đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș william-gillis-partition-entanglement.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:43:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Partition & Entanglement Author: William Gillis Date: January 11th, 2022 Language: en Topics: anarchism, national liberation, anti-nationalism, Nandita Sharma, migration, immigration, indigenous, settler colonialism Source: Retrieved on September 21st, 2022 from https://c4ss.org/content/55841.
âThe entire, eons-long practice of human movement into new places was
pushed out of our imagination â or, perhaps more accurately, was
reimagined as a national security threat. In the process, stasis was
glorified as the normative way of being human.â
âOnly after the death of the national liberation project can we renew
our commitment to decolonization.â
Many years ago a latinx friend of mine designed stickers that simply
read âMigrants Welcome, Against Bordersâ (versions in English and
Spanish) under a circle-A and the two of us covered the Bay Area with
hundreds of them. Amusingly, this provoked the ire of a prominent white
anarchist who denounced the phrase as pro-gentrification. She
emphatically preferred âRefugees Welcomeâ because it distinguished those
who are coercively displaced from their proper homes by various forms of
western imperialism in contrast to those who voluntarily choose to
migrate, like (her example) those moving to the bay for tech jobs.
My friend found this preposterous; we already have lines of critique to
deal with the privileges of the gentrifier class and the negative
structural mechanisms of gentrification. Virtually no one in the
American context calls white tech bros âmigrantsâ â the term has almost
exclusively valences of brown skin and manual labor. The average
American who runs across a âMigrants Welcomeâ sticker knows immediately
what it means (and gets mad about it), whereas the term âRefugeesâ is
much more sparingly used and in many cities is far less contentious or
even that meaningful. This isnât an abstract sense, but something
empirically visible: in San Francisco and Portland white yuppies would
ignore ârefugees welcomeâ stickers my friends ordered from European
antifa distros, but frequently tear down âmigrants welcomeâ â sometimes
even leaving racial slurs scrawled in their place.
Further, my friend argued, surely as anarchists we support the freedom
of individuals to move for whatever personal reason, not just when they
are formally categorized as âvictims.â The response was sharp, no, she
emphasized, neighborhood communes should have the power to
democratically decide who is allowed in.
Nandita Sharma writes from the context of a different intersection of
struggles. Sharma is an anarchist, activist, and academic whose family
was shaped by the traumatic partition of India and their immigration to
so-called Canada. In the dedication to Home Rule: National Sovereignty
and the Separation of Natives and Migrants, she relays her motherâs
dismay at the suppression of a Mohawk revolt: âUs and them, same, same.â
This is the central focus of Home Rule: to ruthlessly criticize and
deconstruct the migrant versus indigenous conceptual dichotomy rather
than ignore it. Whether such categorical distinctions come ââfrom aboveâ
or âfrom below,ââ from the right or from the ostensible left.
It is not a rejection of specific claims or a sweeping leveling of
complex differences in historical injustice. Struggles for land and
liberation, for the defense of culture violently suppressed, in response
to the traumas and particularities, are obviously vital and important.
But Sharma is not tip-toeing around, timidly qualifying statements so
much they say nothing, as so many writers in this space do. Her target
is all nationalism, and ultimately all parochialism, all regionalism,
explicitly including the nationalism of the oppressed, and her argument
is that for all the leftist discursive trappings, such a framework
reproduces the structures of an existing postcolonial order that has
simply laundered power and domination, rather than abolishing it. To
truly break the legacy of colonialism we must break entirely with the
frame of nationalism and the idea of discrete peoples each inherently
âof some place,â cultivating instead, a more complex global commons.
Central to Sharmaâs argument is that notions of nativeness do violence
to the complexities of the actual human tapestry â to fix some people as
being âof a placeâ and others as aliens to it â is a simplification that
benefits power and hierarchy. While the mistaken frame of sovereignty
has spontaneously emerged in various places for thousands of years (to
inevitable damage and horror), todayâs global interlocking nationalist
order is a direct continuation of the imperial and colonial process of
legibility construction.
Home Rule is a book that refreshingly says something, not just with
hyper-particularity, but with general conclusions.
This has been a hard review to write because I unabashedly love this
book and have spent over a year urging every academic anarchist I know
to read it â to universal followup thanks and praise. There are plenty
of merely good books that merely retread or repackage important
positions and critiques, the activist press is filled with them.
Perfectly enjoyable books that get consumed on a monthly subscription
basis by thousands to little fanfare or impact. Rare is the book like
Debt: The First 5000 Years or Caliban And The Witch that become lasting
centers of gravity in the left. And rarer still is the book that doesnât
just meet the radical left where much of it already is, but pushes it
further. I am not given to hyperbole in praise, so let this serve as a
high water mark in a decade of lengthy reviews: Home Rule feels like a
worthy sequel to The Many Headed Hydra.
This may seem a little non-sequitur given how directly Home Rule leans
on a lot of established work in postcolonial studies, but thematically
and ideologically, itâs plain throughout the entire text that Sharma is
tightly aligned with Linebaugh and Rediker. And while their famous
collaboration developed over a series of engaging historical anecdotes
or studies weaving together into a broader picture of universal struggle
for the commons and against power, Sharmaâs is more of a meticulously
broad weapon, rigorously covering a sweeping global history of empire
and the rise of various nationalisms over the last two centuries. Entire
eras in the development of individual nations are sometimes given merely
an incisive paragraph. Sharma strings the reader along with as many
engaging examples and detailed contrasts as she can, but her need to
provide exacting scope leaves much of Home Rule a ratatatat of
globetrotting examples and citations as she presses her general point.
Yet the passionate universalism, the sense that the struggle against
domination is one timeless struggle at the heart of humanity, fills your
chest in a way few other books even bother to attempt.
Sharmaâs approach in Home Rule is to demonstrate 1) How historically
useful the divisions of nationality, of foreigner and native, were to
the European imperialist project. 2) The complex ways that settler
colonial ideology is parasitic on this framework and reproduces it. And
3) how the modern paradigm of a checkerboard of nations covering the
planet was the continuation and â in many ways â intensification of the
logic of prior imperialist horrors.
Today thereâs widespread interest in either painting nationalism as a
timeless reality of human nature and innate community structures, or in
overly distinguishing the particular norms of the westphalian
nationstate system as some kind of totally unique phenomenon. Sharma is
clear that nations in the broader sense have an unfortunately long
legacy reaching back thousands of years, but at the same time European
imperialism played a significant role in deepening the poison. Virtually
all the modern associations we have with borders as well as the
repulsion of non-natives, have their genesis in the administrative needs
of empire.
In the US context we often forget or ignore historical developments
beyond our borders, turning the slave trade into an entirely US-centric
story, for example, and ignoring worldwide phenomena that we werenât
central to. But Sharma draws out how, on the global level, the
abolishment of slavery in the British Empire led to a calamitous decline
in the productivity of centralized capital intensive projects like
plantations, as former slaves focused on efficiently satisfying their
interests as small farmers or paid laborers. Since these decentralized
forms of economic activity are both less taxable and less legible and
more facilitative of resistance and power erosion⊠as always, the
misfortune of high-capital projects means the misfortune of the state.
And of course, low-capital projects like small farmers have little
capacity to capture political power for themselves to stop the state
from recoiling.
The replacement of slave labor with âcoolieâ labor from India and China
filled the same boats, and served the same economic niches, and was
conditioned and controlled through indenture and immigration controls.
It was an explicitly racialized system that in many cases amounted to
contract slavery, but added token paperwork (a contract in an alien
language stamped with your fingerprint and an early passport) and
shifted around (de facto) slave flows to benefit British interests.
Essentially: first you conquer the world, then you slice it up into
little prisons and refuse to allow people to seek economic opportunities
across your new prison walls unless they have certificates that are only
given to those with indenture contracts. Since people have always moved
to seek opportunities, you have a base population of workers, but since
itâs always nice to keep the labor market completely desperate, you also
implement policies of vicious enclosure, dispossession, repression, and
famine-making.
This is the essential thing to understand: even as Americans we live in
the continuation of a global system created in large part by the British
Empire. A system that became so globally encompassing it could do away
with the traditional focus of states or nations on limiting exit and
instead shift to now limiting entry between subdivisions of the empire.
Through systematic dispossession almost every region produced displaced
and desperate workers for the global benefit of the empire, but rather
than have their origin region administrate their distribution to other
regions, it was recipient imperial regions that oversaw admissions.
To be clear â the British themselves didnât need to cover literally
every square inch of the planet, merely a sufficient fraction of it so
as to crystalize a new world system, partially of imitators and
partially of regimes around the periphery who â still focused on
preventing the exit of their own populations â saw the benefit. So, for
example, the nominally independent Chinese government actively
collaborated with this new immigration control system since it offset
the costs of preventing its populationâs escape.
Moreover, paternalistic liberal reformism reinforced this new system,
taking the existing (racialized) internal barriers to movement and
strengthening them. The liberal imperialist declared that Indian and
Chinese migration must be stopped for their own good, so the systematic
dispossession and immiseration of colonial occupation continued, but now
even sharper constraints were put up against rational relocation.
Liberals found the new immigration-regulatory state form quite amenable
to these reforms because it served state and capitalist power.
Sharma emphasizes that these practices of imperialism werenât confined
to contexts like India where partition makes them blindingly apparent,
they were also critical to white settler states like the US, and liberal
paternalistic reformism (intersecting with state needs) likewise played
an important role, although with some limited inversions.
Since local populations (often with access to commons, ecological
knowledge, wider community support, etc.) were at least perceived as
distinctly resistant to work and thus obliging the importing of various
forms of coerced and dispossessed labor, and because their existence
threatened certain mobilizing narratives, a distinct approach was taken
with them. âDefinition, segregation, protection, and immobilizationâ
were repeatedly shepherded by liberal paternalism, flattening the
complexities and dynamism of pre-columbian societies into a fetishized
place-bound ideal of stasis. Notions of âinnocenceâ and âpurityâ were
leveraged to patronizingly preserve âtraditionâ, in ways that
systematically suppressed the native to extremely limited means or modes
of engagement, while stripping anyone who wandered outside those borders
of native status. So for example in Canada,
âIndians needed a permit from a government Indian agent to sell, trade,
or barter (Opekokew 1980; Sluman and Goodwill 1982). Obtaining a
university degree or voting in a Canadian election was declared to be
âun-Indianâ and, if practiced, would, until 1960, result in the loss of
âIndianâ status.â
Meanwhile across settler states it was generally decided that a woman
who married a white man lost her legal ânativeâ protections.
âProtectionâ meant segregation, and âtraditionâ meant deprivement of
wider mobility, solidarity, and economic access.
This suppression of potential market activity no doubt helped
monopolistic ambitions of white capitalists, but itâs a stark comparison
to the forced entry into labor markets going on elsewhere. Sharma roots
the explanation in terms of legitimization processes distinct to white
settler societies.
If the arc in the surrounding British imperial world started with forced
assimilation and then transitioned to the construction of nativism, in
general terms the US and other white settler states went from the
construction of nativism to forced assimilation. These divergent paths
were related to the need of white settler states to construct their own
nationalist sovereignty and identity to bind disparate whites against
the migrant labor being imported. As the pivot from empire to
nationalism took place globally, with for example the US revising its
self-perception into a nation rather than aspiring empire, the white
dominated colonies focused on constructing whiteness as a native
identity (erasing prior complexities and divergences in origins and
motivations).
âwhat makes White Settler colonies distinctive is not that, from the
start, imperial states wanted to extinguish Native life in order to gain
territory to populate with Europeans. Instead, what is unique about them
is that the Whitening of one portion of the working class sowed deep and
long-lasting divisions between workers⊠Arguably, the success of
strategies used to Whiten workers was an initial moment in the imperial
turn to biopower and informed all subsequent âdefine and ruleâ
strategies of indirect-rule colonialism across the empire.â
This inevitably meant championing not just the nationalistic and native
paradigms, but also a framework of extermination, assimilation, and
âpreservationâ that framed prior populations as static snapshots and
objectified them in terms of identification with place and history â to
be treated as museum curios on the side of the road â rather than agents
capable of an active conflicting claim to nativeness. White settlers
could then be constructed as uniquely native and migrant by removing the
agency and presence of existing native populations. And insofar as those
populations were to achieve agency or capacity for self-alteration they
were to be forced into whiteness.
Thus a major byproduct of constructing white settler national identity
as ânativesâ was the construction and reinforcement of national and
native frames in actually native populations. Some of these dynamics are
well known. Policies like the Dawes Rolls incentivized deep alignment
towards the stateâs notion of âindiannessâ by tribal leaders and many
individuals. Blood quantification and discreteness of âmembershipâ were
but part of a wider array of incentivized dynamics in the construction
of identity.
And this followed imperial and colonial patterns worldwide:
âColonialism was now portrayed as necessary, not to change
Indigenous-Natives (e.g., to âcivilizeâ them), but to preserve their
(often invented) traditions and customs as they encountered the âmodernâ
worldâ
Reservations confined survivors to remove them from attention and
facilitate cultural extermination, but they also reinforced and even
created identifications of peoples with place. Imperialist and
settler-colonial practice thus shaped and constructed indigenous
subjectivities. This is both a trivial and a sharp claim, and Sharma
leans into the latter.
The forcible crushing of cultures and knowledge erased much, but it also
imposed opportunity costs. What is lost to western imperialism is not
just what was, but what mightâve grown on their own or in varying
degrees of collaborative contact with distant cultures. The pathways of
exploration and creation â the consensual syntheses and wildly divergent
children â that were made impossible. Such is also the legacy of
colonization.
This is an image of colonialism not just as imposed contact, but
actually as violent segregation. This picture of colonization is the
suppression of meshing networks, instead violently affirming
simplifications and removals. Anything to stop hybridization and complex
cyborg flows or diversifications of agential currents. White settler
society could only hold itself together if it removed all fluidity and
activity from those it wanted to steal ânativenessâ from. Ratcheting up
the definition and immobilization inherent to any construct of
nativeness, hoping to impose such to the point of rigor mortis.
The Third Reich would infamously later take up this ideological drive
into an explicit institutional crusade for the âpreservationâ of local
cultures against the âimperialismâ of global culture. Such
hyper-paternalistic reduction of diverse, mobile, and fluid populations
into fixed eternal peoples with similarly eternally fixed traits and
behaviors was, we must remember, cast as a noble struggle of resistance.
Part of what made national socialism so potent was its self-narrative as
standing up for the little guys worldwide. Germany sincerely saw itself
as defending the indigenous nations of Europe against globalism,
universalism, and foreign corruption. And, just as in the settler states
it took partial inspiration from, this meant concentration camps and
mass murder.
Itâs important to highlight however, that such define-and-rule
paternalism wasnât just the invention of some happenstance global norms
or conventions constraining the arrival of immigrants, it was also bound
up with the wider imposition of capitalist dynamics that incentivized
the perpetuation and reinforcement of these new norms even once the
regional prison administrators had autonomy.
The imperialists put the system into place but could then, in the
twentieth century, step back and let it perpetuate itself.
To put it in more concretely theoretical terms: it took the genocidal
engines of imperialism to push most of the world into a profoundly
suboptimal equilibria state. A new configuration that resisted
transformation and pulled anything nearby into its own destructive form.
Indeed, having brutally reshaped the world into this new norm of states
policing entry, the ruling imperial powers increasingly found it
advantageous to remove their own administrative overhead once a region
had been integrated into the new global system.
That the project of imperialism became constructing these discrete
ânationsâ was explicit in many ways. The League of Nations openly framed
the role of Empire as the development of nations, the âtutelageâ of
populations into becoming distinct âPeoplesâ and then nations.
Of course FDR used British desperation in and after World War 2 to
strong-arm the UK into effectively turning their empire over to the US,
but this wasnât a change of the foundations. The US model was a
decentralized next step in the British approach to administration: where
discrete national prisons were administered through the UN and brought
to heel via one-sided open trade with the US â the last standing
industrial and financial powerhouse â but retained enough independence
to resiliently keep the whole system afloat. It was the intensification
of the British policy of getting Natives to continue the process of
empire themselves. Struggles of resistance, having now aligned with US
power and aspirations, were then able to create a checkerboard of
postcolonial nations.
This escalated processes of enclosure and suppression because local
rulers had local knowledge and were now embedded in more totalizing and
resilient wider incentive structures.
When U Nu, the nationalist first prime minister of Burma, described the
UN charter as âone great mutual security pactâ he was not speaking of
the security of nations against one another, but of the security of
power in the face of that which would dissolve it. In this sense the
interlocking national structure was not a matter of securing peace (wars
continued unabated), but of securing domination itself from the spectre
of revolution, insurrection, and revolt.
Power embraced decentralized fragmentation (according to a fixed logic)
to avoid dissolution.
Natural systems, left to their own devices, will generally entangle.
When ink disperses into water the result is a dissolution of simplistic
discrete categories and structures. This is the opposite of
nationalistic fragmentation which continues the construction of
legibility started by Empire. If the preservation of âorderâ requires a
fractal subdivision of humanity â the forced relocations and
dispossessions of countless souls in endless partitions â then all the
worse for any actual living breathing individual human beings. Humanity
must be fed into the meatgrinder of simplistic abstractions.
Sharma is quite clear that, in her mind, the term âimperialismâ poorly
characterizes the US-created postcolonial system. The US was a hegemonic
locus of power that extracted absurd concessions and material wealth
from the rest of the world, spread its bases everywhere and bombed
civilians, but the global nationstate it built was significantly
different from all prior empires. Sharma is without mercy in her
description of the machinations of the US (and USSR), but itâs still
deeply unsettling to read a leftist author put âUS imperialismâ in scare
quotes, so deeply has the anti-imperialist frame of analysis become
hegemonic. In Sharmaâs insistent frame, neither the US nor the USSR were
âempires,â they were rather postcolonial powers, a classification which
she seeks to give equivalently negative valences.
Sharma is concerned that the âimperialismâ frame centers foreigners
invading and controlling natives, an analysis that both misses critical
dynamics of the Postcolonial New World Order and reproduces the
nationalism it is dependent upon. In her ideal world we would recognize
the âpostcolonialâ system as a distinct and arguably worse evil.
I am, it must be said, not sanguine about this rhetorical strategy.
Whatever our ideal language might be, activist usage largely does not
follow academic invention, but is shaped by and responds to pragmatic
needs and pressures, constantly collapsing to the most succinct frame
that makes intuitive use of existing language. Complex formal
definitions rarely win against general resemblances. And it is simply a
fact that capital flows continue to be centralized in imperial
metropoles. Why shouldnât we speak of the US, USSR, and PRC as empires
and imperialist projects? Their economic as well as political
centralization and direct military domination has clearly followed
longstanding imperialist patterns. Comparisons to imperialism are
inherent because the term has widespread negative cachet in general
populations. There is no feasible pathway to establishing similarly
potent valances for âpostcolonialâ on its own; we struggle mostly within
the language we are given.
Sharma confidently claims that global inequality is worse today than in
the age of empire.
âBetween 1960 and the late 1990s, a significant widening of world income
distribution took place. Indeed, the extent of the disparities surpassed
those during the Age of Empiresâ
But I find such quantifications suspect. One can point to all manner of
depredation and slaughter today, but can anyone really say with any
certainty that todayâs world is more unequal than when the Belgians were
chopping off hands and feet in Congo? This is not to entirely foreclose
the possibility, but it seems like the sort of claim thatâs impossible
to establish. In short it collapses tangles of complexities much the
same way nations collapse the complexity of our social relations. Never
mind the discontinuities of measuring wealth over a period where the
fine-grained legibility of title itself has changed, or the
incomensurabilities papered over by âinflation adjustedâ figures. Even
pointing out the enclosure of the dark parts of the map sweepingly
described as âcommonsâ proves very little about relative degrees of
access and power within said old commons. I simply canât imagine a
single unified measure of âinequalityâ or any bundling of an aggregate
measure that could even remotely establish this claim. (Much less by way
of citation to Samir fucking Armin, a Khmer Rouge and Putin defending
wingnut.)
This is not necessarily to push back on the idea that the creation of
postcolonial national regimes made things overall worse, when examined
within a certain window, but as an argument itâs a quagmire. What sort
of time window should we be using to evaluate this? From one side
someone could make the argument that national liberation struggles led
to a gradual weakening of imperial power long before flags formally
changed on a map, from the other side the nationalist ideologues could
just as easily say âundoing imperialism is just really hard, we need
another five centuries before things get net positive, but then things
will get truly good.â Thereâs no winning once we get bogged down into
arguing over which timescale and period to measure over.
Itâs certainly true that many things have gotten worse in the
postcolonial era. For example, where colonial administration hadnât
managed to implement border controls, the newly âliberatedâ nationstates
acted quickly to create them. This meant that the transition from
colonial rule to postcolonial rule in for example much of Africa saw the
sudden creation of constraints on movement that had been free throughout
prior history. In this respect Sharma is correct in identifying the
postcolonial system as even worse than the imperialist system,
intensifying its logic of domination rather than breaking from it. And
similar analysis can be made in terms of the formalization of new
property regimes and the intensifying legibility of claims at the cost
of the old support mechanisms of the commons.
But this doesnât necessarily prove an overall devolution.
Regardless of whether national liberation was a net advancement or a net
escalation of horrors, I am frankly quite sick of common leftist
rhetoric that dismisses things like the abolition of chattel slavery as
an irrelevant trick of smoke and mirrors. Radicals often feel we have to
pretend we live in the worst of all possible worlds because if people
feel thereâs any advantages to our present order they might not want to
risk toppling it. This is a path by which radicalism perversely ends up
generating reactionary frames at least as noxious as nationalism. The
sloppy leftist dismisses the immense suffering under for example
monarchy and slavery and the awe-inspiring, hard-won social
transformations away from them, declaring instead that all progress so
far has been illusory, even that things have gotten worse. It is true of
course that power has gotten more dextrous, more insidious, and its
function more complex. But that retreat to complex mechanisms is itself
a sign of power on the back foot.
When the mechanisms of power are forced to adopt greater internal
complexity they lose efficiency and either become more brittle or open
up more space for erosion. Power may survive in the face of resistance
by mutating and trying to co-opt or misdirect that resistance, but that
is not necessarily to say it ends up on a stronger footing. Merely that
the strategic landscape changes.
The Left spent the last half of the twentieth century in a tizzy about
insidiously complex systems of control like advertising and the
construction of desire that end up being largely paper tigers. It
convinced itself that progress was impossible, that Moloch had perfected
titanic systems to generate false consciousness, even while progress was
being made in myriad places, often without the help of leftist or
radical theorists. This is not to suggest that nationalism of the
oppressed is a necessary step towards progress, nor that no one knew
better â many anarchists at the time certainly did and far too many paid
with our lives for the sin of correct prognostication â but I do think
we canât afford to ignore or discard the positive currents and
improvements that got mixed up in the noxious morass of national
liberation struggles.
A significant aspect of Sharmaâs argument is that no nation escaped
neoliberalism because in fact nationalism and neoliberalism each imply
the other. In her account national liberation states didnât âsell outâ
to western imperialists, rather they continued the logic of nation
building, that is to say building infrastructure and exclusionary power
systems necessarily provoked positive sum (for capitalists and rulers)
collaboration between nations. Sure the Washington neoliberal
institutions profited immensely, but so too did the ânational
liberationâ projects, once you realize what nation building means. And
Sharmaâs right that in many contexts the most supreme and omnipresent
power in peopleâs lives was national.
Indeed one of the ways national liberation states benefit from the
horrors of global apartheid is by externalizing costs: the rule of
autocrats depends upon exporting the unemployed and dissidents they
create. That those people are made desperate by immigration restrictions
in other countries and at best become a deeply policed inferior class
helps maintain order at home. Obey and stay or else get thrown into a
meatgrinder. Submit to the prison at home, or else become a prisoner
completely without rights or even voice in the global system. The
project of national control is only stabilized by the ability to eject,
to make alien or immigrant, those in the fuzzy areas (which are
ultimately almost everyone). The nationalist and the capitalist both
need the dispossessed underclass inherent to the construction of borders
and national identities.
Sharma drills down in particular on how the specific term
âneo-colonialismâ was invented and theorized by Kwame Nkrumah who ruled
Ghana and served as a major figure in the Non-Aligned Movement. Nkrumah
only wrote and publicized his theory after he had already destroyed the
homes of tens of thousands for a dam to power a smelter for Kaiser
Aluminum, a U.S.-based corporation and then created permanent economic
catastrophe by nationalizing much of the economy into a command system.
Every step of the way Nkrumahâs ruling circle enriched itself while
exacerbating inherent state dysfunction. The national liberation regime
sweepingly tried to do big things with the blunt instrument of the
state, externalizing the costs to the people, while profiting from the
asymmetries. The analysis of âneocolonialismâ thus emerged from the
outset as an apologia and deflection by those in power.
In contrast to this theorizing-from-above, Sharma emphasizes how the rot
of the entire postcolonial system was focused on and critiqued by
theorists-from-below like Ghanaâs Ayi Kwei Armah as having always been
lying in wait in the national liberation project.
In short, our postcolonial hellworld isnât perversion or undermining of
national liberation, but its natural culmination.
Under the postcolonial order all legitimacy lies in being a discrete
People âof place.â Such Peoples can make political claims, declarations,
demands, but the same is virtually unthinkable for migrants, those âout
of placeâ.
âwhile the âhuman rightsâ of many National Citizens were not recognized,
respecting such rights for foreigners was always out of the questionâ
Further, the power structures, the lines of domination that persisted
under or were necessary for the ânationâ were framed as âpeoplesâ
power.â The very possibility of abolishing power itself was thus made
increasingly unthinkable. Rather, the fascistic philosophy shared from
Engels to Schmidt became hegemonic: âthere is nothing outside
domination, only questions of who wields it.â
The paradigm of national liberation thus is the paradigm of postcolonial
apartheid, not of actual decolonization.
In Sharmaâs account the postcolonial period of nationalization was
necessarily a ratcheting of the violent hierarchies introduced or
intensified by colonization. By splintering the world into competing
nations every nation was forced into a âdevelopmentâ arms race that
intensified processes of enclosure. If imperialism had partially
dispossessed a subsistence farmer the nationalist project only furthered
this suffering. Just as capitalism depends on simplistically slicing up
collectively managed commons into fungible and alienable parcels, the
entire paradigm of âthe nationâ works to slice apart different natives,
and create a fungible underclass out of everyone too entangled to fit in
these boxes.
Migrant labor is thus the gasoline that drives the world power system,
while native labor helps structure, condition, direct, and control it.
The global patchwork of discrete nations necessarily creates migrants by
their existence, slicing up (violently simplifying) the inherently more
complex network that is humanity as well as obviously stripping options
and agency from individuals.
All this has deep implications and insights with regard to the turn to
patchwork micronationalism intensifying among most currents of
reactionaries and fascists since the 80s. Obviously a strategy of
fractal secession would only further deepen the creation of oppressed
migrant classes. The micronationalists frequently act like the problem
with existing nationalisms is that they encompass too much complexity
and so the logic of nationalism should be pushed further to the point of
every town, every neighborhood a nation. The fractal checkerboard of
Iraq and Syria emphasizes that this doesnât bring peace, it brings
displacement and more directly attentive gang rule. And, of course, a
mass refugee crisis.
Todayâs reactionaries often fetishize âexitâ on the premise that folks
can vote with their feet and thus minimize the harms of governments, but
the incentive structures of nationalism at the margins, as economists
say, donât work that way. Rather, constructed minorities are targeted
and pushed out of one region on the premise that they have less
legitimate âclaimâ to belonging and then no other region has incentive
to provide them full citizenship. Elevating a stranger to equivalent
political power and rights as you is rarely worth that personâs marginal
economic contribution to your nation. Thus the global ratchet is towards
intense hierarchies of Nth-class noncitizens. A patchwork of democracies
or populist dictatorships thus rapidly converges on arbitrary class
ladders with the enfranchised few shrinking and the base of exploited or
just suppressed constantly expanding.
Itâs easy to lose legitimacy as a ânativeâ but almost impossible to gain
it.
Of course it should always have been trivially apparent that a patchwork
of states would be inclined away from freedom. A market with 200 hundred
competing buyers and seven billion competing sellers is always going to
be skewed to the buyers. When whatâs being sold is labor and the system
iterates constantly the emergence of essentially slavery conditions is a
foregone conclusion. Even if there were two million buyers the asymmetry
in bargaining power will remain pertinent.
This authoritarian ratchet of the inter-national system was what we
opposed in the streets of Seattle fighting the WTO, a system of
âglobalizationâ that used national barriers to reinforce power globally.
The only way to stop the race-to-the-bottom enabled by the interlocking
system of ânationsâ is to abolish them entirely. Sharma is quite clear
that reinforcing borders doesnât protect local workers, it is an
essential component of the overall downward spiral.
If we start from the perspective that the world is an irreducibly
complex network, then itâs preposterous to think that such a network can
be decomposed into a set of discrete villages or cliques. Rather, with
every subdivision forcibly sliced through the tangled knot of humanity,
lives are cut short and single threads cast loose. Fractal secession or
subdivision is thus the most damaging, most harmful, strategy possible.
It looks at the harm caused by nationalism, by borders slicing up the
world, displacement, genocide, and war, and thinks the solution is to
double down.
Instead of framing things in terms of a âright to exitâ we must realize
that the modern nation paradigm is predicated on a claimed âright to
ejectâ that is to manage populations by violently subdividing them, by
the construction of âthe inside and the outside.â The nationalist takes
the nation as given but there is no such cohesive simplistic discrete
set of people. Not even a âfamilyâ has an a priori inside and outside,
lines of connection and association are always graduated and intermeshed
in complex ways that defy simple accounts. The nationalistâs given is
not a reflection of reality, it is an idol he is asserting, an idol
whose ârightsâ inherently require human sacrifice.
Itâs beyond critical that we emphasize this, because the fact that a
structure emerged out of a specific historical context doesnât mean it
wouldnât and hasnât emerged in other contexts. An intellectual fascist,
upon reading Sharma, would no doubt see her argument about the
historical roots in imperial bureaucratic management as beside the
point.
The specificity of ânationalismâ as a word and ideological history has
become blurred out in popular perception to virtually any and all
projects of usness versus themness. The modern proponent of nationalism
would look at two germanic tribes warring with one another thousands of
years ago and see two ânations.â And it is not clear to me that such a
wider definition is âobjectivelyâ wrong. For what it lacks in congruence
with the historical emergence of the term, it can be argued the more
generalized definition does a better job at cutting reality at the
joints. Beyond the relevance of popular usage, to achieve the generality
and universalism of a truly radical analysis, our words should arguably
try to pick out perpetually emergent dynamics, rather than exclusively
tracing out particular usage within a specific historical context.
William C Anderson reminds us of all this in general terms in his
critique of Ashanti Alstonâs sympathies for black nationalism, writing
in The Nation Of No Map, âsome of us are descended from the enslaved
because of the betrayal of nations, one group of people pitting
themselves against another for dominance⊠our past is a cautionary
tale.â [emphasis added] While many horrible particular norms of the
present postcolonial nationstate system were created by Empire, that
system itself had roots in the generalized logic of nations and
division. The pull of simplicity driving clustering dynamics and closed
communities arenât a cure for Empire, theyâre what gave rise to it in
the first place.
Sharma doesnât deny the widespread tendency to chauvinism, but she
doesnât directly address that in Home Rule, being instead at pains to
undermine our current reception of Native and Migrant conceptual
categorizations as timeless, putting their present use in historical
context as products of specific power systems and interests. And, as a
correction Home Rule can at least emphasize that the particular potency
of nationalism and native identification today is overwhelmingly propped
up by a specific history of power. But, while the problem posed by human
inclinations towards clustered communities and simplistic cognitive
abstractions of groups (in-group or out-group) is an eternal threat that
can obviously reproduce territorial barriers and the like on its own,
the history that Sharma highlights has clear general implications.
Even in those cases where a nationalistic tendency is not carrying a
legacy of imperialist managerial needs, the fact that managers love the
nation form and that such can only be cleaved out of humanityâs tangles
via systemic violence is relevant. While there may be a cognitive
laziness in humans that eternally pulls us towards the mistake of
nationalism, this is not at all to say that nations are natural or good,
any more than a common illusion or confusion is.
Common fantasies of a return to perfectly uniform and closed communities
of fixed traditions are motivated by fear of complexity and a hunger for
the abolition of thought and responsibility. This is not to suggest that
complexity is innately good, or truth not often quite simple, but
nations are the product of valuing simplicity as an ends almost unto
itself. Theyâre not about accurately mapping what is true, theyâre about
imposing a reduction of complexity. This is the common goal of would-be
slaves and rulers, and so the historical equivalence and
ever-more-deepening ties between nationalism and various forms of
authoritarianism is unavoidable. The imperialist and post-colonial
leader obviously share in a need to impose simplicity to build power
structures, but so too does a certain type of revolutionary or insurgent
have an investment in making the battlefield simple.
Today if it is said that we can no more envision the end of capitalism
than the end of the world, we can even less envision the end of
nationalism. The only alternative to European imperialism folks can
imagine under its spell is often just European feudalism, re-baked as a
kind of voluntary micronationalism. But the manors of feudal Europe â
with their aspiration to operate villages as closed social universes in
ways wildly different from how bands and sedentary communities have
emerged in other societies â are not some natural configuration emergent
from free association and personal preference. They were, themselves,
the historical product of imperialism and maintained through immense
violence, serving the ends of power.
And this is a critique that can be turned back, to some degree, on
Sharmaâs appeal to and valorization of the commons.
Thereâs a broad metanarrative in circulation, especially among Marxists
looking for a way to ditch their historical materialist baggage by
focusing on the end of the first volume of Capital, that once upon a
time âthe commonsâ provided freedom, security, and community, only to be
brutally sliced up at the onset of capitalism, dispossessing and
creating the working class. As an account of the enclosures this is
certainly quite accurate. And itâs easy to see the congruities between
this aspect of capitalism and what Sharma focuses on in the construction
of nationalism. Similarly the core of her argument that the postcolonial
nation system is worse than imperialism is that it has enabled more
dextrous enclosures. Distant imperial bureaucrats couldnât dream of
incentivizing and handling the construction of modern property norms to
the same extent as local rulers shouting about national honor and
growth.
Libertarians tend to treat Lockean property titles as unalloyed
positives, arbitrarily selecting a thin slice of possible property norms
as the most ideal, in no small part â even when they hide such
consequentialist roots to this position â because it facilitates
fungibility and investment and ideally thus rapid âdevelopment.â
Part of what is glossed over is the cost of such imposed
orthogonalization in property titles. Whereas while every society has a
property system of some kind, claims are usually far more entangled than
anything like the cleanly separable ones of Lockean norms. As claims of
ownership originally emerged in bottom up processes of widely or
mutually useful detentes, they kept all sorts of artifacts of their
context. Someoneâs title to their house might not be exclusive or apply
in every dimension. This impedes selling property, staking it as
collateral, etc, if only because one personâs title claim is not
something entirely in oneâs own hands, and is also ultimately dependent
upon the aggregate acceptance of countless individuals in oneâs
community.
Further, sure, this entanglement in conventional property impedes rapid
âdevelopment,â but when the state violently slices through those
entangled connections to impose one universal and fungible map it can
only assure âdevelopmentâ in a similarly slapdash and unilateral form.
Instead of distributed weighing of every individualâs context and
desires, these violently âoptimizedâ market processes can only serve the
hamfisted ends of power. That is to say: there are very different
directions and branches of âdevelopmentâ possible, serving very
different interests.
But this brings us to some frictions in the popular âlost commonsâ
narrative. Firstly, many societies do not have commons in anywhere near
the same sense as the feudal villages often treated as prototypical.
Even the egalitarian !Kung San hunter-gatherers traded overlapping
titles to regions of land and all their benefits within their gift/debt
system. While their specific individual ownership system and market
norms are quite foreign to our own, they said they found the concept of
âcollective ownershipâ particularly repugnant and hard to conceptualize,
even finding much of the current global norms of property and market
exchange liberating. This is in no remote sense to minimize the
repression that the !Kung San have faced as a minority and the
shittiness of the capitalist dynamics many have been forced into, but
the point is that our world does not have a uniform history and cultural
inheritance.
One huge lurking danger to the valorization of the commons is that to
many the takeaway is always that everyone was at least better off in
subsistence farming villages and should have more or less remained there
in some kind of essentialistic and static natural relationship. Of
course that so many people dig their feet in there is understandable if
the only other pole is to uncritically embrace more or less the exact
infrastructural norms of dominant modernity and say âlook destroying
thousands of villages for some dam is obviously a net positive.â If
these are our only two options then we are indeed in trouble. Hence why
a crucial response to the claims of national liberation states that they
promoted development is to contest what sort of development in what
direction, at what cost. To specify which pathways were available and
which were derailed, by whom. Just as nationalism erases all other modes
of resistance to imperialism, collapsing our options into just
replicating a unified state or âpeopleâ with a military and economy that
fight with (eg interface with) foreign ones on their terms, so too does
it erase all pathways to material abundance that are not in the interest
of power. The problem isnât that infrastructure and property relations
changed after independence, itâs how they were changed. Just as we must
defend the right to move and freely associate globally we must defend
the freedom to evolve, hybridize, and reconfigure ourselves.
Another danger in popular narratives that focus on the enclosures is to
view complexity and illegibility as ends in themselves. In this frame
the commodification eating the world is a matter of increasing precision
and detail in our map of things, going from a lackadaisical commons
where no accounts are kept, to a stressfully overly quantified world
where every single individual grain of rice is indexed, tracked, and
purchasable with a personal loan for a low annual rate. Yet, there is
value to clarity, reconfigurability, and material capacity. Elinor
Ostrom emphasized that not only is the tragedy of the commons a real
danger that communities around the world have long been quite familiar
with, but people solve such in bottom-up ways through a diverse variety
of often overlapping means, including strategies that increase clarity
and even parcel out the commons. Further, being able to extract oneself
from social contexts, to sell oneâs stake in a clean manner has clear
liberatory aspects. Sharma mentions urbanization in the list of effects
of national âdevelopmentâ and neoliberal reforms, and thereâs a serious
danger here of building a narrative against urbanity itself. We must not
pretend that every dynamic driving urbanization was violent or created
by imperial interests, the interconnection of a globalizing world was in
part facilitated by voluntarily adopted technologies and individuals
embracing exit from parochial communities closed as a result of their
own power structures and material constraints. Choice in oneâs social
relations has been an incredibly liberating experience for many and is
deeply related to why migration isnât just an inextricable component of
human existence, but a freedom to be encouraged. And part of having
choice is knowing what the choices are. Legibility and even simplicity
can thus be liberating, in the right contexts.
This is why Iâve emphasized a focus on positive freedom and a network
lens. While I have no doubt Sharma would not embrace any of the
nefarious takes above, she has certainly gotten fastidious about the
dangers of myriad language choices like âglobal southâ and so I must
interject that talk of a global commons does carry its own dangers.
There has never been a true global commons, because we have never been
as strongly and directly connected to one another. Every historical
instance of âcommonsâ was inherently, and usually quite explicitly,
partially closed and parochial. Historically access to the commons of a
village is usually tied to membership within that village, or even oneâs
property title within it. We have never had a global commons in anywhere
near as direct a sense and so the concept is a cipher that people will
take different assumptions and priorities into.
Sharma looks back to the radical aspirations of the Diggers and Ranters,
enormously influential seventeenth century precursors to the modern
anarchist tradition who conjoined a fight for land with grand
aspirations for a world without exclusion or territory. For the Diggers,
âan essential aspect of this freedom/mobility was the ability to change
or shift oneâs identityâ and for the Ranters âthe people in England,
France, and Turkey [must become] one people and one body, for where the
one lives there liveth the other also.â I have long shared in a deep
admiration and love for these proto-anarchists who emerged endogenously
within the belly of European empire at the dawning of capitalism. For
two decades have I teared up while belting âthis earth divided / we will
make wholeâ but the devil is in the details.
My concern with Sharmaâs framework is that while it correctly objects to
the forcible creation of markets and the forcible creation of
dispossession and enclosures, as well as the construction of titanic
industrial infrastructure along a single innovation pathway, her
narrative risks empowering reactive or clumsy rhetorical corrections.
Choice is not quite the same thing as commons, although they can be
allies. In some contexts it can be useful to disentangle local knots so
as to enable more global connections. I have no sweeping answers or
blueprints for property norms, but I know that orthogonalizability is
not always evil. The broad strokes of the historic enclosures at the
dawn of capitalism were surely quite evil in most means and
consequences, similarly the followup processes of enclosures that were
applied beyond Europe by imperialists and then postcolonial
nationalists, but these broad strokes eclipse the people from below who
sincerely and for good reasons pushed for changes in their existing
property norms in ways that included dividing and individualizing some
things. That they didnât get the direction and types of reforms they
wanted nor the results, trammeled over by the powers who orchestrated
and profited from enclosures, doesnât mean they should be erased from
our understanding. I donât think we have to pose their struggle for
liberation against the liberatory aspirations of the Diggers. The truth
here is more complicated. To shift identity and context, to sincerely
struggle to step into alien perspectives, is at the core of building a
better world and resolving the wounds that have been sliced into us by
empire and nation alike. But such individual mobility can require
slicing us free of inherited community, picking up our things and
departing, and in so doing can be quite at odds with many venerations of
âthe commons.â
To connect globally, to build the tower of Babel that Sharma so
resonantly speaks of and quotes Toni Morrison on, should not involve the
flattening or smothering of diverse experiences and views, but the
integration of them. And that includes those who want independence, or,
perhaps better put, a different and more far-reaching type of
interdependence than that provided by the commons of old.
These are of course very broad points, about very broad narratives and
concerns, but the most refreshing thing about Home Rule is the degree to
which it audaciously embraces radicalism, which, lest we forget, is not
a synonym for extremism or coolness but is about getting to the root.
Sharmaâs book contrasts with for example Harsha Waliaâs recent Border &
Rule, which, while powerful in its lists of horrors, avoids comparably
âabstractâ discussion of underlying roots to instead focus on relatively
more particular associations and mechanisms. Where Home Rule traces how
underlying ideas, identities, policy orientations, and narratives came
into being, Border & Rule focuses more on the myriad examples of how
specific border policies functionally interface with or reproduce
patriarchy, white supremacy, ableism, etc. â the long menagerie of
formal oppressions we already instantly recognize as bad â and generally
function as part of a control apparatus to brutally manage the global
workforce. This is certainly valuable, and Walia is a rightfully beloved
figure in the movement, but her words at points reveal, I think, a
difference in philosophy between the two books:
âI align with a leftist politics of no borders, since the borders of
today are completely bound up in the violences of dispossession,
accumulation, exploitation, and their imbrications with race, caste,
gender, sexuality, and ability.â (emphasis mine)
Walia is seemingly not foreclosing support for borders in some other
context, merely our own. Similar arguments and lines have been used by
Marxists to endorse âall cops are bastardsâ and âprison abolitionâ
solely in our present historical and social context, and not universally
as anarchists do. They align with those politics here, today, but make
no promises about tomorrow.
Arguments that critique cops, prisons, and borders, solely because of
their present genealogies, affinities, and structural role leave open
the door to schemes to implement them in the future, âbeyond
capitalism,â âbeyond settler colonialism,â etc. The anarchist project,
however, is not to critique the symptomatic expressions of power in our
time, but the lines of underlying rot that inexorably drive new
expressions as contexts change.
Sharma on the other hand is repeatedly very clear that the logic of
nationalism and borders is rotten not just today, but inherently,
ânational liberation did not result in decolonization, nor could it
have.â (her emphasis)
If Waliaâs case is that borders are today interwoven with the function
of capitalism and that the displacement of migrants is coerced by war
and economic exploitation, Sharmaâs argument is more that borders arose
as a symptom of an underlying viral way of thinking: of cutting the
world up into discrete regions with distinct ânatives,â castigating and
often enslaving the exceptions to this schema as âmigrants.â It is a
nuanced historical picture that traces the complications of white
settlers dancing back and forth between categories as need be to keep
their domination. But Sharma is interested in pushing a point that is
unfortunately novel and contentious in the wider left: ânationalism from
belowâ cannot offer us a break with the horrors we struggle against,
indeed it can ultimately only ratchet up those horrors.
Much structural violence is obviously involved in the displacement of
many migrants today, but Sharma warns against implicitly taking for
granted that people are or should be of some place.
Resistance to imperial domination and struggles embedded in specific
histories of trauma, genocide, and dispossession do not require ceding
to a fixation with collective priority and origin. Weâve repeatedly
seen, from the horrors perpetuated in CĂŽte dâIvoire between groups with
conflicting claims over who was more ânativeâ to the genocide and ethnic
cleansing of the Rohingya as supposedly âillegal Bengali immigrants,â
that such frames are a fountainhead of oppression.
And it must be emphasized that âbeing of placeâ as an ossified
collective identity is quite distinct from active knowledge and love of
the land you work or a bioregion and a painstakingly built web of
ecological relationships. To liberate land, air, and water from those
who would control, monopolize and/or despoil them is not the same thing
as a struggle for territory and sovereignty, concepts inherently tied to
fixed relations, social discreteness, and functions of authority
(whether collective or not).
Sharmaâs rejection of the former is sharp and motivated by a deep
concern that firstness and of-placeness are subsuming the radical
imagination and erasing or placing themselves before all other ethical
considerations. Worse, this replacement of other driving values is
happening in ways that places itself beyond discourse or consideration.
âAll mobilizations of national autochthonous [nativeness] discoursesâŠ
view indigeneity as a first principle of political action⊠autochthony
is usually represented as â âauthentic,â âprimordial,â ânaturalâ and
âself-evident.ââ
While itâs understandable that people leverage what claims are fecund
within an international liberal Wilsonian legal context, we must
undermine the supposed incontestability of this principle of nativeness
and origin. As such legitimization criteria is increasingly accepted as
the starting point of movements of resistance, to engage with critiques
of it increasingly verges on unthinkable. Nevertheless we must think it.
And say it.
We exist in a global discourse and community. Backing a generalized
muddle of autochthonous narratives and implicit first principles in
Turtle Island, for instance, has spillover effects that can hurt
migrants in Europe. For the first principle of nativeness applied
generally has quite noxious implications. Let me be very clear: no
European should ever have a nation, there is no amount of reparations
for the atrocities of imperialism that might âreset the clockâ nor
excuse Fortress Europeâs exclusion of migrants. Fortress Europe is not
bad because of a specific history of European colonialism that they owe
reparations for and invalidates their nations, itâs wrong because fuck
nations, everyone has a right to migrate. While reparations and
liberation in the face of dispossession and oppression is essential, our
goal is not to restore some prehistoric balance wherein an indigenous
âFrenchnessâ can live alongside a checkerboard of other national
identities but to abolish all such discrete categories. To grant wider
and deeper options to everyone and escalate the dynamic swirling
complexity of humanity.
In land projects across North America and Europe itâs common to hear
ecofascists and green reactionaries speaking of seeking, reestablishing,
and defending an âindigeneity.â This can come either in the packaging
that âthe first people colonized were whites by the Romansâ (recasting
whiteness as a gateway to oppressed class status) or it can emerge from
a supposed imperative to land-based spirituality (implying that
constructing abusive mysticisms is a valid path out of white guilt).
The most facile response is to merely critique the absurd bundling and
recent lineage of âwhiteness.â But rarely are the speakers already
unaware of such, nor would grounding oneâs identity in some resurrection
of a more specific lineage and tradition (eg âviking-nessâ) necessarily
avoid anything important. Nor is the important fact that these âland
projectsâ are often on stolen land and facilitating continued settler
colonial dynamics a sufficient response. One shouldnât wish ecofascist
communes on the people of Denmark.
This is not merely two distinct uses and definitions of âindigenousâ in
various languages â for example the chauvinist âhere firstâ usage by
mainstream right-wing political parties in many countries versus a
philosophical or spiritual notion of âecological relationship to the
landâ usage increasingly pushed by younger activists across a subset of
colonized peoples â but in fact a more complicated matter of bleed,
appropriation, and opportunistic mutation. When many white scumfucks,
like infamous political prisoners Sadie and Exile, leaned into fascist
blood-and-soil mysticism they did so draped under the stolen language
and signifiers built up by indigenous activists, not beer-soaked Trump
chuds. And part of why so many US white radicals had trouble identifying
and expelling them was an increasing treatment of âindigeneityâ â even
the pagan playacting of white settlers doused in fascist iconography â
like a third rail. A first principle or apex value that automatically
vanquishes all other considerations, removes all critical thinking and
turns peopleâs knees to jelly.
This is to say that while âlanesâ and epistemic humility can have value,
we should not render ourselves completely useless in some performative
surrender of our minds and thus responsibilities. If white radicals fail
to recognize clearly dangerous invocations of âindigenousâ we will be of
no use to anything or anyone. Sharma covers examples of intensely
reductive ideologies of indigeneity, from Patrick Wolfe declaring that,
âThe fundamental social divide is not the color line. It is not
ethnicity, minority status, or even class. The primary line is the one
distinguishing Natives from settlersâthat is, from everyone else. Only
the Native is not a settler. Only the Native is truly local.â to MĂ©tis
scholar Bonita Lawrence (and self-identified âAsian settler Colonistâ
Enakshi Dua) arguing that because non-indigenous people of color are
functionally settlers âantiracism is premised on an ongoing colonial
project.â
It is, however, important for anarchists to challenge ourselves and read
charitably. Sharma focuses in on various examples of language like âWe
must be the ones who determine who is and who is not a member of our
community, based on criteria accepted by our people,â but while the
inside-outside hierarchies of any sovereignty are inherently abusive and
unjust and itâs trivial to point to examples of First Nations
governments who have wielded access to tribal membership as a tool of
power or exclusion, it warrants emphasis that one of the most pressing
motivations for sovereign control over tribal membership is precisely to
make them more inclusive than settler governments allow. There is little
more universally reviled than the blood quanta system that essentializes
indigeneity as a matter of genes rather than culture and heritage. I
most commonly hear calls for sovereignty over tribal membership invoked
to resist various limits and restrictions imposed by settler
governments. The motivation of settler states is straightforward: not
only do they wish to see tribal membership ultimately evaporate, they
dare not risk a situation where tribal membership expands like a
corrosive acid of more complex overlapping jurisdictions.
I want to be absolutely clear that competitive governance is no grand
improvement, especially when territorial restrictions on scope remain in
play. But itâs easy enough to imagine an enlightened future where the US
faces a crisis of legitimacy and jurisdiction with mass settler
defection into the ranks of strong and expanding first nations. Where
various clear territorial claims break down into more complex and
overlapping communities. This would be far from anarchist ideals, but it
is not quite the same thing as nationalisms of territory and blood. Of
course virtually no one is proposing radical expansions of first nations
ranks divorced from cultural heritage, and unfortunately what Actually
Existing First Nation governments have focused on is quite different
from the idealism of those radical indigenous activists focused on
inclusion.
Sharma zooms in on examples like the Mohawk Council of KahnawĂ :ke
stripping major rights from citizens who married non-citizens and
evicting their partners from tribal land, and â of course â the infamous
Cherokee exclusion of Freedmen. These are obviously horrifying and
reflective of real dangers, but itâs worth noting that many decolonial
indigenous activists who fought against such did so in the frame of
ânationalism,â however awkwardly. For example, Ellen Gabrielâs aghast
statement on the evictions of families in KahnawĂ :ke over what amounts
to miscegenation correctly emphasizes that such constrained or
blood-based notions of identity were imposed by colonizers to whittle
away tribal membership, but she, at the same time, frames inclusion as
necessary to ârebuiding our nations from colonial genocide.â Of course
we might wish that statements like âFor over a hundred years the Indian
Act has coercively indoctrinated Indigenous peoples into believing that
the colonizers definition of identity was true.â would also be applied
to the concept of nations too, but still language usage here can get
muddled and contradictory.
Of course, even if we were to cede that certain activists mean nothing
more than a sense of community with their usage of ânationâ â thereâs
little reason to think this personal or local redefinition will survive
and flourish. As I pointed out against Sharmaâs attempt to change our
language around imperialism, history and popular usage creates certain
gravitational effects on words. The least complex, most intuitive, and
already familiar definition in a language tends to win out. Someone
could, for instance, try to reclaim or redefine the term âfascismâ to
only mean âsolidarity,â but the net effect of their particularized usage
is almost certainly going to be the legitimization of actual fascists
and actual fascism. And thatâs hardly an extreme comparison.
âNationalismâ is pretty much politically interchangeable with âfascismâ
(modulo a myth of palingenesis), with an even wider umbrella of
atrocities it has historically covered. There is no conceivable universe
in which nationalism pivots in its associations. As such, attempts to
gain standing within a wider dominant discourse of nationalism (and
imposed legal context where it has salience) are doomed to only
legitimize such, with all its baggage.
But sadly many in indigenous spaces of resistance donât mean merely
community by their usage of ânationâ and arenât merely opportunistically
exploiting loopholes in the ideological framework of the colonizer,
rather struggles within the nationalist framework have in many cases
taken to heart the logics of national sovereignty, discreteness,
exclusion, and territory.
âSelf-defined anarchist Taiaiake Alfred (2005, 266â267), for instance,
argues that supposedly distinct and discrete ânationsâ can and should
âmove from colonial-imperialist relations to pluralist multinational
associations of autonomous peoples and territories that respect the
basic imperatives of indigenous cultures as well as preserve the
stability and benefits of cooperative confederal relations between
indigenous nations and other governments.â This vision is, of course,
the core of the Postcolonial New World Order.â
Again, such ghastliness isnât to imply that there arenât far more
enlightened, original, complex, and probing perspectives in the
impossibly complex expanse of varied experiences and positions thrown
haphazardly under the umbrella label of âindigeneityâ (and Sharma cites
a wide array of literature across the board) but it does sufficiently
highlight that instances of mistakes exist. One need not point to
unquestionable fascists leveraging both their tribal membership and
frameworks of âindigeneity,â from the national-anarchist Vince Reinhart
to the neonazi Serafin Perez, for the general point about conceptual and
rhetorical dangers to be pressing.
âthe differences posited between autochthons and allochthonsâNatives and
Migrantsâis a fundamental political, as well as ontological and
epistemological, challenge we must address to achieve something that can
live up to our aspirations for liberty.â
It is always hard to critique an ideology that has not yet widely taken
power or begun to implement its vision. When anarchists attacked Marx
for the coming catastrophic failings of his framework we were absolutely
right, but it still took decades for the mounting bloody evidence to
become overwhelming. Sadly, anarchists have not always had such
foresight, and those who participated in national liberation struggles
or made common cause with nationalists have always come to regret it.
Many Korean anarchists today denounce prior generations as fake
anarchists and embarrassments for even temporarily tolerating Korean
nationalism, nevermind how intense and pressing the boot of Japanese
Imperialism was.
While compassion, humility, and attention are extremely warranted when
navigating the complex and fraught complexities of situations of
oppression, I have long since renounced the lefty Irish nationalism I
grew up connected to and have no doubt that in the view of future
generations nationalism-from-below will always prove a grave and
harrowing mistake. I think a lot about Korean anarchists Iâve met who
grimaced in reference to their predecessors. I wonder how long it will
take us to truly learn our lessons.
I have already praised Home Rule as a thematic sequel to The Many-Headed
Hydra, but I worry that it will also take the place of Statism and
Anarchy as a text clarifying emerging fractures and perfectly predicting
mistakes to come, but trapped in the Cassandra gutter anarchists must so
frequently retreat to. Some warnings are as unpopular as they are â
consequently â necessary.
Since publication Sharma has caught some unfair and plainly dishonest
attacks that present her as unattentive to indigenous scholarship and
attempting to fight some kind of battle on behalf of migrants against
natives, when everything in Home Rule seeks to dispel that dichotomy.
âUs and them, same, same.â
This is not a cloak or defense for settler fuckery or a sameness that
erases differences, histories, lines of power, and important lessons.
Itâs a call for solidarity with teeth and audacity. A swirling hurricane
of possibility, rather than a fractal landscape of micro tailored
prisons. Or at least enough audacity to see past lazy simplifications
and the limited imaginary bequeathed us by feudal chains and genocidal
empires.
If nothing else, many of the arguments in Home Rule at least provide a
counter to those who declare that the desire for mobility and wide
connection, thinking in abstract or universal terms rather than
place-based, etc, are all imperialist constructions. Maybe! But the same
can be said about the ideological elevation of local parochialism,
particularity, and fixedness. So letâs just clear out claims of
historical false consciousness and just make direct arguments for a
given value or approach.
The white anarchist who years ago denounced our oh-so contentious
âMigrants Welcomeâ stickers because she couldnât imagine a world without
closed territorial communes of democratic tyranny and who couldnât see
modes of resistance to yuppie fuckery that werenât grounded in
territorial claims is a perfectly fine human being, sincerely trying her
best, her mistake was reflective of a widespread atrophy of our
imagination. And this is one of the worst crimes inflicted by our
rulers. We do not have to turn to fixed, simple models.
Imperialism and colonialism violently, unfairly, and inanely crushed
immeasurable knowledge and culture; healing that damage and tearing down
the power structures that perpetuate it is overwhelmingly in the
interest of all humanity. But ultimately no abstraction or set of
practices has value in and of itself, people matter, actual individual
human beings in all their rich complexity, their agency, their freedom,
is what weâre fighting for, and an ideology or a technology or a
practice or a belief or even âcommunityâ is only valuable insofar as it
furthers that. Healing is not the same thing as preservation. As some
indigenous anarchists have taken to saying a âtraditionâ is something
static and dead âthat sits on a shelf,â in contrast a lifeway is
something that evolves and dances, intertwined and inseparable from the
knot of humanity and nature around us.
As Sharma puts it powerfully for anarchists, âan origin of âstateâ is
âstasis,â or immobility.â