms of confederalism – in which

municipalities were coordinated by mandated and recallable deputies who

were always under public scrutiny – have competed with statist forms and

constituted a challenging alternative to centralization,

bureaucratization, and the professionalization of power in the hands of

elite bodies. Let me emphasize that confederalism should not be confused

with federalism, which is simply the coordination of nation-states in a

network of agreements that preserve the prerogatives of policy-making

with little if any citizen involvement. Federalism is simply the state

writ large, indeed the further centralization of already centralized

states, as in the United States’ federal republic, the European

Community, or the recently formed Commonwealth of Independent States –

all collections of huge continental superstates that remove even further

whatever control the people have over nation-states.

A confederalist alternative would be based on a network of policy-making

popular assemblies with recallable deputies to local and regional

confederal councils – councils whose sole function, I must emphasize,

would be to adjudicate differences and undertake strictly administrative

tasks. One could scarcely advance such a prospect by making use of a

state formation of any kind, however “minimal.” Indeed, to juggle

statist and confederal perspectives in a verbal game by distinguishing

“minimal” from “maximal” is to utterly confuse the basis for a new

politics structured around a participatory democracy. Among Greens in

the United States there have already been tendencies that absurdly call

for “decentralization” and “grassroots democracy” while seeking to run

candidates for state and national offices – that is, for statist

institutions, one of whose essential functions is to confine, restrict,

and essentially suppress local democratic institutions and initiatives.

Indeed, as I have repeatedly emphasized, when radical ecologists and

libertarian socialists of all kinds engage in libertarian municipalist

politics and run for municipal public office, they are not merely

seeking to remake cities, towns, and villages on the basis of fully

democratic confederal networks; they are running against the state and

parliamentary offices. Hence, to call for a “minimal state,” even as a

coordinative institution, as André Gorz and others have done, is to

obscure and countervail any effort to replace the nation-state with a

confederation of municipalities.

It is to the credit of anarchism that it firmly rejects the traditional

socialist orientation toward state power and recognizes the corruptive

role of participating in parliamentary elections. What is regrettable is

that this rejection, so clearly corroborated by the corruption of

statist socialists, Greens, and members of other professed radical

movements, was not sufficiently nuanced to distinguish activity on the

municipal level as the basis of politics in the Hellenic sense: that is

to say, to distinguish electoral activity on the local level from

electoral activity on the provincial and national levels, which I have

argued really constitutes statecraft. The libertarian politics of social

ecology, by contrast, consistently seeks to revive or recreate the

political sphere, in flat opposition to the state; it attempts to create

a dual power to challenge the nationstate and replace it with a

confederation of democratized municipalities. Libertarian municipalism

may indeed begin in a limited way in civic wards, here and there, as

well as in small cities and towns, but its aim is nothing less than the

total remaking of society along rational, nonhierarchical and ecological

lines.

It would not be presumptuous to claim that social ecology, whatever its

other values or failings, represents a coherent interpretation of the

enormous ecological and social problems we face today. Its philosophy,

social theory, and political practice form a vital alternative to the

ideological stagnation and tragic failure of the present socialist,

syndicalist, and radical projects that were so much in vogue even as

recently as the 1960s. As to “alternatives” that offer us New Age or

mystical ecological solutions, what could be more naive than to believe

that a society whose very metabolism is based on growth, production for

its own sake, hierarchy, classes, domination, and exploitation could be

changed simply by moral suasion, individual action, and a childish

primitivism that essentially views technology as a curse and focuses

variously on demographic growth and personal modes of consumption as

primary issues? We must get to the heart of the crisis we face and

develop a popular politics that will eschew statism at one extreme and

New Age privatism at the other. If this goal is dismissed as “merely”

utopian, I am obliged to question what many radicals today would call

“realism.”

Nationalism and the “National Question”

One of the most vexing questions that the Left faces (however one may

define the Left) is the role played by nationalism in social development

and by popular demands for cultural identity and political sovereignty.

For the Left of the nineteenth century, nationalism was seen primarily

as a European issue, involving the consolidation of nation-states in the

heartland of capitalism. Only secondarily, if at all, was it seen as the

anti-imperialist and presumably anti-capitalist struggle that it was to

become in the twentieth century.

This did not mean that the nineteenth-century Left favored imperialist

depredations in the colonial world. At the turn of this century, hardly

any serious radical thinker, to my knowledge, regarded the imperialist

powers’ attempts to quell movements for self-determination in colonial

areas as a blessing. The Left scoffed at and usually denounced the

arrogant claims of European powers to bring “progress” to the

“barbarous” areas of the world. Marx’s views of imperialism may have

been equivocal, but he never lacked a genuine aversion for the

afflictions that native peoples suffered at the hands of imperialists.

Anarchists, in turn, were almost invariably hostile to the European

claim to be the beacon of civilization for the world.

Yet if the Left universally scorned the civilizatory claims of

imperialists at the end of the nineteenth century, it generally regarded

nationalism as an arguable issue. The “national question,” to use the

traditional phrase in which such discussions were cast, was subject to

serious disputes, certainly as far as tactics were involved. But by

general agreement, leftists did not regard nationalism, culminating in

the creation of nation-states, as the ultimate dispensation of

humanity’s future in a collectivist or communist society. Indeed, the

single principle on which the Left of the pre- World War One and the

interwar periods agreed was a belief in the shared humanity of people

regardless of their membership in different cultural, ethnic, and gender

groups, and their complementary affinities in a free society as rational

human beings with the capacity for cooperation, a willingness to share

material resources, and a fervent sense of empathy. The

“Internationale,” the shared anthem of social democrats, socialists, and

anarchists alike up to and even after the Bolshevik revolution, ended

with the stirring cry, “The ‘Internationale’ shall be the human race.”

The Left singled out the international proletariat as the historic agent

for modern social change not by virtue of its specificity as a class, or

its particularity as one component in a developing capitalist society,

but by virtue of its need to achieve universality in order to abolish

class society – that is, as the class driven by necessity to remove wage

slavery by abolishing enslavement as such. Capitalism had brought the

historic “social question” of human exploitation to its final and most

advanced form. “Tis the final conflict!” rang out the “Internationale,”

with a sense of universalistic commitment – one that no revolutionary

movement could ignore any longer without subverting the possibilities

for passing from a “prehistory” of barbarous class interest to a “true

history” of a totally emancipated humanity.

Minimally, this was the shared outlook of the prewar and interwar Left,

particularly of its various socialistic tendencies. The primacy the

anarchists and libertarian socialists have historically given to the

abolition of the state, the agency par excellence of hierarchical

coercion, led directly to their denigration of the nation-state and of

nationalism generally, not only because nationalism divides human beings

territorially, culturally, and economically, but because it follows in

the wake of the modern state and ideologically justifies it.

Of concern here is the internationalist tradition that played so

pronounced a role in the Left of the nineteenth century and the first

third of the twentieth, and its mutation into a highly problematical

“question,” particularly in Rosa Luxemburg’s and Lenin’s writings. This

is a “question” of no small importance. We have only to consider the

utter confusion that surrounds it today – when a savagely bigoted

nationalism is subverting the internationalist tradition of the Left –

to recognize its importance. The rise of nationalisms that exploit

racial, religious, and traditional cultural differences between human

beings, including even the most trivial linguistic and quasi-tribalistic

differences, not to speak of differences in gender identity and sexual

preference, marks a decivilization of humanity, a retreat to an age when

the number of fingers with which people made the sign of the cross

determined whether they and their neighbors would disembowel each other

in bloody conflicts, as Nikos Kazantzakis pointed out in Zorba the

Greek.

What is particularly disturbing is that the Left has not always seen

nationalism as a regressive demand. The modern Left, such as it is

today, all too often uncritically embraces the slogan “national

liberation” – a slogan that has echoed through its ranks without regard

for the basic ideal voiced in the “Internationale.” Calls for tribal

“identity” shrilly accentuate a group’s particular characteristics to

garner constituencies, an effort that negates the spirit of the

“Internationale” and the traditional internationalism of the Left. The

very meaning of nationalism and the nature of its relationship to

statism are raising issues, especially today, for which the Left is

bereft of ideas apart from appeals for “national liberation.”

If present-day leftists lose all viable memory of an earlier

internationalist Left – not to speak of humanity’s historical emergence

out of its animalistic background, its millennia-long development away

from such biological facts as ethnicity, gender, and age differences

toward truly social affinities based on citizenship, equality, and a

universalistic sense of a common humanity – the great role assigned to

reason by the Enlightenment may well be in grave doubt. Without a form

of human association that can resist and hopefully go beyond nationalism

in all its popular variants – whether it takes the form of a

reconstituted Left, a new politics, a social libertarianism, a

reawakened humanism, an ethics of complementarity – anything that we can

legitimately call civilization, indeed, the human spirit itself, may

well be extinguished long before nuclear war, the growing ecological

crises, or, more generally, a cultural barbarism comparable only to the

most destructive periods in history overwhelms us. In view of today’s

growing nationalism, then, few endeavors could be more important than to

examine the nature of nationalism and understand the so-called “national

question” as the Left in its various forms has interpreted it over the

years.

A Historical Overview

The level of human development can be gauged in great part by the extent

to which people recognize their shared unity. Indeed, personal freedom

consists in great part of our ability to choose friends, partners,

associates, and affines without regard to their biological differences.

What makes us human, apart from our ability to reason on a high plane of

generalization, consociate into mutable social institutions, work

cooperatively, and develop a highly symbolic system of communication, is

a shared knowledge of our humanitas. Goethe’s memorable words, so

characteristic of the Enlightenment mind, still haunt as a criterion of

our humanity: “There is a degree of culture where national hatred

vanishes, and where one stands to a certain extent above nations and

feels the weal and woe of a neighboring people as if it happened to

one’s own.”[11]

If Goethe established a standard of authentic humanity here – and surely

one can demand more of human beings than empathy for their “own people”

– early humanity was less than human by that standard. Although a

lunatic element in today’s ecology movement calls for a “return to a

Pleistocene spirituality,” they would in all probability have found that

“spirituality” very dispiriting in reality. In prehistoric eras,

probably marked by band and tribal social organization, human beings

were, “spiritually” or otherwise, first and foremost members of an

immediate family, second, members of a band, and ultimately, members of

a tribe. What determined membership in anything beyond one’s given

family group was an extension of the kinship tie: the people of a given

tribe were socially linked to one another by real or fictive blood

relationships. This “blood oath,” as well as other “biological facts”

like gender and age, defined one’s rights, obligations, and indeed one’s

identity in the tribal society.

Moreover, many – perhaps most – band or tribal groups regarded only

those who shared the “blood oath” with themselves as human. Indeed, a

tribe often referred to itself as “the People,” a name that expressed

its exclusive claim to humanity. Other people, who were outside the

magic circle of the real or mythic blood linkages of a tribe, were

“strangers” and hence in some sense were not human beings. The “blood

oath” and the use of the name “the People” to designate themselves often

pitted a tribe against others who made the same exclusive claim to be

human and to be “the People,” even among peoples who shared common

linguistic and cultural traits.

Tribal society, in fact, was extremely wary of anyone who was not one of

its own members. In many areas, before a stranger could cross a

territorial boundary, he had to submissively and patiently await an

invitation from an elder or shaman of the tribe that claimed the

territory before proceeding. Without hospitality, which was generally

conceived as a quasi-religious virtue, any stranger risked life and limb

in a tribe’s territory, so that lodgings and food were usually preceded

by ritual acts of trust or goodwill. The modern handshake may itself

have originated as a symbolic expression that one’s right hand was free

of weapons.

Warfare was endemic among our prehistoric ancestors and in later native

communities, notwithstanding the high, almost cultic status enjoyed by

ostensibly peaceful “ecological aborigines” among white middle-class

Euro- Americans today. When foraging groups overhunted the game in their

accustomed territory, as often happened, they were usually more than

willing to invade the area of a neighboring group and claim its

resources for their own. Commonly, after the rise of warrior sodalities,

warfare acquired cultural as well as economic attributes, so victors no

longer merely defeated their real or chosen “enemies” but virtually

exterminated them, as witness the near-genocidal destruction of the

Huron Indians by their linguistically and culturally related Iroquois

cousins.

If the major empires of the ancient Middle East and Orient conquered,

pacified, and subjugated many different ethnic and cultural groups,

thereby making alien peoples into the abject subjects of despotic

monarchies, the most important single factor to erode aboriginal

parochialism was the emergence of the city. The rise of the ancient

city, whether democratic as at Athens or republican as in Rome, marked a

radically new social dispensation. In contrast to the family-oriented

and parochial folk who had constituted the tribal and village world,

Western cities were now structured increasingly around residential

propinquity and shared economic interests. A “second nature,” as Cicero

called it, of humanistic social and cultural ties began to replace the

older form of social organization based on the “first nature” of

biological and blood ties, in which individuals’ social roles and

obligations had been anchored in their family, clan, gender, and the

like, rather than in associations of their own choice.

Etymologically, “politics” derives from the Greek politika, which

connotes an actively involved citizenry that formulates the policies of

a community or polis and, more often than not, routinely executes them

in the course of public service. Although formal citizenship was

required for participation in such politics, poleis like democratic

Athens celebrated their openness to visitors, particularly to skilled

craftsmen and knowledgeable merchants of other ethnic communities. In

his famous funeral oration, Pericles declared:

We throw open our city to the world, and never by alien acts exclude

foreigners from any opportunity of learning or observing, although the

eyes of an enemy may occasionally profit by our liberality, trusting

less in system and policy than to the native spirit of our citizens;

where in education, [our rivals in Sparta] from their very cradles by a

painful discipline seek after manliness, at Athens we live exactly as we

please and yet are just as ready to encounter every legitimate

danger.[12]

In Periclean times, Athenian liberality, to be sure, was still limited

by a largely fictitious notion of the shared ancestry of its citizens –

although less than it had been previously. But it is hard to ignore the

fact that Plato’s dialectical masterpiece, The Republic, occurs as a

dialogue in the home of Cephalos, whose family were resident aliens in

the Piraeus, the port area of Athens where most foreigners lived. Yet in

the dialogue itself the interchange between citizen and alien is

uninhibited by any status considerations.

The Roman emperor Caracalla, in time, made all freemen in the Empire

“citizens” of Rome with equal juridical rights, thereby universalizing

human relationships despite differences in language, ethnicity,

tradition, and place of residence. Christianity, for all its failings,

nonetheless celebrated the equality of all people’s souls in the eyes of

the deity, a heavenly “egalitarianism” that, in combination with open

medieval cities, theoretically eliminated the last attributes of

ancestry, ethnicity, and tradition that divided human beings from each

other.

In practice, it goes without saying, these attributes still persisted,

and various peoples retained parochial allegiances to their villages,

localities, and even cities, countervailing the tenuous Roman and

particularly Christian ideals of a universal humanitas. The unified

medieval world was fragmented juridically into countless baronial and

aristocratic sovereignties that parochialized local popular commitments

to a given lord or place, often pitting culturally and ethnically

related peoples against each other in other areas. The Catholic Church

opposed these parochial sovereignties, not only for doctrinal reasons

but in order to be able to expand papal authority over Christendom as a

whole. As for secular power, wayward but strong monarchs like Henry II

of England tried to impose the “king’s peace” over large territorial

areas, subduing warring nobles with varying degrees of success. Thus did

pope and king work in tandem to diminish parochialism, even as they

dueled with each other for control over ever-larger areas of the feudal

world.

Yet authentic citizens were deeply involved in classical political

activity in many places in Europe during the Middle Ages. The burghers

of medieval town democracies were essentially master craftsmen. The

tasks of their guilds, or richly articulated vocational fraternities,

were no less moral than economic – indeed, they formed the structural

basis for a genuine moral economy. Guilds not only “policed” local

markets, fixing “fair prices” and assuring that the quality of their

members’ goods would be high; they participated in civic and religious

festivals as distinct entities with their own banners, helped finance

and construct public buildings, saw to the welfare of the families of

deceased members, collected money for charity, and participated as

militiamen in the defense of the community of which they were a part.

Their cities, in the best of cases, conferred freedom on runaway serfs,

saw to the safety of travelers, and adamantly defended their civic

liberties. The eventual differentiation of the town populations into

wealthy and poor, powerful and powerless, and “nationalists” who

supported the monarchy against a predatory nobility, makes up a complex

drama that cannot be discussed here.

At various times and places some cities created forms of association

that were neither nations nor parochial baronies. These were intercity

confederations that lasted for centuries, such as the Hanseatic League,

cantonal confederations like that of Switzerland, and more briefly,

attempts to achieve free city confederations like the Spanish comuñero

movement in the early sixteenth century. It was not until the

seventeenth century – particularly under Cromwell in England and Louis

XIV in France – that centralizers of one form or another finally began

to carve out lasting nations in Europe.

Nation-states, let me emphasize, are states – not only nations.

Establishing them means vesting power in a centralized, professional,

bureaucratic apparatus that exercises a social monopoly of organized

violence, notably in the form of its armies and police. The state

preempts the autonomy of localities and provinces by means of its

all-powerful executive and, in republican states, its legislature, whose

members are elected or appointed to represent a fixed number of

“constituents.” The citizen in a self-managed locality vanishes into an

anonymous aggregation of individuals who pay a suitable amount of taxes

and receive the state’s “services.” “Politics” in the nation-state

devolves into a body of exchange relationships in which constituents

generally try to get what they pay for in a “political” marketplace of

goods and services. Nationalism as a form of tribalism writ large

reinforces the state by providing it with the loyalty of a people of

shared linguistic, ethnic, and cultural affinities, indeed legitimizing

the state by giving it a basis of seemingly all-embracing biological and

traditional commonalities among the people. It was not the English

people who created an England but the English monarchs and centralizing

rulers, just as it was the French kings and their bureaucracies who

forged the French nation.

Indeed, until state-building began to acquire new vigor in the fifteenth

century, nation-states in Europe remained a novelty. Even when

centralized authority based minimally on a linguistic commonality began

to foster nationalism throughout Western Europe and the United States,

nationalism faced a very dubious destiny. Confederalism remained a

viable alternative to the nation-state well into the latter half of the

nineteenth century. As late as 1871, the Paris Commune called upon all

the communes of France to form a confederal dual power in opposition to

the newly created Third Republic. Eventually the nation-state won out in

this complex conflict, and statism, in fact, was firmly linked to

nationalism. The two were virtually indistinguishable from each other by

the beginning of the twentieth century.

Nationalism and the Left

Radical theorists and activists on the Left dealt in very different ways

with the host of historical and ethical problems that nationalism raised

with respect to efforts to build a communistic, cooperative society.

Historically, the earliest leftist attempts to explore nationalism as a

problem obstructing the advent of a free and just society came from

various anarchist theorists. Pierre‑Joseph Proudhon seems never to have

questioned the ideal of human solidarity, although he never denied the

right of a people to cultural uniqueness and even to secede from any

kind of “social contract,” provided, to be sure, that no one else’s

rights were infringed upon. Although Proudhon detested slavery – he

sarcastically observed that the American South “with Bible in hand,

cultivates slavery,” while the American North “is already creating a

proletariat”[13] – he formally conceded the right of the Confederacy to

withdraw from the Union during the Civil War of 1861–65.

More generally, Proudhon’s federalist and mutualistic views led him to

oppose nationalist movements in Poland, Hungary, and Italy. His

anti-nationalist notions were somewhat diluted by his own Francophilism,

as the French socialist Jean Jaurès later noted. Proudhon feared the

formation of strong nation-states on or near France’s borders. But he

was also a product in his own way of the Enlightenment. Writing in 1862,

he declared: “I will never put devotion to my country before the rights

of Man. If the French Government behaves unjustly to any people, I am

deeply grieved and protest in every way that I can. If France is

punished for the misdeeds of her leaders, I bow my head and say from the

depths of my soul, ‘Merito haec patimur’ – ‘We have deserved these

ills.’”[14]

Despite his Gallic chauvinism, the “rights of Man” remained foremost in

Proudhon’s mind; nor was he oblivious to the fact that India and China

were, in his words, “at the mercy of barbarians.”[15] “Do you think that

it is French egoism, hatred of liberty, scorn for the Poles and Italians

that cause me to mock at and mistrust this commonplace word

nationality,” he wrote to Herzen, “which is being so widely used and

makes so many scoundrels and so many honest citizens talk so much

nonsense? For pity’s sake ... do not take offense so easily. If you do,

I shall have to say to you what I have been saying for six months about

your friend Garibaldi: ‘Of great heart but no brain.’”[16]

Michael Bakunin’s internationalism was as emphatic as Proudhon’s,

although his views were also marked by a certain ambiguity. “Only that

can be called a human principle which is universal and common to all

men,” he wrote in his internationalist vein; “and nationality separates

men, therefore it is not a principle.” Indeed, “There is nothing more

absurd and at the same time more harmful, more deadly, for the people

than to uphold the fictitious principle of nationality as the ideal of

all the people’s aspirations.” What counted finally for Bakunin was that

“Nationality is not a universal human principle.” Still further: “We

should place human, universal justice above all national interests. And

we should once and for all time abandon the false principle of

nationality, invented of late by the despots of France, Russia, and

Prussia for the purpose of crushing the sovereign principle of liberty.”

Yet Bakunin also declared that nationality “is a historic, local fact,

which like all real and harmless facts, has the right to claim general

acceptance.” Not only that, but this is a “natural fact” that deserves

“respect.” It may have been his rhetorical proclivities that led him to

declare himself “always sincerely the patriot of all oppressed

fatherlands.” But he argued that the right of every nationality “to live

according to its own nature” must be respected, since this “right” is

“simply the corollary of the general principle of freedom.”[17]

The subtlety of Bakunin’s observations should not be overlooked in the

midst of this seeming self-contradiction. He defined a general principle

that is human, one that is abridged or partially violated by asocial or

“biological” facts that for better or worse must be taken for granted.

To be a nationalist is to be less than human, but it is also inevitable

insofar as individuals are products of distinctive cultural traditions,

environments, and states of mind. Overshadowing the mere fact of

“nationality” is the higher universal principle in which people

recognize themselves as members of the same species and seek to foster

their commonalities rather than their “national” distinctiveness.

Such humanistic principles were to be taken very seriously by left

libertarians generally and strikingly so by the largest anarchist

movement of modern times, the Spanish anarchists. From the early 1880s

up to the bloody civil war of 1936–39, the anarchist movement of Spain

opposed not only statism and nationalism but even regionalism in all its

forms. Despite their enormous Catalan following, the Spanish anarchists

consistently raised the higher human principle of social liberation over

national liberation and opposed the nationalist tendencies within Spain

that so often divided Basques, Catalans, Andalusians, and Galicians from

one another and particularly from the Castilians, who enjoyed cultural

supremacy over the country’s minorities. Indeed, the word “Iberian”

rather than “Spanish” that appears in the name Iberian Anarchist

Federation (FAI) served to express not only a commitment to peninsular

solidarity but an indifference to regional and national distinctions

between Spain and Portugal. The Spanish anarchists cultivated Esperanto

as a “universal” human language more enthusiastically than any major

radical tendency, and “universal brotherhood” remained a lasting ideal

of their movement – as it historically did in most libertarian socialist

movements up to the present day.

Prior to 1914, Marxists and the Second International generally held

similar convictions, despite the burgeoning of nineteenth-century

nationalism. In Marx and Engels’s view, the proletariat of the world had

no country; authentically unified as a class, it was destined to abolish

all forms of class society. The Communist Manifesto ends with the

ringing appeal: “Working Men of All Countries, Unite!” In the body of

the work (which Bakunin translated into Russian), the authors declared:

“In the national struggles of the proletarians of different countries,

[Communists] point out and bring to the front the common interests of

the entire proletariat, independently of all nationality.”[18] And

further: “The working men have no country. We cannot take away from them

what they have not got.”[19]

The support that Marx and Engels did lend to “national liberation”

struggles was essentially strategic, stemming primarily from their

geopolitical and economic concerns rather than from broad social

principle. They vigorously championed Polish independence from Russia,

for example, because they wanted to weaken the Russian empire, which in

their day was the supreme counter-revolutionary power on the European

continent. And they wanted to see a united Germany because a

centralized, powerful nation-state would provide it with what Engels, in

a letter to Karl Kautsky in 1882, called “the normal political

constitution of the European bourgeoisie.”

Yet the manifest similarities between the internationalist rhetoric of

Marx and Engels in The Communist Manifesto and the internationalism of

the anarchist theorists and movements should not be permitted to conceal

the important differences between these two forms of socialism –

differences that were to play a major role in the debates that separated

them. The anarchists were in every sense ethical socialists who upheld

universal principles of the “brotherhood of man” and “fraternity,”[20]

principles that Marx’s “scientific socialism” disdained as mere

“abstractions.” In later years, even when speaking broadly of freedom

and the oppressed, Marx and Engels considered the use of seemingly

“inexact” words like “workers” and “toilers” to be an implicit rejection

of socialism as a “science”; instead, they preferred what they

considered the more scientifically rigorous word proletariat, which

specifically referred to those who generate surplus value.

Indeed, in contrast to anarchist theorists like Proudhon, who considered

the spread of capitalism and the proletarianization of preindustrial

peasantry and craftspeople to be a disaster, Marx and Engels

enthusiastically welcomed these developments, as well as the formation

of large, centralized nation-states in which market economies could

flourish. They saw them not only as desiderata in fostering economic

development but, by promoting capitalism, as indispensable in creating

the preconditions for socialism. Despite their support for proletarian

internationalism, they derogated what they saw as “abstract”

denunciations of nationalism as such or scorned them as merely

“moralistic.” Although internationalism in the interests of class

solidarity remained a desideratum for Marx and Engels, their view

implicitly stood at odds with their commitment to capitalist economic

expansion with its need in the nineteenth century for centralized

nation-states. They held the nation‑state to be good or bad insofar as

it advanced or inhibited the expansion of capital, the advance of the

“productive forces,” and the proletarianization of preindustrial

peoples. In principle, they looked askance at the nationalist sentiments

of Indians, Chinese, Africans, and the rest of the noncapitalist world,

whose precapitalist social forms might impede capitalist expansion.

Ireland, ironically, seems to have been an exception to this approach.

Marx, Engels, and the Marxist movement as a whole acknowledged the right

of the Irish to national liberation largely for sentimental reasons and

because it would produce problems for English imperialism, which

commanded a world market. In the main, until such time as a socialist

society could be achieved, Marxists considered the formation of large,

ever more centralized nation‑states in Europe to be “historically

progressive.”

Given their instrumental geopolitics, it should not be surprising that

as the years went by, Marx and Engels essentially supported Bismarck’s

attempts to unify Germany. Their express distaste for Bismarck’s methods

and for the landed gentry in whose interests he spoke should not be

taken too seriously, in my view. They would have welcomed Germany’s

annexation of Denmark, and they called for the incorporation of smaller

European nationalities like the Czechs and Slavs generally into a

centralized Austria-Hungary, as well as the unification of Italy into a

nation‑state, in order to broaden the terrain of the market and the

sovereignty of capitalism on the European continent.

Nor is it surprising that Marx and Engels supported Bismarck’s armies in

the Franco‑Prussian war of 1870 – despite the opposition of their

closest adherents in the German Social Democratic party, Wilhelm

Liebknecht and August Bebel – at least up to the point when those armies

crossed the French frontier and surrounded Paris in 1871. Ironically,

Marx and Engels’s own arguments were to be invoked by the European

Marxists who diverged from their anti-war comrades to support their

respective national military efforts at the outbreak of World War One.

Pro-war German Social Democrats supported the Kaiser as a bulwark

against Russian “Asiatic” barbarism – seemingly in accordance with Marx

and Engels’s own views – while the French Socialists (as well as

Kropotkin in Britain and later in Russia) invoked the tradition of their

country’s Great Revolution in opposition to “Prussian militarism.”

Despite many widespread claims that Rosa Luxemburg was more anarchistic

than a committed Marxist, she actually vigorously opposed the

motivations of anarchic forms of socialism and was more of a doctrinaire

Marxist than is generally realized. Her opposition to Polish nationalism

and Pilsudski’s Polish Socialist Party (which demanded Polish national

independence) as well as her hostility toward nationalism generally,

admirable and courageous as it was, rested principally not on an

anarchistic belief in the “brotherhood of man” but on traditional

Marxist arguments – namely, an extension of Marx and Engels’s desire for

unified markets and centralized states at the expense of Eastern

European nationalities, albeit with a new twist.

By the turn of the century, new considerations had come to the

foreground that induced Luxemburg to modify her views. Like many social

democratic theorists at the time, Luxemburg shared the conviction that

capitalism had passed from a progressive into a largely reactionary

phase. No longer a historically progressive economic order, capitalism

was now reactionary because it had fulfilled its “historical” function

in advancing technology and presumably in producing a class-conscious or

even revolutionary proletariat. Lenin systematized this conclusion in

his famous work, Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism.

Thus both Lenin and Luxemburg logically denounced World War One as

imperialist and broke with all socialists who supported the Entente and

the Central Powers, deriding them as “social patriots.” Where Lenin

markedly differed from Luxemburg (aside from the famous issue of his

support for a centralized party organization) was on how, from a

strictly “realistic” standpoint, the “national question” could be used

against capitalism in an era of imperialism. To Lenin, the national

struggles of economically undeveloped colonized countries for liberation

from the colonial powers, including Tsarist Russia, were now inherently

progressive insofar as they served to undermine the power of capital.

That is to say, Lenin’s support for national liberation struggles was

essentially no less pragmatic than that of other Marxists, including

Luxemburg herself. For imperialist Russia, appropriately characterized

as a “prison of nations,” Lenin advocated the unconditional right of

non-Russian peoples to secede under any conditions and to form

nation-states of their own. On the other hand, he maintained,

non-Russian Social Democrats in Russia’s colonized countries would be

obliged to advocate some kind of federal union with the “mother country”

if Russian Social Democrats succeeded in achieving a proletarian

revolution.

Hence, although Lenin’s and Luxemburg’s premises were very similar, the

two Marxists came to radically different conclusions about the “national

question” and the correct manner of resolving it. Lenin demanded the

right of Poland to establish a nation‑state of its own, while Luxemburg

opposed it as economically unviable and regressive. Lenin shared Marx’s

and Engels’s support for Polish independence, albeit for very different

yet equally pragmatic reasons. He did not honor his own position on the

right to secession during the Russian Civil War, most flagrantly in his

manner of dealing with Georgia, a very distinct nation that had

supported the Mensheviks until the Soviet regime forced it to accept a

domestic variant of Bolshevism. Only in the last years of his life,

after a Georgian Communist Party took command of the state, did Lenin

oppose Stalin’s attempt to subordinate the Georgian party to the Russian

– a preponderantly intra-party conflict that was of little concern to

the pro‑Menshevik Georgian population. Lenin did not live long enough to

engage Stalin on this – and other – policies and organizational

practices.

Two Approaches to the National Question

The Marxist and Marxist-Leninist discussions on the “national question”

after World War One thus produced a highly convoluted legacy that

affected the policies not only of the Old Left of the 1920s and 1930s

but those of the New Left of the 1960s as well. What is important to

clarify here are the radically different premises from which left

libertarians and Marxists viewed nationalism generally. Libertarian

socialism and anarchism in the main, aside from some of its variants,

advanced humanistic, basically ethical reasons for opposing the

nation-states that fostered nationalism. Left libertarians did so, to be

more specific, because national distinctions tended to lead to state

formation and to subvert the unity of humanity, to parochialize society,

and to foster cultural particularities rather than the universality of

the human condition. Marxism, as a “socialist science,” eschewed such

ethical “abstractions.”

In contrast to the anarchist opposition to the state and to

centralization, not only did Marxists support a centralized state, they

insisted on the “historically progressive” nature of capitalism and a

market economy, which required centralized nation-states as domestic

markets and as means for removing all internal barriers to commerce that

local and regional sovereignties had created. Marxists generally

regarded the national aspirations of oppressed peoples as matters of

political strategy that should be supported or opposed for strictly

pragmatic considerations, irrespective of any broader ethical ones.

Thus two distinct approaches to nationalism emerged within the Left. The

ethical anti-nationalism of anarchists and libertarian socialists

championed the unity of humanity, with due allowance for cultural

distinctions but in flat opposition to the formation of nation-states;

while the Marxists supported or opposed the nationalistic demands of

largely precapitalist cultures for a variety of pragmatic and

geopolitical reasons. This distinction is not intended to be hard and

fast; socialists in pre-World War One Austria-Hungary were strongly

multinational as a result of the many different peoples who made up the

prewar empire. They called for a confederal relationship between the

German‑speaking rulers of the empire and its largely Slavonic members,

which approximated an anarchist view. Whether they would have honored

their own ideals in practice any better than Lenin adhered to his own

prescriptions once a “proletarian revolution” actually succeeded we will

never know. The original empire had disappeared by 1918, and the

ostensible libertarianism of “Austro-Hungarian Marxism,” as it was

called, became moot during the interwar period. To its honor, I may add,

in February 1934 in Vienna, Austrian socialists, unlike any other

movement apart from the Spaniards, resisted protofascist developments in

bloody street fighting; the movement never regained its revolutionary

élan after it was restored in 1945.

Nationalism and World War Two

The Left of the interwar period, the so-called Old Left, viewed the

fast-approaching war against Nazi Germany as a continuation of the

“Great War” of 1914–18. Anti- Stalinist Marxists predicted a short-lived

conflict that would terminate in proletarian revolutions even more

sweeping than those of the 1917–21 period. Significantly, Trotsky staked

his adherence to orthodox Marxism itself on this calculation: if the war

did not end in this outcome, he proposed, nearly all the premises of

orthodox Marxism would have to be examined and perhaps drastically

revised. His death in 1940 precluded such a reevaluation on his own

part. When the war did not conclude in international proletarian

revolutions, Trotsky’s supporters were hardly willing to make the

sweeping reexamination that he had suggested.

Yet this reexamination was very much needed. Not only did World War Two

fail to end in proletarian revolutions in Europe; it brought an end to

the whole era of revolutionary proletarian socialism and the

class-oriented internationalism that had emerged in June 1848, when the

Parisian working class raised barricades and red flags in support of a

“social republic.” Far from achieving any successful proletarian

revolutions after World War Two, the European working class failed to

exhibit a semblance of internationalism during the conflict. Unlike

their fathers a generation earlier, no warring troops engaged in

fraternization; nor did the civilian populations exhibit any overt

hostility to their political and military leaders for their conduct of

the war, despite the massive destruction of cities by aerial bombers and

artillery. The German army fought desperately against the Allies in the

West and its soldiers were prepared to defend Hitler’s bunker to the

end.

Above all, an elevated awareness of class distinctions and conflicts in

Europe gave way to nationalism – partly in reaction to Germany’s

occupations of home territories, but partly also, and significantly, as

a result of the resurgence of a crude xenophobia that verged on outright

racism. What limited class‑oriented movements did emerge for a while

after the war, notably in France, Italy, and Greece, were easily

manipulated by the Stalinists to serve Soviet interests in the Cold War.

Hence although World War Two lasted much longer than the first, its

outcome never rose to the political and social level of the 1917–21

period. In fact, world capitalism emerged from World War Two stronger

than it had been at any time in its history, owing principally to the

state’s massive intervention in economic and social affairs.

Struggles for “National Liberation”

The failure of serious radical theorists to reexamine Marxist theory in

the light of these developments, as Trotsky had proposed, was followed

by the precipitate decline of the Old Left, the general recognition that

the proletariat was no longer a “hegemonic” class in overthrowing

capitalism, the absence of a “general crisis” of capitalism, and the

failure of the Soviet Union to play an internationalist role in postwar

events.

What came to foreground instead were national liberation struggles in

“Third World” countries and sporadic anti- Soviet eruptions in Eastern

European countries, which were largely smothered by Stalinist

totalitarianism. The Left, in these instances, has often taken

nationalist struggles as general “anti-imperialist” attempts to achieve

“autonomy” from imperialism, and state formation as a legitimation of

this “autonomy,” even at the expense of a popular democracy in the

colonized world.

If Marx and Engels often supported national struggles for strategic

reasons, the Left in the twentieth century, both New and Old, often

elevated such support for such struggles into a mindless article of

faith. The strategic “nationalisms” of Marxist‑type movements largely

foreclosed inquiry into what kind of society a given “national

liberation” movement would likely produce, in a way that ethical

socialisms like anarchism in the nineteenth century did not. It was – or

if not, it should have been – a matter of the gravest concern for the

Old Left in the 1920s and 1930s to inquire into what type of society Mao

Tse-tung, to take a striking case in point, would establish in China if

he defeated the Kuomintang, while the New Left of the 1960s should have

inquired into what type of society Castro, to cite another important

case, would establish in Cuba after the expulsion of Batista.

But throughout the twentieth century, when “Third World” national

liberation movements in colonial countries made conventional avowals of

socialism and then proceeded to establish highly centralized, often

brutally authoritarian states, the Left often greeted them as effective

struggles against imperialist enemies. Advanced as “national

liberation,” nationalism has often stopped short of advancing major

social changes and has even ignored the need to do so. Avowals of

authoritarian forms of socialism have been used by “national liberation”

movements very much the way Stalin used socialist ideologies to brutally

consolidate his own dictatorship. Indeed, Marxism- Leninism has proved a

remarkably effective doctrine for mobilizing “national liberation”

struggles against imperialist powers and gaining the support of leftist

radicals abroad, who saw “national liberation” movements as largely

anti-imperialist struggles rather than observing their true social

content.

Thus, despite the populist and often even anarchistic tendencies that

gave rise to the European and American New Left, its essentially

international focus was directed increasingly toward an uncritical

support for “national liberation” struggles outside the Euro-American

sphere, without regard for where these struggles were leading and the

authoritarian nature of their leadership. As the 1960s progressed, this

incredibly confused movement in fact steadily shed the libertarian and

universalistic ambience with which it had begun. After Mao’s practices

were elevated to an “ism” in the New Left, many young radicals adopted

“Maoism” unreservedly, with grim results for the New Left as a whole. By

1969, the New Left had largely been taken over by Maoists and admirers

of Fidel Castro. An utterly misleading book like William Hinton’s

Fanshen, which uncritically applauded Maoist activities in the Chinese

countryside, was revered in the late 1960s, and many radical groups

adopted what they took to be Maoist organizational practices. So heavily

focused was the New Left’s attention on “national liberation” struggles

in the Third World that the Russian invasion of Czechoslovakia in 1969

hardly produced serious protest from young leftists, at least in the

United States, as I can personally attest.

The 1960s also saw the emergence of yet another form of nationalism on

the Left: increasingly ethnically chauvinistic groups began to appear

that ultimately inverted Euro‑American claims of the alleged superiority

of the white race into an equally reactionary claim to the superiority

of non-whites. Embracing the particularism into which racial politics

had degenerated instead of the potential universalism of a humanitas,

the New Left placed blacks, colonial peoples, and even totalitarian

colonial nations on the top of its theoretical pyramid, endowing them

with a commanding or “hegemonic” position in relation to whites,

Euro‑Americans, and bourgeois‑democratic nations. In the 1970s, this

particularistic strategy was adopted by certain feminists, who began to

extol the “superiority” of women over men, indeed to affirm an allegedly

female mystical “power” and an allegedly female irrationalism over the

secular rationality and scientific inquiry that were presumably the

domain of all males. The term “white male” became a patently derogatory

expression that was applied ecumenically to all Euro‑American men,

irrespective of whether they themselves were exploited and dominated by

ruling classes and hierarchies.

A highly parochial “identity politics” began to emerge, even to dominate

many New Leftists as new “micronationalisms,” if I may coin a word. Not

only do certain tendencies in such “identity” movements closely resemble

those of very traditional forms of oppression like patriarchy, but

“identity politics” also constitutes a regression from the libertarian

and even general Marxian message of the “Internationale” and a

transcendence of all “micronationalist” differentia in a truly

humanistic communist society. What passes for “radical consciousness”

today is shifting increasingly toward a biologically oriented emphasis

on human differentiation like gender and ethnicity – not an emphasis on

the need to foster human universality that was so pronounced among the

anarchist and libertarian socialist writers of the nineteenth century

and even in The Communist Manifesto.

Toward a New Internationalism

How to assess this devolution in leftist thought and the problems it

raises today? I have tried to place nationalism in the larger historical

context of humanity’s social evolution from the internal solidarity of

the tribe to the increasing expansiveness of urban life and the

universalism advanced by the great monotheistic religions in the Middle

Ages and finally to ideals of human affinity based on reason,

secularism, cooperation, and democracy in the nineteenth century. We can

say with certainty that any movement that aspires to something less than

these anarchist and libertarian socialist notions of the “brotherhood of

man,” certainly as expressed in the “Internationale,” is less than

human. Indeed, from the perspective of the beginning of the twenty-first

century, we are obliged to ask for even more than what

nineteenth-century internationalism demanded. We are obliged to

formulate an ethics of complementarity in which cultural differentia

mutualistically serve to enhance human unity itself, in short, that

constitute a new mosaic of vigorous cultures that enrich the human

condition and that foster its advance rather than fragment and decompose

it into new “nationalities” and an increasing number of nation‑states.

No less significant is the need for a radical social outlook that

conjoins cultural variety and the ideal of a unified humanity with an

ethical concept of what a new society should be like – one that is

universalistic in its view of humanity, cooperative in its view of human

relationships on all levels of life, and egalitarian in its idea of

social relations. While internationalist in their class outlook, nearly

all Marxist attitudes toward the “national question” were instrumental:

they were guided by expediency and opportunism, and worse, they often

denigrated ideas of democracy, citizenship, and freedom as “abstract”

and, presumably, “unscientific” notions. Outstanding Marxists accepted

the nation‑state with all its coercive power and centralistic traits, be

they Marx or Engels, Luxemburg or Lenin. Nor did these Marxists view

confederalism as a desideratum. Luxemburg’s writings, for example,

simply take confederalism as it existed in her own time (particularly

the vicissitudes of Swiss cantonalism) as exhausting all the

possibilities of this political idea, without due regard for the left

libertarian emphasis on the need for profound social, political, and

economic changes in the municipalities that are to confederate with each

other. With few exceptions, Marxists advanced no serious critique of the

nation‑state and state centralization as such, an omission that, all

“collectivistic” achievements aside, would have foredoomed their

attempts to achieve a rational society if nothing else had.

Cultural freedom and variety, let me emphasize, should not be confused

with nationalism. That specific peoples should be free to fully develop

their own cultural capacities is not merely a right but a desideratum.

The world will be a drab place indeed if a magnificent mosaic of

different cultures do not replace the largely deculturated and

homogenized world created by modern capitalism. But by the same token,

the world will be completely divided and peoples will be chronically at

odds with one another if their cultural differences are parochialized

and if seeming “cultural differences” are rooted in biologistic notions

of gender, racial, and physical superiority. Historically, there is a

sense in which the national consolidation of peoples along territorial

lines did produce a social sphere that was broader than the narrow

kinship basis for kinship societies because it such consolidation

obviously is more open to strangers, just as cities tend to foster

broader human affinities than tribes. But neither tribal affinities nor

territorial boundaries constitute a realization of humanity’s

potentiality to achieve a full sense of commonality with rich but

harmonious cultural variations. Frontiers have no place on the map of

the planet, any more than they have a place on the landscape of the

mind.

A socialism that is informed by this kind of ethical outlook, with a due

respect for cultural variety, cannot ignore the potential outcome of a

national liberation struggle as the Old and New Lefts alike so often

did. Nor can it support national liberation struggles for instrumental

purposes, merely as a means of “weakening” imperialism. Certainly, such

a socialism cannot, in my view, promote the proliferation of

nation-states, much less increase the number of divisive national

entities. Ironically, the success of many “national liberation”

struggles has had the effect of creating politically independent statist

regimes that are nonetheless as manipulable by the forces of

international capitalism as were the old, generally obtuse imperialist

ones. More often than not, “Third World” nations have not cast off their

colonial shackles since the end of World War Two: they have merely

become domesticated and rendered highly vulnerable to the forces of

international capitalism, with little more than a facade of

self-determination. Moreover, they have often used their myths of

“national sovereignty” to nourish xenophobic ambitions to grab adjacent

territories and oppress their neighbors as brutally as imperialists in

their own right, such as Ghana’s oppression under Nkrumah of the Togo

peoples in West Africa or Milošević’s attempt to “cleanse” Muslims from

Bosnia. What is no less regressive, such nationalisms evoke what is most

sinister in a people’s past – religious fundamentalism in all its forms,

traditional hatreds of “foreigners,” a “national unity” that overrides

terrible internal social and economic inequities, and most commonly, a

total disregard for human rights. The “nation” as a cultural entity is

superseded by an overpowering and oppressive state apparatus. Racism

commonly goes hand in hand with “national liberation” struggles, such as

“ethnic cleansing” and wars for territorial gain, as we see most

poignantly today in the Middle East, India, the Caucasus, and Eastern

Europe. Nationalisms that only a generation ago might have been regarded

as “national liberation” struggles are more clearly seen today, in the

wake of the collapse of the Soviet empire, as little more than social

nightmares and decivilizing blights.

Put bluntly, nationalisms are the kind of regressive atavisms that the

Enlightenment tried to overcome long ago. They introject the worst

features of the very empires from which oppressed peoples have tried to

shake loose. Not only do they typically reproduce state‑machines that

are as oppressive as those the colonial powers imposed on them, but they

reinforce those machines with cultural, religious, ethnic, and

xenophobic traits that are often used to foster regional and even

domestic hatreds and sub-imperialisms. No less important, in the absence

of genuine popular democracies the sequelae of understandably

anti‑imperialist struggles too often include the strengthening of

imperialism itself, such that the powers that have been seemingly

dispossessed of their colonies can now play off the state of one former

colony against that of another, as witness the conflicts that ravage

Africa, the Middle East, and the Indian subcontinent. These are the

areas, I may add, where nuclear wars will be more likely to occur as the

years go by than elsewhere in the world. The development of an Islamic

nuclear bomb to countervail an Israeli one, or of a Pakistani bomb to

countervail an Indian one, portend no good for the South and its

conflict with the North. Indeed, the tendency for former colonies to

actively seek alliances with their erstwhile imperialist rulers is now a

more typical feature of North–South diplomacy than is any unity within

the South against the North.

Nationalism has always been a disease that divided human from human –

“abstract” as traditional Marxists may consider this notion to be – and

it can never be viewed as anything more than a regression toward tribal

parochialism and the fuel for intercommunal warfare. Nor have the

“national liberation” struggles that have produced new states throughout

the “Third World” and in Eastern Europe impaired the expansion of

imperialism or eventuated in fully democratic states. That the

“liberated” peoples of the Stalinist empire are less oppressed today

than they were under communist rule should not mislead us into believing

that they are also free from the xenophobia that nearly all

nation‑states cultivate or from the cultural homogenization that

capitalism and its media produce.

No left libertarian, to be sure, can oppose the right of a subjugated

people to establish itself as an autonomous entity – be it in a

confederation based on libertarian municipalism or as a nation‑state

based on hierarchical and class inequities. But to oppose an oppressor

is not equivalent to calling for support for everything formerly

colonized nation-states do. Ethically speaking, one cannot oppose a

wrong when one party commits it, then support another party who commits

the same wrong. The trite but pithy maxim – “My enemy’s enemy is not my

friend” – is particularly applicable to oppressed people who may be

manipulated by totalitarians, religious zealots, and “ethnic cleansers.”

Just as an authentic ethics must be reasoned out and premised on genuine

humanistic potentialities, so a libertarian socialism or anarchism must

retain its ethical integrity if the voice of reason is to be heard in

social affairs. In the 1960s, those who opposed American imperialism in

Southeast Asia and at the same time rejected giving any support to the

communist regime in Hanoi, and those who opposed American intervention

in Cuba without supporting Castroist totalitarianism, stood on a higher

moral ground than the New Leftists who exercised their rebelliousness

against the United States predominantly by supporting “national

liberation” struggles without regard to the authoritarian and statist

goals of those struggles. Indeed, identified with the authoritarians

whom they actively supported, these New Leftists eventually grew

demoralized by the absence of an ethical basis in their liberatory

ideas. Today, in fact, liberatory struggles based on nationalism and

statism have borne the terrifying harvest of internecine bloodletting

throughout the world. Even in recently “liberated” states like East

Germany, nationalism has found brutal expression in the rise of fascist

movements, German nationalism, plans to restrict the immigration of

asylum-seekers, violence against “foreigners” including victims of

Nazism like gypsies, and the like. Thus the instrumental view of

nationalism that Marxists originally cultivated has left many “leftist”

tendencies like Social Democracy in a condition of moral bankruptcy.

Ethically, let me add, there are some social issues on which one must

take a stand – such as white and black racism, patriarchy and

matriarchy, and imperialism and “Third World” totalitarianism. An

unswerving opposition to racism, gender oppression, and domination as

such must always be paramount if an ethical socialism is to emerge from

the ruins of socialism itself. But we also live in a world in which

issues sometimes arise on which leftists cannot take any position at all

– issues in which to take a position is to operate within the

alternatives advanced by a basically irrational society and to choose

the lesser of several irrationalities or evils over other

irrationalities or evils. It is not a sign of political ineffectuality

to reject such a choice altogether and declare that to oppose one evil

with a lesser one must eventually lead to the support of the worst evil

that emerges. German Social Democracy, by abetting one “lesser evil”

after another during the 1920s, went from supporting liberals to

conservatives to reactionaries – who finally brought Hitler to power. In

an irrational society, conventional wisdom and instrumentalism can

produce only ever‑greater irrationality, using virtue as a patina to

conceal basic contradictions both in its own position and in society.

“[L]ike the processes of life, digestion and breathing,” observed

Bakunin, nationality “has no right to be concerned with itself until

that right is denied.” This was a perceptive enough statement in its

day. With the explosions of barbarous nationalism in our own day and the

snarling appetites of nationalists to create more and more

nation‑states, I am obliged to add that “nationality” is a form of

indigestion and that its causes must be vomited up if society is not to

further deteriorate because of this malady.

Seeking an Alternative

If nationalism is regressive, what rational and humanistic alternative

to it can an ethical socialism offer? There is no place in a free

society for nation-states – either as nations or as states. However

strong may be the impulse of specific peoples for a collective identity,

reason and a concern for ethical behavior oblige us to recover the

universality of the city or town and a directly democratic political

culture, albeit on a higher plane than even the polis of Periclean

Athens. Identity should properly be replaced by community – by a shared

affinity that is humanly scaled, non-hierarchical, libertarian, and open

to all, irrespective of an individual’s gender, ethnic traits, sexual

identity, talents, or personal proclivities. Such community life can

only be recovered by the new politics that I have called libertarian

municipalism: the democratization of municipalities so that they are

self-managed by the people who inhabit them, and the formation of a

confederation of these municipalities to constitute a counter-power to

the nation-state.

The danger that democratized municipalities in a decentralized society

would result in economic and cultural parochialism is very real, and it

can only be precluded by a vigorous confederation of municipalities

based on their material interdependence. The “self-sufficiency” of

community life – even if it were possible today – would by no means

guarantee a genuine grassroots democracy. The confederation of

municipalities, as a medium for interaction, collaboration, and mutual

aid among its municipal components, provides the sole alternative to the

powerful nation-state on the one hand and the parochial town or city on

the other. Fully democratic, in which the municipal deputies to

confederal institutions would be subject to recall, rotation, and

unrelenting public purview, the confederation would constitute an

extension of local liberties to the regional level, allowing for a

sensitive equilibrium between locality and region in which the cultural

variety of towns could flourish without turning inward toward local

exclusivity. Indeed, beneficial cultural traits would also be

“trafficked,” so to speak, within and between various confederations,

along with the interchange of goods and services that make up the

material means of life.

By the same token, “property” would be municipalized, rather than

nationalized (which merely reinforces state power with economic power),

collectivized (which simply recasts private entrepreneurial rights in a

“collective” form), or privatized (which facilitates the reemergence of

a competitive market economy). A municipalized economy would approximate

a system of usufruct based entirely on one’s needs and citizenship in a

community rather than one’s proprietary, vocational, or professional

interests. Where a municipal citizens’ assembly controls economic

policy, no one individual controls, much less “owns,” the means of

production and of life. Where confederal means of administering a

region’s resources coordinate the economic behavior of the whole,

parochial interests would tend to give way to larger human interests and

economic considerations to more democratic ones. The issues that

municipalities and their confederations address would cease to range

around economic self-interest; they would focus on democratic procedures

and simple equity in meeting human needs.

Let there be no doubt that the technological resources that make it

possible for people to choose their own lifestyles and have the free

time to participate fully in a democratic politics are absolutely

necessary for the libertarian, confederally organized society that I

have sketched here. Even the best of ethical intentions are likely to

yield to some form of oligarchy, in which differential access to the

means of life will lead to elites who have more of the good things in

life than do other citizens. On this score, the asceticism that

ecomystics and deep ecologists promote is insidiously reactionary: not

only does it ignore the freedom of people to choose their own lifestyle

– the only alternative in the existing society to becoming a mindless

consumer – but it subordinates human freedom as such to an almost

mystical notion of the dictates of “Nature” – prescribing a “return to

the Pleistocene,” to the Neolithic, or to food gathering, to cite the

most extreme examples. A free ecological society – as distinguished from

one regulated by an authoritarian ecological elite or by the “free

market” – can only be cast in terms of an ecologically confederal form

of libertarian municipalism. When at length free communes replace the

nation and confederal forms of organization replace the state, humanity

will have rid itself of nationalism.

Nationalism and the Great Revolution

During and after the great revolutions in the eighteenth century –

particularly the American and the French – expressions redolent with

nationalism did not have the meaning they often have today. The word

“patriot” was not used to express a special loyalty to a “Fatherland”

two centuries ago; the word normally was used in both the American and

French revolutions to delegitimate the claim of the monarchy to

literally own the countries and colonies it ruled as the personal

patrimony of the King and establish the ordinary citizen’s status as a

“shareholder” in what had previously been regarded as a royal estate.

Accordingly, the American revolutionaries who declared their

independence from the British monarchy in 1776 fundamentally altered

their ties to the “mother country” by replacing royal rule with a

republican system structured politically around citizenship rather than

subjecthood. The French, a decade and a half later, deliberately changed

the title of Louis XVI from “King of France” to “King of the French,” a

shift that was not a mere semantic one. Just as King George III could no

longer claim to possess the American colonies, a claim the colonists

never really regarded as existentially valid, so Louis XVI no longer

“owned” France once the National Assembly was formed.

The word “patriot,” so widely used in both revolutions, and la “Nation”

in the French revolution legally restored a national patrimony to the

people. Indeed, terms like “Nation” essentially referred to the citizen

body as a whole in contrast to the “Court,” which referred to the

proprietary authority of the royal family. Indeed, the distinction

between “Court” and “Country” had already been made in the English

revolution of the 1640s, and was to find expression later in

distinctions between “royalist” and “patriot” during the late 1700s.

Characteristically, the historic documents that proclaimed a fundamental

alteration of of the ties between a “Nation” and its former rulers were

addressed to humanity as a whole, not merely to a given people. Thomas

Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence opens with the challenging

remarks that ”a decent respect for the opinions of mankind require that

[the Americans] should declare what impels them” to sever their bonds

with the British monarchy. Like the French revolutionary documents that

were to follow, it based this claim on the belief ”that all men are

created equal” and that ”Government is instituted among Men, deriving

their just powers from the consent of the governed [emphasis added].”

The American Declaration of July 4, 1776, was to become the theoretical

template for similar declarations by the French revolutionaries. Far

from being nationalistic statements, they were fervently cosmopolitan

and addressed to the world at large. Thomas Paine’s famous personal

maxim, “My country is the world,” was not idiosyncratic to the American

revolutionary leaders. George Washington did not hesitate to declare

that he was “a citizen of the great republic of humanity,” and Benjamin

Rush allowed that the revolution opened “no breach in the republic of

letters.” In a statement that fervently expressed the spirit of the

Enlightenment, John Adams was to state that, the war in the colonies

notwithstanding, “Science and literature are of no party nor nation.”

The phrase “Liberty, Equality, Fraternity” is reported to have been

given to the French by Benjamin Franklin, whose freedom from nationalism

and parochialism earned widespread admiration. “Where liberty is at

stake,” he declared in 1783, “there is my country.”

The thinkers and propagators in the French Enlightenment were no

different in spirit and conveyed it fully to the revolutions of 1789.

Montesquieu, whose Persian Letters (1721) has been called the “first

major work of the French Enlightenment,” by Norman Hampson, was to jot

in his notebooks: “When I act, I am a citizen; but when I write, I am a

man and regard all the peoples of Europe with as much impartiality as

those of Madagaskar.” This universalism was characteristic of

essentially all the Encyclopedists with the possible exception of

Rousseau, whose mystification of his Swiss origins involved a democratic

but often sentimental passion for a fictitious ruralism of which he was

never part of in his real life. That French became the language of

educated Europe was not accidental: the worldly outlook of the

Enlightenment intellectuals, in fact, created a secular republic of

letters that was to be eroded over time by romanticism, mysticism, and

ultimately an identification of nationhood with race or ethnic

superiority.

Nationalism existed outside the orbit of the Enlightenment and the great

revolutions of the eighteenth century, which were explicitly

universalistic in their social and cultural spirit. Never ceasing to be

captivated by cultural variety and its more humanistic features, the

revolutionaries of the time, like the Enlighteners who prepared the

intellectual bases of their social activities, saw themselves above all

as “citizens” of a secular human community that knew no intellectual,

political, or territorial frontiers.

The Historical Importance of the City

I have long argued that libertarian municipalism constitutes the

politics of social ecology, notably a revolutionary effort in which

freedom is given institutional form in public assemblies that become

decision-making bodies. It depends upon libertarian leftists running

candidates at the local municipal level, calling for the division of

municipalities into wards, where popular assemblies can be created that

bring people into full and direct participation in political life.

Having democratized themselves, municipalities would confederate into a

dual power to oppose the nation-state and ultimately dispense with it

and with the economic forces that underpin statism as such.

Libertarian municipalism is above all a politics that seeks to create a

vital democratic public sphere. In my From Urbanization to Cities as

well as other works, I have made careful but crucial distinctions

between three societal realms: the social, the political, and the state.

What people do in their homes, what friendships they form, the communal

lifestyles they practice, the way they make their living, their sexual

behavior, and the cultural artifacts they consume – all these personal

as well as materially necessary activities belong to what I call the

social sphere of life. Families, friends, and communal living

arrangements are part of the social realm.

However much all aspects of life interact with one another, none of

these social aspects of human life properly belongs to the public

sphere, which I explicitly identify with politics in the Hellenic sense

of the term. In creating a new politics based on social ecology, we are

concerned with what people do in this public or political sphere, not

with what people do in their bedrooms, living rooms, or basements.

Let me state from the outset that I have never declared that libertarian

municipalism is a substitute for the manifold dimensions of cultural or

even private life. Yet even a modicum of a historical perspective shows

that it is precisely the municipality that most individuals must deal

with directly, once they leave the social realm and enter the public

sphere. Doubtless the municipality is usually the place where even a

great deal of social life is existentially lived, which does not efface

its distinctiveness as a unique sphere of life.

As a project for entering into the public sphere, libertarian

municipalism calls for a radical presence in a community that addresses

the question of who shall exercise power in a lived sense; indeed, it is

truly a political culture that seeks to re-empower the individual and

sharpen his or her sensibility as a living citizen.

The Erosion of Citizenship

Today, the concept of citizenship has already undergone serious erosion

through the reduction of citizens to “constituents” of statist

jurisdictions or to “taxpayers” who sustain statist institutions. To

further reduce citizenship to “personhood” – or to etherealize the

concept by speaking of an airy “earth citizenship” – is nothing short of

reactionary. It took long millennia for History to create the concept of

the citizen as a self-managing and competent agent in democratically

shaping a polity. During the French Revolution the term citoyen was used

precisely to efface the status-generated relegation of individuals to

mere “subjects” of the Bourbon kings. Moreover, revolutionaries of the

last century – from Marx to Bakunin – referred to themselves as

“citizens” long before the appellation “comrade” replaced it.

We must not lose sight of the fact that the citizen, as he or she should

be, culminates the transformation of ethnic tribal folk, whose societies

were structured around biological facts like kinship, gender

differences, and age groups, and should be part of a secular, rational,

and humane community. Indeed, much of the National Socialist war against

“Jewish cosmopolitanism” was in fact an ethnically (völkisch)

nationalistic war against the Enlightenment ideal of the citoyen. For it

was precisely the depoliticized, indeed, animalized “loyal subject”

rather than the citizen that the Nazis incorporated into their racial

image of the German Volk, the abject, status-defined creature of

Hitler’s hierarchical Führerprinzip. Once citizenship becomes

contentless as a result of the deflation of its existential political

reality or, equally treacherously, by the expansion of its historic

development into a “planetary” metaphor, we have come a long way toward

accepting the barbarism that the capitalist system is now fostering with

Heideggerian versions of ecology.

Today, we cannot allow flippant diminutions of the uniqueness of

citizenship, so pregnant with political meaning, nor can we ignore the

factors that can help us develop a general civic interest today. The

tendency of physiography among ecomystics and spiritualists to overtake

and devour vast socio-cultural differences is nothing less than

dazzling. Put the prefix bio before a word, and you come up with the

most inane, often asocial body of “ideas” possible, such as

bioregionalism, which overrides the very fundamental cultural

differences that demarcate one community or group of communities from

another by virtue of a common watershed, lake, or mountain range.

Bioregionalism, as expressed by John Clark and others, is not only a

mystification of first (biological) nature at the expense of second

(social and cultural) nature; its irrelevance to improving the human

condition is truly incredible. One has only to view the terrible

conflict in the former Yugoslavia, which raged in areas that are almost

identical bioregionally but are grossly dissimilar culturally, to

recognize how meaningless and mystifying are Clark’s expectations of his

bioregional “politics.”

The extent to which contemporary mystical ecologists absorb second

nature into first nature, the social into the biological, ignores the

extent to which the sociosphere today encompasses the biosphere, to

which first nature has been absorbed into second nature, and reveals a

stunning neglect of the decisive importance of society in determining

the future of the natural world. We can no longer afford a naive nature

romanticism, which may be very alluring to juveniles but has been

contributing a great deal to the strident nationalism and growing

ecofascism that is emerging in the Western world.

Oppression and Liberation

libertarian municipalism is that the “Greek polis,” which “advocates of

direct democracy have always appealed to,” was marred by “the exclusion

of women, slaves, and foreigners.” This is certainly true, and we must

always remember that libertarian municipalists are also libertarian

communists, who obviously oppose hierarchy, including patriarchy and

chattel slavery.

As it turns out, in fact, the “Greek polis” is neither an ideal nor a

model for anything – except perhaps for Rousseau, who greatly admired

Sparta. It is the Athenian polis whose democratic institutions I often

describe and that has the greatest significance for the democratic

tradition. In the context of libertarian municipalism, its significance

is to provide us with evidence that a people, for a time, could quite

self-consciously establish and maintain a direct democracy, despite the

existence of slavery, patriarchy, economic and class inequalities,

agonistic behavior, and even imperialism, which existed throughout the

ancient Mediterranean world.

The fact is that we must look for what is new and innovative in a

historical period, even as we acknowledge continuities with social

structures that prevailed in the past. Ancient Athens and other parts of

Greece, it is worth noting in this postmodern era, was the arena for the

emergence not only of direct democracy but of Western philosophy, drama,

political theory, mathematics, science, and analytical and dialectical

logic. On the other hand, I could hardly derive democratic ideas from

the Chinese Taoist tradition, rooted as it is in quietism and a credo of

resignation and submission to noble and royal power (not to speak of the

exclusion of women from socially important roles).[21]

In fact, short of the hazy Neolithic village traditions that Marija

Gimbutas, Riane Eisler, and William Irwin Thompson hypostatize, we will

have a hard time finding any tradition that was not patriarchal to one

degree or another. Rejecting all patriarchal societies as sources of

institutional study would mean that we must abandon not only the

Athenian polis but the free medieval communes and their confederations,

the comuñero movement of sixteenth-century Spain, the revolutionary

Parisian sections of 1793, the Paris Commune of 1871 – and even the

Spanish anarchist collectives of 1936–37. All of these institutional

developments, be it noted, were marred to one degree or another by

patriarchal values.

No, libertarian municipalists are not ignorant of these very real

historical limitations; nor is libertarian municipalism based on any

historical “models.” Neither does anyone who seriously accepts a

libertarian municipalist approach believe that society as it exists and

cities as they are structured today can suddenly be transformed into a

directly democratic and rational society. The revolutionary

transformation we seek is one that requires education, the formation of

a movement, and the patience to cope with defeats. As I have emphasized

again and again, a libertarian municipalist practice begins, minimally,

with an attempt to enlarge local freedom at the expense of state power.

And it does this by example, by education, and by entering the public

sphere (that is, into local elections or extralegal assemblies), where

ideas can be raised among ordinary people that open the possibility of a

lived practice. In short, libertarian municipalism involves a vibrant

politics in the real world to change society and public consciousness

alike, not a program directed at navel-gazing, psychotherapy, and

“surregionalist manifestoes.” It tries to forge a movement that will

enter into open confrontation with the state and the bourgeoisie, not

cravenly sneak around them murmuring Taoist paradoxes.

I should perhaps point out that my appeal to a new politics of

citizenship is not in any way meant to put a rug over very real social

conflicts, nor is it an appeal to class neutrality. The fact is that

“the People” I invoke does not include Chase Manhattan Bank, General

Motors, or any class exploiters and economic bandits; let me emphasize

that I am addressing an oppressed humanity, all of whom must – if they

are to eliminate their oppressions – try to remove the shared roots of

oppression as such.

I have never argued that we can or should ignore class interests by

completely absorbing them into trans-class ones. But in our time

particularization is being overemphasized, to the point where any shared

struggle must now overcome not only differences in class, gender,

ethnicity, “and other issues,” but nationalism, religious zealotry, and

identity based on even minor distinctions in status. The role of the

revolutionary movement for over two centuries has been to emphasize our

shared humanity precisely against ruling status groups and ruling

classes – which Marx, even in singling out the proletariat as hegemonic,

viewed as a “universal class.” Nor are all “images” that people have of

themselves as classes, genders, races, nationalities, and cultural

groups rational or humane, or evidence of consciousness, or desirable

from a radical viewpoint. In principle, there is no reason why

différance as such should not entangle us and paralyze us completely in

our multifarious and self-enclosed “particularity,” in postmodernist,

indeed Derridean fashion. Indeed, today, when parochial differences

among the oppressed have been reduced to microscopic divisions, it is

all the more important for a revolutionary movement to resolutely point

out the common sources of oppression as such and the extent to which

commodification has universalized them – particularly global capitalism.

The deformations of the past were created largely by the famous “social

question,” notably by class exploitation, which in great measure could

have been remedied by technological advances. In short, they were

scarcity societies – albeit not that alone. Of course a new

social-ecological sensibility has to be created, as do new values and

relationships, and it will be done partly by overcoming economic need,

however economic need is construed. Little doubt should exist that a

call for an end to economic exploitation must be a central feature in

any social ecology program and movement, which are part of the

Enlightenment tradition and its revolutionary outcome.

The essence of dialectic is to always search out what is new in any

development: specifically, for the purposes of this discussion, the

emergence of a trans-class People, such as oppressed women, people of

color, even the middle classes, as well as subcultures defined by sexual

preferences and lifestyles. To particularize distinctions (largely

created by the existing social order) to the point of reducing oppressed

people to seemingly “diverse persons” – indeed, to mere “personhood” –

is to feed into the current privatistic fads of our time and to remove

all possibility for collective social action and revolutionary change.

Reason and History

To examine what is really at issue in the questions of municipalism,

confederalism, and citizenship, as well as the distinction between the

social and the political, we must ground these notions in a historical

background where we can locate the meaning of the city (properly

conceived in distinction to the megalopolis), the citizen, and the

political sphere in the human condition.

Historical experience began to advance beyond a conception of mere

cyclical time, trapped in the stasis of eternal recurrence, into a

creative history insofar as intelligence and wisdom – more properly,

reason – began to inform human affairs. Over the course of a hundred

thousand years or so, as we now know, Homo sapiens sapiens slowly

overcame the sluggishness of their more animalistic cousins, the

Neanderthals, and, amidst ups and downs, entered as an increasingly

active agent into the surrounding world – both to meet their more

complex needs (material as well as ideological), and to alter that

environment by means of tools and, yes, instrumental rationality. Life

became longer, more acculturated aesthetically, and more secure, and,

potentially at least, human communities tried to define and resolve the

problems of freedom and consciousness at various levels of their

development.

The necessary conditions for freedom and consciousness – or

preconditions, as socialists of all kinds recognized in the last century

and a half – involved technological advances that, in a rational

society, could emancipate people from the immediate, animalistic

concerns of self-maintenance, increase the realm of freedom from

constrictions imposed upon it by preoccupations with material necessity,

and place knowledge on a rational, systematic, and coherent basis to the

extent that this was possible. These conditions at least involved

humanity’s self-emancipation from the overpowering theistic creations of

its own imagination (creations largely formulated by shamans and priests

for their own self-serving ends, as well as by apologists for hierarchy)

– notably, mythopoesis, mysticism, anti-rationalism, and fears of demons

and deities, calculated to produce subservience and quietism in the face

of the social powers that be.

That the necessary and sufficient conditions for this emancipation have

never existed in a “one-to-one” relationship with each other – and it

would have been miraculous if they had – has provided the fuel for

Cornelius Castoriadis’s rather disordered essays on the omnipotence of

“social imaginaries,” for Theodor Adorno’s basic nihilism, and for

frivolous anarcho-chaotics who, in one way or another, have debased the

Enlightenment’s ideals and the classical forms of socialism and

anarchism. True – the discovery of the spear did not produce an

automatic shift from “matriarchy” to “patriarchy,” nor did the discovery

of the plow produce an automatic shift from “primitive communism” to

private property, as evolutionary anthropologists of the nineteenth

century supposed. Indeed, it cheapens any discussion of history and

social change to create “one-to-one” relations between technological and

cultural developments, a tragic feature of Friedrich Engels’s

simplification of his mentor’s ideas.

In fact, social evolution is very uneven and combined, which one would

hope Castoriadis learned from his Trotskyist past. No less

significantly, social evolution, like natural evolution, is profligate

in producing a vast diversity of social forms and cultures, which are

often incommensurable in their details. If our goal is to emphasize the

vast differences that separate one society from another – rather than

identify the important thread of similarities that bring humanity to the

point of a highly creative development – “the Aztecs, Incas, Chinese,

Japanese, Mongols, Hindus, Persians, Arabs, Byzantines, and Western

Europeans, plus everything that could be enumerated from other cultures”

do not resemble each other, to cite the naive obligations that

Castoriadis places on what he calls “a ‘rational dialectic’ of history”

and, implicitly, on reason itself.[22] Indeed, it is unpardonable

nonsense to carelessly fling these civilizations together without regard

for their place in time, their social pedigrees, the extent to which

they can be educed dialectically from one another, or without an

explanation of why as well as descriptions of how they differ from each

other. By focusing entirely on the peculiarity of individual cultures,

one reduces the development of civilizations in an eductive sequence to

the narrow nominalism that Stephen Jay Gould applied to organic

evolution – even to the point where the “autonomy” so prized by

Castoriadis can be dismissed as a purely subjective “norm,” of no

greater value in this postmodernist world of interchangeable

equivalences than authoritarian “norms” of hierarchy.

But if we explore very existential developments toward freedom from toil

and freedom from oppression in all its forms, we find that there is a

History to be told of rational advances – without presupposing

teleologies that predetermine that History and its tendencies. If we can

give material factors their due emphasis without reducing cultural

changes to strictly automatic responses to technological changes and

without locating all highly variegated societies in a nearly mystical

sequence of “stages of development,” then we can speak intelligibly of

definite advances made by humanity out of animality, out of the timeless

“eternal recurrence” of relatively stagnant cultures, out of blood,

gender, and age relationships as the basis for social organization, and

out of the image of the “stranger,” who was not kin to other members of

a community, indeed, who was “inorganic,” to use Marx’s term, and hence

subject to arbitrary treatment beyond the reach of customary rights and

duties, defined as they were by tradition rather than reason.

Cities in History

Important as the development of agriculture, technology, and village

life were in moving toward this moment in human emancipation, the

emergence of the city was of the greatest importance in freeing people

from mere ethnic ties of solidarity, in bringing reason and secularity,

however rudimentarily, into human affairs. For it was only by this

evolution that segments of humanity could replace the tyranny of

mindless custom with a definable and rationally conditioned nomos, in

which the idea of justice could begin to replace tribalistic “blood

vengeance” – until later, when it was replaced by the idea of freedom. I

speak of the emergence of the city, because although the development of

the city has yet to be completed, its moments in History constitute a

discernable dialectic that opened an emancipatory realm within which

“strangers” and the “folk” could be reconstituted as citizens, notably,

secular and fully rational beings who approximate, in varying degrees,

humanity’s potentiality to become free, rational, fully individuated,

and rounded.

Moreover, the city has been the originating and authentic sphere of

politics in the Hellenic democratic sense of the term, and of

civilization – not, as I have emphasized again and again, of the state.

Which is not to say that city-states have not existed. But democracy,

conceived as a face-to-face realm of policy-making, entails a commitment

to the Enlightenment belief that all “ordinary” human beings are

potentially competent to collectively manage their political affairs – a

crucial concept in the thinking, all its limitations aside, of the

Athenian democratic tradition, and, more radically, of those Parisian

sections of 1793 that gave an equal voice to women as well as all men.

At such high points of political development, in which subsequent

advances often self-consciously built on and expanded more limited

earlier ones, the city became more than a unique arena for human life

and politics, and municipalism – civicism, which the French

revolutionaries later identified with “patriotism” – became more than an

expression of love of country. Even when Jacobin demagogues gave it

chauvinistic connotations, “patriotism” in 1793 meant that the “national

patrimony” was not the “property of the King of France” but that France,

in effect, now belonged to all the people.

Over the long run, the city was conceived as the socio-cultural destiny

of humanity, a place where, by late Roman times, there were no

“strangers” or ethnic “folk,” and by the French Revolution, no custom or

demonic irrationalities, but rather citoyens who lived in a free

terrain, organized themselves into discursive assemblies, and advanced

canons of secularity and fraternité, or more broadly, solidarity and

philia, hopefully guided by reason. Moreover, the French revolutionary

tradition was strongly confederalist until the dictatorial Jacobin

Republic came into being – wiping out the Parisian sections as well as

the ideal of a fête de la fédération. One must read Jules Michelet’s

account of the Great Revolution to learn the extent to which civicism

was identified with municipal liberty and fraternité with local

confederations, indeed a “republic” of confederations, between 1790 and

1793. One must explore the endeavors of Jean Varlet and the Evêché

militants of May 30–31, 1793, to understand how close the Revolution

came in the insurrection of June 2 to constructing the cherished

confederal “Commune of communes” that lingered in the historical memory

of the Parisian fédérés, as they designated themselves, in 1871.

Hence, let me stress that a libertarian municipalist politics is not a

mere “strategy” for human emancipation; it is a rigorous and ethical

concordance, of means and ends (of instrumentalities, so to speak) with

historic goals – which implies a concept of History as more than mere

chronicles or a scattered archipelago of self-enclosed “social

imaginaries.” The civitas, humanly scaled and democratically structured,

is the potential home of a universal humanitas that far transcends the

parochial blood tie of the tribe, the geo-zoological notion of the

“earthling,” and the anthropomorphic and juvenile “circle of all Beings”

(from ants to pussycats) promoted by Father Berry and his acolytes. It

is the immediate sphere of public life – not the most “intimate,” to use

Clark’s crassly subjectivized word – which, to be sure, does not

preclude but indeed should foster intimacy in the form of solidarity and

complementarity.

The civitas, humanly scaled and democratically structured, is the

initiating arena of rational reflection, discursive decision-making, and

secularity in human affairs. It speaks to us from across the centuries

in Pericles’ magnificent funeral oration and in the earthy, amazingly

familiar, and eminently secular satires of Aristophanes, whose works

demolish Castoriadis’ emphasis on the “mysterium” and “closure” of the

Athenian polis to the modern mind. No one who reads the chronicles of

Western humanity can ignore the rational dialectic that underlies the

accumulation of mere events and that reveals an unfolding of the human

potentiality for universality, rationality, secularity, and freedom in

an eductive relationship that alone should be called History. This

History, to the extent that it has culminations at given moments of

development, on which later civilizations built, is anchored in the

evolution of a secular public sphere, in politics, in the emergence of

the rational city – the city that is rational institutionally,

creatively, and communally. Nor can imagination be excluded from

History, but it is an imagination that must be elucidated by reason. For

nothing can be more dangerous to a society, indeed to the world today,

than the kind of unbridled imagination, unguided by reason, that so

easily lent itself to Nuremberg rallies, fascist demonstrations,

Stalinist idolatry, and death camps.

Social ecology refuses to allow this vast movement toward citification

and the emergence of the citizen to be effaced by decontextualizing the

city of its historical development. Nor can we allow the political

domain – the most immediate public sphere that renders a face-to-face

democracy possible – to be collapsed into the social sphere; we cannot

afford to dismiss the qualitatively unique sphere called the civitas,

and its history or dialectic.

Quietism or Confrontation?

The cultural and social barbarism that is closing around this period is

above all marked by ideologies of regression: a retreat into an often

mythic prelapsarian past; a narcissistic egocentricity in which the

political disappears into the personal; and an “imaginary” that

dissolves the various phases of a historical development into a black

hole of “Oneness” or “interconnectedness,” so that all the moments of a

development are flattened out. Underpinning this ideological flattening

is a Heideggerian Gelassenheit, a passive-receptive, indeed quietistic,

“letting things be,” that is dressed up in countervailing Taoist

“contraries” – each of which cancels out its opposite to leave practical

reason with a blank sheet upon which anything can be scrawled, however

hierarchical or oppressive. The Taoist ruler, who John Clark adduces in

his writings, who does not rule, who does nothing yet accomplishes more

than anyone else, is a contradiction in terms, a mutual cancellation of

the very concepts of “ruler” and “sage” – or, more likely, a tyrant who

shrewdly manipulates his or her subject while pretending to be

self-effacing and removed from the object of his or her tyranny.

The Chinese ruling classes played at this game for ages – just as the

pope, to this day, kisses the feet of his newly ordained cardinals with

Christian “humility.” What Marx’s fetishism of commodities is for

capitalism, this Heideggerian Gelassenheit is for present-day ideology,

particularly for deep ecology in all its various mutations. Thus, we do

not change the world; we “dwell” in it. We do not reason out a course of

action; we “intuit” it, or better, “imagine” it. We do not pursue a

rational eduction of the moments that make up an evolution; instead, we

relapse into a magical reverie, often in the name of an aesthetic

vanguardism that surrenders reality to fancy or imagination. Hence the

explosion these days of mystical ecologies, primitivism, technophobia,

anti-civilizationalism, irrationalism, and cheap fads from devil worship

to angelology.

In fact, we are facing a real crisis in this truly counter-revolutionary

time – not only in society’s relationship with the natural world but in

human consciousness itself. When John Clark started designating himself

as a “social deep ecologist or a deep social ecologist,”[23] he

obfuscated earnest attempts to demarcate the differences between a

deadening mystical, often religious, politically inert, and potentially

reactionary tendency in the ecology movement, and one that is trying to

emphasize the need for fundamental social change and fight

uncompromisingly the “present state of political culture.”

Instead of retreating to quietism, mysticism, and purely personalized

appeals for change, social ecology seeks to think out the kinds of

institutions that would be required in a rational, ecological society;

the kind of politics we should appropriately practice; and the political

movement needed to achieve such a society. Should we fail to initiate

new movements, based on new ideas, and advance new programs to mobilize

the great mass of humanity, this planet may well be degraded beyond

redemption socially even before it is degraded beyond redemption

ecologically. It is this terrible prospect social ecology seeks to

avert.

Anarchism as Individualism

I have long suspected that anarchism, if thought out to its logical

conclusions and reasoned out from its most fundamental roots, is

inherently a negative conception of liberty in its most abstract form.

Indeed, if the wild mix of anarchists today and yesterday all share one

thing in common, it is their rejection of state coercion of the

individual.

If we take a closer look at anarchism as an ideology, it has followed a

careening trajectory. It originated (apart from some precursors) in the

1830s and 1840s as a form of unfettered egoism, a radical demand for

personal autonomy. Initially it meant little more than unrelenting

resistance to attempts by society and particularly the state to restrict

individual liberty. Later it flirted with various social movements of

the oppressed, embracing the collectivism of the archaic peasant

village, then the syndicalism of craft and industrial workers, and later

still it was heavily influenced by Marxism and associated itself with a

libertarian form of communism. The commitment to various forms of

collective social organization, I believe, was a response primarily to

the spread of socialism among the working classes of the nineteenth and

early twentieth centuries.

But by the turn of the twenty-first century, in the wake of social and

cultural homogenization that has been produced by modern corporate

capitalism and the mass media, anarchism has come full circle and has

returned to its old individualistic, autonomist origins. Let me

emphasize that recent developments are not anomalous to anarchism. The

“left liberalism” found all over the place in anarchism, as well as the

unsavory, even outright reactionary ideas in Anarchy, Fifth Estate, and

the like (these are the largest circulation anarchist periodicals in the

US), are built into some of the most fundamental premises of anarchism –

notably, the individualism that forms the conceptual building block of

the whole skewed edifice.

History can provide ample examples of how some self-professed anarchists

explicitly denounced mass social action as futile and alien to their

private concerns.[24] Yet, I am not primarily taking issue with

full-frontal individualists or even the often explicitly anti-social

elements that somehow have always been accepted within the folds of

anarchism. What I would like to get at is the essence of this

contradictory “ideology” and the social consequences it yields; even the

most “social” forms of anarchism have been defined by a foundational

individualism. In fact, the ideas of social and economic reconstruction

that have in the past been offered in the name of “anarchy” have

invariably been drawn to a great extent from Marxism and other forms of

socialism. The fact that anarchism came wrapped in socialist concepts

has often prevented anarchists from appearing as what they are: egoists.

The Individualistic Core of Anarchism

As far as I can judge, anarchists basically seek a future of “voluntary

agreements” between individuals. Insofar as anarchists have called for a

communal society, they have meant a form of association that was

necessary for the individual’s achievement of autonomy in a

non-oppressive or “anti-authoritarian” manner. They share the belief

that enforceable, structured or institutionalized relations within and

between communes are evil, threatening their highly treasured individual

autonomy.

Absolutely canonical for all anarchists – yes, including those who call

themselves “anarcho-collectivist,” “anarcho-communist,” and

“anarcho-syndicalist” – is the belief that the individual ego must be

autonomous, and a free society must be one in which individual autonomy

has free rein, unrestricted by laws and constitutions.

Throughout the writings of the canonical theorists militant assertions

of individual liberty abound. Proudhon hardly requires much elucidation

on this score – some of his most basic “social” ideas are built around

entirely bourgeois concepts of individualism. Bakunin and Kropotkin, to

be sure, criticized “Individualists” at great length, but my view is

that their own ideas were themselves essentially individualistic, often

overlaid with socialist ideas – and that the “collectivist” or

“communist” overlay stood in utter contradiction to their

individualistic foundations. I myself once used anarchism as a political

label for my views, but further thought has forced me to conclude that

anarchism is not a social theory at all but rather a personal

psychology; it is not a political movement but a subculture.

Some of the ideas of classical anarchism will certainly be useful for a

future libertarian radicalism. I have consistently invoked confederalism

as one of anarchism’s contributions to social theory. But I have also

pointed out that the confederalist element in historical anarchism,

heavily influenced by Proudhon, is so loosely constructed, and so

charged with a belief in autonomy, that any component of the

confederation could withdraw at any time. The form of confederalism that

anarchists have advanced – “a federation of autonomous communes”

– recapitulates the same self-contradiction between individual and

society: if a commune is completely autonomous, it cannot be part of a

federation. Proudhon, for example, declared that he would divide and

subdivide “power” until he reached its most elementary components. But

in such a situation, nothing remains in the end but the individual, the

purely self-sufficient ego, secure in his own way of life and

sufficiency. Followed to its logical conclusion, Proudhon’s “federalism”

would render organized society untenable because of assertions of

communal and individual “liberties.”

If individuals must be free of constraint, anarchists have argued, so

must the communes in a future society. (How communes could even exist

when their members were all individually autonomous is an unresolved

question.) Although Kropotkin called himself an anarcho-communist, he

essentially agreed with Proudhon on his point: “the social revolution

must be achieved by the liberation of the communes,” he wrote, “and ...

it is the communes, absolutely independent, liberated from the tutelage

of the state, that alone can give us the necessary setting for a

revolution and the means of accomplishing it.”[25] To bolster this

notion, Kropotkin also rejects majority rule: he’s against people

“submitting themselves to the majority-rule, which always is a

mediocrity-rule.”[26]

By the same logic, anarchists claim that the future society must be one

bereft of laws and constitutions, because they necessarily restrict the

sovereign autonomy of the individual. When Proudhon was a member of the

French Chamber of Deputies, he once declared that he refused to vote for

a particular constitution, not because he opposed the content of it, but

simply because it was a constitution. I fail to see how any free society

can be constituted rationally without a constitution – and for that

matter, laws, ordinances, rules, and the like. This condemnation of all

constitutions, laws, and institutions – claiming they are all equivalent

to a state – as all “great” anarchist thinkers did and others today

continually do, is to appeal to wanton chaos, indeed to a sociality that

essentially depends on good instincts and, hopefully, education (to

which Bakunin added custom and others, habit). Such thinking reveals not

only the basic socio-biologism that underpins most anarchist theory (if

one can use the word theory at all), but also the tendency of anarchists

to refer back to primordial levels for their moral philosophy – genes,

custom, habit, tradition, and the like.

The Essence of Anarchy

The tension between individualism and collectivism or communism would

not exist if the interests of individuals could somehow be conceived to

be the same as or at least compatible with the interests of the larger

society. Bakunin and Kropotkin tried to do just that. Bakunin asserted

that individual and social interests were indeed compatible, blaming the

idea that individual and social interests did not always harmoniously

converge on, variously, the state or the religious doctrine of original

sin. Kropotkin went further, maintaining that individual morality was in

the end identical to social morality: he gave a socio-biological basis

to the instinct for mutual aid, saying that most creatures, from the

simplest to the most complex, are driven by an urge to cooperate. This

being the case, he believed, the individual – freed from the trammels of

the state – would make choices in behavior and thinking that were in

harmony with the needs of his or her society. Thus Kropotkin could

write:

Humanity is trying now to free itself from the bonds of any government

whatever, and to respond to its needs of organization by the free

understanding between individuals pursuing the same common aims.... Free

agreement is becoming a substitute for law. And free cooperation a

substitute for governmental guardianship.... We already foresee a state

of society where the liberty of the individual will be limited by no

laws, no bonds – by nothing else but his own social habits and the

necessity, which everyone feels, of finding cooperation, support, and

sympathy among his neighbors.[27]

But this socio-biologically based cooperation rests, of course, on a

fallacy. In fact, individuals have often placed their own personal

interest above those of their community. Since Kropotkin, moreover, was

always prone to highlight the steady advance of mutual aid in the world

in which he lived, he would have had a hard time to explain the

brutalities that occurred from 1914 onward, which opened one of the

bloodiest periods in history. Alas, cooperation is not embedded in our

genes. But it is on such genetically based cooperation that Kropotkin’s

“anarcho-communism” rests; and when it collapses, so does the whole

edifice. What remains, again, is the individual ego.

Martin A. Miller, a Kropotkin biographer, wrote that “Kropotkin argued

for the full and complete liberty of the individual‚ as the ethical

basis of anarchism. He stopped short of falling into the trap of having

to accept egoism and extreme individualism only because he believed in

the innate sociability and passivity of man, when allowed to be free

without constraint from above.”[28] This belief too was mistaken.

Lacking the linchpin that unites individualism and socialism,

“anarcho-communism” and “anarcho-collectivism” become oxymoronic words,

bereft of meaning.

Furthermore, anarchism, grounded in the egoistic individual, tends to

reject anything about Western society with a flat “No!” and to demand

its opposite instead, as if a libertarian society was simply the mere

negation of bourgeois society. Radical as this posturing may seem at

first, it implies the disbanding of society as such. Hence the

fascination of so many anarchist writers with primitivism, their

technophobic outlook, their aversion to regulation of any kind, and

indeed their indifference to the realm of necessity, as though its

compulsions – possibly including death itself – could be abolished.

In its world outlook, anarchism has consistently opposed dialectics and

favored either positivism or mysticism instead. In the absence of any

dialectical theory of history – unless one wants to believe that

humanity is currently progressing toward mutual aid in the form of one

sort of collective or other – anarchism hardly rises beyond a “vision.”

Its most appropriate “philosophy,” in my view, is actually

postmodernism, with its radical fragmentation of reality, its chaos, its

vacuous spontaneity, and as Feyerabend put it, the notion that “anything

goes.”

Anarchists have always shown little regard for the place of reason in

history, and they have not cared for a serious appreciation of

historical development with an endeavor to distinguish the

preconditional in key social developments (where Marx often excelled)

from the conditional. Here, I completely agree with Marx’s statement in

the Eighteenth Brumaire that “men” make history but not under conditions

of their own choosing.

Among anarchists, I find, such views are heinous. As Colin Ward puts it,

“anarchy” is the wonderful society that, like soil, lies beneath the

snow (of capitalism, the state, religion, and oppressive institutions

generally); the snow only has to melt away, and then we will have our

Wonderland. Kropotkin seems to have had no greater appreciation than

other anarchist theorists for the mutual interaction between the legacy

of domination and the legacy of freedom in history. Ward’s “snow”

metaphor is moreover very much in tune with Bakunin’s continual reliance

on an alleged instinct for revolution that lies latent in workers and

peasants, and Kropotkin’s tendency to fall back on an instinct for

mutual aid.

While I would argue that the rejection of any limitation on behavior is

symptomatic of anarchism’s individualistic basis, the way anarchists are

invoking “instinct” as an alternative social foundation not only makes a

mockery of reason but also reduces us to a quasi-animalistic existence.

The absence of any real historical sense – which makes anarchy possible

anytime, even in the “affluent” societies of the Paleolithic and

Neolithic – easily leads anarchists into primitivism and technophobia.

Of course, the disregard for dialectical reason, indeed the antagonism

toward it, fits in with the anti-rationalism that pervades much of

anarchism; it is precisely the hypostatization of instinct, habit, and

tradition, that leads anarchists into mysticism and anti-rationalism,

and reinforces their proclivity for primitivism.[29]

Hence anarchism does not pay any attention to the “forms of freedom,”

nor to the imperative material, technological, and cultural

preconditions for a free and rational society. Few if any of the major

anarchist theorists clearly faced the problem of such institutions, and

certainly none of them today propose to deal with it. Dozens of

questions and issues, ranging from philosophy to the interpretation of

history, to the evaluation of politics, capitalism, organization,

programs, and so on, simply remain beyond the purview of anarchism.

In my mind, these notions taken together form a complete fit, on a level

more basic than the differences between one form of anarchism and

another. That anarchism’s commitment to the ego outweighs its variously

colored socialistic veneers is evident in its history. It is highly

symptomatic that anarchists have been notoriously unable to develop

beyond a small group level or to form organizations. Why not? we ask

ourselves. What stands in the way, I assure you, is not the

“communistic” dimension of anarchism – it is its foundational

individualism.

Between 1917 and 1921, in Europe’s climactic revolutionary years,

anarchism played no major role (although various syndicalists often

temporarily thought of themselves as anarchists). In 1917, for example,

Russian anarchism, much to its discredit, did not embrace syndicalism

but yielded to the Moscow “house expropriators.”

What gave anarchism a semblance of a mass following was syndicalism, a

form of libertarian socialism. It was syndicalists, not anarchists, who

built the CNT, and hence the CNT is an example not of anarchism but of

syndicalism. The anarchists formed a volatile but very small fraction

within the CNT, consisting of small loosely structured affinity groups

inside very highly structured trade unions that quarreled endlessly with

the syndicalists.[30] The continuing demand of the anarchist grupistas,

in the 1920s, was to reject the need for democratic decision-making and

demand ever more decentralization within what was already a loose and

unstable confederation – to the point where the individual group should

be able to function on its own, autonomously, as it saw fit. Here the

anarchists held true to the ideas of Proudhon and Kropotkin, quoted

above. Throughout the 1930s the faístas were in endless conflicts with

the cenetistas. Tragically, in 1933 the grupistas dragged the movement

into the disastrous “cycle of insurrections” that contributed

significantly to the outbreak of the civil war, for which the CNT–FAI

was totally unprepared.

Anarchy or Libertarian Municipalism?

Apart from the syndicalists, many of whom were decidedly not anarchists,

anarchism has shown little regard for institutions of direct democracy.

In fact, the total identification of politics with the state leads

anarchists to pit purely social actions and phenomena against the state,

leading to incidents, “direct actions” such as “reclaiming the streets,”

cooperatives, squats, and mere forms of merriment or theater that I can

no longer take seriously as political work. Some of these actions are

useful gymnastics or training on cooperation, but they exhibit no

concern for or interest in power.

Libertarian municipalism, by contrast, is concerned with power – and who

will have it. How can power be acquired and communally managed by the

oppressed? In what libertarian institutions should it be collected? How

does one move toward creating those institutions?

Popular assemblies, in my view, are the means by which direct democracy

can be institutionalized. While anarchism has no politics, libertarian

municipalism is intensely political. It is my hope that a libertarian

municipalist program will resonate among responsible and thinking people

who are concerned with where power will repose in a free and rational

society.

Libertarian municipalism is not only the end – the political

infrastructure for the future society – but the means; a rare confluence

of means and ends that has not been worked out in either Marxism or

anarchism. Hence it is a matter of vital importance that when we run

candidates to municipal elections, in order to achieve popular

assemblies and confederal structures, they are as a matter of civic and

political responsibility obliged to take office, or else there is no

point in advocating a libertarian municipalist program. Thus to run

candidates who will not occupy seats on city councils or similar

institutions is to turn libertarian municipalism into a theater or

propaganda for other ends. It does not show any true concern for how

power will be institutionalized; indeed it makes a mockery of the

potentialities of the municipality for creating an empowered people’s

assembly.

We are faced with a real dilemma. It is very difficult to govern or

manage society from the “ground up” in an immensely populous and global

world. I envision confederations within confederations, essentially

structured around local, citywide, countywide, provincial, regional, and

national confederal councils based on directly democratic procedures.

The logic of anarchist thought and its endless demands for autonomy

precludes that this vision can be realized within its framework. When

Kropotkin and other anarchists extol “free agreements” they express a

voluntarism by which individuals and communities not only confederate

together but may withdraw from these confederations at will, making

collective social and political life impossible. Popular assemblies,

which would ultimately validate laws and constitutions, must operate

with a deep sense of responsibility for one another by majority votes

and within a framework that limits their right to walk out of a

confederation without the consent of the majority of the entire

confederation’s members.

We must work to make left libertarian thought relevant today, and focus

on how we can remake society by serious libertarian organization. To

this end, I suggest that we must work to create a democratic form of

government, one that is libertarian and municipalist. I prefer the word

government here to self-management or even self-government for several

reasons, most importantly because concepts of self-management and

self-government seem to me to contain the implication – reinforced by

this business-oriented and narcissistic society – that social life is

basically an agglomeration of autonomous egos, or “selves,” and that

communal life can be reduced to them. Indeed, many anarchists often

refer to “self-government” when describing their dismissal of any kind

of obligations of any sort as authoritarian or coercive or worse, since

they are demanding unrestricted rights for every “sovereign” individual

without requiring of them any duties.

I have come to the conclusion that these concerns merely float on the

surface of a deeply flawed view of social reality. We must therefore

clearly distinguish between anarchy and my ideas of libertarian

municipalism. After 40 exhausting years in the anarchist scene, I’ve

been forced to conclude that “anarchism” is more symptomatic of the

decadence that marks the present era than a force in opposition to it.

It is my desire, in the time that I have left, to get out of the

anarchist “loop” (as this generation likes to put it) before it turns

into a noose and strangles me. I’ve tried to rescue a social anarchism,

with social ecology and libertarian municipalism, from the rest of

anarchism; but the response to these efforts have led me to conclude

that this has been a failure among anarchists. With a few notable

exceptions, they simply don’t want these ideas – and that is that. I

would like to put all the distance I can between this scene and myself.

Yet I would also like to believe that we can develop a synthesis of the

best in Marx’s writings and in the anarchist tradition – a communalism

that will be meaningful and relevant to serious, responsible people in

the years ahead. This is the project that is now dearest to my heart,

not an attempt to rescue movements and traditions that have been

outlived by history.

Anarchism, Power, and Government

Today, when anarchism has become le mot du jour in radical circles, the

differences between a society based on anarchy and one based on the

principles of social ecology should be clearly distinguished. Therefore,

just as elsewhere I have distinguished between politics and statecraft,

I must now also point out the distinction between governments and

states. All anarchists, and indeed most left libertarians, dismiss every

government as a state. The fact is that no society can exist without an

orderly way of administering itself, which necessarily implies

administration or regulation of some kind.

Not Every Government is a State

All states are governments, but not all governments are states. A

government is a set of organized and responsible institutions that are

minimally an active system of social and economic administration. They

handle the problems of living in an orderly fashion. A government may be

a dictatorship; it may be a monarchy or a republican state; but it may

also be a libertarian formation of some kind. But without a rudimentary

body of institutions to sort out the rights and duties of its members,

hopefully in a democratic way, society would simply dissolve into a

disorderly aggregation of individuals.

Indeed, the very notion of community is meaningless unless those who

claim allegiance to it take on obligations that allow it to function,

flourish, and meet everyone’s needs. Even self-government is therefore a

form of government, for under systems of self-government community

members contribute to its functioning. It is possible, and indeed

necessary, for human beings to govern themselves in civilized and

rational institutions. In fact, institutions as such are necessary for

social organization.

Social revolutionaries have traditionally sought a social order that is

concerned with “the administration of things, instead of the

administration of men,” but people must first be organized

institutionally in such a way that they can administer things. One, in

effect, cannot be done without the other. Thus if a society is to

socially own or control property, if it is to produce goods to meet the

needs of all instead of allow profit for a few, if it is to organize a

system of distribution so that all rather than an elite share equitably

in the material means of life – then clearly definable administrative

institutions have to be established that not only make them workable but

also constrain irrational behavior. In short, forms of authority have to

be created that are meant not to exploit or oppress human beings, but

rather to ensure that some human beings are not exploited or oppressed

by others and to ensure the means for acquiring the good life.

Such institutions must exist in a society, even a libertarian one. Their

absence would lead to a prevalence of chaos, disorder, instability, and

disequilibrium – none of which necessarily has revolutionary or

liberatory implications. That revolutions produce instability does not

mean that instability is somehow a desirable condition or that it must

produce a libertarian revolution. If “anarchy is the highest form of

order,” as some anarchists have said, then it is also the highest form

of administration and stability.

What kinds of governments, then, are not states? Tribal councils, town

meetings, workers’ committees, soviets (in the original sense of the

word), popular assemblies and the like are governments, and no amount of

juggling with words can conceal that fact. They are organized

institutions that serve generalized human needs, such as those of a

revolutionary proletariat or peasantry, in a libertarian fashion. The

end that a government serves, no less than its structure, is an integral

part of its nature and definition.

A state, by contrast, is a government that is organized to serve the

interests of a privileged and often propertied class at the expense of

the majority. This historic rise of the state transformed governance

into a malignant force for social development. When a government becomes

a state – that is, a coercive mechanism for perpetuating class rule for

exploitative purposes – it invariably acquires different institutional

characteristics. First, its members are professionalized to one degree

or another, in order to separate them from the mass of the population

and thereby impart to them an extraordinary status, which in turn

renders them the full-time protectors of a ruling class. Second, the

state, aided by military and police functionaries, enjoys a monopoly

over the means of violence. The members of a state’s armies and police

may be drawn from the very classes they are organized to coerce – that

is irrelevant; once they are separated from the population at large,

uniformed, rigorously trained, disciplined, and placed in an explicit

chain of command, they cease to belong to any class and become

professional men and women of violence who are at the service of those

who command them. The chain of command binds them together and places

them at the disposal of their commanders.

The tendency of anarchists to classify all governments as states is a

mischievous distortion (just as the tendency of anarchists to identify

constitutions and laws as such with statism verges on the absurd). Both

tendencies are the product of a radical ego-orientation that denies the

need for any constraints – indeed, that unthinkingly sees all

constraints as evil.

This issue is by no means an idle discussion. It played a pivotal role

during the Spanish Revolution of 1936–37, a history that even has

profound implications for the future of left libertarian theory and

practice.

Libertarian Government in Revolutionary Spain

In the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, Spain was the most

important locus of worldwide anarcho-syndicalism. Here, uniquely,

anarchists and syndicalists conjointly developed a mass movement that

persisted for at least two generations. The National Confederation of

Labor (CNT), formed in 1910 in Barcelona, was by the mid-1930s the

largest anarcho-syndicalist union in the world. It was a strong and

vital force, particularly on the eastern coast of Spain.

Despite or perhaps because of its breadth, the CNT was based on at least

two distinct ideologies that were frequently in tension with each other.

The first, syndicalism, was perhaps the most highly organized of all

libertarian ideologies. Syndicalism emphasized discipline and unity, and

its high regard for the importance of organizing the exploited classes

could surpass even that of socialism. Syndicalists would have agreed

strongly with the words of Joe Hill as he faced a firing squad in Utah:

“Don’t mourn – organize!”

For their part, anarchists historically distrusted organization. Leading

figures of Spanish anarchism such as Anselmo Lorenzo and Federico Urales

viewed the formation of the CNT with deep suspicion, if not outright

hostility. Achieving a creative union between the more madcap members of

the Iberian Anarchist Federation (FAI), who in fact were true to their

anarchist precepts, and the syndicalists was difficult; fractious

disputes often shredded the CNT and, in the early 1930s, led to an

outright split.[31]

The outbreak of the Spanish Revolution in 1936 created a decisive crisis

that tested the very integrity of the CNT. In the process, it challenged

anarchism to deal with the serious question of acquiring and holding

power.

On July 21, 1936, the workers of Catalonia and especially its capital,

Barcelona, defeated the rebel forces of General Francisco Franco and

thereby gained control over one of Spain’s largest and most

industrialized provinces, including many important cities along the

Mediterranean coast and a considerable agrarian area. In the face of the

conflict, the Catalan state institutions either floundered helplessly or

dissolved. Something unprecedented in modern history then took place: an

anarcho-syndicalist movement found itself in a position of power. Partly

as the result of an indigenous libertarian tradition and partly as a

result of the influence exercised by the CNT, Spain’s mass

revolutionary-syndicalist trade union was possessed of the authority to

create a libertarian communist society and the institutions to structure

it.

The CNT membership proceeded to create a dazzling series of libertarian

institutions. In the cities it organized a huge network of defense,

neighborhood, factory, supply, and transportation committees and

assemblies, while in the countryside the more radical peasantry (a

sizable part of the agrarian population) took over and collectivized the

land. Catalonia and its population were protected against a possible

counterattack by a revolutionary militia, which, notwithstanding its

often archaic weapons, was sufficiently well armed to have defeated the

rebel army and police force. This committee system assumed control over

the economic and political life of eastern coastal Spain and parts of

the peninsula’s interior. It controlled nearly every aspect of social

life in Barcelona, from the feeding of the city’s population to its

safety.

The committee structure had not been created by an elite group, such as

the Bolsheviks. On the contrary, it decidedly emerged, under the

guidance of CNT militants, from the workers and peasants of Catalonia

themselves – to the surprise and even the patent unease of most of the

CNT’s regional and national leaders, who seemed to be unnerved and

thrown off balance by the rapid tempo of revolutionary events.

Notwithstanding their reputation for indiscipline, the majority of CNT

members, or cenetistas, were libertarian syndicalists rather than

anarchists; they were strongly committed to a well-structured,

democratic, disciplined, and coordinated organization. In July 1936 they

acted, often on their own initiative, to create these councils,

committees, and assemblies, breaking through all predetermined

ideologies within the revolutionary movement.

The result was that they shattered the bourgeois state-machine and

created a radically new government or polity in which they themselves

exercised direct control over public and economic affairs through

institutions of their own making. For several months the CNT’s

grassroots proletarian and peasant militants provided rare examples of

the use of federative principles of economic control, in contrast to

private or statist methods, to effectively manage production in the

cities and the countryside. Put bluntly, they took power by destroying

the old institutions and creating radically new ones whose form and

substance gave the masses the right to determine the operations of

economy and polity.[32]

What they created was a libertarian government, one that constituted the

authentic power in the expansive areas in which they existed.[33] The

anarcho-syndicalist workers clearly desired to prevent the liberals and

conservatives who had run the official Spanish state (and under whose

cover the army rebels had plotted and executed their rebellion) from

returning to power. The committee structure institutionally embodied the

desire of most workers in the large area where it was established to

take over society and manage it in the interests of the oppressed; in

fact, in the interests of humanity as a whole. Never was

anarcho-syndicalism in a more favorable position in its history to

declare libertarian communism, their stated social goal. Many of the

committees were eager to believe that the CNT would ideologically

legitimate their existence and provide them with the guidance needed to

achieve a libertarian communist society. They therefore turned to CNT –

or rather to the union’s “influential militants” (as CNT leaders were

euphemistically called) – to coordinate the new institutions into an

effective government.

The Downfall of Spanish Anarchism

The structure the Catalan workers and peasants had created in fact stood

at odds with the individualism emphasized by anarchism. In this

situation, the anarchist ideology embraced by the CNT leadership gave

them no tools to function appropriately. After all, pure anarchism has

nothing to do with government – indeed it rejects government, even

libertarian, popular government, on the basis that all governments are

inherently states.

Nonetheless, almost as a matter of course, the CNT membership gave its

union leadership the authority to organize a revolutionary government

and provide it with political direction. After all, for years the CNT

had continuously propagated revolutions and uprisings; in the early

1930s it had taken up arms again and again, without the least prospect

of actually being able to change Spanish society. Now in 1936, as its

membership looked to it for coordination, the CNT leadership could

finally have a significant impact on society.

What did it do? Apparently it stood around with a puzzled look, as if

orphaned by the very success of its working-class members in achieving

the goals embedded in its rhetoric. This confusion was not the result of

a failure of nerve; it stemmed from a failure of the CNT’s theoretical

insight. For in the eyes of the “influential militants,” the committee

structure that the revolutionary works had created, and that now ran a

very large part of Spain, bore some resemblance to that perennial

nightmare that haunted the anarchist tradition from its inception: a

state.

On July 23, a mere two days after the workers’ victory over the

Francoist uprising, a Catalan regional plenum of the CNT convened in

Barcelona. Here the CNT leadership would decide what to do with the

power that the workers and peasants had fought for in the streets and

villages and then offered up to it. The leadership could have accepted

that power and decided to use it to transform the social order in the

considerable and strategic area of Spain that was now under the union’s

de facto control. It could have declared libertarian communism and the

end of the old political and social order. It could have created a

“Barcelona Commune,” one that might have been no more permanent than the

“Paris Commune” but would have been far more memorable and inspiring to

later generations. A few delegates from the militant Bajo de Llobregat

region (on the outskirts of the city), and the CNT militant Juan García

Oliver, fervently demanded that the plenum do just this: claim the power

it already possessed and proclaim libertarian communism.

But to the astonishment of these militants, the plenum’s members found

themselves reluctant to take this decisive measure. Federica Montseny

and the arguments of Diego Abad de Santillán (two CNT leaders) urged the

plenum not to take this move, denouncing it as a “Bolshevik seizure of

power.” Their oratory prevailed. Betraying the historic trust of its

class, the CNT plenary instead voted to establish a coalition government

along with all the other parties in Barcelona that had opposed the

military rebellion. This new body, called the Anti-Fascist Militia

Committee, included the bourgeois liberals and the Stalinists. In

effect, the CNT leadership surrendered its own power by entering into

this “People’s Front” style government. Incredibly, all these parties

and unions were granted representation on the basis of parity, not in

proportion to their memberships, which would have certainly provided the

CNT with a commanding majority on the committee.

The monumental nature of this error should be fully appreciated because

it reveals all that is internally contradictory about anarchist

ideology. By mistaking a workers’ government for a state, the CNT

leadership rejected political power in Catalonia at a time when it was

actually in their hands. In effect, the CNT turned the power that the

workers’ committees had vested in their hands over to a new state – and

eventually, a few months later, to the bourgeois Generalidad itself. The

CNT remained “pure” ideologically, but only by acting as a conduit to

transform workers’ power into capitalists’ power. That is, the plenum

did not eliminate power as such; it merely transferred it to its

treacherous “allies.”

In taking its action, the CNT revealed that while it could militantly

protest the abuses of capitalism, it lacked any theoretical and

organizational capacity to replace it. It was incapable of

distinguishing between a worker– peasant government that the masses had

created from below and a capitalist state (or, even more pathetically, a

Stalinist-type dictatorship) carefully contrived by the bourgeoisie from

above. By expressly rejecting the taking of the power as “statist,” even

���Bolshevistic” and “dictatorial,” it permitted the bourgeoisie to occupy

the power arena. This ensured the actual transfer of power away from the

workers and peasants and into the hands of the bourgeoisie and the

Stalinists, who then proceeded to consolidate their power and eventually

used it to destroy the workers’ and peasants’ government. Adding insult

to injury, the CNT soon joined the Generalidad, and the power of the

revolutionary workers and peasants thus passed to the bourgeois state.

Why did the CNT leadership decide to transfer its power to the

Anti-Fascist Militia Committee? Diego Abad de Santillán, who was one of

the principal architects of this curious policy, later articulated the

twisted logic:

We could have remained alone, imposed our absolute will, declared the

Generalidad null and void, and imposed the true power of the people in

its place, but we did not believe in dictatorship when it was being

exercised against us, and we did not want it when we could have

exercised it ourselves only at the expense of others. The Generalidad

would remain in force with President Companys at its head, and the

popular forces would organize themselves into militias to carry on the

struggle for the liberation of Spain.[34]

This statement, reiterated in different ways by nearly all the leading

figures of the CNT, combines outright falsehood with numbing stupidity.

Had the CNT taken the power, it would not have “remained alone.” All the

revolutionary workers and, perhaps, a substantial number of the

enlightened petty bourgeoisie in Catalonia would have supported it.

Certainly the POUM, a large anti- Stalinist Marxist party in the

province, would have actively supported a workers’ government. Even the

Stalinist leadership of the PSUC and UGT (both of which were quite small

in 1936) would most likely have been unable to prevent a majority of

their members from supporting workers’ power in Catalonia.

Nor would a workers’ government have had to be a “dictatorship” in any

usual sense of the term. It could have been quite democratic, indeed

libertarian, and still functioned in the interests of the working class

and other oppressed strata. Structured from the bottom up, it would have

been a popular power or government that could have allowed a free press,

free expression, and public criticism. Even the middle-class press,

provided that it did not incite people to armed rebellion against the

new workers’ regime, might have been allowed to publish its criticisms.

True, the factories would have been taken over by workers’ committees,

but former technicians and even owners could have been employed for

their expertise. In one or another permutation, Catalonia could have

been recreated as a tolerant, even open libertarian communist region

from a civil liberties’ standpoint.

But this was not to be. The CNT’s “influential militants” were wedded to

a pseudo-theory that perceived no distinction between a government and a

state. They were blind to the fact that no bourgeois government such as

the Generalidad would permit the anarcho-syndicalist movement to

exercise effective power once early revolutionary enthusiasm among the

masses waned. Thus the CNT’s shrewd opponents could lead the

“influential militants” by the nose, step by step, into the clutches of

the state apparatus.

Actually, in the intervening year, the CNT leaders discovered that their

rejection of power for the Catalan proletariat and peasantry did not

include a rejection of power for themselves as individuals. Four CNT-FAI

leaders actually agreed to participate in the bourgeois state in Madrid,

as cabinet ministers. But first, with a rather adolescent concern for

form rather than content, they tried to get the prime minister, Largo

Caballero, to change the state’s name from that of a cabinet to a

“Defense Council.” Caballero, a humorless old social democrat, simply

told the CNT to go to hell – whereupon the four anarcho-syndicalists,

who were never notorious for their theoretical insights, meekly joined

the Madrid state as outright ministers in the service of the

bourgeoisie. There, they dutifully served the bourgeois state as long as

they were useful, up to the closing days of the civil war.

Thus did anarcho-syndicalism follow the unrelenting logic of events to

the edge of the political cliff – and ignominiously jump off, by its

presence legitimating a state that it was committed to oppose.

Needless to emphasize, the old ruling classes in Catalonia, the CNT’s

capitalist and petty-bourgeois opponents, celebrated it all. Aided by

the Stalinists, they exhibited no qualms in accepting the power that the

anarchists had donated to them. Inevitably, they used the power the

workers had won to constitute their own state and systematically

demolish all the strategic gains the workers had made.

In the autumn of 1936, the newly reempowered parties set out to

dismantle the workers’ government in the region. Under the

circumstances, that process opened the door to an authoritarian

Stalinist regime. Indeed, the reborn Catalan state, in order to

eviscerate the power of the CNT workers, soon became a violently

counter-revolutionary instrument of the bourgeoisie and the Stalinists.

Systematically and with armed force, it swept away the committee system,

it restored the old police forces (under new names), and it so abridged

workers’ control and management of the factories that their role for the

rest of the civil war was ineffective. Eventually, it hunted down,

arrested, and often executed militant CNT and POUM members. It finally

booted the CNT out of the Catalan government, and the Stalinists had a

free hand to further efface the revolution and hound its supporters.

Rather than refuse the political and economic power that its own members

had offered to it, the CNT plenum should have accepted it and

legitimated and approved the new institutions they had already created.

Instead, the tension between metaphorical claims and painful realities

finally became intolerable, and in May 1937 resolute CNT workers in

Barcelona were drawn into open battle with the revived Catalan state in

a brief but bloody war within the civil war. Finally the bourgeois state

suppressed the last major uprising of the syndicalist movement,

butchering hundreds if not thousands of CNT militants. How many were

killed will never be known, but we do know that before it was over, the

internally contradictory ideology called anarcho-syndicalism lost the

greater part of the following it had possessed in the summer of 1936.

Addressing Power

Pure anarchism seeks above all the emancipation of individual

personality from all ethical, political, and social constraints. In so

doing, it fails to address the concrete issue of power that confronts

all revolutionaries in a period of social upheaval. Rather than address

how the people, organized into confederated popular assemblies, might

capture power and create a fully developed libertarian society,

anarchists have traditionally conceived of power as a malignant evil

that must be destroyed. Proudhon, for example, once stated that he would

divide and subdivide power until, in effect, it ceased to exist.

Proudhon may well have intended that government should be reduced to a

minimal entity, but his statement perpetuates the illusion that power

can actually cease to exist.

Spain revealed the inability of this anti-intellectual,

anti-theoretical, and ego-oriented ideology (however sincere and radical

its adherents) to cope with the compelling issues of power and social

reconstitution. Having staged no less than three insurrections in 1933,

the Spanish anarchists and their syndicalist allies seem never to have

asked themselves what they would do if they actually succeeded in

overthrowing the republic. As a matter of self-defining dogma, anarchism

eschews the creation of institutional power. But in Spain anarchists

could not tolerate even an entity that had sprung from its own loins:

the revolutionary workers’ committees. To stand at the head of these

committees and simply take control over Catalonia and other areas would

have violated a self-defining principle, but one that assured

anarchism’s ineffectuality in a revolutionary period.

Power always exists, and it must always be institutionalized – whether

in democratic forms like popular assemblies, committees, and councils,

or perniciously, in chiefdoms, aristocracies, monarchies, republics,

dictatorships, and totalitarian regimes. To suggest that power can be

abolished, and that “everyone” may come to feel “personally empowered,”

is to play with psychological fallacies that have in the past led more

than one libertarian movement to come to grief. Confusion over the

nature of popular power contributed to popular disempowerment, and to

the disempowerment of popular institutions such as the sectional

assemblies of 1794, the revolutionary clubs of 1848, the neighborhood

committees of 1871, the soviets of 1917, and the committees and

assemblies of 1936.

The fact is that power is as ubiquitous as gravity. Just as gravity is

one of the forces that hold the universe together, so power is one of

the forces that hold any society together. A defining feature of any

society – whether it is tribal, slave, feudal, capitalist, socialist,

communist, or even anarchist – is not whether power is being exercised

but how. To argue that social power as such is somehow wrong or “evil”

is fallacious. What counts is whether it belongs to the people, and by

what kind of institutions is it being exercised. Communalism, to take

one example, seeks as I have argued to transfer power from the state to

organized confederations of popular assemblies.

The Spanish anarchist experience cannot be judged as an anomalous event,

possible only on an isolated peninsula south of the Pyrenees. If we are

to learn anything from this crucial error by the CNT leadership, it is

that power is always a feature of social and political life. The real

question that every revolutionary movement faces is not whether power

has been eliminated, but where it is located: in institutions that serve

the interests of oppressive classes and strata, or in those that serve

the oppressed; will it rest in the hands of an elite or in the hands of

the people?

That which is “pure” exists only within the confines of the laboratory

and the workings of the human brain. In the real world, where real

people, animals, and plants live, impurity is unavoidable; any

development, change, or dialectic yields new elements and phenomena that

instantly adulterate a seemingly pure process. Many of the stark dictums

historically posed by the Left have been shown to belie the authenticity

of the real world, yielding false results for social expectations.

During the classical period of socialism many Marxists believed it

inevitable that socialism would be achieved; similarly, many anarchists

believe it inevitable that freedom can emerge without being conditioned

by necessity. Unless those of us on the libertarian left are to accept

the absurd notion of a decivilized “autonomous individual,” we must

concede that society cannot exist without organized institutions that

abridge pure autonomy by situating the individual within contextual

limitations.

Power that is not placed securely in the hands of the masses must

inevitably fall into the hands of their oppressors. There is no closet

in which it can be tucked away, no bewitching ritual that can make it

evaporate, no superhuman realm where it can be placed in reserve – and

no simplistic ideology can make it disappear. Self-styled radicals may

try to ignore the problem of power, as the CNT leaders did in July 1936,

but it will remain hidden at every meeting, lie concealed in public

activities, and appear and reappear at every rally.

Social revolutionaries, far from removing the problem of power from

their field of vision, must address the problem of how to give power a

concrete institutional emancipatory form. To be silent with respect to

this question, and to hide behind superannuated ideologies that are

irrelevant to the present overheated capitalist development, is merely

to play at revolution, even to mock the memory of the countless

militants who have given their all to achieve it.

The Revolutionary Politics of Libertarian Municipalism

Libertarian municipalism is a revolutionary politics, and not a new

version of Paul Brousse’s reformist “possibilism” of the 1890s.

Libertarian municipalism in no way compromises with parliamentarism,

reformist attempts to “improve” capitalism, or the perpetuation of

private property. Limited exclusively to the municipality as the locus

for political activity, as distinguished from provincial and state

governments, not to speak of national and supranational governments,

libertarian municipalism is revolutionary to the core, in the very

important sense that it seeks to exacerbate the latent and often very

real tension between the municipality and the state, and to enlarge the

democratic institutions of the commune that still remain, at the expense

of statist institutions. It counterposes the confederation to the

nation-state, and libertarian communism to existing systems of private

and nationalized property. Libertarian municipalism is an explicit

attempt to update the traditional anarchist-communist ideal of the

federation of communes or “Commune of communes.” More specifically, it

aims for the confederal linking of libertarian communist municipalities,

in the form of directly democratic popular assemblies as well as the

collective control or “ownership” of socially important property.

Where anarchist-communists in the past have regarded the federation of

communes as an ideal to be achieved after an insurrection, libertarian

municipalists, I contend, regard the federation – or confederation – of

communes as a political practice that can be developed, at least partly,

prior to an outright revolutionary confrontation with the state – a

confrontation which, in my view, cannot be avoided and, if anything,

should be encouraged by increasing the tension between the state and

confederations of municipalities. In fact, libertarian municipalism is a

communalist practice for creating a revolutionary culture, and for

bringing revolutionary change into complete conformity with our social

goals.

In the last case, it unifies practice and ideal into a single and

coherent means-and-ends approach for initiating a libertarian communist

society, without any disjunction between the strategy for achieving such

a society and the society itself. At no point should libertarian

municipalists cultivate the illusion that the state and bourgeoisie will

allow such a continuum to find fulfillment without open struggle.

The Revolutionary Municipality

It would be helpful to place libertarian municipalism in a broad

historical perspective, all the more to understand its revolutionary

character in human affairs generally as well as its place in the

repertoire of anti-statist practices. The town or city, or, more

broadly, the municipality, is not merely a “space” created by a given

density of human habitations. In terms of its history as a civilizing

tendency in humanity’s development, the municipality is integrally part

of the sweeping process whereby human beings began to dissolve

biologically conditioned social relations based on real or fictitious

blood ties, with their primordial hostility to “strangers,” and slowly

replace them by largely social and rational institutions, rights, and

duties that increasingly encompassed all residents of an urban space,

irrespective of consanguinity and biological facts. The town, city,

municipality, or commune (the equivalent word, in Latin countries, for

“municipality”) was the emerging civic substitute, based on residence

and social interests, for the tribal blood group, which had been based

on myths of a common ancestry. The municipality, however slowly and

incompletely, formed the necessary condition for human association based

on rational discourse, material interest, and a secular culture,

irrespective of and often in conflict with ancestral roots and blood

ties. Indeed, the fact that people can come together peacefully and

share creatively in the exchange of ideas without hostility or suspicion

today, despite our disparate ethnic, linguistic, and national

backgrounds, is a grand historic achievement of civilization, one that

is the work of centuries involving a painful discarding of primordial

definitions of ancestry, and the replacement of these archaic

definitions by reason, knowledge, and a growing sense of our status as

members of a common humanity.

In great part, this humanizing development was the work of the

municipality – the increasingly free space in which people, as people,

began to see each other realistically, steadily unfettered by archaic

notions of biological consanguinity, tribal affiliations, and a

mystical, tradition-laden, and parochial identity. I do not contend that

this process of civilization has been completely achieved. Far from it.

Without the existence of a rational society, the municipality can easily

become a megalopolis, in which community, however secular, is replaced

by atomization and an inhuman social scale beyond the comprehension of

its citizens – indeed, becomes the space for class, racial, religious,

and other irrational conflicts.

But both historically and contemporaneously, citification forms the

necessary condition – albeit by no means fully actualized – for the

realization of humanity’s potentiality to become fully human, rational,

and collectivistic, thereby shedding divisive, essentially animalistic

divisions based on presumed blood affiliations and differences, mindless

custom, fearful imaginaries, and a non-rational, often intuitional,

notion of rights and duties.

Hence the municipality is the potential arena for realizing the great

goal of transforming parochialized human beings into truly universal

human beings, a genuine humanitas, divested of the darker animalistic

attributes of the primordial world. The rational municipality in which

all human beings can be citizens – irrespective of their ethnic

background and ideological convictions – constitutes the true arena of a

communalist society. Metaphorically speaking, it is not only a

desideratum for rational human beings, without which a free society is

impossible; it is also the future of a rational humanity, the

indispensable space for actualizing humanity’s potentialities for

freedom and self-consciousness.

I do not presume to claim that a confederation of libertarian

municipalities – a Commune of communes – has ever existed in the past.

Yet no matter how frequently I disclaim the existence of any historical

“models” and “paradigms” for libertarian municipalities, my critics

still try to saddle me with the many social defects of Athens,

revolutionary New England towns, and the like, as if they were somehow

an integral part of my “ideals.” This criticism is cynical demagogy and

beneath contempt. I privilege no single city or group of cities – be

they classical Athens, the free cities of the medieval world, the town

meetings of the American Revolution, the sections of the Great French

Revolution, or the anarcho-syndicalist collectives that emerged in the

Spanish Revolution – as the full actualization, still less the

comprehensive “models” or “paradigms,” of the libertarian municipalist

vision.

Yet significant features – despite various, often unavoidable,

distortions – existed among all of these municipalities and the

federations that they formed. Their value for us lies in the fact that

we can learn from all of them about the ways in which they practiced the

democratic precepts by which they were guided; and we can incorporate

the best of their institutions for our own and future times, study their

defects, and gain inspiration from the fact that they did exist and

functioned with varying degrees of success for generations, if not

centuries.

At present, I think it is important to recognize that when we advance a

politics of libertarian municipalism, we are not engaged in discussing a

mere tactic or strategy for creating a public sphere; rather, we are

trying to create a new political culture that is not only consistent

with our communalist goals but that includes real efforts to actualize

these goals, fully cognizant of all the difficulties that face us and

the revolutionary implications that they hold for us in the years ahead.

Let me note here that the “neighborhood” is not merely the place where

people make their homes, rear their children, and purchase many of their

goods. Under a more political coloration, so to speak, a neighborhood

may well include those vital spaces where people congregate to discuss

political as well as social issues. Indeed, it is the extent to which

public issues are openly discussed in a city or town that truly defines

the neighborhood as an important political and power space.

By this I do not mean only an assembly, where citizens discuss and gird

themselves to fight for specific policies; I also mean the neighborhood

as the center of a town, where citizens may gather as a large group to

share their views and give public expression to their policies. This was

the function of the Athenian agora, for example, and the town squares in

the Middle Ages. The spaces for political life may be multiple, but they

are generally highly specific and definable, not random or ad hoc.

Such essentially political neighborhoods have often appeared in times of

unrest, when sizable numbers of individuals spontaneously occupy spaces

for discussion, as in the Hellenic agora. I recall them during my own

youth in New York City, in Union Square and Crotona Park, where hundreds

and possibly thousands of men and women appeared weekly to informally

discuss the issues of the day. Hyde Park in London constituted such a

civic space, as did the Palais-Royal in Paris, which was the breeding

ground of the Great French Revolution and the revolution of 1830.

And during the early days of the 1848 revolution in Paris, scores

(possibly hundreds) of neighborhood assembly halls existed as clubs and

forums and potentially formed the basis for a restoration of the older

neighborhood sections of 1793. The best estimates indicate that club

membership did not exceed 70,000 out of a total population of about a

million residents. Yet had this club movement been coordinated by an

active and politically coherent revolutionary organization, it could

have become a formidable, possibly a successful, force during the weeks

of crisis that led to the June insurrection of the Parisian workers.

There is no reason, in principle, why such spaces and the people who

regularly occupy them cannot become citizens’ assemblies as well.

Indeed, like certain sections in the Great French Revolution, they may

well take a leading role in sparking a revolution and pushing it forward

to its logical conclusion.

Recreating a Political Sphere

Libertarian municipalism seeks to go beyond the problems and limitations

in classical anarchist-communist theory. Above all by insisting that a

political sphere, distinguishable from the state and potentially

libertarian in its possibilities, must be acknowledged, and its

potentialities for a truly libertarian politics must be explored. We

cannot simply content ourselves with simplistically dividing

civilization into a workaday world of everyday life that is properly

social, as I call it, in which we reproduce the conditions of our

individual existence at work, in the home, and among our friends, and,

the world of the state, which reduces us at best to docile observers of

the activities of professionals who administer our civic and national

affairs. Between these two worlds is still another world, the realm of

the political, where our ancestors in the past, at various times and

places historically, exercised varying degrees of control over the

commune and the confederation to which it belonged.

It has always been a lacuna in anarchist-communist theory that the

political was conflated with the state, thereby effacing a major

distinction between a political sphere in which people in varying

degrees exercised power, often through direct assemblies, over their

civic environment, and the state, in which people had no direct control,

often no control at all, over that environment.

If politics is denatured to mean little more than statecraft and the

manipulation of people by their so-called “representatives,” then a

condition that has acquired varying forms of expression in the classical

Athenian assembly, popular medieval civic assemblies, town meetings, and

the revolutionary sectional assemblies of Paris, is conveniently erased,

and the multitudinous institutions for managing a municipality become

reducible to the behavior of cynical parliamentarians, or worse. Yet, it

is a gross simplification of historical development and the world in

which we live to see the political simply as the practice of statecraft.

Just as the tribe emerged long before the city, so the city emerged long

before the state – indeed, often in opposition to it. Mesopotamian

cities, appearing in the land between the Tigris and Euphrates rivers

some 6,000 years ago, are believed to have been managed by popular

assemblies long before they were forced by intercity conflicts to

establish state-like institutions and ultimately despotic imperial

institutions. It was in these early cities that politics – that is,

popular ways of managing the city – were born and may very well have

thrived. The state followed later and elaborated itself institutionally,

often in bitter opposition to tendencies that tried to restore popular

control over civic affairs.

Nor can we afford to ignore the fact that the same conflict also emerged

in early Athens and probably other Greek poleis long before the

development of the state reached a relatively high degree of completion.

One can see the recurrence of similar conflicts in the struggle of the

Gracchi brothers and popular assemblies in Rome against the elitist

Senate and, repeatedly, in the medieval cities, long before the rise of

late medieval aristocracies and the Baroque monarchies of the fifteenth

and sixteenth centuries. Kropotkin did not write nonsense when he

pointed to the free cities of Europe, marked not by the existence of

states but by their absence.

Indeed, let us also acknowledge that the state itself underwent a

process of development and differentiation, at times developing no

further than into a loose, almost minimal system of coercion; extending

further at other times into an ever-growing apparatus; finally, in this

century in particular, acquiring totalitarian control over every aspect

of human existence – an apparatus that was only too familiar thousands

of years ago in Asia and even in Indian America in pre-Columbian times.

The classical Athenian city-state was only partially statist; it

constituted a fraternity, often riven by class conflicts, of select

citizens who collectively oppressed slaves, women, and even foreign

residents. The medieval state was often a much looser state formation

than, say, the Roman imperial state, and at various times in history

(one thinks of the comuñeros in Spain during the sixteenth century and

the sections in France during the eighteenth) the state almost

completely collapsed and direct democracies based on what approximated

communalist political principles played a hegemonic role in social

affairs.

Libertarian municipalism is concerned with this political sphere,

including aspects of basic civic importance, such as economic issues, as

well as the many cultural factors that must play a role in the formation

of true citizens, indeed, of rounded human beings. (In this respect, it

does not draw strict impenetrable barriers between politics and

economics to the point where they are implacably set against each other:

libertarian municipalism calls for the municipalization of the economy

and, where material interests between communities overlap, the

confederalization of the economy.) In a very fundamental sense, the

libertarian municipalist arena may be a school for educating its youth

and its mature citizens; but what makes it particularly significant,

especially at this time, is that it is a sphere of power relations that

must be crystallized against capitalism, the marketplace, the forces for

ecological destruction, and the state. Indeed, without a movement that

keeps this need completely in mind, libertarian municipalism may easily

degenerate in this age of academic cretinism into another subject in a

classroom curriculum.

Libertarian municipalism rests its politics today on the historically

preemptive role of the city in relation to the state, and above all on

the fact that civic institutions still exist, however distorted they may

appear or however captive to the state they may be, institutions that

can be enlarged, radicalized, and eventually aimed at the elimination of

the state. The city council, however feeble its powers may be, still

exists as the remnant of the communes with which it was identified in

the past, especially in the Great French Revolution and the Paris

Commune of 1871. The possibility of recreating a sectional democracy

still remains, assuming either a legal or extralegal form. We must bear

in mind that the French revolutionary sections did not have any prior

tradition on which to rest their claims to legitimacy – indeed, they

even emerged from the elitist assemblies or districts of 1789, which the

monarchy had created to elect the Parisian deputies to the Estates

General – except that they refused to disband after they completed their

electoral role and remained as watchdogs over the behavior of the

Estates in Versailles.

We, too, are faced with the task of restructuring and expanding the

civic democratic institutions that still exist, however vestigial their

forms and powers may be; of attempting to base them on old or new

popular assemblies – and, to be quite categorical, of creating new legal

or, most emphatically, extralegal popular democratic institutions where

vestiges of civic democracy do not exist. In doing so, we are direly in

need of a movement – indeed, a responsible, well-structured, and

programmatically coherent organization – that can provide the

educational resources, means of mobilization, and vital ideas for

achieving our libertarian communist and municipalist goals.

Our program should be flexible in the special sense that it pose minimum

demands that we seek to achieve at once, given the political

sophistication of the community in which we function. But such demands

would easily degenerate into reformism and even possibilism if they did

not escalate into a body of transitional demands that would ultimately

lead to our maximum demands for a libertarian and ecological society.

Nor can we give up our seemingly utopian vision that the great

metropolitan areas can be structurally decentralized. Cities on the

scale of New York, London, and Paris, not to speak of Mexico City,

Buenos Aires, Bombay, and the like, must ultimately be parceled into

smaller cities and decentralized to a point where they are once again

humanly scaled communities, not huge and incomprehensible urban belts.

Libertarian municipalism takes its immediate point of departure from the

existing facts of urban life, many of which are beyond the comprehension

of its residents. But it always strives to physically as well as

politically fragment the great cities, until it achieves the great

anarchist-communist and even Marxian goal of scaling all cities to human

dimensions.

Criticisms of Assembly Democracy

Perhaps the most common criticism that both Marxists and anarchists have

presented against libertarian municipalism is the claim that modern

cities are too huge to be organized around workable popular assemblies.

Some critics assume that if we are to have true democracy, everyone from

age zero to one hundred, irrespective of health, mental condition, or

disposition, must be included in a popular assembly – and that an

assembly must be as small as a touchy-feely American encounter group

(say 30 or 40 people), or “affinity group,” as one critic calls it. But

in large world cities, these critics suggest, which have several million

residents, we would require many thousands of assemblies in order to

achieve true democracy. In such cities such a multiplicity of small

assemblies, they argue, would be just too cumbersome and unworkable.

But a large urban population is itself no obstacle to libertarian

municipalism. Indeed, based on this kind of calculation – which would

count all residents as participating citizens – the 48 Parisian sections

of 1793 would have been completely dysfunctional, in view of the fact

that revolutionary Paris had a total of 500,000 to 600,000 people. If

every man, woman, and child, indeed every pathological lunatic and

totally dysfunctional person, had attended sectional assemblies, and

each assembly had had no more than 40 people, my arithmetic tells me

that about 15,000 assemblies would have been needed to accommodate all

the people of revolutionary Paris. Under such circumstances one wonders

how the French Revolution could ever have occurred.

Such critics are usually not revolutionaries at all, and would probably

believe that history would have been all the better if the sections had

never existed to push the French Revolution forward. Their objection

represents the instrumental mind qua calculating machine at its worst. A

popular democracy, to begin with, is not premised on the idea that

everyone can, will, or even wants to attend popular assemblies. Nor

should anyone make participation compulsory, coercing everyone into

doing so. Even more significantly, it has rarely happened – indeed, to

my knowledge, it has never happened in revolutionary history – that the

great majority of people in a particular place, still less everyone,

engage in revolution. In the face of insurrection in a revolutionary

situation, while unknown militants aided by a fairly small number of

supporters rise up and overthrow the established order, most people tend

to be either active or inactive observers.

Having reviewed carefully the course of almost every major revolution in

the Euro-American world, I can say with some knowledge that, even in a

completely successful revolution, it was always a minority of the people

who attended meetings of assemblies that made significant decisions

about the fate of their society. The very differentiated political and

social consciousness, interests, education, and backgrounds among masses

in a capitalist society guarantee that people will be drawn into

revolutions in waves, if at all. The foremost, most militant wave is, at

first, numerically surprisingly small; it is followed by seeming

bystanders who, if an uprising seems to be capable of success, merge

with the foremost wave, and only after the uprising is likely to be

successful do the politically less developed waves, in varying degrees,

follow it. Even after an uprising is successful, it takes time for a

substantial majority of the people to fully participate in the

revolutionary process, commonly as crowds in demonstrations, more rarely

as participants in revolutionary institutions.

In the English Revolution of the 1640s, for example, it was primarily

the Puritan army that raised the most democratic issues, with the

support of the Levellers, who formed a very small fraction of the

civilian population. The American Revolution was notoriously supported,

albeit by no means actively, by only one-third of the colonial

population; the Great French Revolution found its principal support in

Paris and was carried forward by 48 sections, most of which were rooted

in assemblies that were poorly attended, except at times when momentous

decisions aroused the most revolutionary neighborhoods.

Indeed, what decided the fate of most revolutions was less the amount of

support their militants received than the degree of resistance they

encountered. What brought Louis XVI and his family back to Paris from

Versailles in October 1789 was certainly not all the women of Paris –

indeed, only a few thousand made the famous march to Versailles – but

the king’s own inability to mobilize a sufficiently large and reliable

force to resist them. The Russian Revolution of February 1917 in

Petrograd – for many historians the “model” of a mass spontaneous

revolution (and an uprising far more nuanced than most accounts suggest)

– succeeded because not even the tsar’s personal guard, let alone such

formerly reliable supports of the autocracy as the Cossacks, was

prepared to defend the monarchy. Indeed, in revolutionary Barcelona in

1936, the resistance to Franco’s forces was initiated by only a few

thousand anarcho-syndicalists with the aid of the Assault Guards, whose

discipline, weaponry, and training were indispensable factors in pinning

down and ultimately defeating the regular army’s uprising.

It is such constellations of forces, in fact, that explain how

revolutions actually succeed. They do not triumph because “everyone,” or

even a majority of the population, actively participates in overthrowing

an oppressive regime, but because the armed forces of the old order and

the population at large are no longer willing to defend it against a

militant and resolute minority.

Nor it is likely, however desirable it may be, that after a successful

insurrection the great majority of the people or even of the oppressed

will personally participate in revolutionizing society. Following the

success of a revolution, the majority of people tend to withdraw into

the localities in which they live, however large or small, where the

problems of everyday life have their most visible impact on the masses.

These localities may be residential and/or occupational neighborhoods in

large cities, the environs of villages and hamlets, or even at some

distance from the center of a city or region, fairly dispersed

localities in which people live and work.

In short, I fail to see why the large size of modern cities should

constitute an insuperable obstacle to the formation of a neighborhood

assembly movement. The doors of the neighborhood assemblies should

always be open to whoever lives in the neighborhood. Politically less

aware individuals may choose not to attend their neighborhood assembly,

and they should not be obliged to attend. The assemblies, regardless of

their size, will have problems enough, without having to deal with

indifferent bystanders and passersby. What counts is that the doors of

the assemblies remain open for all who wish to attend and participate,

for therein lies the true democratic nature of neighborhood assemblies.

Another criticism I have heard against libertarian municipalism is that

a forceful speaker or faction may manipulate a large crowd, such as

numerous citizens at an assembly meeting. This philistine criticism

could be directed against any democratic institution, be it a large

assembly, a small committee, an ad hoc conference or meeting, or even an

“affinity” group. In my view, such a transparent effort to inflict

bruises on any attempt to create a popular organization hardly deserves

discussion. The size of the group is not a factor here – some very

abusive tyrannies appear in very small groups, where one or two

intimidating figures can completely dominate everyone else.

What the critics might well ask – but seldom do – is how we are to

prevent persuasive individuals from making demagogic attempts to control

any popular assembly, regardless of size. In my view the only obstacle

to such attempts is the existence of an organized body of

revolutionaries – yes, even a faction – that is committed to seeking

truth, exercising rationality, and advancing an ethics of public

responsibility. Such a faction or organization will be needed, in my

view, not only before and during a revolution but also after one, when

the constructive problem of creating stable, enduring, and educational

democratic institutions becomes the order of the day.

Such an organization will be particularly needed during the period of

social reconstruction, when attempts are made to put libertarian

municipalism into practice. We cannot expect that, just because we

propose the establishment of neighborhood assemblies, we will always –

or perhaps even often – be the majority in the very institutions that we

have significantly helped to establish. We must always be prepared, in

fact, to be in the minority, until such time as circumstances and social

instability make our overall messages plausible to assembly majorities.

Class And Trans-Class Issues

Indeed, wherever we establish a popular assembly, with or without legal

legitimacy, it will eventually be invaded by competing class interests.

Libertarian municipalism, I should emphasize here, is not an attempt to

overlook or evade the reality of class conflict; on the contrary, it

attempts, among other things, to give due recognition to the class

struggle’s civic dimension. Modern conflicts between classes have never

been confined simply to the factory or workplace; they have also taken a

distinctly urban form, as in “Revolutionary Paris,” “Red Petrograd,” and

“Anarcho-syndicalist Barcelona.” As any study of the great revolutions

vividly reveals, the battle between classes has always been a battle not

only between different economic strata in society but also within and

between neighborhoods.

Moreover, the neighborhood, town, and village also generates searing

issues that cut across class lines: between working people (the

traditional industrial proletariat, which is now dwindling in numbers in

Europe and the United States and is fighting a rearguard battle with

capital), middle-class strata (which lack any consciousness of

themselves as working people), the vast army of government employees, a

huge professional and technical stratum that is not likely to regard

itself as a proletariat, and an underclass that is essentially

demoralized and helpless.

We cannot ignore the compelling fact that capitalism has changed since

the end of the World War Two; that it has transformed the very social

fiber of the great majority of people, both attitudinally and

occupationally, in Western Europe and the United States; that it will

wreak even further changes in the decades that lie ahead, with dazzling

rapidity, especially as automation is further developed and as new

resources, techniques, and products replace those that seem so dominant

today.

No revolutionary movement can ignore the problems that capitalism is

likely to generate in the years that lie ahead, especially in terms of

capital’s profound effects on both society and the environment. The

futility of syndicalism today lies in the fact that it is still trying

to address the problems generated by the old Industrial Revolution, and

in the context of the social setting that gave these problems meaning in

the first half of the twentieth century. If we have historically

exhausted the syndicalist alternative, it is because the industrial

proletariat is everywhere destined, by virtue of technological

innovation, to become a small minority of the population. It will not do

to try to theoretically fabricate a “proletariat” out of clerical,

service, and professional “workers” who, in many if not most cases, will

not acquire the class consciousness that identified and gave a

historical standing to the authentic proletarian.

But these strata, often among the most exploited and oppressed, can be

enlisted to support our communalist ideals on the basis of the larger

environment in which they live and the larger issues of their

sovereignty in a world that is racing out of control: namely their

neighborhoods, cities, and towns, and the expansion of their democratic

rights as free citizens in a world that has reduced them to mere

electoral constituents. They can be mobilized to support our communalist

ideals because they feel their power to control their own lives is

diminishing in the face of centralized state and corporate power.

Needless to say, I am not denying that working people have grim economic

problems that may pit them against capital, but their quasi-middle-class

outlook if not status diminishes their ability to see the ills of

capitalism exclusively as an economic system.

Today we live in an era of permanent industrial revolution in which

people tend to respond to the extreme rapidity and vast scope of change

with a mysticism that expresses their disempowerment and a privatism

that expresses their inability to contend with change. Indeed,

capitalism, far from being “advanced,” still less “moribund,” continues

to mature and extend its scope. What it will look like half a century or

a century from now is open to the boldest of speculations.

Hence, more than ever, any revolutionary left libertarian movement must,

in my view, recognize the importance of the municipality as the locus of

new, indeed often trans-class problems that cannot simply be reduced to

the struggle between wage labor and capital. Real problems of

environmental deterioration affect everyone in a community; real

problems of social and economic inequities affect everyone in a

community; real problems of health, education, sanitary conditions, and

the nightmare, as Paul Goodman put it, of “growing up absurd” plague

everyone in a community – problems that are even more serious today than

they were in the alienated 1960s decade. These trans-class issues can

bring people together with workers of all kinds in a common effort to

seek their self-empowerment, an issue that cannot be resolved into the

conflict of wage labor against capital alone.

Nor are workers mere “agents” of history, as vulgar Marxists (and

implicitly, syndicalists) would have us believe. Workers live in cities,

towns, and villages – not only as class beings but also as civic beings.

They are fathers and mothers, brothers and sisters, friends and

comrades, and no less than their ecological counterparts among the petty

bourgeoisie, they are concerned with environmental issues. As parents

and young people, they are concerned with the problems of acquiring an

education, entering a profession, and the like. They are deeply

disturbed by the decay of urban infrastructures, the diminution of

inexpensive housing, and issues of urban safety and aesthetics. Their

horizon extends far beyond the realm of the factory or even the office

to the residential urban world in which they and their families live.

After I had spent years working in factories, I was not surprised to

find that I could reach workers, middle-class people, and even

relatively affluent individuals more easily by discussing issues

relating to their lived environments – their neighborhoods and cities –

rather than to their workplaces.

Today, in particular, the globalization of capital raises the question

of how localities can keep productive resources within their own

confines without impairing the opportunities of peoples in the so-called

“Third World” or South to freely develop technologically according to

their own needs. This conundrum cannot be resolved by legislation and

economic reforms. Capitalism is a compulsively expansive system. A

modern market economy dictates that an enterprise must grow or die, and

nothing will prevent capitalism from industrializing – more accurately,

expanding – endlessly over the entire face of the planet whenever it is

prepared to do so. Only the complete reconstruction of society and the

economy can end the dilemmas that globalization raises, including the

one-sided economic development of the South, often at the expense of

workers in the North, and the enhancement of corporate power to the

point of threatening the stability, indeed the very safety, of the

planet.

Here again, I would contend that only a grassroots economic policy,

based on a libertarian municipalist agenda and movement, can offer a

major alternative – and it is precisely an alternative that many people

seek today – capable of arresting the impact of globalization. For the

problem of globalization, there is no global solution. Global capital,

precisely because of its very hugeness, can only be eaten away at its

roots, specifically by means of a libertarian municipalist resistance at

the base of society. It must be eroded by the myriad millions who,

mobilized by a grassroots movement, challenge global capital’s

sovereignty over their lives and try to develop local and regional

economic alternatives to its industrial operations. Developing this

resistance would involve subsidizing municipally controlled industries

and retail outlets, and taking recourse to regional resources that

capital does not find it profitable to use. A municipalized economy,

slow as it may be in the making, will be a moral economy, one that –

concerned primarily with the quality of its products and their

production at the lowest possible cost – can hope to ultimately subvert

a corporate economy, whose success is measured entirely by its profits

rather than by the quality of its commodities.

Let me stress that when I speak of a moral economy, I am not advocating

a communitarian or cooperative economy in which small profiteers,

however well-meaning their intentions may be, simply become little

“self-managed” capitalists in their own right. In my own community I

have seen a self-styled “moral” enterprise, Ben and Jerry’s Ice Cream,

grow in typical capitalist fashion from a small, presumably “caring,”

and intimate enterprise into a global corporation, intent on making

profit and fostering the myth that “capitalism can be good.”

Cooperatives that profess to be moral in their intentions have yet to

make any headway in replacing big capitalist concerns or even in

surviving without themselves becoming capitalistic in their methods and

profit-oriented in their goals.

The Proudhonist myth that small associations of producers – as opposed

to a genuinely socialistic or libertarian communistic endeavor – can

slowly eat away at capitalism, should finally be dispelled. Sadly, these

generally failed illusions are still promoted by liberals such as Harry

Boyte and by naive lifestyle anarchists such as the journalistic

ruffians at Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, and pure academics such

as John Clark and his associates. Either municipalized enterprises

controlled by citizens’ assemblies will try to take over the economy, or

capitalism will prevail in this sphere of life with a forcefulness that

no mere rhetoric can diminish.

Capitalist society has effects not only on economic and social relations

but on ideas and intellectual traditions as well, indeed, on all of

history, fragmenting them until knowledge, discourse, and even reality

become blurred, divested of any distinctions, specificity, and

articulation. The culture that promotes this celebration of diffuseness

and fragmentation – a culture that is epidemic in American colleges and

universities – goes under the name of poststructuralism or, more

commonly, postmodernism. Given its corrosive precepts, the postmodernist

worldview is able to level or homogenize everything that is unique or

distinctive, dissolving it into a low common denominator of ideas.

Consider, for example, the obscurantist term “earth citizenship,” which

dissolves the very complex notion of “citizenship,” with its

presuppositions of paideia – that is, the lifelong education of the

citizen for the practice of civic self-management – into a diffuse

category, by extending (and cheapening) the notion of citizenship to

include animals, plants, rocks, mountains, the planet, indeed the very

cosmos itself. With a purely metaphorical label for all relationships as

an “earth community,” the historical and contemporary uniqueness of the

city disappears. It presumably preempts every other community because of

its wider scope and breadth. Such metaphors ultimately flatten

everything, in effect, into a universal “Oneness” that, in the name of

“ecological wisdom,” denies definition to vital concepts and realities

by the very ubiquity of the “One.”

If the word “citizen” applies to every existing thing, and if the word

“community” embraces all relationships in this seemingly “green” world,

then nothing, in fact, is a citizen or a community. Just as the logical

category “Being” is rendered as mere existence, Being can only be

regarded as interchangeable with “Nothing.” So, too, “citizen” and

“community” become a universal passport to vacuity, not to uniquely

civic conditions that have been forming and differentiating

dialectically for thousands of years, through the ancient, medieval, and

modern worlds. To reduce them to an abstract “community” is to

ultimately negate their wealth of evolutionary forms and particularly

their differentiation as sophisticated aspects of human freedom.

Challenges for Our Movements

As a revolutionary politics, libertarian municipalism must nonetheless

be conceived as a process, a patient practice that will probably have

only limited success at the present time, and even then only in select

areas that can at best provide examples of the possibilities it could

hold if and when it is adopted on a large scale. We will not create a

libertarian municipalist society overnight, and in this era of

counter-revolution we must be prepared to endure more failures than

successes. Patience and commitment are traits that revolutionaries of

the past cultivated assiduously; alas today, in our fast consumerist

society, the demand for immediate gratification, for fast food and fast

living, inculcates a demand for fast politics. Individuals who are prone

to adopt a fast lifestyle over one that acknowledges the need for slow

growth, with all its disappointments, would do well to learn the art of

throwing bricks and painting graffiti rather than commit themselves to

the educational responsibilities required by a libertarian municipalist

movement. What should count for us is whether libertarian municipalism

is a rational means for achieving the rational culmination of human

development, not whether it is suitable as a quick fix for present

social problems.

We must learn to be flexible without allowing our basic principles to be

replaced by a postmodernist quagmire of ad hoc, ever-changeable

opinions. For example, if we have no choice but to use electronic means,

such as to establish popular participation in relatively large citizens’

assemblies, then so be it. But we should, I would argue, do so only when

it is unavoidable and for only as long as is necessary. By the same

token, if certain desirable measures require a degree of centralization,

then we should accept that – without sacrificing, let me insist, the

right to immediate recall. But here, too, we should endure such

organizational measures for only as long as they are necessary and no

longer. Our basic principles in such cases must always be our guide: we

remain committed to a direct face-to-face democracy and a

well-coordinated, confederal, but decentralized society.

Nor should we fetishize consensus over democracy in our decision-making

processes. Consensus, as I have argued, is practicable with very small

groups in which people know each other intimately. But in larger groups

it becomes tyrannical because it allows a small minority to decide what

will be the practice of a large or even sizable majority; and it fosters

homogeneity and stagnation in ideas and policies. Minorities and their

factions are the indispensable yeast for maturing new ideas – and nearly

all new ideas start out as the views of minorities. In a libertarian

group, the “rule” of the majority over a minority is a myth; no one

expects a minority to give up its unpopular beliefs or to yield its

right to argue its views – but the minority must have patience and allow

a majority decision to be put into practice. This experience and the

discussion it generates should be the most decisive element in impelling

a group or assembly to reconsider its decision and adopt the minority’s

viewpoint, spurring on the further innovation of practices and ideas as

other minorities emerge. Consensus decision-making can easily produce

intellectual and practical stagnation if it essentially compels a

majority to forgo a specific policy in order to please a minority.

I will not enter here into my distinction between policy decisions and

their enactment in practice by those qualified to administer them. I

will only note something that my friend Gary Sisco has pointed out: that

if the US Congress – a gathering, for the most part, of lawyers – can

make basic policy decisions on the reconstruction of the American

infrastructure, on war and peace, on education and foreign policy, etc.,

without having full knowledge of all aspects of these fields, leaving

the administration of their decisions to others, then it is difficult to

understand why a citizens’ assembly cannot make policy decisions on

usually more modest issues and leave their administration, under close

supervision, to experts in the fields involved.

Among the other issues we must at some point consider are the place of

law or nomos in a libertarian municipalist society, as well as

constitutions that lay down important principles of right or justice and

freedom. Are we to vest the perpetuation of our guiding principles

simply in blind custom, or in the good nature of our fellow humans –

which allows for a great deal of arbitrariness? For centuries oppressed

peoples demanded written founding constitutional provisions to protect

them from arbitrary oppression by the nobility. With the emergence of a

libertarian communist society, this problem does not disappear. For us,

I believe, the question can never be whether law and constitutions are

inherently “authoritarian,” but whether they are rational, mutable,

secular, and restrictive only in the sense that they prohibit the abuse

of power.

Admittedly, the present time is not one that is favorable for the spread

of revolutionary and libertarian anti-capitalist ideas and movements.

Unless we are to let the capitalist cancer spread over the entire

planet, however, absorbing even the natural world into the world

economy, we must develop a theory and practice that provides us with an

entry into the public sphere – a theory and practice, I should

emphasize, that is consistent with the goal of a rational libertarian

communist society.

Finally, we must assert the historic right of speculative reason –

resting on the real potentialities of human beings as we know them from

the past as well as the present – to project itself beyond the immediate

environment in which we live, indeed, to claim that the present

irrational society is not the actual – or “real” – that is worthy of the

human condition. Despite its prevalence – and, to many people, its

permanence – the present society is untrue to the project of fulfilling

humanity’s potentiality for freedom and self-consciousness, and hence it

is unreal in the sense that it is a betrayal of the claims of humanity’s

greatest qualities, the capacity for reason and innovation.

If our attempts to think, fight for, educate people about, and rise in

battle for, a libertarian communist society based on the Commune of

communes, are evidence of “Bakuninist will,” for which present-day

mystics such as John Clark (aka “Max Cafard” or “C”) have criticized me,

then I can only reply that I find all the more flattering this

association with Bakunin, who would have denounced Clark’s Taoist

notions of passivity and “going with the flow” as a fundamental

accommodation to the status quo. Libertarian municipalists must

distinguish themselves from those who, in the name of organic thought,

reduce themselves to bystanders, their behavior guided by the Taoist

doctrine of “wu-wei,” that is, the “virtues” of non-action.

By the same token, that broad school of ideas we call “anarchism” is

faced with a parting of the ways between those who genuinely wish to

focus their efforts on the revolutionary elimination of hierarchical and

class society, and self-indulgent lifestyle anarchists who, if they

believe in anything beyond mere adventures (say, throwing bricks at

police), see social change only in terms of their personal

self-expression and the replacement of serious ideas with mystical

fantasies.

Left libertarian revolutionaries cannot have any hopes of creating a

public movement unless they formulate a politics that opens it to social

intervention, indeed that is brought into the public sphere as an

organized movement that can grow, think rationally, mobilize people, and

actively seek to change the world. The social democrats have offered us

parliamentary reforms as a practice, and the results they have produced

have been debilitating – most notably, a radical decline in public life

and a disastrous growth in consumerist self-indulgence and privatism.

Although the Stalinists as architects of the totalitarian state have

mostly passed from the public scene, a few persist as parasites on

whatever radical movement may emerge among oppressed peoples. And

fascism, in its various mutations, has attempted to fill the void

created by disempowerment and a lack of human scale in politics as well

as community, with tragic results.

As left libertarians we must ask ourselves what mode of entry into the

public sphere is consistent with our vision of empowerment. If our ideal

is the Commune of communes, then I submit that the only means of entry

and social fulfillment is a politics – that is, a movement and program

that finally emerges on the local electoral scene as the uncompromising

advocate of popular neighborhood and town assemblies and the development

of a municipalized economy. I know of no other alternative to

capitulation to the existing society – unless some among us wish to

throw rocks at police, deface walls with graffiti, or engage in ad hoc

“actions” that disappear without any trace like a pebble thrown into a

lake.

I have no doubt that libertarian municipalism, if it meets with a

measure of success, will face many obstacles and the possibility of

being co-opted or degenerated; that it will face not only a civic realm

of ideological discord but internal discord within its own

organizational framework; and that it opens a broad field of political

conflict, with all its risks and uncertainties. At a time when social

life has been trivialized beyond description, when accommodation to

capitalist values and life-ways has reached unprecedented levels, when

anarchism and socialism are seen as the “lost causes” of the nineteenth

and early twentieth centuries – one can only hope that such discord

becomes a genuine public reality. At no time has mediocrity been more

triumphant than it is today, and at no time has indifference to social

and political issues been as widespread.

I do not believe that social change can be achieved without taking

risks, allowing for uncertainties, and recognizing the possibility of

failure. If we are to have any effect on the fossilization of public

life – to the extent that the present period is marked in any sense by a

genuine public life – history too must move with us. On this score, I am

much too old to make worthwhile predictions about how the course of

events will unfold, except to say that the present, whether for good or

ill, will hardly be recognizable to the generation that will come of age

50 years from now, so rapidly are things likely to change in the present

century.

But where change exists, so too do possibilities. The times cannot

remain as they are – any more than the world can be frozen into

immobility. What we can hope to do is to preserve the thread of

rationality that distinguishes true civilization from barbarism – and

barbarism would indeed be the outcome of a world that is permitted to

tumble into a future without rational activity or guidance. For those

who will a world of freedom and self-consciousness, there can be no

accommodation with the status quo.

The Future of the Left

By the beginning of the twentieth century, the Left had reached an

extraordinary degree of conceptual sophistication and organizational

maturity. Generally what was called leftism at that time was socialist,

influenced in varying degrees by the works of Karl Marx. This was

especially the case in Central Europe, but socialism was also intermixed

with populist ideas in Eastern Europe and with syndicalism in France,

Spain, and Latin America. In the United States all of these ideas were

melded together, such as in Eugene V. Debs’s Socialist Party and in the

Industrial Workers of the World (IWW).

On the eve of World War One leftist ideas and movements had become so

advanced that they seemed positioned to seriously challenge the

existence of capitalism, indeed, of class society as such. The words

from the Internationale, “Tis the final conflict,” acquired a new

concreteness and immediacy. Capitalism seemed faced with an insurgency

by the world’s exploited classes, particularly the industrial

proletariat. Indeed, given the scope of the Second International and the

growth of revolutionary movements in the West, capitalism appeared to be

facing an unprecedented, international social upheaval. Many

revolutionaries were convinced that a politically mature and

well-organized proletariat could finally take conscious control over

social life and evolution and satisfy, not the particularized elitist

interests of a propertied minority class, but the general interests of

the majority.

The “Great War,” as it was called, actually did end amid socialistic

revolutions. Russia established a “proletarian dictatorship,” premised

ostensibly on revolutionary Marxist principles. Germany, with the

largest and most ideologically advanced industrial proletariat in

Europe, went through three years of Marxist-influenced revolutionary

upheaval, while Bavaria, Hungary, and other places experienced

short-lived insurgencies. In Italy and Spain, the end of the war saw the

emergence of great strike movements and near-insurrections, although

they never reached a decisive revolutionary level. Even France seemed to

be teetering on revolution in 1917, when entire regiments at the Western

Front raised red flags and tried to make their way to Paris. Such

upheavals, which recurred into the 1930s, appeared to support Lenin’s

view that a “moribund” capitalism had finally entered into a period of

war and revolution, one that in the foreseeable future could end only

with the establishment of a socialist or communist society.

From Classicism to Decadence

By this time, moreover, major intellectual innovators – from Diderot and

Rousseau through Hegel and Marx to an assortment of libertarian rebels –

had brought secular and radical ideologies to a point where, sorted into

a logical whole, they provided the framework for a truly coherent body

of ideas that gave a rational meaning to historical development,

combining a due recognition of humanity’s material needs with its hopes

for intellectual and social emancipation. For the first time, it seemed,

without recourse to divine or other archaic non-human forms of

intervention, humanity would finally be able to draw upon its own

advancing intellectuality, knowledge, and virtues, and upon its unique

capacity for innovation, to create a new world in which all the

conditions would exist to actualize its potentiality for freedom and

creativity. These eminently human goals, embodied in Marx’s great

theoretical synthesis of the ideas he had drawn from the Enlightenment

as well as new ideas he had developed on his own, could be initiated in

practice by the downtrodden themselves, who would be driven inexorably

by the contradictions of capitalist society into revolution and the

establishment of a rational society for humanity as a whole.

I should note that many of my own words – “inexorably,” “moribund,”

“decaying,” and “general interests” – are drawn from the literature of

early twentieth-century leftist theorists and movements. Yet whatever

may be the limits of this literature and its writers – as we, at the

turn of the millennium, are now privileged to see in retrospect – this

sweeping language was not the product of mere sloganeering: it was

derived from an integrated and coherent leftist outlook and culture that

appeared on the eve of the Great War. This outlook and culture formed

what we can properly call a classical body of universalist ideas,

continually enlarged by the generations that followed the French

Revolution of 1789 to 1794. In the years that passed, this body of ideas

was steadily enlarged by experience and succeeded in mobilizing millions

of people into international movements for human emancipation and social

reconstruction.

Quite obviously, the Enlightenment goals and Lenin’s prognoses, with

their promise of successful socialist revolutions, were not to be

realized in the twentieth century. Indeed, what has occurred since the

midpoint of the twentieth century is a very different development: a

period of cultural and theoretical decadence so far as revolutionary

ideas and movements are concerned – a period of decomposition, in fact,

that has swept up nearly all the philosophical, cultural, ethical, and

social standards that the Enlightenment had produced. For many young

people who professed to hold a radical outlook in the 1960s and 1970s,

leftist theory has shriveled in scope and content to the level of

spectatorial esthetics, often focused on the scattered works of people

like the indecisive critic Walter Benjamin, the postmodernist Jacques

Derrida, or the constipated structuralist Louis Althusser, as social

theory has retreated from the lusty debating forums of 1930s socialism

to the cloistered seminar rooms of contemporary universities.

Now that the twentieth century has come to a close, we are justified in

asking: Why has humanity’s emancipation failed to achieve fruition? Why,

in particular, has the proletariat failed to make its predicted

revolution? Indeed, why did the once-radical Social Democrats fail from

their very inception to achieve even a majority vote in such centers as

Germany? Why did they, in 1933, surrender so tamely to Hitler? (The

German Communists, of course, were simply shunted aside after 1923,

assuming they could even be taken seriously in that year, except as

contrived targets for demagogic propagandistic purposes to frighten the

middle classes with the menace of social disorder.)

How, moreover, did capitalism manage to free itself from the “chronic

economic crisis” in which it seemed hopelessly mired during the 1930s?

Why, especially after World War Two, did it produce advances in technics

so dazzling that bourgeois society is now undergoing a permanent

“Industrial Revolution” whose results are difficult to foresee? Finally,

why did it come to pass that, following the profound economic and social

crises of the 1930s, capitalism emerged from a second world war as a

more stable and more socially entrenched order than it had ever been in

the past?

None of these events, so important in the predictive calculations of

revolutionary Marxists, have been adequately explained in a fundamental

and historical sense, notably the progressive role that Marx assigned to

capitalism in his “stages theory” of history.[35] Instead, for years

Marxists largely expended their polemical energy in throwing epithets at

each other and at other labor movements for their “betrayals” – without

asking why Marxism was so vulnerable to betrayal in the first place. In

more recent years Marxists have tried to appropriate fragments of ideas

that belong to once-despised utopian ideologies, such as Fourierism

(Marcuse, to cite only one example) or to other alien ideologies, such

as syndicalism, anarchism, ecology, feminism, and communitarianism,

appropriating ill-fitting ideological tenets from one or the other to

refurbish their limited view of a changing bourgeois reality, until what

passes for Marxism today is often a pastiche of fragments patched

together with planks from basically alien ideologies.

How, in short, did it come to pass that the classical era, marked by its

coherence and unity in revolutionary thought and practice, gave way to a

completely decadent era in which incoherence is celebrated, particularly

in the name of a postmodernism that equates chaotic nihilism with

freedom, self-expression, and creativity – not unlike the chaos of the

marketplace itself?

Moribund or Mature Capitalism?

We can answer these questions because we now enjoy over a half-century

of hindsight. What the past fifty years have shown us is that the

uniquely insurgent period between 1917 and 1939 was not evidence of

capitalist morbidity and decline, as Lenin surmised. Rather, it was a

period of social transition. During those decades the world was so torn

by circumstantially created tensions that Lenin’s view of capitalism as

a dying social order seemed indeed confirmed by reality.

What this classical prognosis and its supporting theoretical corpus did

not take into account were various alternative developments that faced

capitalism before the outbreak of the Great War and even during the

interwar period – alternatives that lay beneath the tumultuous surface

of the early twentieth century. The classical Left did not consider

other possible social trajectories that capitalism could have followed –

and eventually did follow – that would make for its stabilization. It

not only failed to understand these new social trajectories but also

failed to foresee, even faintly, the emergence of new issues that

extended beyond the largely worker-oriented analysis of the classical

Left.

For one thing, what makes so much of the classical revolutionary

prognoses formulated by prewar and wartime socialism seem paradoxical is

that the “moribund” period in which many classical leftists anchored

their hopes for revolution was still not even a period of “mature”

capitalism, let alone one of “dying” capitalism. The era before the

Great War was one in which mass production, republican systems of

government, and so-called “bourgeois-democratic” liberties were still

emerging from a chrysalis of precapitalist forms of craft production and

commerce, state structures ruled by royal families and courts, and

economies in which ennobled landlords such as the German Junkers,

British aristocrats, and Latin Grandees coexisted with a huge,

technically backward peasant population. Even where most great estates

were owned by bourgeois elements, as in Spain, their management of

agriculture was conducted lethargically, emulating the diffident

economic habits that characterized parasitic agrarian elites of a

precapitalist era. Capitalism, while it was the dominant economy of the

United States, Great Britain, Germany, more ambiguously France, and only

marginally in other European countries, was still subordinated

culturally and even structurally to elite strata, often based on

kinship, that were more feudal than bourgeois, and marked by the rentier

and militaristic values that distinguished a waning era.

In effect, even modern industry, while becoming central to the

development of major nation-states in the early twentieth century, was

still anchored in a craft-peasant social matrix. The ownership of land

and of small-scale workshops, often family managed, formed the

traditional features of social status in a very status-ridden world,

such as England and Germany. It is hard to recall today how low was the

real status of women during the early 1900s; how degraded was the status

of propertyless, often mendicant workers; how eagerly even substantial

capitalists tried to marry into titled families; how feeble were

elementary civil liberties in a world that acknowledged the validity of

inherited privilege and the authority of monarchs; and how embattled was

the industrially regimented proletariat (often removed by a generation

or two from village life with its more natural life-ways) in its efforts

to merely organize reformist trade unions.

The Great War – a monstrous event that was as much, if not more, the

product of dynastic ambitions, military obtuseness, and the awesome

authority allowed to preening monarchs, as it was of economic

imperialism – was not a “historical necessity.” An entangled Europe,

caught up in Kaiser Wilhelm II’s juvenile posturing and dizzying images

of German national grandeur, the blind spirit of French revanchisme

following the country’s loss of Alsace and Lorraine in 1871 to the

Wilhelmine Reich, and the naive nationalism of the masses, whose class

internationalism was often more rhetorical than real – all led to a

horrible form of trench warfare that should have been unendurable to any

civilized people within a few months after it fell into place, let alone

for four bloody years. The Deutsche Mark, the emblematic expression of

German capitalism, managed to perform economic prodigies that neither

Wilhelm’s nor Hitler’s bayonets could hope to perform during the last

century – so different are the alternatives that the postwar era finally

revealed!

Yet, ironically, it was not the battlefront in the Great War that

generated the revolutions of 1917–18; it was the rear, where hunger

managed to do what the terrifying explosives, machine guns, tanks, and

poison gas at the front never quite succeeded in achieving – a

revolution over issues such as bread and peace (in precisely that

order). It is breathtaking to consider that, after three years of

constant bloodletting, mutilation, and incredible daily fear, the German

strikes of January 1918 that had the pungent odor of revolution actually

subsided, and the German workers remained patiently quiescent when

General Ludendorff’s spring and summer offensives of that year gained

substantial ground from French and British troops in the West to the

“greater glory” of the Reich. So much for the “revolutionary instincts”

of the people, which Bakunin was wont to celebrate. It speaks volumes

that, despite the horrors of the Great War, the masses went along with

the conflict until it was completely unendurable materially. Such is the

power of adaptation, tradition, and habit in everyday life.

A Period of Transition

Notwithstanding the Russian Revolution, the Great War came to an end

without overthrowing European capitalism, let alone world capitalism.

The war actually revealed that the classical tradition of socialism was

very limited and, in many respects, was greatly in need of repair.

Understandably, Lenin and Trotsky tried to foreshorten historical

development and bring about the likelihood of socialism within their own

life spans, although this is less true of Luxemburg and particularly of

Marx, who was far more critical of Marxism than his acolytes. Indeed,

Marx was at pains to warn that it had taken centuries for feudalism to

die and for capitalism to emerge, hence Marxists should hardly expect

that the bourgeoisie would be overthrown in a year, a decade, or even a

generation. Trotsky was far more sanguine than Lenin in his conviction

that capitalism was “moribund,” “decaying,” “rotting,” and otherwise

falling apart, and that the proletariat was growing “stronger,” or “more

class conscious,” or “organized” – but it matters little today to dwell

on his expectations and prognoses.

Nevertheless the Great War – while not completely sweeping the

historical slate clean of the feudal detritus that contributed so

greatly to its outbreak – left the Western world in a cultural, moral,

and political stupor. An era was clearly ending, but it was not

capitalism that was faced with imminent oblivion. What was disappearing

was the traditional, time-worn status and class system of a feudal past,

yet without any fully developed form of capitalism to take its place.

With the Great Depression, British landlordism began to enter into hard,

even devastating times, but it had not completely disappeared during the

1930s. The Prussian Junkers were still in command of the German army at

the beginning of the 1930s and, thanks to von Hindenburg’s election as

president of the German state, still enjoyed many of the privileges of

an established elite early in the Hitler period. But this once haughty

stratum was eventually faced with the challenge of Hitler’s

Gleichschaltung, the process of social leveling that finally degraded

the Prussian officer caste. In the end, it was the Anglo-American and

Russian armies that swept the Junkers away by seizing their estates in

the East and dissolving them as a socio-economic entity. France was

fighting its last battles as a middle-class republic during the mid

1930s, with Catholic reactionaries and the blooded young fascists of the

Croix de Feu, who aspired to an aristocratic Gallicism led by rich and

titled leaders.

Thus, the interwar decades were a stormy period of transition between a

declining quasi-feudal world, already shattered but not buried, and an

emerging bourgeois world, which, despite its vast economic power, had

still not penetrated into every pore of society and defined the basic

values of the century. The Great Depression, in fact, showed that the

pedestrian maxim, “money isn’t everything,” is true when there is no

money to go around. Indeed, the Depression threw much of the world,

especially the United States, into a disorderly world that resembled its

own hectic populist era of the 1870s and 1880s, hence the flare-up of

trade unionism, violent strikes, great demonstrations, and “Red”

agitation that swept over the American and European continents in the

1930s.

In this socially hyperactive but indecisive period of social tensions

between the old and new, when the ruling classes as well as the

dominated masses lived in murderous antipathy toward each other, history

unlocked the door to revolutionary upheavals. Amid the uncertainty of a

tension-filled world, the fulfillment of Marx’s dream – a democratic

workers’ system of government – seemed achievable. As a result of the

tensions that existed within that interwar period, it appeared that

capitalism had collapsed economically and a worldwide movement toward a

democratic, possibly libertarian socialist society was achievable. But

to create such a society required a highly conscious movement with an

able leadership and a clear-eyed sense of purpose.

Tragically, no such movement appeared. Grossly pragmatic bureaucrats

such as Friedrich Ebert and Philip Scheidemann, and pedestrian theorists

such as Karl Kautsky and Rudolf Hilferding, assumed the deflated mantle

of the Socialist International and set its tone up until the rise of

German fascism. Shortly afterward Stalin intervened in every potentially

revolutionary situation in Europe and poisoned it to serve Russia’s –

and his own – interests. The prestige of the Bolshevik revolution, to

which this tyrant contributed absolutely nothing and which he defamed

when he came to power, was still not sufficiently sullied to allow the

classical Left to create its own authentic movements and expand its

vision to accord with emerging social issues that reflected changes in

capitalism itself.

What must now be acknowledged is that between 1914 and 1945 capitalism

was enlarging its foundations with mass manufacture and new industries,

not digging its grave, as Lenin and Trotsky had opined. Its status as a

dominant world economy and society still lay before it in 1917, not

behind it. And it would be sheer myopia not to see that it is still

industrializing the world – the agrarian as well as the urban – which is

basically what the word “globalization” means. Moreover, it is still

eroding the particularisms that divide human beings on the basis of

nationalism, religion, and ethnicity. Most of the “fundamentalisms” and

“identity politics” erupting in the world today are essentially

reactions against the encroaching secularism and universalism of a

business-oriented, increasingly homogenizing capitalist civilization

that is slowly eating away at a deeply religious, nationalistic, and

ethnic heritage. The commodity is still performing prodigies of social

erosion in precapitalist cultures, be they for good or bad, such as Marx

and Engels described in the first part of The Communist Manifesto. Where

sanity and reason do not guide human affairs, to be sure, the good is

nearly always polluted by the bad, and it is the function of any serious

revolutionary thinker to separate the two in the hope of unearthing the

rational tendency in a social development.

At the same time capitalism is not only homogenizing old societies and

remaking them in its urbanized, commodity-oriented image; it is doing

the same to the planet and the biosphere in the name of “mastering” the

forces of the natural world. This is precisely the “historically

progressive” role that Marx and Engels assigned, in a celebratory

manner, to the capitalist mode of production. How “progressive” this

process of homogenization is, in fact, remains to be seen. For the

present, it behooves us to examine the failure of Marxism and anarchism

(arguably the two principal wings of the revolutionary tradition) to

deal with the transitional nature of the twentieth century.

Assessing The Revolutionary Tradition

In the post-World War Two period the weakest elements in Marx’s schema

of history, class struggle, capitalist development, and political

activity have been subjected to penetrating critical examination.[36]

The Marxian canon to the contrary, history, viewed as a whole, cannot be

reduced to economic factors as Marx tried to do in his key works,

although capitalism may well be mutating homo sapiens into homo

consumerans and fostering the tendency among masses of people to

experience reality as a huge market. Marx’s basic views may have

provided his acolytes with the necessary or preconditional causes for

social development – admittedly material or economic causes – but they

failed to explain the enormous role of the efficient causes – the

immediate causes, such as culture, politics, morality, juridical

practices, and the like (which Marx denoted as a “superstructural”) –

for producing social change.

Indeed, what else besides “superstructural” (particularly moral,

religious, and political) factors can explain why the development of

capitalism, which always existed in varying degrees in agrarian and

craft economies, was arrested for thousands of years and became a major

economy in only one country (England) early in the nineteenth century?

Or why revolutions occur only under conditions of complete social

breakdown, that is, after a vast body of massively influential

“superstructural” belief systems (often accepted in their time as

eternal realities) are shattered? Marx was not oblivious to the extent

to which belief-systems override bourgeois forces in precapitalist

societies, especially in his discussions on the predominance of agrarian

values over urban ones in his Grundrisse. Very significantly, Marxists

were riddled by conflicts over the status of capitalism at various

points in its development, especially during the early twentieth

century, when the bourgeoisie faced one of the stormiest periods of its

history – precisely because capitalism had not fully shed the trappings

of feudalism and come “completely into its own,” so to speak.

How, for example, was it possible for many Marxists to insist that

capitalism was in decline at a time when major technical innovations

like mass manufacture, radically new forms of transportation such as the

automobile, advances in electrical and electronic machines and goods,

and new chemical innovations were occurring in the decade directly

following the Great War? Had Marx not written, after all, that “No

social order ever perishes before all the productive forces [technology]

for which there is room in it have developed”?[37] Could this be said of

capitalism in 1914–18 and 1939–45? Indeed, will it ever be said of the

capitalist mode of production in the future?

In asking these questions, I am not trying to suggest that capitalism

will never produce problems that necessitate its overthrow or

replacement. My purpose is, rather, to suggest that the problems that

may well turn most of humanity against capitalism may not necessarily be

strictly economic ones or rooted in class issues.

Arguable as Marx’s productivist interpretation of social development and

its future may be, it becomes a very forced and artificial, even

contorted explanation of history if it is not greatly modified by the

dialectic of ideas, that is, by political and social ideology, morality

and ethics, law, juridical standards, and the like. Marxism has yet to

forthrightly acknowledge that these different spheres of life have their

own dialectic, indeed, that they can unfold from inner forces of their

own and not simply result from a productivist dialectic called the

“materialist interpretation of history.” Moreover, it has yet to

emphasize that a dialectic of ethics or religion can profoundly affect

the dialectic of productive forces and production relations. Is it

possible, for example, to ignore the fact that Christian theology led

logically to a growing respect for individual worth and finally to

radical conceptions of social freedom – a dialectic, in turn, that

profoundly influenced social development by altering the way human

beings interacted with each other and with the material world?

By the time of the French Revolution, centuries of deeply entrenched

ideas on property, such as the enormous esteem that accompanied the

ownership of land, were intermingling and modifying seemingly objective

social forces, such as the growth of an increasingly capitalistic

market. As a result, the exalted image of the independent, often

self-sufficient peasant, who began to emerge in the wake of the

Revolution with his small bit of property and his craft-oriented

village, actually inhibited capitalist economic development in France

well into the nineteenth century by closing off large parts of the

domestic market to commodities mass-produced in the cities. The image of

the French Revolution as a “bourgeois” revolution that fostered a

capitalist development at home is arguably more fictitious than real,

although in the long run it created many preconditions for the rise of

the industrial bourgeoisie.

In short, by educing the dialectic of history along overwhelmingly

productivist lines, Marx easily deceived himself as well as his most

important followers, notably Lenin and Trotsky, about capitalism’s

morbidity, by assuming that the bourgeoisie had finally prepared all the

economic preconditions for socialism and hence was prepared to be

replaced by socialism. What he ignored was that many of the problems,

contradictions, and antagonisms he imputed almost exclusively to

capitalism were, in fact, the product of lingering feudal traits that

society had not shed; moreover, that the seemingly “superstructural”

institutions and values that had characterized precapitalist societies

played a major role in defining a seemingly predominant capitalist

society that was still aborning. On this score, the anarchists were

right when they called not so much for the economic improvement of the

proletariat as for its moral development being vital to the formation of

a free society – improvements that the Marxists largely brushed aside as

issues that fell within the domain of “private life.”

Marx and Marxism also fail us when they focus overwhelmingly on the

working class – even enhancing its social weight by presumably elevating

transparently petty-bourgeois elements such as salaried white-collar

employees to a proletarian status when industrial workers are evidently

declining numerically. Nor does the authentic proletariat, which assumed

an almost mystical class status in the heyday of Marxism, act as though

it is a uniquely hegemonic historical agent in the conflict with

capitalism as a system. Nothing proved to be more misleading in the

advanced industrial countries of the world than the myth that the

working class, when appealed to as an economic class, could see beyond

the immediate conditions of its given life-ways – the factory and

bourgeois forms of distribution (exchange).[38] It consistently adopted

reformist programs designed to gain higher wages, shorter working days,

longer vacations, and improved working conditions until thunderous

events drove it to revolutionary action – together, it should be added,

with non-proletarian strata. Virtually none of the classical socialist

movements, it is worth noting, appealed to the workers as people, such

as parents, city dwellers, brothers and sisters, and individuals trying

to live decent lives in a decent environment for themselves and their

offspring.

Most conventional Marxist theorists to the contrary, the worker is first

of all a human being, not simply the embodiment of “social labor” that

is definable in strictly class terms. The failure of classical socialism

to make a human and civic appeal to the worker – even to seriously

consider him or her as more than a class being – created a warped

relationship between socialist organizations and their alleged

“constituency.” Although the classical Social Democracy, especially the

German Social Democrats, provided workers with a highly varied cultural

life of their own, from educational activities to sports clubs, the

proletariat was usually boxed into a world bounded by a concern for its

most immediate material interests. Even in the pre-World War Two

cultural centers of the socialists, such as the casas del pueblo

established by the Spanish Socialists, it was fed primarily on

discussions of its exploitation and degradation by the capitalist

system, which in any case it experienced daily in factories and

workshops. The attempt to redefine the proletariat and make it a

majority of a national population lost all credibility when capitalism

began to create a huge “salariat” of office employees, managers, sales

people, and an army of service, engineering, advertising, media, and

governmental personnel who see themselves as a new middle class deeply

invested in bourgeois property through stocks, bonds, real estate,

pensions, and the like, however minor these may seem by comparison with

the big bourgeoisie.

Finally, a very significant failing of Marxism when it came to building

a revolutionary movement was its commitment to the statist acquisition

and maintenance of parliamentary power. By the late 1870s Marx and

Engels had developed into “Red Republicans,” notwithstanding Marx’s

encomiums to the Parisian Communards and their quasi-anarchist vision of

a confederal form of government. What is often ignored is that Marx

disclaimed these encomiums shortly before his death a decade later.

Doubtless Marx’s vision of a republic was marked by more democratic

features than any that existed in Europe and America during his

lifetime. He would have favored the right to recall deputies at all

levels of the state, as well as minimal bureaucracy and a militia system

hopefully based on working-class recruits. But none of the institutions

he attributed to a socialist state were incompatible with those of a

“bourgeois-democratic” state. Not surprisingly, he believed that

socialism could be voted into power in England, the United States, and

the Netherlands, a list to which Engels years later added France.

In vowing that only insurrection and a complete restructuring of the

state were compatible with socialism, Lenin and Luxemburg among others

(especially Trotsky) decidedly departed from Marx and Engels’s political

ideas in their late years. At least in trying to work within republican

institutions, the early Social Democrats were more consistently Marxist

than were their revolutionary critics. They viewed the German Revolution

of 1918– 19 as an indispensable preliminary to the creation of a

republican system that would open a peaceful but, more significant,

institutionally sound road to socialism. That workers’ councils such as

the Russian soviets and German Räte were more radically democratic made

them, as institutional measures, frightening, more akin to anarchism and

certainly Bolshevism than to a parliament elected by universal suffrage.

Although a younger Marx would have found a state structured around

councils more to his taste, there is little to show in his later

writings (apart from his flirtation with the libertarian features of the

Paris Commune) that he would have “smashed the state,” to use Lenin’s

terminology, to the point of rejecting parliamentary government.

Does this mean that anarchist precepts, spawned nearly two centuries

ago, provide a substitute for Marxism?

After 40 years of trying to work with this ideology, my own very

considered opinion is that such a hope, which I entertained as early as

the 1950s, is unrealizable. Nor do I feel that this is due only to the

failings of the so-called “new anarchism” spawned in recent years by

young activists. The problems raised by anarchism belong to the days of

its birth, when writers like Proudhon celebrated its use as a new

alternative to the emerging capitalist social order. In reality,

anarchism has no coherent body of theory other than its commitment to an

ahistorical conception of “personal autonomy” – that is, to the

self-willing, asocial ego, divested of constraints, preconditions, or

limitations short of death itself. Indeed, today, many anarchists

celebrate this theoretical incoherence as evidence of the highly

libertarian nature of their outlook and its often dizzying, of not

contradictory, respect for diversity. It is primarily by giving priority

to an ideologically petrified notion of an “autonomous individual” that

anarchists justify their opposition not only to the state but to any

form of constraint, law, and often organization and democratic

decision-making based on majority voting. All such constraints are

dismissed in principle as forms of “coercion,” “domination,”

“government,” and even “tyranny” – often as though these terms are

coequal and interchangeable.

Nor do anarchist theorists take cognizance of the social and historical

conditions that limit or modify the ability to attain “Anarchy,” which

is often described as a highly personal affair or even an episodic or

“ecstatic” experience. Followed to its logical conclusion, indeed to its

most fundamental premises, Anarchy to anarchists is essentially a moral

desideratum, a “way of life,” as one anarchist put it to me, that is

independent of time or place. Anarchy, we are justified in concluding,

emerges from the exercise of pure will. Presumably, when enough wills

converge to “adopt” Anarchy, it will simply be – like the soil that

remains beneath melting snow, as one British anarchist ideologist put

it.

This revelatory interpretation of how Anarchy makes its appearance in

the world lies at the core of the anarchist vision. Anarchy, it would

appear, has always been “there,” as Isaac Puente, the most important

theorist of Spanish anarchism in the 1930s, put it, save that it was

concealed over the ages by an historically imposed layer of

institutions, entrenched experiences, and values that are typified by

the state, civilization, history, and morality. Somehow, it must merely

be restored from its unsullied past like a hidden geological stratum.

This summary easily explains the emphasis on primitivism and the notion

of “recovery” that one so often encounters in anarchist writing.

Recovery should be distinguished from the notion of discovery and

innovation that modern thinking and rationalism was obliged to

counterpose to the premodern belief that truth and virtue in all their

aspects were already in existence but concealed by an oppressive or

obfuscating historical development and culture. More than one anarchist

could easily use this formulation to justify social passivity apart from

mere protest. One had only to let the “snow” (that is the state, and

civilization) melt away for Anarchy to be restored, a view that may well

explain the pacifism that is so widespread among anarchists throughout

the world today.

In any event, some anarchists have argued that the civilization,

technics, and rationality which in recent years have been singled out by

many anarchists as the greatest failings of the human condition must be

replaced by a more primitive, presumably “authentic” culture that

eschews all the attainments of history in order to restore humanity’s

primal “harmony” with itself and with an almost mystical “Nature.”

Insofar as anarchists currently espouse this view, they have actually

returned anarchism to its true home after its centuries-long meanderings

through the mazes of syndicalism and other basically alien social

causes. Proudhon’s wistful image of the self-sufficient peasant farm or

village, wisely presided over by an all-knowing paterfamilias, is

finally recovered – this, I would add, at a time when the world is more

interdependent and technologically sophisticated than at any other in

history!

Inasmuch as anarchism emphasizes primitivism as against acculturation,

recovery as against discovery, autarchy as against interdependence, and

naturism as against civilization – often rooting its conceptual

apparatus in a “natural,” conceivably “basic” ahistorical autonomous

ego, freed of the rationalism and theoretical burden of “civilization” –

it in fact stands in marked contrast to the real ego, which is always

located in a given temporal, technological, cultural, traditional,

intellectual, and political environment. Indeed, the anarchist version

of the stripped-down, indeed vacuous, ego disturbingly resembles Homer’s

description of the Lotus Eater in the Odyssey, who, while eating the

lotus fruit, slips into the indolence of forgetfulness, atemporality,

and blissfulness that actually represents the very annihilation of

personality and selfhood.

Historically, this “autonomous ego” became the building block that

anarchists used to create various movement-type structures that often

gave it a highly social and revolutionary patina. Syndicalism, to cite

the most important case in point, became the architectural form in which

these blocks were most commonly arranged – not as a defining foundation

for an anarchist movement but as a highly unstable superstructure. When

workers in the closing decades of the nineteenth century became actively

involved in socialism, unionism, organization, democracy, and everyday

struggles for better living and working conditions, anarchism took on

the form of a radical trade unionism. This association was precarious at

best. Although both shared the same libertarian ambience, syndicalism

existed in sharp tension with the basic individualism that pure

anarchists prized, often above – and against – all organizational

institutions.

Both ideologies – Marxism and anarchism – emerged at times when

industrial societies were still in their infancy and nation-states were

still in the process of being formed. While Marx tried to conceptualize

small-scale, often well-educated Parisian craftsmen as “proletarians,”

Bakunin’s imagination was caught up with images of social bandits and

peasant jacqueries. Both men, to be sure, contributed valuable insights

to revolutionary theory, but they were revolutionaries who formulated

their ideas in a socially limited time. They could hardly be expected to

anticipate the problems that emerged during the hectic century that

followed their deaths. A major problem facing radical social thought and

action today is to determine what can be incorporated from their time

into a new, highly dynamic capitalist era that has long transcended the

old semi-feudal world of independent peasants and craftsmen; a new era,

also, that has largely discarded the textile– metal–steam-engine world

of the Industrial Revolution, with its burgeoning population of totally

dispossessed proletarian masses. Their place has been taken in great

part by technologies that can replace labor in nearly all spheres of

work and provide a degree of abundance in the means of life that the

most imaginative utopians of the nineteenth century could not have

anticipated.

But just as advances in an irrational society always taint the most

valuable of human achievements with evil, so too the Industrial

Revolution has produced new problems and potential crises that call for

new means to deal with them. These new means must go beyond mere protest

if they are not to suffer the fate of all movements such as the

Luddites, that could offer little more than a return to the past by

trying to destroy the technical innovations of their era. Any assessment

of the revolutionary tradition immediately raises the question of the

future of the Left in a social environment that is not only beset by new

problems but demands new solutions. What can incorporate the best of the

revolutionary tradition – Marxism and anarchism – in ways and forms that

speak of the kind of problems that face the present time? Indeed, in

view of the remarkable dynamism of the twentieth century and the

likelihood that changes in the new one will be even more sweeping, it

now behooves us to speculate about the analyses that will explain its

forthcoming development, the kind of crises it is likely to face, and

the institutions, methods, and movements that can hope to render society

rational and nourishing as an arena for human creativity. Above all, we

must think beyond the immediate present and its proximate past by trying

to anticipate problems that may lie at least a generation, if not

further, beyond a highly transitory present.

Capitalism and Globalization

What remains very contemporary in Marx’s writings, even after a century

and a half, is the insight they bring to the nature of the capitalist

development. Marx fully explored the competitive forces that inhere in

the buyer–seller exchange, a relationship that, under capitalism,

compels the bourgeoisie to continually expand its enterprises and

operations. Ever since the capitalist economy became prevalent over a

sizable area of the world it has been guided by the competitive market

imperative of “grow or die,” leading to continual industrial expansion

and to the consolidation of competing concerns into ever-larger,

quasi-monopolistic complexes. Would the process of capital concentration

culminate in a worldwide economy under the tutelage of a few or of a

single corporate entity, thereby terminating the process of accumulation

and bringing capitalism to an end? Or would capital expansion (that is,

“globalization”) so level market differentials that the exchange of

commodities as a source of accumulation becomes impossible? These were

serious topics of discussion during the heyday of classical Marxism.

They remain conundrums today.

Today we can say for certain that existing quasi-monopolistic complexes

furiously accelerate the rate at which society undergoes economic and

social change. Not only do firms expand at an ever-increasing pace,

either annihilating or absorbing their competitors, but the commodities

they produce and the resources they devour affect every corner of the

planet. Globalization is not unique to modern capitalist industry and

finance – the bourgeoisie has been eating its way into isolated and

seemingly self-contained cultures for centuries and, either directly or

indirectly, transforming them. What is unusual about present-day

globalization is the scale on which it is occurring and the far-reaching

impact it is having on cultures that once seemed to be insulated from

modern commodity production and trade and from nation-state sovereignty.

Now the presumably “quaint” traits of precapitalist peoples have been

turned into marketable items to titillate Western tourists who pay

exorbitant prices to enjoy a presumably “primitive” item or experience.

Marx and his followers considered this process of expanding

industrialization and market relations to be a progressive feature of

the capitalist “stage” of history, and they expected that it would

eventually eliminate all preexisting territorial, cultural, national,

and ethnic ties and replace them with class solidarity, thereby removing

obstacles to the development of revolutionary internationalism.

Commodification, Marx famously emphasized, turns everything solid into

air. It once eliminated the economic exclusivity of guilds and other

economic barriers to innovation; and it continues to corrode art,

crafts, familial ties, and all the bonds of human solidarity – indeed,

all the honored traditions that nourished the human spirit.

Marx saw the homogenizing effects of globalization as destructive

insofar as they dissolved the meaningful relationships and sentiments

that knitted society together; but his formulation was not only a

critique. He also saw these effects as progressive insofar as they

cleared away precapitalist and particularistic detritus. Today, radicals

emphasize that the worldwide invasion of the commodity into society is

overwhelmingly destructive. Capitalism (not simply globalization and

corporatization) not only turns everything solid into air but replaces

earlier traditions with distinctly bourgeois attributes. Implicit in

Marx’s remarks was the belief that globalized capitalism would provide

the future with a clean slate on which to inscribe the outlines of a

rational society. But as capitalism writes its message of uniquely

bourgeois values, it creates potentially monstrous developments that may

well undermine social life itself. It supplants traditional ties of

solidarity and community with an all-pervasive greed, an appetite for

wealth, a system of moral accounting focused on “the bottom line,” and a

heartless disregard for the desperation of the poor, aged, and

physically disabled.

Not that greed and heartlessness were absent from capitalism in the

past. But in an earlier time, the bourgeoisie was relatively marginal

and vulnerable to the patronizing outlook of the landed nobility;

preindustrial values more or less held capitalists in check. Then the

market economy rendered increasingly prevalent an unbridled capitalist

spirit of self-aggrandizement and unfeeling exploitation. Naked

bourgeois greed and heartlessness, illuminated by the vigilance of great

writers such as Balzac and Dickens, produced a wave of revulsion that

swept over people who were exposed. In past epochs the rich were neither

admired nor turned into embodiments of virtue. The honored virtue of

most of the precapitalist world, rather, was not self-aggrandizement but

self-sacrifice, not accumulating but giving, however much these virtues

were honored in the breach.

But today capitalism has penetrated into all aspects of life; greed, an

inordinate appetite for wealth, an accounting mentality, and a

disdainful view of poverty and infirmity have become a moral pathology.

Under these circumstances bourgeois traits are the celebrated symbols of

the “beautiful people” and, more subtly, of yuppified baby boomers.

These values percolate into less fortunate strata of the population who,

depending upon their own resources, view the fortunate with envy, even

awe, and guiltily target themselves for their own lack of privilege and

status as “ne’er-do-wells.”

In this new embourgeoisement the dispossessed harbor no class

antagonisms toward the “rich and beautiful” (a unique juxtaposition) but

rather esteem them. At present, poor and middle-class people are less

likely to view the bourgeoisie with hatred than with servile admiration;

they increasingly see the ability to make money and accrue wealth not as

indicative of a predatory disposition and the absence of moral scruples,

as was the case a few generations ago, but as evidence of innate

abilities and intelligence. Newsstands and bookstores are filled with a

massive literature celebrating the lifestyles, careers, personal

affairs, and riches of the new wealthy, who are held up as models of

achievement and success. That these “celebrities” of postmodernity

bubble up from obscurity is an added asset: it suggests that the

admiring but debt-burdened reader can also “make it” in a new bourgeois

world. Any obscure candidate can “become a millionaire” – or a

multimillionaire – merely by winning in a television game show or a

lottery. The myriad millions who envy and admire the bourgeoisie no

longer see its members as part of a “class”; they are rather a

“meritocracy” who have become, as a result of luck and effort, winners

in the lottery of life. If Americans once widely believed that anyone

could become the president of the United States, the new belief holds

that anyone can become a millionaire or – who knows? – one of the ten

richest people in the world.

Capitalism, in turn, is increasingly assumed to be the natural state of

affairs toward which history has been converging for thousands of years.

Even as capitalism is achieving this splendor, we are witnessing a

degree of public ignorance, fatuity, and smugness unseen since the

inception of the modern world. Like fast food and quick sex, ideas and

experiences simply race through the human mind, and far from being

absorbed and used as building blocks for generalizations, they quickly

disappear to make room for still newer and faster-moving ideas and

experiences, of an ever more superficial or degraded character. Every

few years, it would seem, a new generation initiates ostensibly “new

causes” that were exhausted only a decade or two earlier, thereby

casting into ideological oblivion invaluable lessons and knowledge that

are indispensable for a radical social practice. Each new generation has

a concomitantly arrogant notion that history began only when it was

born; hence all experiences from the past, even the recent past, are to

be ignored. Thus the struggle against globalization, which was fought

for decades under the rubric of anti-imperialism, has been reinvented

and renamed.

The problem of lost definition and specificity, of everything being

turned into “air,” and the disastrous loss of the memory of experiences

and lessons vital to establishing a Left tradition, confronts any

endeavor to create a revolutionary movement in the future. Theories and

concepts lose their dimensions, their mass, their traditions, and their

relevance, as a result of which they are adopted and dropped with

juvenile flippancy. The chauvinistic notion of “identity,” which is the

byproduct of class and hierarchical society, ideologically corrodes the

concept of “class,” prioritizing a largely psychological distinction at

the expense of a socio-political one. “Identity” becomes a highly

personal problem with which individuals must wrestle psychologically and

culturally rather than a root social problem that must be understood by

and resolved through a radical social approach.

Indeed, the bourgeoisie can easily remedy such a problem by promoting

ethnically discriminated employees to upper-level managers and by

promoting female lieutenants in the military into majors or generals.

Hence the amazing willingness that new enterprises and the media exhibit

in selecting blacks and women for high spots in their operations or

media presentations. Baby-boomer capitalists such as Tom Peters, who

season their ideas of non-hierarchical practices in business

administration with dashingly anarchic traits, often regard race and

gender as archaisms. Colin Powell has shown that even with an

African-American as chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, the American

military can be as deadly as it needs to be, and Oprah Winfrey has

demonstrated that what Americans read or buy needs have no bearing on

the race or gender of a television purveyor of those commodities.

The middle and working classes no longer think of the present society as

structured around classes. Current opinion holds that the rich are

deserving and the poor are not, while an incalculable number of people

linger between the categories. A huge section of public opinion in the

Western world tends to regard oppression and exploitation as residual

abuses, not inherent features of a specific social order. The prevailing

society is neither rationally analyzed nor forcefully challenged; it is

prudently psychoanalyzed and politely coaxed, as though social problems

emerge from erratic individual behavior. Although strident protests

explode from time to time, a growing gentility is watering down the

severity of social disputes and antagonisms, even among people who

profess leftist views.

Beyond a Politics of Protest

What is absent in this type of sporadic and eruptive opposition is an

understanding of the causal continuities that only serious and above all

rational explorations can reveal. In the so-called “Seattle rebellion”

in late November and early December 1999 against the World Trade

Organization, what was at issue was not the substitution of “fair trade”

for “free trade.” It was the question of the ways in modern society

produces the wealth of the world and distributes it. Although some

militant demonstrators attempted to invoke the “injustices” of

capitalism – actually, capitalism was not being peculiarly “unjust” any

more than lethal bacilli are being “unfair” when they produce illness

and death – few, if any, of the demonstrators appeared to understand the

logic of a market economy. It has been reported that during anti-WTO

demonstrations little literature was distributed that explained the

basic reason for denouncing the WTO and “preventing” its delegates from

doing their business.

Indeed, the demonstration in Seattle, like the one in Washington, DC,

that followed it several months later, however well-meant, created the

illusion that acts of mere disruption, which became increasingly staged,

can do more than moderate the “excesses” of globalization. The

Washington demonstration, in fact, was so negotiated in character that

the police allowed the demonstrators to walk across a chalked line as a

mere symbol of illegality and then to allow themselves to be escorted

into buses as arrestees. Police spokesmen pleasantly agreed that the

young demonstrators were “decent” and “socially concerned kids” who

meant well, and WTO delegates tolerantly acknowledged that the

demonstrators drew their attention to troubling economic and

environmental problems that needed correction. Undoubtedly, the

authorities expect these “socially concerned kids” to eventually grow up

and become good citizens.

The demonstrations appeared more like acts of catharsis than aroused

protest; demonstrators hugged each other lovingly and wore idiosyncratic

clothing, unwittingly turning themselves into cultural oddities. If

anything, they separated themselves from the general public rather than

related to it. Rather than meaningful protests, the demonstrations were

noteworthy mainly because protest of any kind is such a rarity today.

The limited number of participants seemed to lack an in-depth

understanding of what the WTO represented. Even to protest “capitalism”

is simply to voice an opposition to an abstract noun, which in itself

tells us nothing about capitalist social relations, their dynamic, their

transformation into destructive social forces, the prerequisites for

undoing them, and finally the alternatives that exist to replace them.

Few of the demonstrators appeared to know the answers to these

questions; thus they castigated corporations and multinationals, as

though these are not the unavoidable outcome of historic forces of

capitalist production. Would the dangers of globalization be removed

from the world if the corporations were scaled down in size? More

fundamentally, could smaller enterprises ever have been prevented from

developing into industrial, commercial, and financial giants that would

not differ from modern multinationals?

My point is less to advance criticisms than to question the extent to

which the Seattle and Washington demonstrators adequately understood the

problems they were dealing with. Indeed, what is a demonstration meant

to demonstrate? It must not only protest but also confront official

power with popular power, even in incipient form. Demonstrations are

mobilizations of sizable numbers of serious people who, in taking to the

streets, intend to let the authorities know that they earnestly oppose

certain actions by the powers-that-be. Reduced to juvenile antics, they

become self-deflating forms of entertainment. As such, they constitute

no challenge to the authorities; indeed, where idiosyncratic behavior

replaces the forcefulness of stern opposition, they merely show the

public that advocates of their view are mere eccentrics who need not be

taken seriously and whose cause is trivial. Without the gravitas that

commands respect – and, yes, the discipline that reveals serious

intentionality – demonstrations and other such manifestations are worse

than useless; they harm their cause by trivializing it.

A politics of mere protest, lacking programmatic content, a proposed

alternative, and a movement to give people direction and continuity,

consists of little more than events, each of which has a beginning and

an end and little more. The social order can live with an event or

series of events and even find this praiseworthy. Worse still, such a

politics lives or dies according to an agenda established by the social

order it opposes. Corporations proposed the WTO; they needed worldwide

participation in the Organization and, in their own way, generated the

very opposition that now denounces its lack of democracy and lack of

humaneness. They expected opposition, and only police amateurism in

Seattle let it get slightly out of hand. It ill-becomes such an

opposition to then plan to demonstrate before nominating conventions of

major political parties whose very existence many of the demonstrators

profess to oppose. Indeed, the demonstrators, however well-meaning,

legitimate the existence of the parties by calling upon them to alter

their policies on international trade, as though they even have a

justifiable place in a rational society.

A politics of protest is not a politics at all. It occurs within

parameters set by the prevailing social system and merely responds to

remediable ills, often mere symptoms, instead of challenging the social

order as such. The masked anarchists who join in these events by

smashing windows use the clamor of shattered glass to glamorize limited

street protests with the semblance of violence and little more.

A Left for the Future

I have not made these critical remarks about the state of the Left today

in order to carp against people, activities, and events, or from any

generational or sectarian disdain. On the contrary, my criticisms stem

from a deep sympathy for people who are sensitive to injustices and

particularly for those who are striving to remedy them. Better to do

something to end the silence of popular acquiescence than simply to

perpetuate the complacency generated by a consumer-oriented society.

Nor have I presented my criticisms of Marxism and anarchism – the main

players in the classical Left – in order to try to astound a new

generation of activists with the grandeur of revolutionary history that

they somehow must match. Again to the contrary, I have invoked the

classical Left of yesteryear not only to suggest what it has to teach us

but also to note its own limitations, as the product of a different era,

and one that, for better of worse, will never return. What the classical

Left has to teach us is that ideas must be systematic – coherent – if

they are to be productive and understandable to people who are seriously

committed to basic social change; indeed, a future Left must show that

the seemingly disparate problems of the present society are connected

with each other and that they stem from a common social pathology that

must be removed as a totality. Moreover, no attempts to change the

existing society will ever be basic unless we understand how its

problems are interconnected and how the solutions that can resolve them

can be educed from humanity’s potentialities for freedom, rationality,

and self-consciousness.

By coherence, I do not mean only a methodology or a system of thinking

that explores basics; rather that the very process of attempting to link

together the various social pathologies to common causes and to resolve

them in their totality is an ethical endeavor. To declare that humanity

has a potentiality for freedom, rationality, and self-consciousness –

and, significantly, that this potentiality is not being realized or

actualized today – leads inexorably to the demand that every society

justify its existence according to the extent to which it actualizes

these norms. Any endeavor to assess a society’s success in achieving

freedom, rationality, and self-consciousness makes an implicit judgment.

It raises the searing question of what a society “should be” within its

material and cultural limits. It constitutes the realizable ideal that

social development raises for all thinking people and that, up to now,

has kept alive movements for the fulfillment of freedom.

Without that ideal as a continual and activating presence, no lasting

movement for human liberation is possible – only sporadic protests that

themselves may mask the basic irrationality of an unfree society by

seeking to cosmetically remove its blemishes. By contrast, a constant

awareness that a given society’s irrationality is deep-seated, that its

serious pathologies are not isolated problems that can be cured

piecemeal but must be solved by sweeping changes in the often hidden

sources of crisis and suffering – that awareness alone is what can hold

a movement together, give it continuity, preserve its message and

organization beyond a given generation, and expand its ability to deal

with new issues and developments.

Too often ideas that are meant to yield a certain practice are instead

transported into the academy, as fare for “enriching” a curriculum and,

of course, generating jobs for the growing professoriat. Such has been

the unhappy fate of Marxism, which, once an embattled and creative body

of ideas, has now acquired academic respectability – to the extent that

it is even regarded as worthy of study.

At the same time the routine use of the word “activist” raises problems

that unintentionally can be regressive. Can there be action without

theory and insight into the nature of social ills and an understanding

of the measures needed to resolve them? Can the activist even act

meaningfully and effectively without drawing upon the rich body of

experiences and ideas that have grown up over the years and that can

show us the dangerous pitfalls that lie below the surface, or the many

strategies that have been tested by earlier generations?

In what likely directions is capitalist society developing in the coming

century, and what are the most basic problems it is raising for

humanity? Is there any special sector, class, or group in society to

which we must appeal if we are to hope to create a revolutionary

movement? What kind of movement and institutions must we create that

will play a leading role in social change? Do we need any well-organized

movement at all, or will our hoped-for changes occur spontaneously,

emerging out of demonstrations around specific issues or street

festivals or communitarian enterprises such as co-ops, alternative

enterprises, and the like? Or do we have to build political entities,

and if so, what kind? What is the relationship of a revolutionary

movement to these new political entities? And how should power be

situated and institutionalized in a rational society? Finally, what

ethical considerations should guide us in our efforts?

Marxism failed to form an adequate picture of the worker as a many-sided

human being and indeed fetishized him or her to the point of absurdity.

It did not normally see workers as more than economic entities, but

rather endowed them with semi-mystical properties as revolutionary

agents, possessed of secret powers to understand their interests and a

unique sensitivity to radical possibilities in the existing society. To

read Rosa Luxemburg, Karl Liebknecht, Leon Trotsky, the syndicalist

propagandists, and even run-of-the-mill old-time Social Democrats is to

sense that they held the socialist judgment of workers in awe and imbued

them with remarkable revolutionary powers. That workers could also

become fascists or reactionaries was inconceivable.

This mystification has not entirely been dispelled, but even so we must

ask: which part of society can play a leading role in radical change

today? The fact is that the leveling role of Western capitalism and the

increasing development of social struggles along ever vaguer lines has

opened up a vista much different from that which once hypnotized the

classical Left. The technological level of the Industrial Revolution was

highly labor intensive; the brutish exploitation of labor and the

simplification of the work process with its consequent destruction of

skills by a deadening division of labor made it possible for Marx and

other theorists to single out the proletariat as the principal victim of

capitalism and the principal engine of its demise.

Although many traditional factories are still with us, especially in the

Third World, in Europe and North America they are giving way to highly

skilled and differentiated systems of production. Many new strata can no

longer be regarded, except in the most elastic way, as “workers” in any

industrial sense. Such people are even becoming the majority of the

“working class,” while the industrial proletariat (contrary to Marx’s

expectations) is visibly becoming an ever-smaller minority of the

population. For the present, at least, these workers are well paid

(often receiving salaries rather than wages), consumer-oriented in

tastes, and far removed from a working-class outlook and a disposition

to hold leftist social views.

Capitalism, in effect, is creating the bases for a populist politics –

hopefully a radical and ultimately revolutionary one – that is focused

on the broadening and expanding of professional opportunities, the

quality of life, and a more pleasant environment. Economically, maturing

capitalism can properly be descriptively divided into strata of the

wealthy, the well-off, the comfortable, and the poor. Industrial wage

workers in the West have more in common with salaried technicians and

professionals than with underpaid unskilled workers in the service

sector of fast-food restaurants and retail sales and the like, let alone

with the nearly lumpenized poor. In the absence of economic crises,

social disquiet may focus on fears of crime, shortcomings in public

services and education, the decline of traditional values, and the like.

More momentously, this populist outlook fears environmental degradation,

the disappearance of open spaces, and the growing congestion of

once-human-scaled communities – indeed, of community life in all its

aspects.

For more than a half century, capitalism has managed not only to avoid a

chronic economic crisis of the kind Marx expected but also to control

crises that potentially had a highly explosive character. As a system,

capitalism is one of the most unstable economies in history and hence is

always unpredictable. But equally uncertain is the traditional radical

notion that it must slip with unfailing regularity into periodic crises

as well as chronic ones. The general population in Europe and the United

States has displayed a remarkable confidence in the operations of the

economy; more than 40 percent of US families have now invested in the

stock market and accept its huge swings without being swept up by

panics, such as afflicted financial markets in the past. A strictly

class-oriented politics based on industrial workers has receded, and the

Left now faces the imperative to create a populist politics that reaches

out to “the people” as they are today, in anticipation that they can now

more easily be radicalized by issues that concern their communities,

their civil liberties, their overall environment, and the integrity of

their supplies of food, air, and water, not simply by a focus on

economic exploitation and wage issues. The importance of economic issues

cannot be overstated, but especially in periods of relative well-being a

future Left will be successful only to the extent that it addresses the

public as a “people” rather than as a class, a population whose disquiet

has at least as much to do with freedoms, quality of life, and future

well-being as it does with economic crises and material insecurity.[39]

By the same token, a future Left can hope to exercise influence only if

it can mobilize people on issues that cut across the class lines. From

Marx’s day until the Depression and fascist decade of the 1930s, the

principal victims of capitalist exploitation appeared to be workers at

the point of production. The French Revolution, it was argued, allowed

the peasantry to gain greater control of the land, and the democratic

revolutions of the eighteenth century granted the lower middle classes a

major place in all spheres of French society. But they left one class

unsatisfied: the emerging industrial proletariat, which was subjected to

harsh working conditions, prevented from organizing, and suffered a

declining standard of living. Engels portrayed a working-class life

based on the English proletariat of 1844 at the height of the first

Industrial Revolution; Marx argued that the concentration of capital and

the displacement of workers by machines would create insufferable misery

in the factories of England and the continent. This anti-capitalist

vision was predicated on the belief that the proletariat’s material

conditions of life would worsen steadily while its numbers would

increase to a point where it became the majority of the population.

By the late nineteenth century, however, these predictions were falling

short, and by 1950 they were wholly discredited. What with the

sophistication of machinery, the appearance of electronics, the

spectacular increase in motor vehicle production, the rise of the

chemical industry, and the like, the proportion of industrial workers to

the population at large was diminishing, not rising. Moreover, due in

large part to the struggles of legal trade unions to improve the living

conditions of the proletariat in particular, the conflict between

capital and labor was being significantly muted. Marxism, then, was

clearly boxed into the class relations of a historically limited period,

the era of the first Industrial Revolution.

Far from becoming proletarianized or declining to a minority of the

population, as Marx had predicted, the middle class retained the

psychology and consciousness of people who could hope for an ever-higher

status. Propertyless as it may have been in reality and often cowed by

the real bourgeoisie, the petty bourgeoisie was (and remains to a great

extent) convinced that it has a privileged place in the market economy

and entertains expectations that it can climb upward on the social

ladder of the capitalist system. If anything, the working class has made

sufficient gains that it expects its children, equipped with a better

education than their parents, to step upward in life. Small property

owners are invested by the millions in financial markets. Workers now

describe themselves as “middle class” or, with a nuance that heightens

the dignity of labor, as “working families.” Combative and exclusive

expressions like “workers,” “toilers,” and “laborers” that once

implicitly hinted at the existence of class struggle are now used with

increasing rarity or not at all.

The sharp lines that once distinguished a plant’s accounting office from

the proletariat are being blurred ideologically and eating away at

working-class consciousness. Notwithstanding Marx’s theory of history as

an account of class struggles, with its many truths, a class is no more

authentic than the consciousness with which it views reality. No worker

is truly a class being, however much he is exploited, when he views

social life in bourgeois terms. The bourgeoisie learned this fact quite

early when it exploited ethnic, religious, gender, and craft divisions

within the proletariat as a whole. Hence the blue-collar or white-collar

worker is a class being according to how she thinks of herself, relates

to her boss, and holds expectations in life. A worker without a

combative class consciousness is no more an exploited proletarian, for

all practical purposes, than a policeman is an ordinary worker. Radical

intellectuals’ mystification of the worker has its origins in their

imputation that “consciousness follows being,” that is, when the worker

recognizes that he is exploited and that capitalism is his social enemy.

What does this mean for a future Left? Unless capitalism unexpectedly

collapses into a major chronic crisis (in which case workers may well

turn to the fascism of a Le Pen in France or the reactionism of a

Buchanan in the US), then the Left must focus on issues that are

interclass in nature, addressing the middle as well as the working

class. By the very logic of its “grow or die” imperative, capitalism may

well be producing ecological crises that gravely imperil the integrity

of life on this planet. The outputs of factories and the raw material

industries, the destructive agricultural practices, and the consumption

patterns in privileged parts of the world are simplifying the highly

complex ecological ties that emerged over millions of years of natural

evolution, reducing highly fertile areas to concrete landscapes, turning

usable water into an increasingly degraded resource, surrounding the

planet with a carbon dioxide layer that threatens to radically change

the climate, and opening dangerous holes in the ozone layer. Rivers,

lakes, and oceans are becoming garbage dumps for poisonous and

life-inhibiting wastes. Almost every tangible component of daily life,

from the food on the dinner table to substances used in the workplace,

is becoming polluted with known or potentially dangerous toxicants.

Cities are growing into vast, polluted, sprawling environments whose

populations are larger than those of many nation-states only a few

decades ago. The equatorial belt of tropical forests that surround the

planet’s land areas and large parts of the temperate zones are being

deforested and denuded of their complex life-forms.

Yet for capitalism to desist from its mindless expansion would be for it

to commit social suicide. By definition capitalism is a competitive

economy that cannot cease to expand. The problems it may be creating for

humanity as a whole – problems that transcend class differences – can

easily become the bases for a vast critique if current environmentalists

are willing to raise their concerns to the level of a radical social

analysis and organize not simply around saving a select species or

around the vices of automobile manufacturers but around replacing the

existing irrational economy by a rational one. The fact that the nuclear

industry still exists must be seen not simply as an abuse or a matter of

stupidity, for example, but as an integral part of a greater whole: the

need for an industry in a competitive economy to grow and out-compete

its rivals. Similarly, the successes of the chemical industry in

promoting the use of toxicants in agriculture, and the growing output of

the automobile and petroleum industries – all must be seen as the

results of the inner workings of a deeply entrenched system. Not only

workers but the public must be educated in the reality that our emerging

ecological problems stem from our irrational society.

Issues such as gender discrimination, racism, and national chauvinism

must be recast not only as cultural and social regressions but as

evidence of the ills produced by hierarchy. A growing public awareness

must be fostered that oppression includes not only exploitation but also

domination, and that it is based not only on economic causes but on

cultural particularisms that divide people according to sexual, ethnic,

and similar traits. Where these issues come to the foreground in the

form of patent abuses, then a conscious revolutionary movement must

expand their implications to show that society as it exists is basically

irrational and dangerous.

Such a revolutionary movement needs a distinctive body of tactics

designed to expand the scope of any issue, however reformist it may seem

at first glance, steadily radicalizing it and giving it a potentially

revolutionary thrust. It should make no agreement with liberals and the

bourgeoisie on retaining the existing order. If the solution to a

specific environmental problem seems fairly pragmatic, then the movement

must regard it as a step for widening a partly open door until it can

show that the entire ecological problem is systemic and expose it as

such to public view. Thus a revolutionary movement should insist not

only on blocking the construction of a nuclear plant but on shutting

down all nuclear plants and replacing them with alternative energy

sources that enhance the environment. It should regard no limited gains

as conclusive but rather must clearly link a given demand to the need

for basic social change. The same strategy applies to the use of

chemicals in agriculture, current agricultural methods of growing food,

the manufacture of harmful means of transportation, the manufacture of

dangerous household products – indeed, every item whose production and

use debases the environment and degrades human values.[40]

Programmatic Issues and Prospects

I have examined elsewhere the reasons why power cannot be ignored – a

problem that beleaguered the Spanish anarchists. But can be we conceive

of a popular movement gaining power without an agency that can provide

it with guidance?

A revolutionary Left that seeks to advance from protest demonstrations

to revolutionary demonstrations must resolutely confront the problem of

organization. I speak here not of ad hoc planning groups but rather of

the creation and maintenance of an organization that is enduring,

structured, and broadly programmatic. Such an organization constitutes a

definable entity and must be structured around lasting and formal

institutions to make it operational; it must contain a responsible

membership that firmly and knowledgeably adheres to its ideals; and it

must advance a sweeping program for social change that can be translated

into everyday practice. Although such an organization may join a

coalition (or united front, as the traditional Left called it), it must

not disappear into such a coalition or surrender its independence, let

alone its identity. It must retain its own name at all times and be

guided by its own statutes. The organization’s program must be the

product of a reasoned analysis of the fundamental problems that face

society, their historical sources and theoretical fundaments, and the

clearly visible goals that follow from the potentialities and realities

for social change.

One of the greatest problems that revolutionaries in the past faced

(from the English revolutionaries in the seventeenth century to the

Spanish in the twentieth) was their failure to create a resolute,

well-structured, and fully informed organization with which to counter

their reactionary opponents. Few uprisings expand beyond the limits of a

riot without the guidance of a knowledgeable leadership. The myth of the

purely spontaneous revolution can be dispatched by a careful study of

past uprisings (as I have attempted in my own work on The Third

Revolution). Even in self-consciously libertarian organizations,

leadership always existed, even in the form of “influential militants,”

spirited men and women who constituted the nuclei around which crowds

transformed street protests into outright insurrections. In his famous

etching “The Revolt,” Daumier intuitively focuses on a single

individual, amid other rebels, who raises the cry that brings the masses

into motion. Even in seemingly “spontaneous insurrections,” advanced

militants, scattered throughout rebellious crowds, spurred the uncertain

masses on to further action. Contrary to anarchistic myths, none of the

soviets, councils, and committees that arose in Russia in 1917, Germany

in 1918, and Spain in 1936 were formed simply of their own accord.

Invariably specific militants (a euphemism for leaders) took the

initiative in forming them and in guiding inexperienced masses toward

the adoption of a radical course of action.

Absorbed as they were with making concrete and immediate demands, few of

these councils and committees had a broad overview of the social

possibilities opened by the insurrections they initiated or a clear

understanding of the enemies they had temporarily defeated. By contrast,

the bourgeoisie and its statesmen knew only too well how to organize

themselves, thanks to their considerable experience as entrepreneurs,

political leaders, and military commanders. But the workers too often

lacked the knowledge and experience so vital to developing an overview.

It remains a tragic irony that insurrections that were not defeated

outright by superior military forces often froze into immobility once

they took power from their class enemies and rarely took the

organizational steps necessary to retain their power. Without a

theoretically trained and militant organization that had developed a

broad social vision of its tasks and could offer workers practical

programs for completing the revolution that they had initiated,

revolutions quickly fell apart for lack of further action. Their

supporters, zealous at the outset and for a brief period afterward, soon

floundered, became demoralized for want of a thoroughgoing program, lost

their élan, and then were crushed physically. Nowhere was this

destructive process more apparent than in the German Revolution of

1918–19 and, to a great degree, in the Spanish Revolution of 1936–37,

mainly because the mass anarcho-syndicalist union, the CNT, surrendered

the power it had received from the Catalan workers in July 1936 to the

bourgeoisie.

A future Left must carefully study these tragic experiences and

determine how to resolve the problems of organization and power. Such an

organization cannot be a conventional party, and find a comfortable

place in a parliamentary state, without losing its revolutionary élan.

The Bolshevik party, structured as a top-down organization that

fetishized centralization and internal party hierarchy, exemplifies the

way a party can merely replicate a state and become a bureaucratic and

authoritarian entity.

If Marxists, when they found themselves in revolutionary situations,

could not conceive of any politics that abolished the state, then the

anarchists, and tragically the syndicalists who were deeply influenced

by them intellectually, were so fixated on avoiding the state that they

destroyed vital, self-governing revolutionary institutions. This not the

place to discuss Spanish anarchism and its rather confused

anarcho-syndicalist “farrago,” as Chris Ealham has so aptly called

it,[41] but the CNT-FAI leadership seems to have lacked the slightest

idea how to achieve a libertarian communist revolution: when power was

actually thrust into their trembling hands, it simply did not know what

to with it.

Every revolution, indeed, even every attempt to achieve basic social

change, will always meet with resistance from the elites in power. Every

effort to defend a revolution will require the amassing of power –

physical as well as institutional and administrative – which is to say,

the creation of a government. Anarchists may call for the abolition of

the state, but coercion of some kind will be necessary to prevent the

bourgeois state from returning in full force with unbridled terror. For

a libertarian organization to eschew, out of misplaced fear of creating

a “state,” the taking of power when it can do so with the support of the

revolutionary masses is confusion at best and a total failure of nerve

at worst. Perhaps the CNT-FAI actually lived in awe of the very state

apparatus whose existence it was committed to abolish. Better that such

a movement gets out of the way than remain cloaked in a seemingly

“radical” camouflage that makes promises to the masses that it cannot

honor.

The history of the libertarian Left does suggest, however, a form of

organization that is consistent with attempts to create a left

libertarian society. In a confederation, seeming higher bodies play the

role of administering policy decisions that are made at the base of the

organization. In the end, nearly all policy decisions, especially basic

ones, must be made at the base of the organization by its branches or

sections. Decisions made at the base move to the top and then back again

in modified form to the base until, by majority votes at the base, they

become policies whose implementation is often undertaken by special or

standing committees.

No organizational model, however, should be fetishized to the point

where it flatly contradicts the imperatives of real life. Where events

require a measure of centralization, coordination at a confederal level

may have to be tightened to implement a policy or tactic – to the extent

that it is necessary and only for as long as it is necessary. A

confederation can allow necessary centralization on a temporary basis,

without yielding to a permanent centralized organization, only if its

membership is conscious and thoroughly informed, theoretically, to guard

against the abuses of centralization and only if the organization has

structures in place to recall leaders who seem to be abusing their

powers. Otherwise we have no certainty that any libertarian practices

will be honored. I have seen people who for decades were committed to

libertarian practices and principles throw their ideals to the wind, and

even drift into a coarse nationalism, when events appealed more to their

emotions than to their minds. A libertarian organization must have in

place precautions such as the right to recall by the organization’s

membership and the right to demand a full accounting of a confederal

body’s practices, but the fact remains that there is no substitute for

knowledge and consciousness. Certainly no dogmatic formula can provide

an adequate method for defying the imperatives of real life,

particularly in times of armed conflict.

A libertarian communist society would have to make decisions on how

resources are to be acquired, produced, allocated, and distributed. Such

a society must seek to prevent the restoration of capitalism and of old

or new systems of privilege, which may involve civil war and military

regimentation. It must try to achieve a degree of administrative

coordination and regulation on a huge scale among communities, and

decision-making must be forceful if social life of any kind is not to

collapse completely.

These constraints are necessary to provide the greatest degree of

freedom possible, but they will not be imposed simply by “good will,”

“mutual aid,” “solidarity,” or even “custom,” and any notion that they

will rests more on a prayer than on human experience. Material want will

quickly erode any “good will” and “solidarity” that a successful, indeed

forceful revolution with its fighting and expropriations creates among

the libertarian victors; hence the need for post-scarcity as a

precondition for a communalist society. In the Spanish Revolution of

1936– 37 many of the new society’s collectives – all flying the

black-and-red flag of anarcho-syndicalism – entered into blatant

competition with one another for raw materials, technicians, and even

markets and profits. The result was that they had to be “socialized” by

the CNT – that is, the trade union had to exert control to equalize the

distribution of goods and the availability of costly machinery, and

oblige “rich” collectives to share their wealth with poor ones. (Later

this authority was taken over by the Madrid nation-state for reasons of

its own.) Nor were all peasants eager to join collectives when they were

also afforded the opportunity to function as small property owners.

Still others left the collectives in sizable numbers when they found

themselves free to do so without fear. In other words, to establish a

viable communalist society, more than personal and moral commitments

will be needed – least of all, those extremely precarious variables that

are based on “human nature” and “instincts for mutual aid.”

The problem of achieving libertarian communism is one of the most

untheorized aspects of the libertarian repertoire. The communist maxim

“From each according to ability, to each according to need” presupposes

a sufficiency of goods and hence complex technological development. That

achievement involves a close agreement with Marx’s emphasis that

advances in the instruments of production are a precondition for

communism. The success of libertarian communism, then, depends

profoundly on the growth of the productive forces over many centuries

and on the increasing availability of the means of life.

History is filled with countless examples where natural scarcity or

limited resources obliged peoples to turn popular governments into

kingly states, captives into slaves, women into subjugated drudges, free

peasants into serfs, and the like. No such development lacks excesses,

and if kindly rulers did not turn into brutal despots, it would have

been miraculous. That we can sit in judgment on these societies, their

states, and their oppressive methods is evidence that progress has

occurred and, equally importantly, that our circumstances differ

profoundly from theirs. Where famine was once a normal feature of life,

we today are shocked when no effort is made to feed the starving. But we

are shocked only because we have already developed the means to produce

a sufficiency, disallowing indifference to scarcity. In short, the

circumstances have changed profoundly, however unjust the distribution

of the means of life may continue to be. Indeed, that we can even say

that the distribution is unjust is a verdict that only a society that

can eliminate material scarcity – and create, potentially, a

post-scarcity society – can make.

Thus our expansive visions of freedom, today, have their preconditions:

minimally, technological advancement. Only generations that have not

experienced the Great Depression can ignore the preconditional bases for

our more generous ideologies. The classical Left – particularly thinkers

such as Marx – gave us much systematic thinking on history and

contemporary social affairs. But will we elect to follow a truly

libertarian use of the resources at our command and create a society

that is democratic, communistic, and communalistic, based on popular

assemblies, confederations, and sweeping civil liberties? Or will we

follow a course that is increasingly statist, centralized, and

authoritarian? Here another “history” or dialectic comes into play – the

great traditions of freedom that were elaborated over time by unknown

revolutionaries and by libertarian thinkers such as a Bakunin,

Kropotkin, and Malatesta. We are thus faced with two legacies that have

unfolded in tandem with each other: a material one and an ideological

one.

Let us be frank and acknowledge that these legacies are not well-known

or easily understood. But from them we can weave an ethical approach to

social change that can give our endeavors definition and a possibility

of success. For one thing, we can declare that “what should be,”

humanity’s potentialities for freedom, rationality, and

self-consciousness, is to be actualized and guide our social lives. We

can affirm “what should be” on the basis of decidedly real material

possibilities and realizable ideological ones. Knowledge of “what should

be” if reason is to guide our behavior becomes the force driving us to

make social change and to produce a rational society. With our material

preconditions in place and with reason to guide us to the actualization

of our potentialities, notably a rational society, we can begin to

formulate the concrete steps that a future Left will be obliged to take

to achieve its ends. The material preconditions are demonstrably at

hand, and reason, fortified by a knowledge of past endeavors to produce

a relatively rational society, provides the means to formulate the

measures and the means, step by step, to produce a new Left that is

relevant for the foreseeable future.

An Ethical Compass for the Left

Far from eschewing reason and theory, a future Left that is meaningful

must be solidly grounded in theory if it is to have any power to

understand the present in relationship to the past, and the future in

relationship to the present. A lack of philosophical equipment to

interpret events, past and present, will render its theoretical insights

fragmentary and bereft of contextuality and continuity. Nor will it be

able two show how specific events relate to a larger whole and link them

together in a broad perspective. It was this admirable intention, I

should note, that induced Marx to give his ideas a systematic and

unified form, not any personal disposition on his part for

“totalitarianism.” The world in which he lived had to be shown that

capital accumulation and the bourgeoisie’s unrelenting concentration of

industrial resources were not products of greed but vital necessities

for enterprises in a sharply competitive economy.

One can project an alternative to the present society only by advancing

rational alternatives to the existing order of things – alternatives

that are objectively and logically based on humanity’s potentialities

for freedom and innovation. In this respect, the ability of human beings

to project themselves beyond their given circumstances, to rationally

recreate their world and their social relations, and to infuse

innovation with ethical judgments, becomes the basis for actualizing a

rational society.

This “what should be,” as educed by reason, stands on a higher plane of

truthfulness and wholeness than does the existential and pragmatic “what

is.” Figuratively speaking, the contrast between the “what should be”

and the “what is,” as elaborated and challenged by mind as well as by

experience, lies at the heart of dialectic. Indeed, the “what should

be,” by sitting in judgment on the validity of the given, joins

dialectical development in the biosphere with dialectical development in

the social sphere. It provides the basis for determining whether a

society is rational and to what degree it has rational content. Absent

such a criterion, we have no basis for social ethics apart from the

egocentric, adventitious, anarchic, and highly subjective statement “I

choose!” A social ethics cannot remain suspended in the air without an

objective foundation, a comprehensive evolution from the primitive to

the increasingly sophisticated, and a coherent content that supports its

development.

Moreover, without an objective potentiality (that is, the implicit

reality that lends itself to rational eduction, in contrast to mere

daydreaming) that sits in “judgment” of existential reality as

distinguished from a rationally conceived reality, we have no way to

derive an ethics that goes beyond mere personal taste. What is to guide

us in understanding the nature of freedom? Why is freedom superior to

mere custom or habit? Why is a free society desirable and an enslaved

one not, apart from taste and opinion? No social ethics is even

possible, let alone desirable, without a processual conception of

behavior, from its primal roots in the realm of potentiality at the

inception of a human evolution, through that evolution itself, to the

level of the rational and discursive. Without criteria supplied by the

dialectically derived “ought,” the foundations for a revolutionary

movement dissolve into an anarchic vacuum of personal choice, the

muddled notion that “what is good for me constitutes the good and the

true” – and that is that!

As much as we are obliged to deal with the “what is” – with the

existential facts of life, including capitalism – it is the

dialectically derived “true,” as Hegel might put it, that must always

remain our guide, precisely because it defines a rational society.

Abandon the rational, and we are reduced to the level of mere animality

from which the course of history and the great struggles of humanity for

emancipation have tended to free us. It is to break faith with History,

conceived as a rational development toward freedom and innovation, and

to diminish the defining standards of our humanity. If we often seem

adrift, it is not for lack of a compass and a map by which to guide

ourselves toward the actualization of our uniquely human and social

potentialities.

Which leads us to another premise for acquiring social truth: the

importance of dialectical thinking as our compass. This logic

constitutes both the method and the substance of an eductive process of

reasoning and unfolding. Eduction is the procedure that immanently

elicits the implicit traits that lend themselves to rational

actualization, namely freedom and innovation. A deep ecologist once

challenged me by asking why freedom should be more desirable than

unfreedom. I reply that freedom, as it develops objectively through

various phases of the ascent of life, from mere choice as a form of

self-maintenance to the recreation of the environment by intellection

and innovation, can make for a world that is more habitable, humane, and

creative than anything achieved by the interplay of natural forces.

Indeed, to rephrase a famous axiom of Hegel’s, a point can be reached in

a free society where what is not free is not real (or actual).

Indeed, a task of dialectical thinking is to separate the rational from

the arbitrary, external, and adventitious in which it unfolds, an

endeavor that demands considerable intellectual courage as well as

insight. Thus the conquests of Alexander the Great dovetail with the

rational movement of History, insofar as Alexander unified a decomposing

world made up of rotting city-states and parasitic monarchies and

transmitted Hellenic thought to it. But the explosion of Mongol horsemen

from the steppes of central Asia contributed no more to the rational

course of events than did, say, a decline in rainfall over North Africa

that turned a vast forested area into a grim formidable desert.

Moreover, to speak of a Mongol invasion as evidence of a “potentiality

for evil” is to divest the rich philosophical term potentiality of its

creative content. Much better to use here the ideologically neutral term

capacity, which can be applied anywhere for any phenomenon – and to no

intelligible purpose whatever.

The Libertarian Municipality

Remote as it may seem to some, dialectical thinking is in my view

indispensable for creating the map and formulating the agenda for a new

Left. The actualization of humanity’s potentiality for a rational

society – the “what should be” that is achieved by human development –

occurs in the fully democratic municipality, the municipality based on a

face-to-face democratic assembly composed of free citizens, for whom the

word politics means direct popular control over the community’s public

affairs by means of democratic institutions. Such a system of control

should occur within the framework of a duly constituted system of laws,

rationally derived by discourse, experience, historical knowledge, and

judgment. The free municipality, in effect, is not only a sphere for

deploying political tactics but a product of reason. Here means and ends

are in perfect congruence, without the troubling “transitions” that once

gave us a “dictatorship of the proletariat” that soon turned into a

dictatorship of the party.

Furthermore, the libertarian municipality, like any social artifact, is

constituted. It is to be consciously created by the exercise of reason,

not by arbitrary “choices” that lack objective ethical criteria and

therefore may easily yield oppressive institutions and chaotic

communities. The municipality’s constitution and laws should define the

duties as well as the rights of the citizen – that is, they should

explicitly clarify the realm of necessity as well as the realm of

freedom. The life of the municipality is determined by laws, not

arbitrarily “by men.” Law as such is not necessarily oppressive: indeed,

for thousands of years the oppressed demanded laws, as nomos, to prevent

arbitrary rule and the “tyranny of structurelessness.” In the free

municipality, law must always be rationally, discursively, and openly

derived and subject to careful consideration. At the same time we must

continually be aware of regulations and definitions that have harnessed

oppressed humanity to their oppressors.

As Rousseau saw, the municipality is not merely an agglomeration of

buildings but of free citizens. Combined with reason, order can yield

coherent institutions. Lacking order and reason, we are left with a

system of arbitrary rule, with controls that are not accountable or

answerable to the people – in short, with tyranny. What constitutes a

state is not the existence of institutions but rather the existence of

professional institutions, set apart from the people, that are designed

to dominate them for the express purpose of securing their oppression in

one form or another.

A revolutionary politics does not challenge the existence of

institutions as such but rather assesses whether a given institution is

emancipatory and rational or oppressive and irrational. The growing

proclivity, in oppositional movements, to transgress institutions and

laws merely because they are institutions and laws is in fact

reactionary and, in any case, serves to divert public attention away

from the need to create or transform institutions into democratic,

popular, and rational entities. A “politics” of disorder or “creative

chaos,” or a naive practice of “taking over the streets” (usually little

more than a street festival), regresses participants to the behavior of

a juvenile herd; by replacing the rational with the “primal” or

“playful,” it abandons the Enlightenment’s commitment to the civilized,

the cultivated, and the knowledgeable. Joyful as revolutions may

sometimes also be, they are primarily earnestly serious and even bloody

– and if they are not systematic and not astutely led, they will

invariably end in counter-revolution and terror. The Communards of 1871

may have been deliriously drunk when they “stormed the heavens” (as Marx

put it), but when they sobered up, they found that the walls surrounding

Paris had been breached by the counter-revolutionary Versaillais. After

a week of fighting, their resistance collapsed, and the Versaillais shot

them arbitrarily and in batches by the thousands. A politics that lacks

sufficient seriousness in its core behavior may make for wonderful

Anarchy but is disastrous revolutionism.

What specific political conclusions do these observations yield? What

political agenda do they support?

First, the “what should be” should preside over every tenet that makes

up a future political agenda and movement. As important as a politics of

protest may be, it is no substitute for a politics of social innovation.

Today Marxists and anarchists alike tend to behave defensively, merely

reacting to the existing social order and to the problems it creates.

Capitalism thus orchestrates the behavior of its intuitive opponents.

Moreover it has learned to mute opposition by shrewdly making partial

concessions to protesters. Thus when an anti-nuclear movement reaches

major proportions, one country may decide to limit the construction of

new reactors – but they multiply in other countries where no

anti-nuclear movement is threatening. Similarly, bioengineered foods may

be curbed in some places because of public fears about their effects,

but bioengineering expands exponentially in other places and

disciplines; or the industry may agree to take prudent self-limiting

measures rather than yield to complete public control.

The municipality, as we have seen, is the authentic terrain for the

actualization of humanity’s social potentialities to be free and

innovative. Still, left to itself, even the most emancipated

municipality may become parochial, insular, and narrow. Confederalism

remains at once the operational means of rounding out the deficits that

any municipality is likely to face when it introduces a libertarian

communist economy. Few, if any, municipalities are capable of meeting

their needs on their own. An attempt to achieve economic autarchy – and

the concomitant cultural parochialism that it so often yields in less

economically developed societies – would be socially undesirable. Nor

does the mere exchange of surplus products remove the commodity

relationship; the sharing of goods according to a truly libertarian view

is far different from an exchange of goods, which closely resembles

market exchanges. By what standard would the “value” of surplus

commodities be determined – by their congealed labor? The incipient

bases for a capitalist economy remained unrecognized even in anarchist

Catalonia, among those who boasted of their communist convictions.

Still another distinction that must be drawn is that between

policy-making decisions and strictly administrative ones. Just as the

problems of distribution must not be permitted to drag a community into

capitalist mores and market practices, administrators must not be

allowed to make policy decisions, which properly belong to the popular

assemblies. Such practices must be made, quite simply, illegal – that

is, the community must establish regulations, with punitive features,

forbidding committees and agencies to exercise rights that properly

belong to the assembled community. As insensitive as such measures may

seem to delicate libertarian sensibilities, they are justified by a

history in which hard-won rights were slowly eroded by elites who sought

privileges for themselves at the expense of the many. Post-scarcity in

the availability of the means of life may serve to render any pursuit of

economic privilege a laughable anachronism. But, as hierarchical society

has shown, something more than economic privileges, such as the

enhancement of status and power, may be involved.

Human beings actualize their potentialities not only in the free

municipality but in one that is rationally and discursively constituted

and institutionalized in free popular assemblies. Whatever politics

abets this development is historically progressive; any self-professed

politics that diminishes this development is reactionary and reinforces

the existing social order. Mere expressions of formless “community” that

devolve into “street festivals,” particularly when they become

substitutes for a libertarian municipalist politics (or, more

disturbingly, a distortion of them), feed the overall juvenilization

that capitalism promotes through its impetus to dumb down society on a

massive scale.

The Radical Challenge

During the interwar years, when proactive forces for revolutionary

change seemed to threaten the very existences of the social order, the

classical Left was focused on a distinct set of issues: the need for a

planned economy, the problems of a chronic economic crisis, the

imminence of a worldwide war, the advance of fascism, and the

challenging examples provided by the Russian Revolution. Today,

contemporary leftists are more focused on major ecological dislocations,

corporate gigantism, the influence of technology on daily life, and the

impact of the mass media. The classical Left looked at deep-seated

crises and the feasibility of revolutionary approaches to create social

change; the contemporary Left is more attentive to a different set of

abuses.

The issues dominant today are characteristic of a seemingly settled and

basically secure society that feels it can contain demands for change

within its orbit. The ills that currently exist, however troubling, seem

correctable without challenging the premises of the existing society.

Continental Europe especially, where cynicism has taken deep root in an

“end of history” mentality and where an unending repetition of the

status quo is assumed as the only future of humanity, sees the United

States as emblematic of the unshakable overall stability of the existing

order. America, in turn, has become almost gluttonously consumerist;

capitalist accumulation has brought with it a form of public

accumulation in which a corps of buyers with an unending number of

insatiable needs purchases an infinity of new products. Indeed, one of

the greatest problems facing American industry and commerce is how to

create new products to titillate public taste, even it means dredging up

old, long-discarded forms of entertainment and products and adding on

the vulgar glitz of the present age.

The capitalism under which we live today is far removed from the

capitalism that Marx knew and that revolutionaries of all kinds tried to

overthrow in the first half of the twentieth century. It has, indeed,

developed in great part along the lines Marx suggested in his closing

chapters of the first volume of Capital: as an economy whose very law of

life is accumulation, concentration, and expansion. When it can no

longer develop along these lines, it will cease to be capitalism. This

follows from the very logic of commodity exchange, with its expression

in competition and technological innovation.

Marxist productivism and anarchist individualism have both led to blind

alleys, albeit widely divergent ones. Where Marxism tends to

over-organize people into parties, unions, and proletarian “armies”

guided by elitist leaders, anarchism eschews organization and leaders as

“vanguards” and celebrates revolutionism as an instinctive impulse

unguided by reason or theory. Where Marxism celebrates technological

advances, without placing them in a rational, ethical, and ecological

context, anarchism deprecates sophisticated technics as the demonic

parent of the “technocratic man” who is lured to perdition by reason and

civilization. Technophilia has been pitted against technophobia;

analytical reason against raw instinct; and a synthetic civilization

against a presumably primeval nature.

The future of the Left, in the last analysis, depends upon its ability

to accept what is valid in both Marxism and anarchism for the present

time – and for the future that is coming into view. In an era of

permanent technological revolution, the validity of a theory and a

movement will depend profoundly on how clearly it can see what lies just

ahead. Radically new technologies, still difficult to imagine, will

undoubtedly be introduced that will have a transformative effect upon

the entire world. New power alignments may arise, that may well produce

a degree of social disequilibrium that has not been seen for decades.

New weapons of unspeakable homicidal and ecocidal effects may emerge.

The ecological crisis may continue.

But no greater damage could afflict human consciousness than the loss of

the Enlightenment program: the advance of reason, knowledge, science,

ethics, and even technics, which must be modulated to find a progressive

place in a free and humane society. Without the attainments of the

Enlightenment, no libertarian revolutionary consciousness is possible.

In assessing the revolutionary tradition, a reasoned Left has to shake

off dead traditions that, as Marx warned, weigh on the heads of the

living, and to commit itself to create to a rational society and a

rounded civilization. A Marxism that retains a meaningless focus on

proletarian hegemony, and an anarchism that has never stirred the “soil”

beneath the “snow” of reason, civilization, and technics, may well serve

to make irrelevant the components of past revolutionary ideologies that

are still vital, components whose lasting achievements our time greatly

needs.

Toward a Communalist Approach

There is an urgent need for a new radical approach to adequately address

the new economic, ecological, technological, and cultural challenges of

contemporary society; it must be one of theory and action, one that will

draw on features from classical Marxism, socialism, and anarchism, yet

go beyond their historical and theoretical limitations.

Conceived as they all were in the socially tumultuous era of industrial

revolution, the ideologies of communism, socialism, and the more social

versions of anarchism responded with a reasonable degree of adequacy to

the challenges of the oppressive and exploitative circumstances and

contexts in which they took form. In Marx’s hands, communism provided a

philosophy, a theory of history, and a political strategy centered on a

revolutionary class agent – the industrial proletariat – the coherence

of which was unequaled by any other body of social theory and practice

in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. But Marxism’s

historical adequacy as a revolutionary ideology depended overwhelmingly

on the social and economic conditions of the Industrial Revolution as

they existed between 1848 and 1871. The degradation of the factory

proletariat and the oppressions inflicted by the industrial bourgeoisie

led to a furious class war. A remarkable confluence of circumstances –

particularly the outbreak in 1914 of the worst war that humanity had

ever known and the instability of quasi-feudal governments in most of

continental Europe – allowed Lenin to use (and misuse) Marxism to take

power in a vast, economically backward empire. The first “proletarian

state” to hold power in history went on to produce a tyrannical state

system that lasted for decades and tragically smothered socialism under

a dark totalitarian regime.

Once World War One opened the revolutionary interwar period, however,

socialism qua social democracy, despite its professed radical goals,

responded by retreating to the liberal credo it had always held close to

its heart, finally abandoning all its rhetorical pretensions as a

radical movement for social change. In all fairness, however, the

conventional social democratic parties constituted more of an authentic

working-class movement than most of their competitors on the Left. Apart

from rare – and remarkable – occasions brought about by unusual

constellations of events, the proletariat proved not to be the fervent

revolutionary agent that Marx, Engels, and the syndicalist theorists had

believed it was. While its left-wing devotees celebrated the working

class fervently for its alleged susceptibility to revolutionary ideas,

workers in reality proved to be as closely wedded to bourgeois society

as were the middle classes with which Marxists and anarcho-syndicalists

contrasted them. With few exceptions the proletariat responded in vastly

greater numbers to the reformist directives of pragmatic trade union

leaders than to the revolutionary pleas of communist propagandists. Rosa

Luxemburg and Karl Liebknecht of the revolutionary Spartacus League, for

example, never exercised the enormous influence over the German workers

that Karl Legien, of the reformist (social democratic) Free Trade

Unions, enjoyed.

Capitalism thus survived the horrors of two long world wars, the

international impact of the Russian Revolution, and a highly unstable

Depression decade in the 1930s. Although it was badly shaken at times,

in the end capitalism did not lose its overall legitimacy (except

perhaps in Spain in 1936) in the eyes of the very class that Marxism and

syndicalism had selected as its historically revolutionary agent.

Anarchism (which should not be confused with syndicalism and communism)

in its pure form meant little more than unrelenting resistance to and

protest against attempts by society and particularly the state to

confine individual liberty. It appealed mainly to marginal, déclassé

elements, ranging from the dispossessed to idiosyncratic artists and

writers. Although rarely influential as an ideology, it resonated with

the agrarian bunty, the Russian peasant uprisings that were notorious

for their destructive, sometimes anti-urban insurrections. When

impulsive anarchist sentiments affected well-organized proletarian

struggles, they mutated into anarcho-syndicalism, which was seldom

internally stable or free of serious tensions. Many anarcho-syndicalist

notions, such as workers’ control over industry and confederally

structured revolutionary trade unions, enjoyed a considerable vogue

among industrial workers; still, in the absence of external pressure and

persecution by the bourgeoisie and the state, anarcho-syndicalist unions

seldom refrained from compromising their libertarian principles.

The great theories advanced by Marxists, socialists, anarchists, and

anarcho-syndicalists, then, were insightful on many issues and were

sometimes inspiring in making a socialistic revolution a realizable

possibility. But today these theories are understandably incapable of

encompassing and programmatically integrating into a coherent whole the

new social issues, potential class realignments, and economic advances

that have arisen (and that continue to arise) with extraordinary

rapidity since the end of World War Two. To simply resuscitate them,

even in the face of the failures they produced, and pretend that they

enjoy an unchallengeable ideological immortality, would be dogmatic

fatuity.

Significantly, capitalism has changed in many respects since World War

Two. It has created new, generalized social issues that are not limited

to wages, hours, and working conditions – notably environmental, gender,

hierarchical, civic, and democratic issues. The problems raised by these

issues cut across class lines, even as they exacerbate or modify the

problems that once gave rise to the classical revolutionary movements.

Older definitions of freedom, while preserving certain unassailable

components, become inadequate in the light of later historical advances;

so too older revolutionary theories and movements, while losing none of

their insights and lessons, become inadequate with the passage of time,

as the emergence of new issues necessitate broader programs and

movements.

Since Marxism was fashioned in the context of the Industrial Revolution,

it would indeed be uncanny if it did not require sweeping revisions and

redefinitions as a body of ideas. Or if socialism (qua social democracy)

– all its cross-currents and variations notwithstanding – remained a

fixed strategy for achieving basic social change in the face of new

developments over the past fifty years. Or if anarchism and its

variants, with their central demand for personal autonomy (as opposed to

social freedom), could adequately deal with the new ecological,

hierarchical, technological, democratic, and civic issues that have

arisen.

Nor can the proletariat, whose class identity is being subverted by an

immense middle class, hope to speak for the majority of the population.

Capitalism is inflicting generalized threats on humanity, sweeping

problems such as globalization, climate changes that may alter the very

face of the planet, challenges to civil rights and traditional freedoms,

and the radical transformation of civic life as a result of rampant

urbanization; other issues have yet to emerge as a result of the

immensely transformative technologies that will make the coming century

unrecognizable. A new revolutionary movement must be capable of dealing

not only with the more familiar issues that linger on, but with new,

more general ones that potentially may bring the vast majority of

society into opposition to an ever evolving and challenging capitalist

system.

That these major problems that confront us were not on the agenda of

previous socialistic movements, or else were treated marginally, should

not surprise us. A socially oriented ecology has yet to take hold,

despite newly arrived anarchists’ attempts to impute one to Peter

Kropotkin or Elisée Reclus. Older movements regarded hierarchy, if they

saw it as undesirable at all, more as an epiphenomenon of class

structures and the state than as the oppressive institutionalization of

cultural and economic differentiation among men, and between men and

women, that emerged very early in social life. Classical socialists and

anarchists cloaked the role of the city and democracy in human affairs

in such strictly class terms that they barely explored them as arenas

for human development and self-realization. Indeed, nearly all classical

radical and revolutionary discussions centered on the industrial

proletariat, which was supposed to become the majority of the population

in Western European countries and would inevitably be driven to

revolution by capitalist exploitation and immiseration.[42]

What classical revolutionary ideologies can teach us is that capitalism

remains a grossly irrational social order in which the pursuit of profit

and the accumulation of wealth for its own sake pollutes every material

and spiritual advance. It is an economic and social order that now

threatens to afflict humanity with the homogenization and atomization of

human relationships by the spread of commodity production and by the

disintegration of community life and solidarity. This crisis-ridden

society will not disappear on its own: it has to be opposed

unrelentingly by a dedicated Left that must be committed to the rescuing

of the high estate of reason in human affairs that is currently under

siege by anti-Enlightenment forces. To encompass the problems we face

today, the ideological orbit described by Marxism, anarchism, and (to a

lesser degree) socialism qua social democracy would have to be expanded

beyond recognition. To this end the idea of communalism is presented as

a project – one that will render the best in classical revolutionary

ideologies relevant to a new century and confront problems that were

formerly little more than ancillary anticipations.

What is Communalism?

Communalism is an attempt to enter into a more advanced terrain of

revolutionary ideas. From the outset, we must distinguish communalism,

as a tradition and a theory, from communitarianism, with which it is

often mistaken. Communitarianism was and is a movement to establish

communities that are organized around cooperative personal living and

working arrangements, such as were common among counter-cultural youth

during the 1960s and 1970s. Their propagators saw these islets of the

good life as products of healthy normal human impulses, in contrast to

evil conventional norms that warped or blotted out such impulses. The

most famous communitarians were nineteenth-century utopian visionaries

such as Robert Owen (whose followers established the New Harmony

community) and John Humphrey Noyes (a religious social reformer who

established the more successful Oneida community in New York State).

These experiments and radical ones like them rested on the conviction

that once enough people adopted cooperative lifestyles, they would

eventually abandon the evil world of private property and egoism in

favor of new cooperative living arrangements.

Most commonly, however, the social perspective of communitarians was

highly limited. They usually saw their communities as personal refuges

from the ills of the surrounding world. But communitarianism – which is

still alive in the writings of Robert Theobald, a variety of

cooperativists, and assorted anarchists – is basically a lifestyle

project, committed to the ethical and often quasi-religious principle

that humanity is innately good and must be restored to its pristine

condition of kindness and mutual aid, primarily by example and gradual

physical expansion. In a word, communitarianism – to the extent that it

even seeks to change the world – slowly inculcates the values of

goodness by a one-to-one conversion to particular living arrangements.

Communalism, by contrast, is a revolutionary political theory and

practice, deeply rooted in the general socialist tradition. Far from

setting up models or examples of cooperative lifestyles, it actively

seeks to confront capital and the basic structures of state power. Far

from functioning as a personal refuge, it seeks to construct a broad

civic sphere and markedly enhance political involvement. Indeed, it

seeks to reconstruct municipalities as a whole to form a counter-power

to the nation-state. The word has roots as a political term in the Paris

Commune of 1871, when the armed people of the French capital fought for

the idea of a quasi-socialistic confederation of the nation’s cities and

towns or communes (as they are called to this day in many parts of

Europe). Today, we can still get a sense of the far-reaching social

goals of communalism from consulting even conventional reference books

like The American Heritage Dictionary.

Socialist revolutionary theory seldom attributed an important place to

municipalities. Early nineteenth-century socialists were concerned

mainly with influencing the working class and ultimately gaining control

of the nation-state. Apart from anarchists, most left-wingers tended

retrospectively to admire the Jacobins of the Great French Revolution,

who were the advocates of a highly centralized state apparatus. The

Jacobins’ principal opponents on the Left, the Girondins, preached a

federalist message but were closely associated with the

counter-revolution of the 1790s and hated revolutionary Paris so deeply

that their federalist ideas fell into disrepute on the Left. Not for

decades would federalism gain a good name among French radicals.

After the Revolution the most active European movements for social

change were spawned less in the countryside than in towns and cities.

Insurgent Paris exploded in the insurrection of 1830 and in a workers’

uprising in June 1848 – and the French capital was highly conscious of

its ancient municipal identity and liberties. Well into the twentieth

century it clung to that identification with civic freedom with

extraordinary fervor. Indeed, in the years to come many socialistic

revolutions that swept over Europe, even those that were

internationalist in character, were notable for the hegemonic role that

municipalities played in their uprisings. “Red Petrograd,” “Red Berlin,”

and “Red and Black Barcelona” became synonymous with particularly

incendiary uprisings between 1917 and 1936. More often than not, a

municipality initiated a revolution, and its success in overthrowing the

old local authorities initiated a nationwide insurrection.

On closer inspection, the civic nature of most modern revolutions points

to the fundamental role that municipalities have played as incubators of

social development and the functions they have performed in fulfilling

humanity’s potentialities. When Aristotle wrote his political works he

set a standard for the Western conception of the city, defining it as

the arena for the development of citizenship and even humanness itself,

specifically reason, self-consciousness, and the good life. The Hellenic

word polis, from which we derive the word political, has too often been

wrongly translated as “city-state.” In fact the Athenian polis was not a

state but a humanly scaled municipality that became an outright

face-to-face democracy. The Athenians of the fifth century BCE would

have regarded even a modern republic as oppressive and would have found

its bureaucratic apparatus oligarchical at best and tyrannical at worst.

In Periclean times they drew a clear distinction between monarchy,

aristocracy, oligarchy, and democracy. They generally viewed a

face-to-face democracy as the fulfillment of the polis’s evolution out

of assemblages of households, and they continued to treasure its

essentially democratic features over all other forms, even after their

Roman conquerors virtually eliminated it.

Communalism not only recaptures these functions but goes beyond them as

an effort to constitute the developmental arena of mind and discourse.

By contrast, modern urbanized cities reduce citizens to mere co-dwellers

who live in close physical proximity to one another, or to taxpayers who

expect the city to provide them with goods and services in return for

revenue. As such, communalism sees the municipality as potentially a

transformative development beyond organic evolution into the domain of

social evolution. Indeed, for communalists the municipality is the

domain wherein mere adaptation to changing environments is supplanted by

proactive association based on the free exchange of ideas, the creative

endeavor to bring consciousness to the service of change, and the

collective vehicle, where necessary, to intervene in the world with a

view toward ending environmental as well as economic insults. The

municipality, once it is freed of hierarchical domination and material

exploitation – indeed, once it is recreated as rational arena for human

creativity in all spheres of life – is potentially the ethical space for

the good life. It is also potentially the school for the formation of a

new human being, the citizen, who has shed the archaic blood ties of

tribalism and the hierarchical impulses created by differences in

ethnicity, gender, and parochial exclusivity.

Historically, the municipality was the domain that, at least

juridically, dissolved the blood tie, which had formerly united family

and tribe according to the facts of biology, to the exclusion of the

outsider. It was in the municipality, eventually, that the once-feared

stranger could be absorbed into a community of citizens, initially as

the coequal of all other residents who occupied a common territory and

eventually as a member of the citizens’ assembly, engaging with all

other free male residents in making policy decisions. In this respect,

the formation of the municipality antedated the rise of the state –

which, it is worth noting, appeared among agrarian peoples well before

it appeared among their urban cousins.

Indeed, the state, which may be defined as an organized system of

dominance by a privileged class, was continually in tension, if not in

open warfare, with the municipality. The so-called autonomous cities of

the medieval world were in conflict with medieval and Renaissance

monarchs as well as with territorial lords, both of whom threatened

their civic freedoms. To be sure, internal conflicts raged within their

own walls between various classes and estates. But if they were not

often at peace either with themselves or with their external opponents,

their libertarian origins were seldom forgotten: during periods of

crisis, these sentiments surfaced as revolutionary upsurges in Europe

and even Asia. Indeed today, when the nation-state seems supreme,

whatever rights municipalities retain are the hard-won gains of

commoners, who over the course of history preserved them against

assaults by ruling classes. Characteristically, the comuñero uprising of

the Castilian cities in 1520–22 and the journées of the Parisian

sectional assemblies during the French Revolution (to cite only two of

the more outstanding cases) were impelled by strong civic sentiments and

by demands for a Federation of Communes.

Thus communalism is no contrived body of political and social concepts,

spun out from the vagrant fancies of mere imagination. In many respects,

it expresses an abiding concept of political reconstruction, one that

long antedates nationalism. As a movement of downtrodden classes, its

pedigree is perhaps more ambiguous. The guildsmen who kept their muskets

and swords at the ready beside their workbenches, so as to be able to

immediately rise to the defense of their hard-won liberties, often had a

class status somewhere between the beggarly crowds that filled the

medieval cities and the patricians. In fact, upper-class nobles often

hired déclassés from the towns to undermine the status and political

influence of the craftsmen-burghers. Nevertheless, it was this burgher

stratum that fashioned the ideals of civic freedom and political

participation, upon which all the great revolutionaries of later years

drew, often with no knowledge of their medieval origins.

Here, too, however, contemporary language betrays the past, just as it

does when polis is translated as “city-state.” The word politics,

derived as it is from the Greek word for “city,” denotes an activity

that is charged with moral obligation to one’s own community – in

contrast to statecraft, which minimally presupposes a professionalized

and bureaucratic state apparatus that is expressly set apart from the

people. Politics once referred to the civic responsibilities that all

citizens were expected to discharge as ethical beings. In the Middle

Ages, citizens committed themselves to undertake these political

responsibilities by swearing an ethical oath or pledge of fraternity – a

conjuratio – which was seen not as a contract but minimally as a moral

vow to act in the interests of all who lived and worked in the city.

They participated in citizens’ assemblies that either formulated civic

policies themselves or else annually elected a publicly responsible

administrative committee. The city was defended from external threats by

a popular militia, while a citizens’ guard maintained domestic peace.

Any attempt at professionalization of the city’s administrative

apparatus, even if tentatively undertaken to deal with the dangers of

invasion and war, was viewed with deep suspicion.

Thus politics originally did not mean statecraft. In contrast to the

self-governing polis, the state consists of the institutions by which a

privileged and exploitative class imposes itself, by force where

necessary, on an oppressed and exploited class. Statecraft is the

activity of officials within that professional machinery to control the

citizenry in the interests of that privileged class. By contrast,

politics is the active participation of free citizens in managing the

affairs of the city and defending its freedom. Only after centuries of

civic debasement, marked by class formation, conflict, and mutual

hatred, was the state produced and politics degraded to the practice of

statecraft. With the rise of statecraft, people became disengaged from

moral responsibility for their cities; the city was transformed,

ultimately along with the nation, into a provider of goods and services.

Proactive citizens, filled with a deep moral commitment to their cities,

gradually gave way to the passive subjects of rulers and to the

constituents of parliamentarians, until today they are, in fact, little

more than consumers whose free time is spent in shopping malls and

retail stores.

Municipal Freedoms and Autonomy

Communalism is in every way a decidedly political body of ideas that

seeks to recover the city or commune in accordance with its greatest

historical traditions, and to advance its development. It seeks to

create popular assemblies as vital decision-making arenas for civic

life. It advances a civic ethics predicated on reason, and a

municipalized economy.

In advancing these goals, communalism seeks to actualize the traits that

potentially make us human. It departs decidedly from Marxist notions of

a centralized state, let alone a dictatorial regime ostensibly based on

the interests of a single class. At the same time it goes beyond loose

anarchist notions of autonomous confederations, collectives, and towns,

which ostensibly can “go it on their own” as they choose without due

consideration for the society as a whole. These ad hoc, often chaotic

and “spontaneous” anarchic escapades in autonomy, even in “temporary

autonomous zones,” usually express individualistic, indeed egocentric,

impulses that in practice lead to demands for the unrestricted rights of

sovereign individuals without requiring of them any obligatory duties.

Anarchists and their affines often dismiss obligations of any sort as

authoritarian or worse. But one of the great maxims of the First

International, to which all factions subscribed, was Marx’s slogan: “No

Rights Without Duties, No Duties Without Rights.” In a free society, as

revolutionaries of all kinds generally understood, we would enjoy

freedoms (“rights”), but we would also have responsibilities (“duties”)

we would have to exercise. The concept of individual autonomy becomes

meaningless when it denies the obligations that every individual owes to

society as social responsibilities.

We are all shaped to one degree or another by forces outside our control

and, frankly, beyond our control. No one can live forever, or do without

nutrition; and after a certain age simply keeping oneself in health

requires numerous – even onerous – efforts. In the fullness of daily

life, long life requires effort and calls for actions that may be

painful, annoying, demanding, and disagreeable. We are thus always under

some kind of constraint; the real issue is whether a constraint is

rational and advances the fulfillment of the good life or whether it is

exploitative and irrational. It is the height of hubris to believe that

total “autonomy” – including the right to “choose” whatever one wants

about anything – can coexist with society.

Communalists seek to create a democratic, collectivist social order.

Property, in a communalist society, will be municipalized and its

overall management placed in the hands of popular assemblies. In past

revolutions efforts at “workers’ control” over factories and farms were

frequently plagued by parochialism and evolved into forms of

collectivistic capitalism. By contrast, communalism calls for the full

administrative coordination of all public enterprises by confederal

committees, whose members are the responsible voices of the popular

assemblies; without the assent of the citizenry as a whole in a

confederation-wide vote, no policy-making confederal decision can be

valid.

Pragmatically, a communalist polity requires a written constitution and,

yes, regulatory laws, to avoid a structurelessness that would yield

mindless anarchy. The more defined the rights and duties of citizens

are, the more easily can they be upheld as part of the general interest

against the intrusion of petty tyrannies. It is not the clarity of

definitions that has oppressed humanity; rather, wrong definitions have

been used cannily to uphold privilege and domination. Indeed,

constitutions and laws served to free the ancient bondsman of arbitrary

despotism and even women of patriarchal control. From the earliest times

oppressed peoples have raised the demand for constitutions and laws; in

their absence “barons” (to use Hesiod’s term in the seventh century BCE)

arbitrarily inflicted rule and terror on the masses. Anarchist demands

to eliminate law as such, without providing for substantive ways to

avoid the oppressions of structurelessness and arbitrary behavior, have

produced mayhem and tyranny more reliably than liberty and autonomy.

Historically, constitutions and laws have indeed been oppressive, often

grossly so, but this raises the question of their content, not the fact

of their existence. Indeed, only a peculiarly egocentric mentality will

assume that a rationally constituted society and a rationally formulated

body of laws must necessarily violate personal autonomy and hence social

freedom. Nothing more clearly sheds light on the individualistic basis

of present-day anarchism and its Proudhonesque origins than this

personalistic fear of any limitation on individual behavior. Taking

recourse to biologistic “instinct” as a guide to a libertarian

lifestyle, rooting freedom in human nature and in prehistory, anarchists

inadvertently petrify freedom rather than ensure it.

Communalism’s concept of the free municipality (in contrast to the

primitivistic, technophobic anarchic image of “autonomy”) is, I would

argue, a product of reason in history, or what I have called the “legacy

of freedom,” and indeed the embodiment of reason institutionally and

legally. It is reason constituted in institutions, embodied in the

functioning of these institutions – that is, in their constitution and

their laws, as well as in citizens, and their personal life-ways,

productive activities, and intersubjective relations or

“socializations.” To reduce constitutions and laws ipso facto to

trammels that bind free will is to make a mockery not only of reason but

of humaneness – for what remains of the human being, after this

reduction, is little more than animality and biology. It thereby negates

the historic function of the free city except as a habitation of a

peculiar kind, and in the spirit of William Morris (whose utopia News

from Nowhere is by no means a credit to a rational vision of society),

the less we have of it, the better!

Communalism, in effect, declares that each individual should act with

full regard for the needs of all, and that democracy decidedly includes

the rights of a dissenting minority to freely and fully express itself.

Within a confederation over broader regional areas the decisions of

individual assemblies merge with those of all the assemblies; thus the

popular decisions of the entire confederation are taken as a single

assembly.

Assuredly, a failure to deal rationally and humanely with necessity,

which cannot be evaded in any aspect of life, is the most certain path

to oppression and worse. Pure anarchism, whose crude individualism

regards the ego as a natural entity rather than a socially formed

subject, tends to negate everything about capitalist society and seek

out its opposite without any qualifications, as though a libertarian

society is the mere negation of bourgeois society. In its most extreme

form, this express individualism demands the disbanding of society as

such; hence the fascination of so many anarchist writers with

primitivism, their technophobic outlook, their aversion to regulation of

any kind, and indeed their hatred of necessity. Must even the

self-regulatory features of social life really be abolished in favor of

reliance on an alleged instinct for mutual aid or, more startling, on

custom? Beyond such mechanism, anarchism in fact relies on old socialist

tenets, such as workers’ control and direct democracy, which it has

picked up and, in the best of cases, eagerly embraced as its own.

Communalism demands great advances in theory (not its denigration) as

well as permanent activity (in the form of firmly established

institutions, deeply rooted in a community and marked by their

continuity) – not ad hoc escapades that dissipate after a demonstration,

riot, or the establishment of a “temporary autonomous zone.” If activism

is reduced to demonstrations, riots, and TAZs, then revolution is

nothing but a few hours of frolicking, after which the real authority of

the state and ruling class takes over. Capitalism has nothing to fear

from frolicking; indeed, its fashion designers and lifestyle specialists

are only too eager to turn juvenile expressions of dissent into highly

merchandisable commodities.

No less disturbing is the passion that many devotees of pure anarchism

exhibit for consensus as a form of decision-making. The veneration of

individual autonomy can become so radical that it would permit no

majority, no matter how large, to override even “a majority of one,” as

some anarchist writers have put it. In this extreme fetishization of

individualism, the core anarchic concept of the all-sovereign ego

stands, in all its splendor, against the wishes of the majority. By

permitting the self-sufficient ego, by its merest inclinations, to

override the wishes of the community, anarchism becomes untenable.

Coordinated political organization become impossible, as it did in Spain

in 1933, when part of the Nosotros affinity group, led by Buenaventura

Durruti, chose to lead an insurrection in Saragossa (which was doomed),

while others like Juan García Oliver, his trusted compañero, simply

abstained and discouraged others from giving military aid to their

comrades in the Aragonese city.

Communalist Organization

The establishment of an organization places certain constraints on the

autonomy of its members, but that in itself does not necessarily make it

authoritarian. “Libertarian organization” is not a contradiction in

terms. In the early twentieth century leading Spanish anarchists had

opposed the very formation of the CNT because it was an organization and

as such demanded of its members the fulfillment of onerous duties. But

organization as such is not authoritarian.

The formation of communalist political institutions depends on the

formation of a communalist organization. How can one be established? It

would be useful to provide a summary of some measures that will be

necessary to create such an organization, as well as briefly describe

the role it can be expected to play in a larger libertarian municipalist

movement.

To begin with, politically concerned individuals who feel the need to

explore communalist ideas and practices may form a study group in a

given neighborhood or town. The study groups seek to inform and develop

those interested in social and political change into fully competent

individuals and leaders. At a time when the knowledge of philosophy,

history, and social theory has retreated appallingly, the objects of

study may range from immediate political issues to the great

intellectual traditions of the past. Minimally, however, the group

should give social theory and the history of ideas pronounced attention,

particularly insofar as these subjects enlarge members’ understanding of

a municipalist approach to democracy and social change.

The study groups, whose members are by now composed of individuals who

are committed to a serious exploration of ideas, should begin to

function within the neighborhood, town, or city in which they are

located. They seek to enter and remain in the public domain – to be a

continual revolutionary presence by virtue of their ideas, their

emphasis on organization, their methods, and their goals. Communalists

refuse to withdraw from the public domain in the name of individual

sovereignty, artistic expression, or self-absorption. They wear no ski

masks, either metaphorically or physically, and do not allow mindless

dogmatic assumptions and simplifications to stand in their way. They are

always accessible and transparent, involved and responsible. They can be

expected to establish a well-informed, carefully structured

organization, if possible with neighborhood branches.

The organization’s goals should be carefully formulated into a concrete

program, based on communalist principles, that consistently demands the

formation of policy-making municipal popular assemblies. As a component

of a minimum program, no issue is too trivial for communalists to

ignore, be it transportation, recreation, education, welfare, zoning,

environment, housing, public safety, democracy, civil rights, and the

like. The primacy that communalists give to the establishment and

development of popular assemblies does not mean that they ignore other

issues of concern to the citizenry. To the contrary they resolutely

fight – both within municipal institutions and outside them – for all

steps to improve civic life in their communities and elsewhere. On

specific issues, such as globalization, environmental problems, ethnic

and gender discrimination, communalist organizations freely enter into

coalitions with other organizations to engage in common struggles, but

they should never surrender their ideological or organizational

independence or their claim to their own independent action. Their

identity, ideas, and institutions are their most precious possessions

and must never be impugned in the interests of “unity.”

Indeed, while working on these issues, they always seek to enlarge them,

to reveal through a transitional program their deep-seated roots. They

escalate cries for reforms into radical demands, seeking to expand every

civil and political right of the people by creating the institutional

power to formulate decision-making policies and see to their execution.

The implications of solving these problems is a call for a revolution in

social relations – that is, the achievement of a maximum program based

on the confederation of municipalist assemblies in which property is

steadily municipalized and subjected to coordination by confederal

administrative bodies.[43]

The communalist organization, while always retaining its identity and

program, initiates regular public forums to engage in discursive,

face-to-face democratic exploration of ideas – partly to spread its

program and basic ideas and partly to create public spaces that provide

venues for radical civic debate, until actual popular assemblies can be

established. While it will clearly become involved in local issues, its

primary focus should be the public domain where real power is vested:

municipal elections, which allow for a close association between

communalist candidates (for city councils or their equivalents) and the

people.

The ablest members of the communalist organization should stand in

municipal elections and call for the changing of city charters so as to

legally empower the municipal assemblies. The new communalist

organization should expressly seek to be elected to municipal positions

with a view to using charter or extralegal changes to significantly

shift municipal power from existing state-like and seemingly

representative institutions to popular assemblies as embodiments of

direct democracy. Where no city charter exists that can be changed

electorally, communalists should attempt (both educationally and

organizationally) to convene direct democratic assemblies on an

extralegal basis, exercising moral pressure on statist institutions, in

the hope that people will, in time, regard them as authentic centers of

public power with the expectation that they can thereby gain structural

power. Communalism never compromises by advocating delegated or statist

institutional structures, and in contrast to organizations such as the

Greens, it refuses to exist within the institutional cage of the

nation-state or to try to gild it with reforms that ultimately simply

make the state more palatable.

A communalist group or movement that refuses to run candidates in

municipal elections where it can, and thereby removes its focus on the

centers of institutionalized municipal power, will shrivel into an ad

hoc, rootless, sporadic, polymorphous form of anarchic protest and

quickly fade away. It will be communalist in name only, not in content.

It is concerned not with the locus of power but with mere defiance at

best, which leads nowhere or terminates in frolicking with the system at

worst. In the communalist vision, public assemblies in confederation are

a means for destroying the state and capitalism, as well as the

embodiments of a rational society. To hop from demonstration to

demonstration without attempting to recreate power in the form of public

assemblies by taking control of city councils (which means practicing

politics in opposition to parliamentary statecraft) is to make a mockery

of communalism.

Communalists seek to create a fully democratic society, but they never

fetishize numbers, be it numbers of members, voters, participants in

public assemblies, and the like. In a communalist polity it suffices

that the doors of a public assembly are always open to the citizenry. If

a majority of a neighborhood, town, or city choose to attend an assembly

meeting and become participants in making important decisions, all the

better, but if only a few are sufficiently interested in the political

fate of their community to attend, so be it. The assembly’s decisions

carry the same weight, regardless of whether the number of people

present is a dozen, a hundred, or several thousand. Political decisions

should be made by politically involved citizens: Under no circumstances

should poor attendance at a public assembly be an excuse to abandon a

direct and discursive democracy in favor of anonymous voting at polls,

which renders politics impersonal and non-discursive.

Communalist groups call for the popular assemblies – be they legally

empowered or only morally empowered – to confederate, with a view toward

replacing the state. In effect, communalists aim at establishing a dual

power of citizen-constituted institutions that will challenge the

authority, legitimacy, and policies of existing institutions.

Throughout, municipal confederations should hold regular congresses and

conferences, plenaries and committee meetings. As need arises, they

establish extraordinary commissions to undertake specific tasks.

Wherever assemblies elect delegates to coordinate a confederal

association, they ensure that the delegates’ powers are always mandated

by their respective citizens’ assemblies and that the delegates

themselves are always subject to recall. Emerging libertarian

municipalities must be united through the formation of well-organized

and socially responsible confederations.

An organization that is more advanced theoretically and programmatically

than the broader public movement of which it is part has every right to

regard itself as a vanguard, just as the French term avant-garde denoted

that certain artistic, musical, and other schools were more advanced in

practice and thought. Obviously, such an acknowledgement does not confer

upon a vanguard any special privileges, but it simply recognizes that

their ideas and practical contributions can be expected to have a

marked, indeed guiding, importance. An advanced, highly conscious

political organization should provide leadership, yet always retaining

its independence institutionally and functionally. By the same token,

not everyone in an organization has the same level of experience,

knowledge, wisdom, and leadership ability. Leadership that is not

formalized will be informal, but it will not disappear. Many individuals

in revolutionary groups were outright leaders, whose views had more

significance than others; it is a disservice to perpetuate the deception

that they were simply “influential militants.” Leadership always exists,

however much libertarians try to deny the fact by concealing its

existence beneath euphemisms.

A serious libertarian organization would establish not only leaders but

also means by which the membership may recall leaders whose views and

behavior they oppose, and effectively modify their activities. On the

other hand, frivolous opposition to leaders for its own sake should

never be tolerated. One of the most scandalous features of anarchist

organizations (when they exist) has been the dizzying individualism that

permits neurotic personalities to disrupt meetings and activities as

expressions of selfhood. Similarly, the use of ad hominem attacks,

gossip, and personal rumors to undermine the influence of leaders and

subvert serious ideas has done much to prevent anarchists from

establishing effective organizations.

Finally, communalism is not simply a vehicle for establishing a

communalist polity and the appropriate institutions. It is also an

outlook that includes a philosophical approach to reality as well as

society and toward the natural world as well as human development. It

contends that the ongoing crisis in our culture and values stems not

from an overabundance of civilization but from an insufficiency of it.

It defends technological development, used rationally and morally, as

reducing labor and creating free time that potentially allows citizens

to participate in public affairs, time for creativity, a reasonable

abundance in the means of life, and even, in a rational and ecological

society, the ability to improve upon the impact of natural forces.

Post-scarcity abundance (not to be confused with the mindless

consumerism fostered by capitalism) must be wisely tempered and

controlled by municipal assemblies and the free confederal institutions

that an emancipated society can create.

Above all, communalism stakes out a claim as a continuation of all that

is emancipatory in the Enlightenment tradition of the seventeenth and

eighteenth centuries. It firmly shares the Enlightenment’s conception

that freedom constitutes the defining potentiality of humanness: the

potentiality for the self-elaboration of reason by rational praxis until

humanity finally achieves the actualization of a truly rational society.

This self-actualization of humanity’s potentiality for reason,

creativity, and self-consciousness is more than a distant ideal; it is

the one abiding goal that gives meaning to any effort to change the

world. Indeed, the magnificent goal of advancing reason, creativity, and

self-consciousness in human affairs is all that gives meaning to the

evolution of humanity itself as the potentially creative agent; in its

absence the world has no meaning. This goal should hover over every

transformative project that communalists undertake in their efforts to

make an inhuman world into a human one and an irrational society into a

rational one – favoring a commitment to truth and innovation,

irrespective of what is so misleadingly called realism and adaptation.

It is not by any pragmatic map but by this flame, which is fueled by

reason’s conception of “what should be” as against “what is,” that

humanity can fulfill its potentiality for reason and self-consciousness,

thereby justifying itself in the scheme of things.

[1] The most comprehensive and accessible overview of these ideas is

Janet Biehl’s book The Politics of Social Ecology: Libertarian

Municipalism (Montréal: Black Rose Books, 1998), a work that Bookchin

himself often recommended as the best introduction to his political

ideas.

[2] The book was originally published by Sierra Club Books (San

Francisco) as The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship in

1987; republished by Black Rose Books (Montréal) in 1992 as Urbanization

Without Cities: The Rise and Decline of Citizenship; and finally

republished in a revised version as From Urbanization to Cities: Toward

a Politics of Citizenship, by Cassell (London) in 1995. Despite the

fairly dry titles, the book gives a vivid account of the emergence and

meaning of politics, citizenship, and civic development.

[3] This small book was published by AK Press in 2007.

[4] We also discussed his manuscript on philosophy, The Politics of

Cosmology, which he wanted me to work on; he gave me a copy with

instructions on how to edit it, and I gave him my promise that I would

see to its publication.

[5] Communalism was first launched in October 2002 on the Internet.

Apart from Murray Bookchin and myself, the other members of the

editorial board were Janet Biehl, Peter Zegers, Gary Sisco, and Sveinung

Legard. (At our first meeting, in August 1999, I was elected general

editor.) Bookchin suggested the subtitle on its masthead – International

Journal for a Rational Society – and took a great interest in the

workings of the journal, although his declining health impeded him from

playing a more active role. (The journal continues to appear, at

www.communalism.net; now available in print.)

[6] For Janet Biehl’s account of this ideological break, see “Bookchin

Breaks with Anarchism,” in L. Gambone and P. Murtagh, eds., Anarchism

for the 21^(st) Century (Edinburgh and Oakland: AK Press, forthcoming).

This essay was also published in Communalism, no. 12 (October 2007).

[7] This introduction was written on December 14, 2002, and has been

known only to Scandinavian audiences. See Murray Bookchin, Perspektiv

för en ny vänster: Essäer om direct demokrati, moralisk ekonomi,

socialekologi och kommunalism, translated by Jonathan Korsár and Mats

Runvall (Malmö: Frihetlig Press, 2003).

[8] In fact, the original essay should be read together with Bookchin’s

“The Role of Social Ecology in a Period of Reaction,” in Social Ecology

and Communalism (Edinburgh and Oakland: AK Press, 2007), pp. 68–76;

“Whither Anarchism? A Reply to Recent Anarchist Critics,” in Anarchism,

Marxism, and the Future of the Left: Interviews and Essays 1993–1998

(Edinburgh and Oakland: AK Press, 1998), particularly pp. 216–46; and

“Turning Up the Stones: A Reply to John Clark’s October 13 Message,”

sent to the RA-list and available online at

dwardmac.pitzer.edu/Anarchist_ Archives/bookchin/turning.html.

[9] Murray Bookchin, Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An

Unbridgeable Chasm? (Oakland and Edinburgh: AK Press, 1994).

[10] This essay was originally published in Communalism, no. 2 (November

2002), and later included in Social Ecology and Communalism.

[11] Goethe quoted in Bertram D. Wolfe, Three Who Made a Revolution: A

Biographical History, 3^(rd) edn. (New York: The Dial Press, 1961), p.

578.

[12] Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, Book 2, Chapter 4 (New York:

Modern Library, 1944), pp. 121–2.

[13] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, letter to Dulieu, December 30, 1860, in

Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, ed. Stewart Edwards, trans.

Elizabeth Frazer (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1969), p. 184.

[14] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, La Fédération et l’unité en Italie (1862),

in Selected Writings, pp. 188–9.

[15] Proudhon, letter to Dulieu, December 30, 1860, in Selected

Writings, p. 185.

[16] Proudhon, letter to Alexander Herzen, April 21, 1861, in Selected

Writings, p. 191.

[17] All Bakunin quotations are from P. Maximoff, ed., The Political

Philosophy of Bakunin: Scientific Anarchism (New York: Free Press of

Glencoe; London: Collier-Macmillan Ltd., 1953), pp. 324–35; emphasis

added.

[18] Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, “Manifesto of the Communist Party,”

Selected Works, vol. 1 (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1969), p. 120.

[19] Marx and Engels, “Manifesto,” p. 124.

[20] Despite the genderedness of these words – a product of the era in

which Bakunin lived – they obviously may be interpreted as signifying

humanity generally.

[21] Elites who studied the Tao Te Ching, for their part, could easily

find it a useful handbook for ruling and manipulating a servile

peasantry. Depending upon which translation the English reader uses,

several interpretations are valid, but what is clear to everyone but the

blind is that quietism underlies the entire work.

[22] Cornelius Castoriadis, Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy: Essays in

Political Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 63.

[23] John Clark, “Not Deep Apart,” The Trumpeteer, vol. 12, no. 2

(Spring 1995), p. 104.

[24] A striking example is found in Victor Serge’s quarrel with his

French “pure” anarchist compatriots over the historical importance of

the outbreak of revolution in Russia. In response to Serge’s excitement,

these café anarchists or “Individualists,” as he chooses to call them,

“mocked [Serge] with their store of cynical stock phrases: ‘Revolutions

are useless. They will not change human nature. Afterwards reaction sets

in and everything starts all over again. I’ve only got my own skin; I’m

not marching for wars or revolutions, thank you.’” Victor Serge, Memoirs

of a Revolutionary, translated and abridged by Peter Sedgewick

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963), p. 53.

[25] Peter Kropotkin, “The Commune,” in Words of a Rebel (Montréal:

Black Rose Books, 1992), p. 81; emphasis added.

[26] See Peter Kropotkin, “Anarchist Communism: Its Basis and

Principles,” in R. Baldwin, ed., Kropotkin’s Revolutionary Pamphlets

(New York: Dover Press, 1970), pp. 51–2.

[27] Peter Kropotkin, “Anarchist Communism,” p. 63; also Conquest of

Bread, ed. P. Avrich (New York: New York University Press, 1972), pp.

66–7.

[28] Martin A. Miller, “Introduction” to Peter Kropotkin’s Selected

Writings on Anarchism and Revolution, ed. M.A. Miller (Cambridge, MA:

MIT Press, 1970), p. 31.

[29] These basic assumptions can also go a long way in explaining why

anarchism has been so fascinated by mystifications of the peasantry,

bioregionalism, not to speak of deep ecology, Buddhism, Tolstoyism,

Gandhi-ism, and the like.

[30] It should be mentioned, though, that despite their basic

differences, syndicalism has also been burdened by its expressly

anti-intellectual stance, and it shares with authentic anarchism a

disdain for rationalism and theory. Despite its commitment to mass

organization and social transformation, syndicalism has no strategy for

fundamental change beyond the general strike. Invaluable as general

strikes may be in revolutionary situations, they do not have the

essentially mystical capacity that syndicalists assigned to them, as the

vast general strike initiated in Germany in 1921 during the Kapp Putsch

demonstrated. Such failures are, in fact, evidence that militant direct

actions in themselves are not equatable with revolutions nor even with

profound social changes. For a critique of syndicalism, see my “The

Ghost of Anarcho- Syndicalism,” in Anarchist Studies, vol. 1, no. 1

(Spring 1993).

[31] As Ronald Fraser observes in Blood of Spain (in my view the best

book to date on the Spanish Revolution): “The two differentiated but

linked concepts which comprised anarcho-syndicalism, as its hyphenated

name suggested, could by the 1930s be schematically stated in a series

of polarities: rural/urban, local/ national, artisanal/industrial,

spontaneous/organized, autarkic/ interdependent,

anti-intellectual/intellectual.” Ronald Fraser, Blood of Spain: An Oral

History of the Spanish Civil War (New York: Pantheon Books; 1972), p.

542. These polarities were never reconciled; indeed, the civil war of

1936–39 exacerbated them to a near breaking point.

[32] These revolutionary syndicalists conceived the means by which they

had carried out this transformation as a form of direct action. They

meant by that term well-organized and constructive activities directly

involved in managing public affairs. Direct action, in their view, meant

the creation of a polity, the formation of popular institutions, and the

formulation and enactment of laws, regulations, and the like – which

authentic anarchists regarded as an abridgment of individual will or

autonomy.

[33] The Spanish socialists of the UGT, who rivaled the CNT among the

workers, also created an appreciable number of these committees or

participated in them, but the committee structure was primarily – and in

Catalonia, entirely – in the hands of CNT workers.

[34] Quoted in Pierre Broué and Emile Témine, The Revolution and the

Civil War in Spain, trans. Tony White (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1970),

p. 131.

[35] Whether in Russia or in Germany, the conviction that “bourgeois

democracy” (that is, capitalism) was a preconditional stage for leading

society to socialism helped justify the reluctance of Social Democracy

to lead the workers to make a proletarian revolution between 1917 and

1919. Marx’s “stages theory,” in effect, was not only an attempt to give

an interpretation to historical development; it played a vital role in

Marxist politics from the German and Russian Revolutions of 1917–21 to

the Spanish Revolution of 1936–37.

[36] I refer, here, not to the conventional criticisms that were mounted

against Marxism by political opponents – criticisms that emerged from

the very inception of Marx’s theoretical activities and the emergence of

the socialist movements based in varying degrees on his ideas. Nor am I

concerned with Marxist critics such as Eduard Bernstein, who mounted

their critiques within the Marxist movement itself in the 1890s. Rather

I refer to the critiques that emerged with the Frankfurt School and

assorted writers like Karl Korsch, who seriously challenged the many

premises of Marx’s philosophical and historical concepts.

[37] Karl Marx, “Preface to a Contribution of the Critique of Political

Economy,” in Selected Works (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1969), Vol. 1,

p. 504.

[38] All of which induced Georg Lukács to impart this hegemonic role to

the “proletarian party,” which mystically embodies the proletariat as a

class even when its leadership is usually predominantly petty bourgeois.

[39] I am not trying to downplay the importance of economic issues.

Quite to the contrary: only in recent times, especially since the mid

twentieth century, has capitalism’s commodity economy become a commodity

society. Commodification has now penetrated into the most intimate

levels of personal and social life. In the business-ese that prevails

today, almost everything is seen as a trade-off. Love itself becomes a

“thing” with its own exchange value and use value, even its own price –

after all, do we not “earn” the love of others by our behavior? Still,

this kind of commodification is not complete; the value of love is not

entirely measurable in terms of labor or supply and demand.

[40] What the public thinks at any time should play no role in

determining the policies of a rational movement. If the public should

want nuclear power, then it is wrong – and nothing more – and the

movement should do whatever can be done to change its mind in a manner

consistent with democratic procedure. But at no time, in my view, should

the movement drop, modify, or bypass the issue of eliminating nuclear

power because it lacks public support or alienates people. In this

terribly dumbed-down and juvenilized society, truth must learn to stand

on its own feet, so to speak, and continually gnaw away at public

naivety, ignorance, and fatuity, if only to provide an example of

integrity.

[41] Chris Ealham, “From the Summits to the Abyss: The Contradictions of

Individualism and Collectivism in Spanish Anarchism,” in The Republic

Besieged: Civil War in Spain, eds. Paul Preston and Ann L. Mackenzie

(Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1996), p. 140. This essay is one

of the most important contributions I have read to the literature on the

contradictions in anarchism.

[42] Today ecological issues are highly fashionable and acceptable to

leftists, but even during the tumultuous 1960s they were readily

dismissed. I recall publishing key, manifesto-type articles such as

“Ecology and Revolutionary Thought” in 1964, and raising environmental

issues for years in radical circles, only to be snidely derogated for

“ignoring” class issues (as though the two were in conflict with each

other!) and not adopting views that were more closely linked to Cold War

diplomacy than they were to socialism. The same was true of feminist

issues. It took the Left decades to show any appreciation of the crises

opened by global warming, to which I had alluded in “Ecology and

Revolutionary Thought,” and several decades to remove itself from the

mire of Cold War “socialism,” such as Maoism. Now, to be sure, one

learns that Marx, Engels, Kropotkin, and Reclus were ecologically

oriented all the time – as far back as the nineteenth century – and

clairvoyantly anticipated all the new issues that were raised in the

last half of the twentieth century! Nevertheless, the left-wing

movements lack a clear idea of how these issues can be given a

programmatic character on which people can act.

[43] The term “transitional program,” coined by Trotsky in the 1930s,

could be applied to any socialist program that seeks to escalate

“reformist” demands to a revolutionary level. That the phrase was

formulated by Trotsky does not trouble me; it is precise and

appropriate, and its use does not make one into a Bolshevik.