đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș jesse-cohn-demodernizing-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:11:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2023-03-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Demodernizing Anarchism Author: Jesse Cohn Date: May 5, 2022 Language: en Topics: modernity, modernism, land back, indigenous, Magic Source: Retrieved on 2022-05-16 from https://anarchiststudies.org/demodernizing-anarchism-jesse-cohn/
I should begin by acknowledging my positioning: I am writing as a white
settler anarchist on land stolen from the Neshnabé (Potawatomi) in
so-called Northwest Indiana, and I intend here to address mainly other
settler anarchists of North America/Turtle Island. I feel that we are
laboring under some unhelpful and indeed harmful habits of thought when
it comes to imagining how we might relate our traditions to the
far-older ones of Indigenous peoples everywhere and of Native Americans
in particular.
In my book about the history of global anarchist resistance culture,
Underground Passages, I found an astonishing degree of coherence between
the newspapers, songs, poems, visual art, and novels produced by
anarchists in Chile and China, Argentina and Australia. From one
perspective, this similitude is a remarkable cultural achievement; from
another, the cultural expressions of these non-European militants did
not significantly deviate from those of their European counterparts for
over a hundred years, and innovations flowed largely from center to
periphery. And in Anarquistas de Ultramar: Anarquismo, Indigenismo,
DescolonizaciĂłn (Overseas Anarchists: Anarchism, Indigenism,
Decolonization), Carlos Taibo attempts to come to grips with the fact
that while anarchyâmutual aid, direct democracy, communism, and so onâis
to be found in the practices and concepts of nearly every culture
(provided one looks far enough back), anarchism as a doctrine appears to
arrive âoverseasâ as a modern European import.
âImportâ is, of course, a euphemism: if the migration of working-class
European anarchists into the Americas was pushed along by waves of
capital, we have to admit that this emigration was also a form of
colonization. Moreover, these arrivalsâsettlers, invadersâmost often
carried with them the sense that science was superior to traditions,
that emancipation was linked to modern progress, and that these things
meant not only the advance of technology but the dethronement of gods
and the subsequent placement of humanity at the center of the universe.
In short, the colonizer culture was Eurocentric, anthropocentric, and
resolutely modernâopposed in every way to the native cultures being
displaced.
It might be fairly objected that contemporary Indigenous peoples are
modern. Certainly, the myth of the âvanishing Indianâ must be vehemently
opposed; Native Americans have adapted to modernity and survive and
sometimes even thrive within it. The Ojibwe/Dakota scholar Scott Lyons
argues for âembracing modernity and resisting essentialismâ (xiii),
suggesting that even the âconsentâ of Native Americans to modern
âconcepts, policies, technologies, [and] ideas,â even when âcontaminated
and coerced,â has sometimes led to positive change (2â3): for instance,
as Michael P. Taylor observes, even the genocidal institution of the
Indian boarding schools had the perverse result of ârevitaliz[ing] ... a
transindigenous network of Indigenous solidarity.â The suppression of
traditional Native American dances likewise led to the invention of
transindigenous powwow culture, now a key institution of Native
resistance culture. It was at one such powwow that the transindigenous
term âTwo-Spiritâ made its debut. None of what follows is intended to
argue for a return to âpureâ Indigenous identities, or to suggest that
all that is traditional is simply good in contrast to an all-bad
modernity. I would rather affirm, with Eduardo Galeano, that it is not a
matter of âbeliev[ing] in traditions simply because they are
traditions.â Instead, as he expresses it,
I believe in the legacies that multiply human freedom, and not in those
that cage it .... I am not proposing a return to the sacrificial rites
that offered up human hearts to the gods, nor am I praising the
despotism of the Inca or Aztec monarchs. (177)
However, it must be recognized that crucial institutions of Indigenous
cultures, notably traditions of land tenure and property relations, are
absolutely excluded by the modern state, which still sends military
forces in response to any effort to assert them, as we have seen in the
current cycle of protests against petrochemical pipelines running
through tribal lands and waters. Modernity cannot allow any exception to
the laws of the state and the laws of the market to stand alongside it,
much less outside of it. Modernityâs statism and capitalism, consumerist
individualism and ideology of progress, stand as obstacles to
decolonization and re-Indigenization.
If âdecolonizationâ is now a watchword, calls to âdecolonize anarchismâ
must run up against the insistence of Eve Tuck and K. Wayne Yang that
âdecolonization is not a metaphor,â nor is it exclusively or even
primarily a matter of changing mindsets. Instead, they argue,
non-Indigenous anarchists help to decolonize when they fight to restore
land and autonomy to Indigenous peoples. However, as they point out,
some conceptual updates might make it easier to join in those struggles.
The lingering attachment of non-Indigenous anarchists to modernity is an
obstacle to the construction of bonds of solidarity and to shared
struggle with Indigenous counterparts for whom modernity has been an
almost completely unmitigated disaster. It is necessarily difficult to
join hands with people whose spirituality one has labeled as naive and
foolish at best, whose culture one regards as merely particular and
parochial, and whose identification with the land one sees as a quaint
but misconceived projection of human qualities onto an indifferent
nonhuman world.
Accordingly, we might want to explore ways to demodernize anarchism.
First, however, we should identify some possible false starts and
cul-de-sacs. To begin with, we must not be mystified by discourses of
the âtraditionalistâ Far Right that identify âmodernityâ with such
supposedly debauched notions as feminism or queerness (Burley). On the
contrary, such fascist ideologies, which we must absolutely refuse, wish
to immortalize what Taibo argues is âone of the first marks of
modernity,â in spite of modernityâs egalitarian self-image: namely, âthe
consolidation of a world of hierarchies and separationsâ (107). Thus,
women, queer and trans folks, and nonwhite people find themselves in the
crosshairs of fascist entrepreneurs such as the so-called Traditionalist
Worker Party or the National Anarchist Tribal Alliance. Nothing can be
more disgusting than the spectacle of white people such as Jacob
Chansley, known as the âQAnon Shaman,â cosplaying as Indigenous, whether
to appropriate Native American identities orâall the worseâto make
parallel identitarian claims for âWestern peoplesâ âreclaimingâ European
âancestral roots.â Key to these arguments, as journalist and author
Shane Burley notes, is âa caricature of leftist âidentity politicsââ
that imagines identity in terms of ancestral âbloodâ or an authentic
racial âessence,â rather than in terms of oneâs position within
structures of power or oneâs experience of oppression. Wherever we
encounter anti-modernists like these, we encounter not allies but
enemies: self-mythologizing white supremacists and would-be patriarchs.
So-called primitivist and anti-civilizational anarchists have indeed
militated against modernity, but theirs is a âmodernityâ defined
primarily by its technological base. They have imagined a ânaturalâ
human being who emerges only when stripped of technological
externalities (which Fredy Perlman memorably imagined as âmasks and
armorsâ). This seems to me a misidentification of the problem. I would
rather begin with the philosophers Gilles Deleuze and FĂ©lix Guattariâs
recognition that everything is simultaneously ânatureâ and âmachines.â
The question is how these nature-machines are to relate to one another:
Must they be organized hierarchically, with some of them harming and
destroying others and cutting them off from their possibilities? An
anarchist wants to answer in the negative. We must question the very
distinction between the natural and the human worlds, which sociologist
and anthropologist Bruno Latour (a problematic thinker, but Iâll follow
him this far) claims is the founding distinction of modernity. It is the
âpremoderns,â he argues, who insist on treating ânaturalâ beings as part
of the âhumanâ social world, thanking animals after taking their lives
and listening to speaking stones. We moderns, on the contrary, can only
encounter ânatureâ as a silent, essentially alien other that makes no
social demands of us and listens to no entreaties.
Some anarchist theory is so modern as to regard listening to ânatureâ as
the very sign of human self-enslavement. The late political philosopher
Eduardo Colombo, extending a line of thinking derived from Cornelius
Castoriadis, regarded human freedom as a project of âautonomyâ imagined
as the refusal to allow anything other than human decision making to
determine the outcome of decisionsânot God (as in Western theology), not
the economy (as under capitalism), and not nature (as among
âpremodernsâ):
Since the vanished obscurity of ancient times, human thought, in order
to constitute itself as such, had to separate, to distinguish, to
oppose, to unify. It had to organize the flux of perception and
construct discrete and determinate representations; it had to make a
cosmos out of chaos. Human beings instituted the earth and the heavens,
created the gods and all things. Humanity â the human collective â
created itself, and in the same movement subjected itself to the
heteronomy of its own creation. Everything came to us from beyond, from
on high, from the center. We, as creatures, are seen as dispossessed and
dependent. (2008, 14)
Here Colombo relies on the structural anthropology of Claude
LĂ©vi-Strauss, for which human beings are indeed those who impose
structure on the world through language, the world in itself being
without meaningful form or clear demarcations. The classic example of
this transformation of âchaosâ into âcosmosâ is the color spectrum, a
continuum that different languages âcarve upâ in sometimes wildly
different ways (LĂ©vi-Strauss 92â94). Structuralist theory predicted that
the speakers of those different languages would in fact see different
colors. However, it seems that while language âinfluencesâ visual
perception (particularly in the right field of vision), the hypothesis
that language determines perception is at best only âhalf rightâ (Regier
and Kay).
Deleuze, following the philosopher Gilbert Simondon, would point to the
dependence of this kind of language-centered theory on âthe hylomorphic
schema,â a model of reality as divided into shapeless matter (in Greek,
hyle) and intelligible form (morphe). At least since Bakunin, anarchist
theory has found this model to be incipiently hierarchical and
dominatory, since it asks us to imagine a world of masters bestowing
form on lump-like slaves. In God and the State, Bakunin writes that âthe
vile matter of the idealists,â having been âstripped by them of ...
intelligence, life, all its determining qualities, active relations or
forces, motion itself,â was âindeed a stupid, inanimate, immobile
thing,â unlike âthe matter of which materialists speak, matter
spontaneously and eternally mobile, active, productiveâ (12â13). Such a
conception of matter, as anthropologist Tim Ingold notes, takes as its
basis a different theory of reality: âThis is the ontology of animismâ
(214).
Can anarchists be animists? Murray Bookchin seems to briefly entertain
the idea in the first edition of The Ecology of Freedom (1983), where he
writes with admiration of the âoutlookâ of Indigenous societies:
I am eager to determine what can be recovered from that outlook and
integrated into our own ... perhaps we can achieve a way of thinking and
experiencing that involves a quasi-animistic respiritization of
phenomenaâinanimate as well as animateâwithout abandoning the insights
provided by science and analytical reasoning. (14)
By 1991, however, Bookchin felt compelled to add:
Without a sense of contrast between the human and nonhuman, people are
limited to the bedrock existence of seeking mere survival, to a way of
life so undifferentiated from that of other living things that they know
little more than the unmediated confines of their limited ecological
community. This way of life is bereft of purpose, meaning, or
orientation, apart from what people create in their imagination. And it
is a way of life that no human being could endure except by ceasing to
think. (xlv)
The lives of animists thus go from being represented as full and rich, a
source of renewal and inspiration, to impoverished and empty even of
thought itself. In subsequent years, Bookchin would double down on
âcivilization, progress, and scienceâ with Re-enchanting Humanity
(1995), wherein he insists that âit was primarily in Europe that a
remarkable constellation of historical and ideological factors converged
to produce a common emphasis on reason, the importance of the
individual, and a healthy naturalismâ (4, 249).
If commitments to humanism can lead someone as smart and imbued with
libertarian ethos as Bookchin or Colombo into the crassest endorsements
of colonial ideology, maybe we ought to listen once again to the
postanarchist critique of humanismâs presence in the anarchist
genealogy. Colonialism may go unmentioned in the classic texts of the
postanarchists, but perhaps we dismissed their concerns about humanism
too quicklyâor perhaps they located this humanism in the wrong place.
Bakunin, for example, is indeed too canny to embrace the simple-minded
notions of a âgood human natureâ that the Anglo-American postanarchists
attributed to him; his conception of âthe humanâ surely includes the
potential for domination as well as for freedom. However, he never pays
anything like sufficient attention to the realities of colonial genocide
and enslavement, and he repeatedly assumes, like Bookchin, that Europe
has been the privileged locus for humanityâs developmentâa development
that must take us away from âfetichismâ and âthe primitive religion of
savagesâ (1974, 110). Once youâve accepted that the Enlightenment
spelled out, for once and for all, the future of humanity, youâve
accepted a Eurocentric ideology of progress.
Glen Coulthard, a scholar of Indigenous studies, helpfully names this
ideology ânormative developmentalismâ (9); it is a fault Bakunin shares
especially with Marx, for whom âprimitive communismâ must necessarily
give way to all the other historical stages leading to a second and
final communism. This Eurocentrism, this ideology of progress, this
imagination that takes just one of the âgenres of being humanâ as the
universal (Wynter 26), could not fail to taint European anarchistsâ
anticolonial commitments, and historically, as Taibo reminds us, the
anarchist anticolonialists tended to tacitly accept âthe superiority of
Western civilization and, with it, of a significant part of the colonial
discourseâ (117). In the end, he finds, âalthough anarchists sharply
criticized the many excesses that characterized colonization, it seems
as if they accept that the latter constituted a natural process
justifiable under the scientific and technical superiority of Western
civilization, hand in hand with an argument that could not but remind
many of Marx and Engelsâ assertions on the subjectâ (117â18).
What might anarchism look like if it really gave up on the notion that,
as our fascist enemies have it, âthe West is the bestâ? Perhaps it might
follow Bakuninâs suggestion and (in spite of him) become animist.
Proudhon had already hinted at something like this when he wrote that
âintellect sleeps in the stone, dreams in the animal, reasons in the
manâ (3:267). In the early twentieth century, anarchist journals devoted
substantial print to the scientific theories of the âplasmogenists,â
which suggested something strikingly similar: if, under the right
circumstances, even inorganic chemicals could be observed behaving in a
quasi-animate fashion, why draw a distinction between dead or inert
matter and the biochemistry of life (Quintana-Navarrete 88â89)? Why not
attribute an incipient motion, liveliness, intelligence, even
consciousness to all kinds of material beings?
The late anthropologist David Graeber was moving in just such a
direction when he published the essay âWhatâs the Point If We Canât Have
Fun?â in The Baffler in 2014. Drawing on the vast ethological literature
about the prevalence of play in species other than oursâeven ants, he
points out, ânot only engage in frivolous activities as individuals, but
also have been observed since the nineteenth century to arrange
mock-wars, apparently just for the fun of itâ (52)âhe goes on to
speculate about matter itself, including, for instance, the seemingly
capricious behavior of electrons under certain circumstances:
If one wants a consistently materialist explanation of the worldâthat
is, if one does not wish to treat the mind as some supernatural entity
imposed on the material world, but rather as simply a more complex
organization of processes that are already going on, at every level of
material realityâthen it makes sense that something at least a little
like intentionality, something at least a little like experience,
something at least a little like freedom, would have to exist on every
level of physical reality as well. (57)
This hypothesis, sometimes called âpanpsychism,â has been increasingly
widely entertained by philosophers of science in recent years, who find
in it an alternative to âemergentism,â the doctrine that mental
phenomena are not visible in but somehow arise from micro-scale material
like electrochemical exchanges between neurons. While satisfying in some
ways, emergentist explanations of mind seem to mystify rather than
resolve what cognitive scientist David Chalmers calls âthe puzzle of
conscious experienceâ (80). How far are such speculations, really, from
the theoriesâlabeled, in the colonizersâ language, âspiritualityâ or
âreligionââof the Ojibwe (Chippewa), Haudenosaunee (Iroquois), or DinĂ©
(Navajo) peoples? In fact, what is âreligion,â and if we oppose it, why?
âBlasphemy,â writes Colombo, âis perhaps the first point of rebellion
against the established order,â insofar as a society that locates the
source of its own norms in the sacredâthat is, in the mythical deeds and
words of gods, heroes, or ancestorsâis by definition heteronomous rather
than autonomous, since those norms then are âdictated once and for
always,â and the âsymbolic-instituting powerâ that established them is
sealed off in a transcendent beyond (2006 15â16). Surely this seems like
a good description of the way that the sacred has served the interests
of power in Western history, at least. Yet the best examples we know of
self-managing communist societies with long duration were Indigenous.
Sociologist Ronald Creagh suggests a possible solution to this seeming
paradox in a study of seventeenth-century Jesuitsâ perplexed accounts of
the Wendat (Huron) and Innu (Montagnais) people. Agreeing with Colombo,
in essence, that the problem with religion has to do with this âtheft
... of humanityâs symbolic-instituting power,â that is, the âpower to
organize society for ourselvesâ (Colombo 2006, 16; Creagh 75â76), Creagh
warns against a too-hasty understanding of Native American religion in
terms of Western concepts of the sacred:
The struggle between the missionary and the sorcerer is nothing other
than the manifestation of a conflict between two different approaches to
the sacred. Because if, in the Catholic Church, this phenomenon is
characterized by a recourse to transcendence, is it the same for âthe
Indianâ? ...
[W]hile for Catholics the sacred and the profane refer to two different
worlds, the terrestrial here-and-now and the hereafter, which
communicate only through certain more or less sacramental acts and
places, the religious type described by Mr. Eliade sees only one
universe. The Montagnais, the Hurons and several of these tribes that
the Jesuits meet are on the same level as the forces of nature; these
âspiritualâ intensities do not possess any ontological distinction from
those which animate men. (84â85)
In short, Western religions âfounded on transcendenceâ do not have the
same social functions as âan Indian âreligionâ for which everything can
become hierophanic because the sacred is immanent in the worldâ (88).
Note that this immanent sacred runs directly contrary to the root
concept of sacredness in the Western traditionââDedicated, set apart,
exclusively appropriated to some person or some special purposeâ (OED);
in Hebrew, kadosh, translated as âsacredâ or âholy,â signifies
âotherness,â which can be read as indicating an apartness from the
ordinary world (Armstrong 41). Amplified by combination with Platonist
idealism, it was erected into the most thoroughly transcendent version
of the sacred in Christianity. Yet the immanence of Native religious
concepts and practices, in which âany object can become hierophanic, a
sign of the âdivine,ââ denies any âdisembodied beyondâ (Creagh 85â86).
Does this other, animist form of the sacred even belong, in the terms
set out by anarchists from Bakunin to Bookchin, in the category of
âreligionâ?
This approach to understanding animisms would entail a radical
reassessment of our commitment to a strict atheism (or, as Bakunin
dubbed it, âanti-theologismâ). Religion scholar Paul-François Tremlett
notes that while the majority discourse on religion among anarchists is
âmodernist,â âbroadly constitut[ing] religion and the past as conditions
to be overcome,â there is a countervailing discourse critical of
secular, scientistic modernity, in which âreligion emerges as a means of
imagining the free, creative and autonomous individual,â of
âre-enchant[ing] the presentâ (367, 377). Anarchist animism might then
follow in the footsteps of thinkers such as Gustav Landauer, for whom it
is the Marxist âscience of historyâ that represents superstition (âOld
wives prophesy from coffee dregs. Karl Marx prophesied from steamâ),
while the âglimmer ... of beautyâ belonging to tradition is needed to
break the spell of capitalist modernity: âTherefore let us be the type
of innovators in whose anticipatory imagination, that which they want to
create already lives as something ... anchored in the past, in primeval
and sacred lifeâ (65, 93). Such thinkers provide useful precedents for
critiques of religion that are more sophisticated than blanket
endorsement or reflexive condemnation.
Rather than presenting a contradiction in terms, an animist anarchism
would be more consistent in its critique of instrumental rationalityâthe
worldview for which all of nature consists of mere âraw materialsâ (or,
at best, ânatural resourcesâ) set aside (as if by a transcendent God)
for human beings to own and use. It might or might not adhere to
veganism or vegetarianismâanimism could provide a basis for this, but it
most often does notâbut it would be a more consistently ecological
anarchism, as we shall see. And it would be better theoretically
positioned to struggle alongside Indigenous peoples, no longer
encumbered by a crude materialism for which it is self-evidently absurd
to listen to nonhuman beings.
Can nonhumans speak? Iwona Janicka, author of Theorizing Contemporary
Anarchism, suggests that the question is not so much one of âwho can
speak?â as it is of âhow best to listen.â Even human beings are enabled
to speak (rather than simply emit meaningless noise) by the efforts of
listeners to âtranslateâ them. Accordingly, listening to nonhumans is a
matter of constructing âhuman-nonhuman assemblagesâ (5â6) capable of
translating between, for instance, Algae and English or Ant Swarm and
Swahili:
Humans do not âgive meaningâ to nonhuman entities as such or âinterpret
brute matter,â but rather they create favorable conditions in which
nonhuman entities become visible. In order to do that, however,
nonhumans and humans alike require a set of devices, gestures, settings,
procedures, instruments, trials and sites. (7â8)
Such devices might include the apparatus given to Koko the gorilla to
communicate with her human counterparts and the instruments currently
being used to understand the quarrels of bats, but also the methods used
to measure glacial formation and movement, the Bolivian Ley de Derechos
de Madre Tierra that accords legal standing and representation to
âMother Earthââand the customs and rituals that Native Americans have
used for thousands of years (which, in spite of some episodes of
overhunting, have worked quite well in most cases, at least insofar as
âworkingâ means functionally establishing balanced ecological
relationships).
One of the most concrete obstacles to mutual understanding between our
movements arises when white anarchists balk at Indigenous demands for
the return of ancestral lands. Here, too, anarchism is ill served by its
fidelity to modernity. In the modern imaginary, land is an ownable
object, a commodity; the radical modern demand has typically been a
demand for redistribution of the commodity. We moderns have by and large
not imagined land as an agent, a process that acts on us and interacts
with us. We imagine that persons have rights, but that land only has
valueâexchange value under modern capitalism, or use value under modern
communism. Many Indigenous languages have the advantage of being verb
based (unlike European languages like English, which require nouns to
fill the role of subject in a sentence), so that this agency of land is
more self-evident (Kimmerer). In Peskotomuhkati-latuwewakon (the
Passamaquoddy language), for instance, the English noun âfieldâ is
rendered instead as a verb, pomskute, âa field goes alongâ; instead of
saying that the berries (a substantive) are growing in the field (a
location), one attaches a kind of quasi-adverbial expression, pemskutek,
as if the berries were growing fieldishly (Francis et al.).
It is not only whiteness but a white supremacist modernity that makes it
difficult for white anarchists to understand the Indigenous slogan âNo
socialism on stolen land.â âStolenâ seems to presuppose a regime of
private property rights, and arenât we against private property? But
this is a misunderstanding (even if, to some extent, a willful
misunderstanding). The point of the demand for the return of sovereignty
over Indigenous lands and waters has never been to simply change one set
of proprietors for another; it is, rather, a reassertion of a very
different kind of land tenure, one that falls outside the bounds of
capitalist property relations, in part because the âpropertyâ in
question is a living agent, not an individual but a web of relations in
which Indigenous humans are already enmeshed.
As many have pointed out, the demands of Indigenous peoples do not
necessarily include the expulsion of the non-Indigenous or our return to
our supposed âhomesâ in Europe, Africa, and so on. Other models of life
after coloniality proliferate; among them, many look back to the Two-Row
Wampum (TeiohĂĄte Kaswenta) that was created early in the seventeenth
century to solemnize a covenant between the ĂgwĂ«âö:weh (âoriginal
peopleâ) and the Skaghneghtadaronni(Dutch settlers) (Hill 1). Figured in
the wampum beads are two canoes in the same river, side by side; neither
tries to interfere with the other. Here is an Indigenous vision of
peaceful coexistence, a direction not taken by history but which yet
might be.
What might be harder for settler anarchists to understand, given our
universalistic biases, is the way that land is tied to experience,
memory, understanding, and hence knowledge. In trying to explain âthe
Indigenous experience with a layered sense of place that is at one and
the same time ordinary and holy,â Arapaho scholar Michael Marker
proposes that âthe methodology for learning about powerful forms of
consciousness and visions cannot be extracted from the âbeing in placesâ
where the powers existâ (462â63, 456). Indigenous place-based
epistemologies yield not an abstract Truth, to be applied everywhere
regardless of context, but localized, particular, context-sensitive
truths. When Bookchin reads of an Ojibwe elder listening to the
anthropologistâs question, âAre all the stones we see about us here
alive?â and answering âNo! But some areâ (Hallowell 24), he is
constrained to hear this as âa very shrewd response,â a cynical hedging
of bets: âAboriginal peoples are not so absurd as to view stones and
horses ... as equally alive. However, âanimisticallyâ they regard the
natural world in theory, in practice they apply their animistic views
with considerable discretionâ (1995, 135â36). In pragmatist terms, a
difference in discourse without a corresponding difference in behavior
is empty verbiage. But clearly, animistic discourse among Indigenous
peoples does make a difference in how they interact with the landscape,
just as one might expect. For Indigenous people, some truths only obtain
partially, locally, within a particular place, precisely because that
place is another âsentient being,â not only a âknownâ but simultaneously
a âknowerâ and a condition for knowing (Marker 457, 461).
It is still more difficult for modern anarchists to trust those who
believe, as is commonplace among Indigenous peoples, in various forms of
what we call âmagicâ: spirits, sorcery, and the like. As materialists,
we reason that spirits, immaterial beings, cannot exist; as disenchanted
descendants of the Enlightenment, we fear that according any reality or
truth to enchantment will drag us back to the Dark Ages. And yet, as we
have seen, the spirits of Wendat cosmology, for example, are never
allowed to drift away from the living materiality of the natural world,
to become transcendent authorities reigning over life. Spirit does not
have to supply that which the body supposedly lacks, to represent an
eternal reality outside of the world; as the Sioux scholar Vine Deloria
points out, âthe afterlife was not of overwhelming concern to people of
the tribal religions.... No highly articulated or developed theories of
the afterlife were ever necessary, and certainly none projected a life
radically different than that experienced on Earthâ (179). Before
dismissing Indigenous cosmologies because of their magical content, we
ought at least to ask: What is the social content of this magic?
The answer is bound to vary widely among the more than five thousand
Indigenous peoples. However, we might find many conceptions of spirit
not drastically different from the atheist Landauerâs. For Landauer,
spirit (Geist) is simply that which unifies people (33); it does not
need to be regarded as a being as much as a doing, an action. In social
scientist Howard Richardsâs words,
Spirits comfort, bring joy, inspire, keep families together, win
football games, carry patients through illnesses, move the hardhearted
to forgiveness, unite friends, put charity fundraising campaigns over
the top, give courage to the weak, bring life to parties, energy to
concerts, success to business enterprises, and do a million and one
other things, even though a spirit is not a thing, and if one were
obliged to answer the question, âWhat exactly is it?â one would have to
answer, in all honesty, âNothing.â But having to answer, âNothing,
no-thing,â no longer bothers me. I am past the point where I expect
every word to refer to a thing.
This social account of the reality of spirits, Richards notes, yields âa
greater access to the wisdom of traditional peoples, who almost
invariably are found by anthropologists to enjoy communing with spiritsâ
(142).
Deloria cautions against an overly literalistic interpretation of
Indigenous magic, such as those promulgated by skeptics and
ârepresentatives of other religions seeking to discredit tribal
religionsâ who deliberately violate their sacred places in order to
demonstrate the non-reality of spiritsâreflecting âa strange non-Indian
belief in a form of mechanical magic that is touchingly adolescentâ
(280). Indeed, they are treating Indigenous Geist as if it were
something rigid, like a dogma. As the Colombian comrades of the Alas de
Xue collective point out, modern theories of magic, from Francis Bacon
to Paul Radin, tend to represent it as a primitive phase of human
development, something to be transcended in favor of rational cognition,
or at best, as a means of coping with âeconomic insecurityâ (116).
âUnity in diversity,â they argue,
means respecting individuals and peoples who dream their utopias based
on their own traditions and myths; this respect must arise from a study
of ethnic and cultural diversity, incorporating their contributions and
expectations, accepting difference as a driving force towards the
construction of Magical Socialism. (121)
Despite the poetic flourish of the phrase socialismo mĂĄgico (a play on
the literary phrase âmagical realism,â perhaps), the direction suggested
by the collective is essentially practical, aimed at making do with what
we have together. From a pragmatist perspective, magic, like spirit, is
what it does. We might understand magic in a very broad sense as the
efficacy of wordsâthe phenomenon in which saying something makes it so.
âWithin Indigenous science,â writes theoretical physicist F. David Peat,
âto say something is to create an objective event and release a process
of energetic vibrations that enter into relationships with the other
powers and energies of natureâ (226). As much as this might sound like
New Age nonsense, it need not be understood in a supernatural sense, for
in fact, we are always making things happen with words. Linguists refer
to these events as âspeech acts,â one of the most common species of
which is the making of promises. Here, rather than describing some real
state of affairs in the world, a description that could be verified or
falsified by inspection, the words uttered actually perform the act of
promising, thus creating, when successful, a new state of affairsâa
social relationship. The classic example is the wedding, in which âI doâ
creates spouses. Promises, when successful, create new states of
affairs; they bring together partners, alliances, federations. It seems,
then, that mere words can create (social) worlds.
Granted, this redescription of magic as a kind of speech act may not
please everyone equally. Surely it does a little rationalization as
well, although I hope that it does not disrespect Indigenous
self-understandings. But pragmatist accounts of such things as spirits
and magic may be one effective way of translating between cosmologies,
allowing us to unsettle some of our own assumptions long enough to
listen and learnâperhaps even long enough to jointly construct a
socialismo mĂĄgico that defies what British theorist Mark Fisher calls
âcapitalist realism.â (2)
One of modernityâs ideological articles of faith is that there is but
one path to futurity, and that it runs through modernity. Modern images
of the future, of course, sometimes include mournful, apocalyptic dreams
in which the world reverts to some previous historical condition, to the
Middle Ages or to some imaginary Wild West; its utopian dreams, when
they do not similarly cast backward for their images, often represent
the shiny new futureâas Bookchin once observedâas just more of the same:
taller skyscrapers, faster cars, and so on (1980, 277). This is cruel,
because it forecloses the imagination of other futures, and impossible,
because it offers more of the same, continuing the project of extraction
indefinitely on a finite earth. Anarchist visionaries have had to
struggle to imagine different futures, often reproducing these modern
tropes.
Nonmodernity, as we might develop it, does not offer to return us to an
imaginarily perfect past, though it does entail surrendering the land
back to Indigenous peoples; it is not a simple inversion or negation of
modernity, much less a simple extension of modernity into the future. It
would seek something elseâa retrieval of past possibilities that is also
a ânew emergence,â in the words of Mississauga Nishnaabeg writer Leanne
Betasamosake Simpson. As such, it would explore previously foreclosed
possibilities for the development of sciences and technologies (always
to be understood in the plural). After all, Indigenous peoples have not
been incurious about the universe or lacking in inventiveness. Indeed,
for as much as settler archaeologists like Elizabeth Weiss and projects
like the construction of the Thirty Meter Telescope on sacred Mauna Kea
portray Indigenous people as obstacles to scientific knowledge, we can
and do speak of Indigenous sciences and technologies.
A demodernized anarchism would not have to abandon the sciences, but it
would abandon scientism. Scientismâthe insistence that scientific method
is the only legitimate means of access to truth, and that therefore it
can be applied everywhere and always without regard for social or
cultural contextâhas promised to liberate us from all the traditional
forms of oppression associated with what the JineolojĂź Committee Europe
identifies as a five-thousand-year-old patriarchal âstate civilizationâ;
where that civilization disrupted relations between humanity and nature
(97), modern scientism proposed to bridge the supposed gap between human
and natural realms by studying both with the same tools. Historian Arif
Dirlik writes of some of the early Chinese anarchists that they âvalued
science to the point of scientism,â in part precisely because it offered
to dissolve the respect for traditions that held the social hierarchies
inherited from Chinese âstate civilizationâ in placeâa major source of
oppression for them (108). In practice, however, scientism also degrades
the spirit of scientific inquiry into âan ideology for viewing the world
as an ethically neutral, essentially mechanical body to be manipulatedâ
(Bookchin 1991, 268)âas well as for so viewing the human body and mind.
Most shamefully, anarchistsâ embrace of scientism led us, for a long
time, to endorse eugenics (47). Freed from scientism, the sciences
become one highly valuable mode of knowing among others. Better still,
Western sciences are freed to encounter other sciences on egalitarian
terms.
The possibilities for combining Indigenous and modern technologies are
similarly wide open. Neither refusing technology completely as bad nor
embracing it in toto as good, we could blend horticultural techniques,
architectures, and practices of medical and psychological healing, for
instance. No longer committed to modern technology as a whole, we might
instead practice many convivial technics, both old and new. Again, this
would necessitate a rejection of the normative developmentalism that
indiscriminately discards traditional ways of knowing and doing as
obsolete on the assumption that there is only one culture that is ânewâ
and that only the new can be better.
We settler anarchists must acknowledge our complicity with colonialism,
and we must not turn living, breathing Indigenous people into our
fantasy objects. As the GuaranĂ activist Bettina Escauriza writes, it is
impossible for settlers to become Indigenous, and beside the point: âThe
issue is not for an individual to become something they are not, but
rather for a centering of other ways of being in the world that may make
our final years on this planetâhowever many or few there may beâones
worth livingâ (102).
We may dimly recognize these âother waysâ as the source of our own best
ideas. Bakunin and Proudhon came of age politically in an intellectual
environment stimulated by accounts of the New World and of its peoples,
who seemed not to recognize the kinds of distinctions drawn by the
colonists, soldiers, and missionaries who encountered them, testifying
to the possibility of radically different worlds. Modern anarchism, as
developed in Europe, was a codification of practices already found in
nonmodern cultural repertoires, practices which anarchism imperfectly
but usefully translated into the conceptual idiom of modernity: mutual
aid, communism, affinity groups, direct democracy, consensus, direct
action.
This is not to say, of course, that all Native American societies were
anarchist in the modern sense of the concept. Clearly, some adhered and
still do adhere to hierarchies of their own. We should not regard these
as a permanent feature of these societies, either (indeed, to say
âsocietyâ is to call any âpermanent featuresâ into question); some were
acquired as a direct result of colonization, and others have been and
may yet be called into question by a process of immanent critique. Such
processes of self-reconstruction emphatically do not require
colonization. If it is anyoneâs turn to listen respectfully, to give
thanks, and to show solidarity, it is white settler anarchists vis-Ă -vis
our Indigenous counterparts.
One thing that Indigenous knowledge can impart to a nonmodern anarchism
is a long experience of linking disparate societies with different
traditions in democratic confederations. Probably the best known of
these is the Haudenosaunee (Iroquois), a confederation that linked first
five and later six nations, an assemblage of considerable power and
influence. The Neshnabé, who were forcibly expelled from Indiana a
little less than a hundred years ago, participated in the Council of
Three Fires with the Odawa (Ottawa) and Ojibwe (Chippewa) peoples, as
well as in the larger culture of the Anishinaabe, which linked them with
the Algonquin, Mississauga, and Nipissing. In the years before their
Removal, they joined in Tecumsehâs much vaster Confederacy to fight the
settlers. Their experience has much to say about the lived experience of
democratic confederationâhow to establish effective unity between
disparate social worlds, how to achieve the coordination of action and
the coexistence of plural truths without the imposition of uniformity
from above.
None of this is really possible if we cling to the project of modernity,
with all that it entails. Letâs demodernize anarchism!
Jesse Cohn is part of the Institute for Anarchist Studies. He teaches in
the Department of English at Purdue University Northwest, in Indiana. He
is the author of Underground Passages: Anarchist Resistance Culture,
1848â2011 (AK Press, 2015), translated, A Little Philosophical Lexicon
of Anarchism from Proudhon to Deleuze (Minor Compositions, 2019), and
has published other books and essays, including in Anarchist Studies,
Fifth Estate, and Radical Philosophy.
Armstrong, Karen. A History of God: The 4,000-Year Quest of Judaism,
Christianity and Islam. Random House Publishing Group, 2011.
Bakunin, Mikhail Aleksandrovich. God and the State. Dover, 1970.
âââ. The Political Philosophy of Bakunin: Scientific Anarchism. Free
Press, 1974.
Bookchin, Murray. The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution
of Hierarchy. Black Rose Books, 1991.
âââ. Re-enchanting Humanity: Defense of the Human Spirit Against
Antihumanism, Misanthropy, Mysticism and Primitivism. Cassell, 1995.
âââ. Toward An Ecological Society. Black Rose Books, 1980.
Burley, Shane. Fascism Today: What It Is and How to End It. AK Press,
2017.
Chalmers, David J. âThe Puzzle of Conscious Experience.â Scientific
American, vol. 273, no. 6, 1995, pp. 80â86.
Colectivo âAlas de Xue.â Una historia del anarquismo en Colombia :
CrĂłnicas de utopĂa (apuntes, momentos y pĂĄginas selectas para una
historia del movimiento libertario americano). FundaciĂłn de Estudios
Libertarios âAnselmo Lorenzo,â 1999.
Colombo, Eduardo. LâEspace politique de lâanarchie: Esquisses pour une
philosophie politique de lâanarchisme. Atelier de crĂ©ation libertaire,
2008.
âââ. âEl anarquismo ante la crisis de las ideologĂas.â AcciĂłn Directa
vol. 1, no. 1, 2006, pp. 15â17.
Creagh, Ronald. âLe Huron et le JĂ©suite.â LâImagination dĂ©robĂ©e, Atelier
de crĂ©ation libertaire, 2004, pp. 69â90.
Deleuze, Gilles, and FĂ©lix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Translated by Robert Hurley et al., University of
Minnesota Press, 1983.
Deloria, Vine. God Is Red: A Native View of Religion. Fulcrum
Publishing, 2003.
Escauriza, Bettina. âThat Which Will Become the Earth:
Anarcho-Indigenous Speculative Geographies.â Journal Des Anthropologues.
Association Française Des Anthropologues, no. 152â153, Apr. 2018, pp.
83â106. journals.openedition.org, https://doi.org/10.4000/jda.6884.
Fisher, Mark. Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Zero Books,
2010. pp 2.
Francis, David A., et al. âpemskutek, pemaskutek.â
Passamaquoddy-Maliseet Language Portal,
https://pmportal.org/dictionary/pemskutek-pemaskutek.
âââ. âpomskute, pomaskute.â Passamaquoddy-Maliseet Language Portal,
https://pmportal.org/dictionary/pomskute-pomaskute.
Galeano, Eduardo. âThe Blue Tiger.â Rethinking Columbus: The Next 500
Years, edited by Bill Bigelow and Bob Peterson. Rethinking Schools,
1998, pp. 177â78.
Graeber, David. âWhatâs the Point If We Canât Have Fun?â The Baffler,
no. 24, pp. 50â58.
Gross, Lawrence William. Anishinaabe Ways of Knowing and Being. Ashgate,
2014.
Hill, Rick. âTalking Points on History and Meaning of the Two Row Wampum
Belt.â Two Row Wampum Renewal Campaign, Mar. 2013,
https://honorthetworow.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/03/TwoRowTalkingPoints-Rick-Hill.pdf.
Ingold, Tim. âBeing Alive to a World without Objects.â The Handbook of
Contemporary Animism, edited by Graham Harvey. Acumen Handbooks, 2013,
pp. 213â25.
Janicka, Iwona. âWho Can Speak? RanciĂšre, Latour and the Question of
Articulation.â Humanities vol. 9, no. 123, 2020, pp. 1â16.
JineolojĂź Committee Europe. JineolojĂź. Mezopotamien Verlag und Vertriebs
GmbH, 2018,
https://jineoloji.org/en/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Jineoloj%C3%AE-English-v2-Final.pdf.
Kimmerer, Robin Wall. âSpeaking of Nature.â Orion Magazine, June 12,
2017, https://orionmagazine.org/article/speaking-of-nature/.
Landauer, Gustav. For Socialism. Translated by David J. Parent. Telos
Press, 1978.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Translated by Catherine
Porter. Harvard University Press, 1993.
LĂ©vi-Strauss, Claude. Structural Anthropology. Translated by Claire
Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf. Basic Books, 2008.
Lyons, Scott Richard. X-Marks: Native Signatures of Assent. University
of Minnesota Press, 2010.
Marker, Michael. âThere Is No Place of Nature; There Is Only the Nature
of Place: Animate Landscapes as Methodology for Inquiry in the Coast
Salish Territory.â International Journal of Qualitative Studies in
Education, vol. 31, no. 6, 2018, pp. 453â64.
Peat, F. David. Lighting the Seventh Fire: The Spiritual Ways, Healing,
and Science of the Native American. Carol Publishing Group, 1994.
Perlman, Fredy. Against His-Story, Against Leviathan!: An Essay. Black &
Red, 1983.
Proudhon, P. J. Oeuvres complĂštes. Edited by CĂ©lestin Charles Alfred
Bouglé and Henri Moysset. Slatkine, 1982.
Quintana-Navarrete, Jorge. âBiopolĂtica y vida inorgĂĄnica: La
plasmogenia de Alfonso Herrera.â Revista HispĂĄnica Moderna, vol. 72, no.
1, 2019, pp. 79â95.
Regier, Terry, and Paul Kay. âLanguage, Thought, and Color: Whorf Was
Half Right.â Trends in Cognitive Sciences, vol. 13, no. 10, Oct. 2009,
pp. 439â46. ScienceDirect, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.07.001.
Richards, Howard. Letters from Quebec: A Philosophy for Peace and
Justice. International Scholars Publications, 1996.
âsacred, adj. and n.â OED Online, Oxford University Press, September
2021, www.oed.com/view/Entry/169556.
Simpson, Leanne Betasamosake. Dancing on Our Turtleâs Back: Stories of
Nishnaabeg Re-Creation, Resurgence and a New Emergence. Arbeiter Ring
Publishing, 2011.
Taibo, Carlos. Anarquistas de ultramar: anarquismo, indigenismo,
descolonizaciĂłn. Los Libros de la Catarata, 2018.
Taylor, Michael P. ââIndians MUST Organizeâ: Reimagining Indigenous
Modernity through the Writings of the National Council of American
Indians.â Modernism/Modernity Print Plus, Johns Hopkins University
Press, March 2021. modernismmodernity.org,
https://modernismmodernity.org/forums/posts/taylor-indians-must-organize.
Warburton, Theresa. Other Worlds Here: Honoring Native Womenâs Writing
in Contemporary Anarchist Movements. Northwestern University Press,
2021.
Wynter, Sylvia. âHuman Being as Noun? Or Being Human as Praxis?: Towards
the Autopoetic Turn/Overturn: A Manifesto.â Unpublished essay.