💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › dora-marsden-why-we-are-moral.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:14:37. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Why We Are Moral
Author: Dora Marsden
Date: 1914
Language: en
Topics: cant, egoism, morality, The Egoist
Source: Retrieved on 09/26/2021 from https://modjourn.org/issue/bdr521215/
Notes: Originally published in The Egoist Volume I Number 23 (December 1, 1914).

Dora Marsden

Why We Are Moral

Although—and as we have many times explained—morals are modes of conduct

which have become customary, and the intent of the passionate rage in

support of the moral is to shield these customs from anything which may

cause them to vary, this exposition does not explain why these modes,

primarily special and particular, adapted to serve the interests not of

All but of a Few should have become customary for All: so much so in

fact that the guardianship of morals is in the safest hands when it is

left to the fierce partisan feelings of the "Crowd." Before going into

the psychology which explains this problem, so perplexing on the

surface, it is advisable to indicate a nice distinction which has come

to exist between kinds of conduct to which, in popular usage, is given

the term "Custom," and conduct equally customary but to which the term

morals ordinarily is given.

Custom is habitual conduct, but to the observance of which public

opinion attaches small weight either by way of approval or disapproval.

The emotion which failure to observe it calls up is, in the main,

surprise, not the blind, passionate rage which the bulk of people show

at the infringement of morals. Its observance or otherwise is left to

individual whim; judgment as to its benefits or disadvantages is left to

the caprice of private opinion. It is a habit which lies open and

unprotected from vulgar inquiry and personal individual tests of its

value. Its valuation is not fixed though its observance be wide-spread

and general. What separates Morals from Custom (popular version) is the

value which Authority (which commands public opinion) sets upon the

habit's significance. If the reference is to customary conduct of which

the continuance is necessary for the maintenance of the power which

keeps the articulate class in authority, such conduct is carefully

extracted from its association with mere customs and elevated by

Authority to the plane of the Sacred by the laying of the Taboo on all

discussions as to its origin and the fundamental nature of its motives,

so that in time it comes to be regarded as the Mysterious, the Occult,

the Supernatural, the Divine. Whereas customs are exposed and open to

valuation, their ancestry apparent and their future the possible victim

of whim and caprice, morals are kept unsullied from the common and

mundane touch and their origin and valuation one may question only under

pain of becoming impious and a blasphemer. Naturally many customs are on

the fringe between the status of Customs and that of Morals, a fact to

which elegant if delicate young intellectuals owe many hours of exciting

and dangerous sport. The debating clubs of the Literary and Philosophic

Societies and of the Young Men's Mutual Improvement Society, of the

Y.W.C.A's, not to mention the Smart Set and the Cranks: what violent

intellectual striving has given these birth if not the desire to settle

points of such cosmic significance as the Right and the Wrong of

church-going, theatre-going, gambling, racing; of those crimes or larks

for women: smokes, bicycles and bloomers, dyed hair and paint ? To

decide whether these things belonged to the go-as-you-please realm of

Custom or to that realm which supports the Cosmos high above Chaos

—Morals, has provided occasion for the exercise of the strong and daring

young wits of the last half-century.

---

This popular distinction between Morals and Custom throws into relief

the question which still awaits an answer as regards the genesis of

morals.

If men have held to custom, common sense is ready to suggest that this

is not due to accident, and if customs have been fostered it has been

because— sheer ease apart—the results which come from doing so are such

as seem to serve their interests best. Did they not, the custom would

surely if not speedily have been abandoned. And if not from a prescience

of this willingness of men to abandon a custom productive of

disappointing results, what other motive would the authorities have had

for taking measures to ensure such customs as they consider significant

from the possibility of such a fate, by protecting them with that

"Mystery" which results in their conversion into Morals. Customs are

habits which may be kept up. Morals are customs which Authority insists

must be kept up, good results or no. What, then, is the instinct,

primary and fundamental as it must be to have held good for so long,

which makes the great mass of people, the governed classes, not merely

faithful to morals in face of their ill-effects, but faithful in an

ardent and passionate spirit which does not seek to spare either

themselves or those near and dear to them? The character and working of

the inducements which are responsible for this seeming miracle, reveal

how unerring is the instinct which leads men steadily to track down

their major satisfactions through a whole complex tangle of conflicting

considerations.

---

The basis of any scheme of morals is altruism. The moral claim that its

observance, against or in conformity to inclination is for "Good,"

obviously is prepared to demand the over-riding of the private "good" of

him whose inclination is against it in favour of the "good" of those

"others" who constitute the All: in which remote good the thwarted one

is vaguely enjoined to believe that he will once again refind his own.

An element of strong, if vague, distrust of the belief that one finds

one's interest served best in the good of All, does not encourage a

close observer to seek for the clue of unswerving moral action in the

influence of this generalisation: the Unity of Humanity. One is tempted

rather to look about for definite egoistic rewards in altruism itself

than to believe there exists so much solid weight in flighty conceptual

stretches for the popular intelligence. What, then, does Altruism offer

to these egoists of not-too-intelligent an order? On its face value the

theory of Altruism appears to be a tactful statement of the case for

peaceful submission among the Dominated, and is made current by the

powerful egoists who are the backbone of the dominant class what time it

suits the latter's interests to remain at peace: that is, while

refraining from those more violent forms of competition called war. It

is the inculcation of the principle that it is wise to make peaceful

terms with, and good friends of, those who have established a dominance

by respecting their status, their interests and their wishes. That it is

the dominated class which practises altruism whereas the dominant

practise it only in so far as their necessities, i.e., their interests,

permit them, in no way detracts from the weight of evidence which goes

to prove its origin among the dominant: it merely supplies additional

testimony as to the fine quality of the tact employed in its

inculcation. Thus morality, i.e., the habitual practice of altruism made

compulsory by Authority and Public Opinion, is part of the great game of

egoistic war—the interplay of interests—which ebbs and flows ceaselessly

wherever life is. In that warfare, however, morality represents such a

distinction as to method that it is convenient to label it separately

and allocate it to a niche of its own. Morality is the mode of warfare

made use of during the "civil" periods, its rĂ´le corresponding to the

physical slaughter which is the mode when the warfare of civilisation

gives place to a special kind of warfare ordinarily called war. The

difference consists in the substitution of weapons—of Words in place of

Armaments. The nature of moral warfare necessitates a sort of

seige-action in place of the aggressive physical assaults of armed

warfare. The moral concepts fence round the authoritarian class as

effectually as, if not more than, concrete fortifications do a city; the

action of these Sacred Words being not so much to withstand the savagery

of an onslaught as to paralyse the forces of the enemy before he can

lift up an arm against them.

Their effect, handled as Authority tactfully handles them, amounts to

that of hypnotism: results not however due to a brilliantly conceived,

conscious artifice or planned contrivance of means to purposed ends on

the part of the dominant: but of a semi-conscious exploiting on their

part of an elementary human instinct too obviously in existence for its

possibilities to be ignored. On the other hand the practice of altruism

as opposed to its theoretical exhortation, subserves urgent egoistic

needs on the part of the second-rate egoistic powers. If its observance

by the dominated serves the egoism of the dominant inasmuch as it spares

their energies from the necessity of constant reassertion of

superiority, it spares at the same time the vanity of the dominated. The

"status quo" which at first blush was accepted through necessity and

fear by the class which that "state" leaves subjected, is, thanks to

morality, afterwards accepted in happy submission by dint of the tactful

assaults which the moral concepts make on their vanity. Owing to the

comforting hypnotism of "morality" and its "altruism” the submissively

dominated are able to flatter themselves with the thought that the

"Great" most scrupulously desire and strive after the formers' own

special and particular "good": that these actually make themselves

anxious on account of the state of their souls in addition to care for

their temporal good; and. later, in return for the adoption of the

course of action enjoined by the conceptual scheme—action which always

turns to the Good of the established, by the way—they are rendered

happier still by the sound of the inflating "well done" of their

betters. It all works extremely well. Man is the vainest of the animals,

and individual men are vain in inverse ratio to the stoutness of their

spiritual stamina. The "Crowd" the Non-distinctive, the Majority being

the vainest, the appeal of Morality realises its own special

hunting-ground in their midst. The "Crowd" provide the country's moral

backbone. They even make a boast of it. And sensibly enough since such

Conduct as we arrange to live by, we arrange also to praise if we value

our own comfort. And the adoption of Morality is as much a piece of

distinctive human ingenuity—a display of intelligence—as is the adoption

of Arms. That it is more definitely connected with the swagger of the

dominated, whereas prowess in Arms is the swagger of the Dominant, need

not necessarily induce the former to misprise the solaces of their

class.

---

Tennyson somewhere sings, not without a gasp of surprise indeed at his

unexpected discovery, of the speech which half reveals and half conceals

the thought within. As far as the speech, which moral concepts are

wrapped in is concerned, the poet has gone wrong in his proportions.

Their whole intent is to conceal: and the motive is as purposive with

those who practice them as with those who teach. That both sides are

inarticulate and only semi-conscious does not detract from the

superlative skill with which the set purpose is achieved. It enhances it

rather. Moral principles resting on altruism, by a skilful sleight of

hand conceal the fact that altruism is an illusion created to subserve

motives wholly egotistic; that the interchange can be effected without

raising a breath of suspicion, is due to the suffusing influence of one

of the most fundamental elements affecting human emotion: to the action

of vanity.

Vanity skilfully played upon goes a long way towards confounding even

the soundest human judgment. As palpably as heat expands a gas, flattery

expands the human spirit beyond the normal. It is this sense of

expansion which causes men to feel pleasure; it is the sensation of

conscious life in actual being: it is in fact the sense we call power. A

flouting of vanity depresses spirit and creates despondency. Both

actions—inflation and depression—tend to take place the more readily the

flimsier the vital force on which repute acts, but it is probable that

on no single intelligent human being can they fail to make some little

variation. It is true that those who are concerned with their own

self-initiated interests and with whom the powers which have play over

their spirits are more self-centred and self-impelled, are less

responsive to outside treatment. It happens however, that with the vast

majority of men, obedience and imitation are the strongest springs of

action. To be capable of acting from a self-interested motive is

extremely rare. Hence it turns out that the balance of pleasure for most

men must be come at by way of honour conferred by stronger and more

definitely conscious egoistic powers. The balance of satisfaction when

all has been counted in fear of failure, fear of envy, of punishment,

hostility, fear of lonelessness, and a deadening sense of

uncertainty—for the vast majority of men falls on the side of honour

rather than on the other. Accordingly men's actions inevitably set

towards Honour and the earning of Applause. Whereupon propitiation

rather than aggression becomes their natural rĂ´le. It becomes their

virtue and all forces— men and things.—which make little of

propitiation— which is peace, love—are their natural enemies. All things

propitiatory become thereupon "good": propitiatory proposals, offers of

peace, civility, mildness of temper, and all species of intra-mediation

are "good": and those w h o make them are "good": and it is "good" to

fall in with them. "Good," that is, for those who love Honour, for

Morality, for the reputation of Altruism. Hence the moral demands find

in these second-rate egoists a mind and temper ready prepared for them:

those who desire to be persuaded are already waiting for those who will

persuade them: the two come together by an inevitable attraction: the

outcome of a natural desire to make use of each other. United, they make

a compound hard and resistant enough to baffle all attempts to break in

upon it: a nugget to break one's teeth against rather than to crack.

Between the ardour of each for the other there is nothing to choose.

---

There are unobserving persons who imagine that human beings desire a

commodity which they call Truth. Now truth is a much-used word which may

mean anything or nothing according as one is pleased to employ it: but

allowing for the moment that it means what such persons imagine it to

mean, i.e., a faithful description of passions and motives and of the

relative powers among the individuals of a community, it is the crassest

stupidity to think that people desire truth or anything approaching it.

You, dear reader, don't want such truth about yourself. I, dear reader,

won't have it about myself. The maximum quantity of this species of

truth which you and I can stand is just as much as we are compelled to

swallow from our own disillusioning experiences; and even this amount we

prefer not to discuss with any, particularly not with familiars—families

and friends. But many of us are not averse from airing this truth as it

relates to others: our rivals and acquaintances, though even here we

must be content with a reasonable amount: penetration must not penetrate

too far because instinctively we are aware that some short distance

beneath its surface-layer the fabric of truth is in one piece: lower

than a certain depth the same fabric covers us all; penetrate inwards

too deeply and w e all stand with our motives naked and exposed. And our

motives are far more elegant clothed, as clothed they are. Men have

clothed them partly, perhaps, on account of use and comfort, and partly

because they have conceived a shame for them: a shame which is the

reverse side of the cult of Honour in fact. Only the external motive-—

the altruistic motive—is kept in evidence: the motive which was the

motive of the show of altruism is concealed: instinctively men know that

it is of the egoistic and dishonourable kind, and a poor specimen at

that. Men would never indeed have fallen into the attitude which makes

them ashamed of it had they not been aware that it was poor. Altruism is

egoism at the second and tenth rate, adopted because of one's inability

to make headway in the best. If men do not feel themselves possessed of

the power to make themselves respected on account of their skill in

getting what they want they compound in a purely egoistic bargain and

become Moral. And serviceably and comprehensibly enough. The pleasure

they will get from applause is likely to exceed any satisfaction they

expect to get from enterprises initiated by themselves: and on show of

the balance their egoism makes choice—for a cloak of altruism. (The

disadvantages they meet will form another story.) But because they are

not proud of the necessity which forces them they conceive a quite sound

detestation for the "Searchers for Truth ": alongside their approval of

the preachers of the Moral Ideal, They are suspicious of the evidences

of "Truth": they are not suspicious of the Moralist's praise: they have

no need to be, because praise to them is an end in itself: it is what

they want: the bona-fide exchange for the services they have rendered.

The Trojans were advised to be on their guard against the Greeks when

they came offering gifts; and sensibly, because such gifts to the

Trojans were of small concern: had these gifts been more to them than

Troy itself what would there have been to fear in receiving them? So

with the Moral and the Dominated's reception of the praise of the

Moralists. Their praise is Honour and Honour they have made into the

crown of life: how should they then allow the prying chatter of

so-called "Searchers for Truth" to endanger that which can confer on

them their most desired boon: allow the spoil-sports and kill-joys a

free hand amongst their own selected "good." And a moral community is

not going to welcome with a shout of glad surprise a too closely probing

inquiry into the reasons of morals ! They consider it is enough that

they are moral because it suits them, all things considered. And they

are not prepared to regard it as good manners to inquire beyond a point

what those things are. Their elaborate altruistic make-believe : their

artificial moralist construction is built round about what for them

constitutes the charm of life: subtly flattered vanity. The fact that it

is all on an "artificial" basis: a verbal basis does not affect them:

indeed the fact is lost sight of until civilisation gives place to war:

when this base proves to have been not only artificial but a trifle

flimsy.

Men find morality none the worse, i.e., it gives no less satisfaction

because it is artificial than a picture or a novel does because it is

artificial; the subtlest situations in life gather round just those

things which are most frail at their foundations, assumptions which, by

a tacit understanding are allowed for, but which are too perishable to

be battered about in discussion. The artificialities of civilisations

are not despicable because a sword may one day shatter all their

delicate and subtle tracery; they are to be despised only when they fail

in that which they set out to accomplish, i.e., to provide satisfactions

equal to or greater than those which they might have attained by a more

natural, i.e., a more frankly egoistic application of ability would have

furnished. One would be for instance an ingrate, not to say a fool, to

cavil at those aids to beauty which an ill-favoured human adopts to

avert at least the repulsion of his fellows, just because they were

artificial: if they serve their purpose. Very amusing, charming,

important, and impressive are the things which are "artificial." Even a

Krupp gun is artificial. In fact it is not artificiality which affects

the question: it is utility. The measure of the value of artificialities

like the measure of the value of everything else is gauged by the

purpose to which they are set, and their efficacy in achieving that

purpose. And purposes depend on the men who propose them: their

spiritual size among other things. He is a sad and sorry man who seeks

to frame a purpose bigger than he has the capacity to enjoy the

achieving of. So a man with a passion for big schemes but without the

capacity to effect them draws greater satisfaction from being a

doorkeeper in the houses of the great than he could eating out his heart

toiling at his own bench, the independence of which his taste cannot

relish: it is, in fact, too independent for him. What he would gain in

satisfaction, of course by so doing, he sacrifices in status: but then

all satisfactions demand their price. When these are greater than our

natural competence provides for we perforce let ourselves out into

bondage if bent on securing them. Our too great wants and our too small

abilities are the exploiter's opportunity.

---

One begins to understand why cranks and their works come to so little.

They have the misfortune to witness an indiscretion: one little brick in

the wall of pretence has fallen away and one thin shaft of light has

revealed egoism and duplicity at some point in the scheme of things. And

for the rest of their lives they live in wonder and uneasiness at their

own discovery. They devote their energies to the blocking-out of that

one gleam. They inaugurate a "propaganda." That it is but one thin

pencil streak of an ever-shining sun-like orb does not occur to them.

The world, to be sure, is heedless of their "discovery," and is in no

WAY "upset" to meet their "exposure.' Nor is it alarmed by those who cry

out against "Cant." Though men do not clearly know, they instinctively

feel that one who makes a fuss about "cant" does not understand cant.

They feel it is not cant that is objectionable but poor cant: cant that

is so badly sung that it fails in its purpose, i.e., the complete

deception of those whom it is intended to impress. The way to deal with

him who objects to cant is to ignore him or soothe him as the case may

demand, but never to follow up his argument. The Church of Rome has the

prescient understanding which knows this: it does not make the mistake

of thinking that doubts can be laid to rest piecemeal. It knows its

business and promptly anathematises doubt. It knows that the correct

answer to all the arguments of the Devil is to kill the Devil. Nor is

the World greatly put about by those who make light of its morals on the

big scale: it forgives its Napoleons as soon as their immediate

disagreeableness is forgotten and withdrawn: while as for the immoral on

a small scale, men content themselves with administering the usual and

necessary severe rebuke and punishment. It is a different person for

whom they reserve their full implacable rancour. Napoleon at the close

of a single century after his death is already held in honour more or

less: but four centuries have passed since Machiavelli wrote the

"Prince," and he still remains "Old Nick." In fact, the Devil is a

symbolic generalisation of all the injuries done to the Altruistic

Interpretation by those who dare to crumble the moral concepts, and lay

bare their egoistic foundations: so robbing them of their popular title

to Honour. The Devil is the common spirit of all Blasphemers everywhere:

Blasphemers being those who speak injuriously against the Sacred Words.

The Blasphemers are the figures drawn up in antithesis to those of the

Heroes. A Hero is one who represents the sublimation-point of adhesion

to the Divine; his distinguishing attribute is his close kinship with

the Gods to whose greater glory his bold deeds minister: that is, he is

one whose deeds establish the Word-System, the Moral-Scheme, the

Altruistic-Good, by providing them with a supremely hypnotising Crown of

Honour. Of course the Moral or Altruistic Scheme holds good only within

the limits of the particular community which has conceived its own

sum-total of the "All" as the single Organic Unit. Morality can only

find a place in a community in which the various factions have tried

their strength, and have more or less contentedly accepted the verdict

and settled down in their suitable classes as Servers and Served,

Dominant and Dominated. When two such moral communities are at

logger-heads and proceed to violent war, moral blandishments are at a

discount. As it is not the common people—the practisers of the

altruistic and the moral—who make international wars, but rather the

dominant and more strongly egoistic classes, the warring parties do not

attempt to address each other in terms of morals save in so far as it is

necessary to spare the moral susceptibilities of their own respective

following—their respective crowds. Otherwise, in war, it is bluntly a

struggle of Might against Might: and all the weapons of Might are

pressed into service precisely in so far as they give promise of

success, i.e., of crushing the opponent. But articulate spokesman of

neither side could say as much openly because of the attentive ears of

their followers as was said above: They know that sooner or later this

specific kind of warfare, fierce as for the moment it is, will cease for

a period and no matter which side wins or loses each will have to settle

down in their own communities and make good once more the Altruistic

Tale among their fellows. A wise economy, therefore, teaches them that

though war compels them to stand face to face with all verbal veils

withdrawn before the eyes of an acknowledged enemy, it is not necessary

to destroy these veils. If they have no place in war they have a place

of extreme importance among subjected peoples as long as ever the

Dominant seek to perpetuate submission by dint of the artifices of

peace: by Words in preference to the Sword.