💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › ron-tabor-marxist-philosophy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:46:47. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Marxist Philosophy
Author: Ron Tabor
Date: 2012
Language: en
Topics: marxism, political philosophy, The Utopian
Source: Retrieved on 6th August 2021 from http://utopianmag.com/archives/tag-The%20Utopian%20Vol.%2010%20-%202011/marxist-philosophy/][utopianmag.com]] and [[http://utopianmag.com/archives/tag-The%20Utopian%20Vol.%2011%20-%202012/marxist-philosophy-part-ii-utopian/
Notes: Part I published in The Utopian Vol. 10. Part II published in The Utopian Vol. 11. Editors’ Note: This article is Chapters 7 and 8 of a work in progress on Marxism.

Ron Tabor

Marxist Philosophy

PART I. IS THERE A MARXIST PHILOSOPHY, AND IF SO, WHAT IS IT?

It should be clear by now that I think there is, in fact, a Marxist

philosophy. Throughout this book, I have tried to show that Marxism is

best understood as a philosophical worldview – specifically, a variant

of Hegelian Idealism that sees itself and presents itself as

materialist. Beyond this, I believe Marx and Engels did hold to a

conscious ontological position, a view of the nature and structure of

the natural world, one that has come to be called “Dialectical

Materialism.” Although I suspect that most Marxists, especially the

“orthodox” Marxists of the Stalinist, Leninist, Maoist, and Trotskyist

persuasions, would agree with me, some commentators have argued that

there is not, and cannot be, a truly Marxist philosophy of nature, and

definitely not one called “dialectical materialism.” Among these figures

are the Hungarian philosopher and literary critic, Georg Lukacs (at

least in his book, History and Class Consciousness); the former Polish

dissident, once-Marxist, and ultimately religious thinker, Leszek

Kolakowski; and the major French spokesperson of the philosophy of

Existentialism, Jean-Paul Sartre. In the view of those who hold to this

position, Marx, in contrast to Engels, was not interested in questions

of “metaphysics,” that is, abstract speculation about the nature of the

universe, and as a result, did not have an ontology/philosophy of nature

of any kind, and certainly not one describable by the term “dialectical

materialism.”

The contention of Lukacs, Kolakowski, Sartre, and the others who share

their opinion, rests on several interrelated claims and arguments, some

implicit, some explicit. The first of these is that neither Marx nor

Engels ever used the term “dialectical materialism.” This is literally

but not substantially true. Although the precise words, “dialectical

materialism,” do not occur in any of Marx and Engels’ works, Engels does

use the term “materialist dialectic” in his Ludwig Feuerbach and the

Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, originally published in 1888

(C.P. Dutt, ed., International Publishers, New York, 1941, p. 44).

This, it seems to me, amounts to the same thing as “dialectical

materialism.” Moreover, in this work, Engels approvingly credits Joseph

Dietzgen, a German worker who, according to various sources, was the

first person to coin the term “dialectical materialism,” with coming up

with the idea independently of Marx and himself, in a work published in

1869. So, it seems safe to say that while Marx may not have used the

term, “dialectical materialism,” Engels (basically) did. The precise

formulation, “dialectical materialism,” later appeared in a book about

Engels by Karl Kautsky, the major theoretician of the Second or

“Socialist” International, and was eventually popularized by the “father

of Russian Marxism,” George Plekhanov.

The second claim of the deniers of “dialectical materialism” is that the

mature Marx – by all accounts, including Engels’, the dominant and

intellectually superior partner of the Marx-Engels collaboration – never

wrote a systematic work on philosophy. All we have from Marx’s pen that

explicitly address philosophical questions are works that are considered

to be “immature”; that is, material written before he had come to his

fully Marxist conclusions. These works include: (1) Marx’s doctoral

dissertation on the philosophies of the ancient materialists,

particularly, Democritus and Epicurus; (2) The Economic and Philosophic

Manuscripts of 1844, which take up such questions as “alienation” and

advocate what some, such as Raya Dunayevskaya, Erich Fromm, and

Kolakowski himself, have characterized as a “humanistic” Marxism; (3)

The Holy Family, a polemical, almost satirical, critique of several of

Hegel’s disciples; (4) the “Theses on Feuerbach,” terse comments, adding

up to just a few pages, on the philosophy of the German materialist,

Ludwig Feuerbach; and (5) The German Ideology, a work co-written with

Engels that attempts to come to grips with their philosophical past. All

of this was written prior to late 1847–early 1848, the date generally

considered to denote Marx’s arrival at his supposedly mature and

scientific world-view. The only substantial writings devoted

specifically to philosophical questions produced by the pair after they

had reached their maturity were written by Engels, and the position

Engels propounds in these works is not, according to Lukacs, Kolakowski,

Sartre, and others, really Marxist at all.

The third, and more meaningful, argument of those who contend that

Marxism (or at least Marx’s Marxism) does not have an ontology is that

the “dialectic” – roughly (and this is my definition), the conception of

reality as a complex and contradictory process whose component parts

simultaneously interpenetrate, oppose and negate, modify and generate

each other – applies to history, but not to nature. More specifically,

to these thinkers, the dialectic primarily characterizes the

socio-economic process, involving material reality, consciousness, and

self-consciousness, in which human beings change the material world,

themselves, and their conception of themselves (and of the world),

through work (labor) and struggle. (Among some Marxist theoreticians and

others knowledgeable about Marxism, this process is called praxis, from

the Greek word for “practice.”) It is in and through this process –

according to Marxism – that human consciousness arises and develops,

simultaneously shaped by and shaping that work, struggle, and nature

itself. Only praxis, these commentators insist, displays “internal

relations,” that is, constitutes an organic whole whose

components/internal parts interact in an interpenetrating and mutually

generating – in other words, in a truly dialectical – fashion. In

contrast, this argument goes, nature does not exhibit “internal

relations.” The relations among natural phenomena are “external”; the

entities and processes of nature always stand outside of each other, do

not interpenetrate, and therefore cannot be said to interact in a

dialectical manner. As a result, since nature itself is not and cannot

be dialectical, there can be no such thing as “dialectical materialism,”

in the sense of a Marxist philosophy of nature.

At the risk of simplifying, I would say that for Lukacs, Kolakowski,

Sartre, and those who think as they do (and they believe for Marx, but

not for Engels), if a process does not involve consciousness or ideas,

it cannot be dialectical. Pure nature – that is, nature as it supposedly

is in itself, outside of humanity’s interaction with it, which is what

an ontology attempts to describe – exhibits no dialectic.

Fourth, to these philosophers, the very notion that Marx might have had

a philosophy of nature is false on the face of it. This is because, from

what they see as the real Marxist point of view, nature as it is in

itself cannot be conceived.

Since, to Marx, knowledge emerges out of praxis, that is, humanity’s

efforts to transform nature through labor, humanity cannot know nature

in any other way than through how human beings interact with it. In

other words, all humans can know is nature as we relate to it – as we

interact with it and change it, as we exercise our labor, including our

scientific labor, on it – not how it is in itself. As a result, a

Marxist ontology/philosophy of nature is an absurdity, and the concept

of “dialectical materialism” or a “materialist dialectic,” as put

forward by Engels and other Marxists, is un-Marxist.

Last, in the view of these thinkers, Marx could not have held to a

philosophy of “dialectical materialism” because such a philosophy

implies a rigid deterministic framework that is alien to Marx’s view of

history, which, based as it is on the centrality of praxis, is

open-ended and undetermined. According to this claim, in Marx’s view,

but not in Engels’, humanity determines its own future and its own fate,

and is not bound by the determinism postulated by dialectical

materialism.

I do not believe the standpoint of these thinkers on this question can

be sustained. While it is true that there are contradictions between

certain facets of the Marxian theory of history (the “materialist

conception of history” or “historical materialism”) and the Marxian

conception of nature (the “materialist dialectic” or “dialectical

materialism), as well as within each of these, it is much too pat (and

too convenient) to describe this simply as a contradiction between the

fully Marxist outlook of Marx and the supposedly “positivist,”

“scientistic,” and ultimately unMarxist, position of Engels. In light of

the evidence, it is much more reasonable to argue that Marxism as a

whole, including the supposedly “real” Marxism of Marx, contains

“positivistic,” and “scientistic” elements that coexist uneasily with

other aspects of the Marxian worldview.

Let’s try to answer these contentions in more detail.

First off, Marx and Engels were life-long friends, collaborators, and,

as the Marxist movement often describes them, comrades-in-arms. They met

as young men and discovered that they were thinking along similar lines

and had reached similar conclusions. They struggled together in various

arenas throughout their adult lives, were in constant communication, as

shown by their voluminous correspondence, and spent hours in

broad-ranging conversation when they had the opportunity to do so. It is

hard to believe that they did not discuss all the subjects that

interested them, including those of philosophy and science, at great

length. It is also difficult to imagine that they were not in

fundamental agreement on what to them would have been fundamental

questions. Both were men of extremely strongly-held opinions (as

reflected in the many, usually ferocious, polemics they wrote against

those who differed with them), and if they had disagreed with each other

in meaningful ways, this would almost inevitably have been reflected in

their correspondence. (In fact, it probably would have led to a break in

their personal/political relations.) But there is no evidence of this.

Second, two of the books, and the most important ones, Engels wrote that

deal with questions of philosophy/ontology were written, or were at

least begun, while Marx was still alive. The first of these, Herr Eugen

Dühring’s Revolution in Science, now known as Anti-Dühring, a polemic

against a recent convert to socialism, was first published as a series

of articles in the Leipzig Vorwärts, the central organ of the German

Social-Democratic Party, in 1877 and 1878, and later compiled in book

form. It is extremely unlikely that these articles, and later the book,

would have been published had Marx not agreed with and approved of them.

In fact, according to Engels’ preface to the second edition of the book:

“...it was of course self-understood between us that this exposition of

mine should not be issued without his [Marx’s – RT] knowledge. I read

the whole manuscript to him before it was printed....” (Anti-Dühring,

International Publishers Co., Inc., New York, 1939, p.13.)

The second book, left by Engels as an unfinished manuscript and

published much later as The Dialectics of Nature, was begun some time

after 1871, probably 1872. This was when Engels came to London (from

Manchester, where he had managed the family textile business) and began

to immerse himself in the scientific literature of the day. According to

the British scientist and Marxist, J.B.S. Haldane:

“He (Engels) had always been a student of science. Since 1861 he had

been in close touch with the chemist Schorlemmer at Manchester, and had

discussed scientific problems with him and Marx for many years.”

(Preface to Engels, Dialectics of Nature, International Publishers,

N.Y., 1940, p. viii.)

Moreover, in his preface to the book, Haldane indicates that quotations

from Greek philosophers, written in Marx’s handwriting, appear in

Engels’ manuscript, suggesting that Marx had read Engels’ work at some

point.

In light of this, to draw a sharp distinction between Engels’ and Marx’s

views on questions of science and philosophy seems far-fetched. It is

possible, indeed, probable, that Marx would have expressed himself

differently from and better than Engels. But it is not likely that he

would have disagreed substantially with what Engels wrote.

Third, even if we leave all these considerations aside, even if we just

consider Marx himself, it is virtually impossible to come to a different

conclusion. Marx was a person with an extensive background and ongoing

interest in philosophy, including philosophies of nature. As mentioned,

he had written his doctoral dissertation on the outlooks (the

ontologies) of ancient materialist philosophers, while a significant

section of his book, The Holy Family, consists of a discussion of the

English empiricists and the French materialists. For a time, he

considered himself to be a follower of Hegel (who did have a philosophy

of nature) and openly admitted Hegel’s great influence on his thinking.

In addition, all of Marx’s early writings are highly philosophical in

both content and form, and even his mature, supposedly scientific,

works, such as Capital, are laced with philosophical terminology and

concepts. Indeed, as I have argued in previous chapters, these mature

works are fundamentally philosophical in nature. Not least, Marx was a

systematic thinker. He was interested in, was extremely knowledgeable

about, and had written substantial works that touched on, a large number

of fields. Indicative of this, his theory of history encompasses, and

attempts to explain in a logically consistent way, virtually all areas

of human endeavor, including ontologies. It is difficult to believe, as

Lukacs, Kolakowski, and Sartre imply, that Marx was not interested in

ontological questions and even harder to accept that he did not have an

ontology, a systematic conception of the nature and structure of the

universe, of his own.

And if Marx did have such an ontology, what kind could it have been

except something that might be called “dialectical materialism”? In the

first place, how could it have been anything but materialist? Marx’s

theory of history is, at least consciously, materialist, and militantly

so. He considered non-materialist, that is, Idealist, theories of

history to be little more than a cover for religion, which he viewed as

a noxious delusion, an example of “false consciousness.” Is it

reasonable to accept that Marx was a materialist in matters of history

and an Idealist (or something else – and if so, what?) in matters of

ontology? Marx also considered his view of history, indeed, his entire

conception of socialism, to be scientific, and like many observers of

science at the time and since, he considered science to be inherently

materialist. So how could he have been anything but a materialist?

Beyond this, Marx criticized previous materialists for being mechanical

and one-sided. This one-sidedness is what, he said, led to the active

side of philosophical/critical thought being developed by the Idealists.

How, then, could his materialist ontology have been anything but

“dialectical,” a concept borrowed from the Idealists, particularly

Hegel. In sum, if we accept this line of reasoning, how could Marx not

have had an ontology, and how could it have been anything but something

that might accurately be termed “dialectical materialism”?

(The fact that Lukacs, Kolakowski, Sartre, and others believed that the

dialectic applies only to praxis and history but not to nature does not

mean that Marx did, too. Interestingly, Lukacs, Kolakowski, and Sartre

are in agreement with Hegel on this point. Hegel insisted that nature is

not dialectical; only the realm of the Ideal, that is, the realm of

spirit, mind, consciousness, exemplifies the dialectic. In Hegel’s

conception, nature is the alienated “other” of mind or spirit, and, as

such, exhibits no truly dialectical processes or structure.)

Finally, in the previous chapter, I dealt with the question of Marx’s

theory of history, including its ambiguity on the question of whether

history is open-ended or determined. As I’ve argued throughout this

book, the insistence on the part of both Marx and Engels that their

brand of socialism is “scientific” as opposed to “utopian” ultimately

rests on their contention that socialism/communism, to be achieved

through a revolution and the establishment of the dictatorship of the

proletariat, is the “necessary” and “inevitable” outcome of human

history. Marx believed this as much as Engels. It is this that explains

why the terms “necessary,” “historical necessity,” “necessarily,”

“inexorable,” etc., appear so often throughout the writings of the pair,

not only the works of the supposed “positivist” Engels, but also those

of the “real” Marxist, Marx himself. The use of such language strongly

suggests that the fundamental position of Marxism, including Marx’s

Marxism, is that history is determined and predictable, not contingent.

This question will be taken up at greater length in the next chapter.

Based on all this, I think it is safe to say: (1) Marxism does have a

consciously held ontological standpoint (a philosophy of nature); (2)

This outlook can accurately be described as “dialectical materialism”;

(3) Engels’ writings on philosophy can be taken to be an adequate

representation of what Marx also believed and therefore an accurate

presentation of the Marxist viewpoint (however embarrassing this may be

to some people).

(The most substantial case for the un-Marxist nature of “dialectical

materialism” is made by Kolakowski in his threevolume magnum opus, Main

Currents of Marxism (Oxford University Press, 1978). Among other things,

this is a very erudite, very sophisticated, and ultimately very

strained, attempt to delineate and defend a humanist, libertarian

version of Marxism, and to blame the Stalinist outcomes of Marxism on

Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin, and other supposed misinterpreters of the

“real” Marxism of Marx (although Kolakowski does not let Marx entirely

off the hook). Interestingly, although Kolakowski discusses Engels’

“scientistic” views at some length in Volume One, he never mentions the

fact that, as I indicated above, Marx read, and apparently approved,

Engels’ writings on ontological questions.)

With this said, we can proceed to a discussion of dialectical

materialism.

MATERIALISM

As the term implies, dialectical materialism (or the “materialist

dialectic”) consists of two facets: materialism and dialectics. Let’s

take a look at them, starting with materialism.

Marx and Engels divided the various philosophies expounded over the

millennia into two major categories or schools – Idealism and

materialism – based on these philosophies’ stance on the nature of the

fundamental substance in the universe. (In contrast to other writers, I

capitalize Idealism to delineate it from the more commonly understood

sense of the word.) Idealists believe that thought (or ideas –

including, spirit, mind or consciousness) constitutes the fundamental

substance, and that matter flows out of, is created by, or is otherwise

based on, thought, mind, spirit, or consciousness. Materialists, in

contrast, contend that matter is the fundamental substance in the

universe and that it is matter that gives rise to thought, mind,

consciousness, and what other people (though generally not materialists)

call spirit.

Here is how Engels puts it, in his Ludwig Feuerbach:

“The great basic question of all philosophy, especially of modern

philosophy, is that concerning the relation of thinking and being.”

“The answers which the philosophers gave to this question split them

into two great camps. Those who assert the primacy of spirit to nature

and, therefore, in the last instance, assumed world creation in some

form or other...comprised the camp of idealism. The others, who regarded

nature as primary, belong to the various schools of materialism. (Ludwig

Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, op. cit., pp.

20, 21.)

(In fact, I would argue, both schools of philosophy implicitly accept

the idea that there are two fundamental substances in the universe –

thought and matter. This is because, despite their claims, neither

school is convincingly able to completely reduce either of the two

entities – matter or mind – to the other. The question that really

concerns them is which of the two substances is primary – which comes

first and gives rise to, or causes, the other. Thus, Idealism accepts

that there is such a thing as matter, which is qualitatively different

from mind or spirit [otherwise, why have a separate term for it?]; it

merely insists that matter flows out of, is [or was] created by, or is

in some way dependent on, thought, mind, consciousness or spirit. In the

same manner, materialism accepts that there is such a thing as thought,

mind, or consciousness that is distinct from matter but insists that

these things flow out of, are created by, are dependent on, or are

reflections or forms of, matter. In a sense, then, both schools of

philosophic thought are dualist, in that they believe that there are two

substances – matter and mind/ideas – that make up the universe, not

one.)

In this debate, Marxism takes its stand on the side of materialism. As

we have seen, it developed and defends what it calls the “materialist

conception of history” or “historical materialism” in the realm of human

society, while in the realm of nature or natural phenomena, it propounds

what came to be called “dialectical materialism.”

Significantly, the meanings of the terms “material,” “materialist,” and

“materialism” differ substantially in these two facets of Marxist

theory. In historical materialism, “material” basically means

“economic,” or somewhat more broadly, “socio-economic.” Thus here,

“materialism” means the belief that economic production plays the

determinant role in human history – specifically, determining the nature

and evolution of each form of society – and probably most importantly,

that “social being determines social consciousness.” In dialectical

materialism, “material” means “having to do with matter,” that is,

material particles and other material entities. As a result,

“materialism” in this realm refers to the view that human

consciousness/ideas/mind are products of the human brain, as well as the

claim that consciousness and ideas are ultimately caused by the impact

of material particles on the human body through the five senses. These

two meanings of the terms “material,” “materialist,” and “materialism”

are never clearly differentiated in Marxist thought; nor are the

differing conceptions of the role of the “material” world in determining

human consciousness ever integrated. In fact, in neither facet of their

theory do Marx or Engels ever try to explain precisely how these two

(somewhat distinct) “material” worlds actually determine human

consciousness.

Beyond this, Marx and Engels never really argue for their materialist

standpoint, in the sense of presenting an elaborated case in favor of

their position. They merely assert it and assume it to be true. Insofar

as there is an implied argument in their discussions, it is that

materialism is the only truly scientific standpoint – that materialism

is the actual, proper, and only possible philosophy of science. In other

words, Marx and Engels’ argument in favor of materialism comes down to

the assumption that science is inherently materialistic; as a result,

materialism is scientific and hence true, while Idealism is

“metaphysics” – religion in disguise, mere speculation – and thus false.

What enables Marx and Engels to get away with this is that, at first

glance, science does appear to be materialist. In fact, this view is

commonplace in much writing on science, certainly that found in popular

science publications. It is also the opinion of many scientists. And a

superficial look at specific natural sciences suggests that this is the

case: physics, chemistry, biology, geology, and their various

subdivisions all seem to be concerned with material entities and seek

exclusively natural explanations for the phenomena they study, while

rejecting God, disembodied minds/consciousnesses, and spirit as

explanatory principles. As a result, it would seem, they should be

classified as materialist. But further thought suggests that this

seemingly obvious contention might not be true.

The problems with the idea that science is materialist are most clearly

seen in physics. This is ironic, since physics, in some sense the

foundation of the other sciences, would appear to be the most

materialist of them all, dealing as it does with material bodies and

processes. In fact, though, materialist descriptions of physical

phenomena have become quite problematical ever since the developments

that occurred in physics in the early 20^(th) century, particularly the

theories of relativity and quantum mechanics. Yet, the problems of the

materialist standpoint can be seen even in earlier stages of physics.

Materialism, in one of its classic definitions, insists that the

universe is made up of matter in motion. Let us assume, for the moment,

that matter is what Marx, Engels, and most materialists throughout the

millennia thought it was: little hard particles whirling around in

space. But this leaves a crucial question: What makes matter move; what

causes the material particles to whirl around? Some materialists,

including Engels, insist that motion is intrinsic to matter. But this is

merely a tautology that evades the question; it doesn’t explain why and

how matter moves, it just defines it as moving. A more substantial

answer is that matter is moved by energy, a term that came into

existence in the 19^(th) century with the development of thermodynamics.

This formulation results in another statement of materialism: the

universe consists of matter and energy. But what, then, is energy? It is

not simply matter; if it were, why don’t we say simply that the universe

consists of matter? Moreover, to say that energy is something that moves

matter does not get us very far, because this still does not tell us

what energy is. According to Einstein’s theory of relativity, matter and

energy are equivalent. One can change or be changed into the other

according to the equation E=mc2: energy equals mass times the speed of

light squared. But this does not help us conceptually. It merely tells

us that matter can be turned into energy – and vice versa – according to

a specific mathematical ratio. Even if we assert, as some scientists do,

that “matter is energy and energy is matter,” this does not give us a

clear conception of what energy is. We have a pretty clear common-sense

idea of what matter is, but what, exactly, is energy (aside from the

assertion that it is really matter)? A source of this difficulty is the

fact that energy is not directly perceived; its existence and quantity

are inferred by its effects – by the motion of matter that it causes and

that we sense and measure, for example, as heat. In sum, we cannot

clearly conceive – and scientific theory does not really tell us –

precisely what energy is.

Since we have reached a dead-end here, let’s turn to another formulation

of materialism. This is that the universe consists of “matter and its

laws of motion.” But what, exactly, are these “laws of motion”? At the

time Marx and Engels wrote, these laws included those discovered by

Isaac Newton, including his famous three laws of motion and his law of

universal gravitation, the three laws of planetary motion discovered by

Johannes Kepler, the laws of thermodynamics, Maxwell’s laws (equations)

about electro-magnetism, and the various other scientific laws already

discovered or in the process of being discovered in other fields of

science. These “laws” describe how matter behaves under various

circumstances. When they take mathematical form, as they usually do (at

least in physics), they are (or are represented by) mathematical

equations. When they do not, they represent different kinds of logic,

descriptions of the behavior of matter under specific conditions. But

once again, we have a problem. These “laws” and logics – the

mathematical equations and descriptions – are not themselves material;

they are not matter. They describe how matter moves or behaves, which is

different. We might say that these “laws” are descriptions of

fundamental structures of the universe. But the laws themselves do not

further describe these structures. Are these structures themselves

material? This is questionable: matter is material; the structures are

something else, and the laws themselves do not tell us what they are.

Meanwhile, all we can really say about these structures is that they are

described by laws, which, in turn, are... mathematical equations and

descriptions; in other words, they are ideas.

Physicist Mario Livio, in his book, Is God a Mathematician?, put it this

way:

“Once many repeated scientific experiments or observations produce the

same functional interrelationships, those may acquire the elevated

status of laws of nature – mathematical descriptions of a behavior all

natural phenomena are found to obey. (Livio, Is God a Mathematician?,

Simon and Schuster, New York, London, Toronto, Sydney, 2009, p. 96.)

What I am getting at here is that when we attempt to describe the world

scientifically and materialistically, we come up against something that

is not material, something that cannot be defined in, or reduced to,

strictly materialistic terms. In the case of scientific “laws,” they can

only be defined, described, and understood as ideas, in other words, as

ideal.

We can see this even more clearly when we turn our attention more

narrowly to matter itself. As I mentioned, when Marx and Engels were

alive, matter was thought of in atomistic terms, that is, as tiny

particles moving around in space. Atoms, and this is the meaning of the

word, were conceived as the fundamental building blocks of the universe;

they could not be broken down any further. This certainly reinforced the

notion that materialism was the true philosophy of science.

But today science tells us that atoms are not fundamental, in the sense

understood in the 19^(th) century, but themselves consist of component

parts – protons, neutrons, electrons, and a myriad other subatomic

particles, all of which are made up of still other entities called

quarks – along with a vast amount of empty space (in fact, most of

matter consists of empty space). Moreover, these particles are held

together by three distinct forces: the electro-magnetic force, which

holds the electrons in their orbits around the nucleus; the strong or

nuclear force, which holds the particles in the nucleus together; and

the weak force, which governs radioactive decay, all of which are

conveyed through yet other particles. And these forces themselves cannot

be fully described materialistically. Like energy, forces are inferred,

in other words, recognized by their effects, and they, too, are

scientifically described in terms of mathematics, specifically as

fields, that is, as sets of numerical values at defined points in

various kinds of space.

To make things more complicated, science now tells us that what we

usually think of as material particles – electrons, protons, neutrons,

and photons (the particles that make up visible light and other forms of

electromagnetic radiation) – are not fully particulate. In fact, they

have a dual nature: sometimes they act as particles and sometimes they

act as waves. Or, to put it differently, they exhibit two types of

behavior, one of which can be explained by thinking of them as particles

– they have defined positions in space, momenta (the products of their

masses times their velocities), and kinetic energy (energy of motion) –

while the other can be explained by thinking of them as waves – they

have wavelengths and frequencies, refract (change direction) when going

from one medium to another, diffract (change direction when passing the

edges of solid objects or through small apertures), interfere

constructively and destructively with each other, and behave in other

wave-like ways. Intriguingly, these entities never exhibit both types of

behavior simultaneously: at any given point in time, they act – and can

only be understood – as either particles or waves, but not both. Nor

have scientists ever been able to reduce these two forms to one

underlying, more fundamental entity. According to the standard

“Copenhagen” interpretation of quantum mechanics, this dual, but

mutually exclusive, characteristic of the nature and behavior of matter

is called “complementarity.”

Moreover, while the particulate behavior of subatomic particles is at

least somewhat consistent with a materialist conception of reality,

their wave-like behavior is not. Most waves are not themselves material;

they are characteristics – modifications, perturbations, undulations –

of the material media in which the waves are propagated, primarily

liquids, such as water, and gases, such as air. Given this, for many

years, light, whose fundamental behavior was understood in terms of wave

mechanics, was assumed to travel through a highly refined medium, called

the “aether”; visible light and other forms of electromagnetic radiation

were conceived to be periodic, wave-like, undulations of this aether.

Eventually, however, it was demonstrated that the aether did not exist

(this was one of the events that lead to the development of relativity),

and that, in contrast to more common wave phenomena, such as water waves

and sound waves, electromagnetic waves are not periodic undulations of a

material medium, but something else. But exactly what they are cannot be

fully explained in common-sense, materialistic terms. They are

scientifically represented and understood in terms of the mathematical

equations that describe their behavior, specifically, as intertwined

electrical and magnetic fields that generate each other at right angles

to each other. As a result, today, electromagnetic radiation (photons)

are now understood to be somewhat, but not entirely, discrete “packets”

of energy, called “quanta,” also with a dual nature, sometimes acting as

particles, sometimes acting as waves, but never both at once.

So, whereas energy was once conceived to be infinitely divisible – like

a liquid – while matter was believed to be entirely particulate, today,

both energy and matter are understood to be “quanta,” semi-discrete

entities that exhibit, at different times, the respective behaviors of

particles and waves. Some physicists call them “wavicles.”

To make the question even more obscure, photons and other subatomic

entities exhibit bizarre types of behavior that are not characteristic

of what we think of as matter in our normal, macro world. In the

super-atomic realm, at any given time, material entities, such as

baseballs and planets, can be precisely located in space, while their

physical characteristics, such as their momenta, can also be precisely

determined. This is not so in the subatomic realm. There, the more

precisely the position of a subatomic particle, say, an electron, is

determined, the more indeterminate becomes its momentum, and vice versa;

the more precisely its momentum is determined, the less defined is its

position. As a result, the behaviors of subatomic entities are not

describable in the exact, deterministic manner that we use in the macro

world. Instead, they are described in terms of probabilities that

represent the chances of finding a given particle in a given place at a

given time. And, it turns out, one form of the mathematics that

describes these probabilities is the very same as that which represents

the wave-like behavior of these particles. Moreover, rather than being

describable as they are, in themselves, the characteristics of these

subatomic entities are determined, to some degree, by the very act of

observation. Thus, when scientists look for (that is, set up an

apparatus to measure) the particulate characteristics and behavior of,

say, a single electron, its wave-like behavior disappears. Conversely,

when they wish to observe the wave-like behavior of electrons, their

particulate behavior vanishes.

The weirdness of the nature and behavior of subatomic particles has been

neatly summed in a book that attempts to explain the conceptual

difficulties of quantum mechanics by resorting to an explicitly

Idealistic standpoint.

“Behold the following quantum properties:

place at the same time (the wave property).

reality until we observe it as a particle (collapse of the wave).

there; we cannot say it went through the intervening space (the quantum

jump).

simultaneously influences it correlated twin object — no matter how far

apart they are (quantum action-at-a-distance).

(Amit Goswami, Ph.D. with Richard E. Reed and Maggie Goswami, The

Self-Aware Universe, Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam, a member of

Penguin/Putnam Inc., New York, 1993.)

(In fact, physicists believe that quantum mechanics does describe the

behavior of super-atomic entities, although until recently, it was

assumed that in this realm quantum effects were negligible and could,

for all practical purposes, be ignored. However, scientists are

currently discovering a variety of significant quantum effects that

occur on the molecular, that is, super-atomic, level. [See “Living in a

Quantum World,” by Vlatko Vedral, Scientific American, June 2001.])

What this adds up to (among other things) is that the more science has

plumbed the depths of the supposedly material world, the less material

does it appear to be. This is what led some scientists and philosophers

of science, from the beginning of the 20^(th) century on, to abandon, or

at least to question, materialist explanations of subatomic phenomena.

(One of the more prominent of these figures was the physicist and

philosopher, Ernst Mach, who was one of the main targets of Lenin’s

polemical defense of materialism, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism.) It

is also what led other scientists, including Albert Einstein, to

challenge the conclusions of quantum mechanics (even though he had been

instrumental in its early development): “God does not play dice with the

universe,” he insisted. And to this day, there is no universally

agreed-upon philosophical interpretation of quantum mechanics (or of

many of the other discoveries of modern physics, for that matter), a

fact that has led most scientists to avoid philosophical speculation

altogether (at least while they are doing their work) and to accept, and

to base their work on, the mathematical apparatuses (“formalisms”) that

describe that world. Significantly, these mathematical apparatuses, that

is, the equations and mathematical procedures that describe the nature

and behavior of the subatomic world, work and have been consistently

corroborated in the more than eight decades of their existence.

As a result, it can be argued that from a scientific point of view, the

fundamental reality of the subatomic world (and, by implication, the

entirety of the universe) is not matter at all, but mathematics, that

is, ideas. In other words, according to modern science, the ultimate

reality of the universe consists not of matter, but of the mathematical

equations that describe the behavior of the entities that our “common

sense” understanding conceives of as matter.

(We can see the same thing in the macro realm. According to the general

theory of relativity, space, which Einstein called “space-time” [to

incorporate the notion that, according to his theory, time is not

absolute], is curved, the degree of curvature in any given vicinity

being dependent upon the amount of matter found there. This curvature is

not itself material; it can only be conceptualized and analyzed

mathematically, through the geometry of curved surfaces [tensor

analysis], in other words, ideationally.)

And what is true of physics is true of the other sciences. More

fundamental than the material entities with which they deal are the

descriptions, the structures or patterns, of the processes through which

these entities move and interact. These, too, are conceptual,

ideational, that is, ideas.

If we accept this, we have to accept the counter-intuitive conclusion

that science is not really materialist at all, but a special form of

Idealism: for it, the fundamental reality of the universe consists not

of matter, but of ideas. True, these ideas (the mathematical equations,

categories, rules of procedure, descriptions, and theories of science)

are not the mind, spirit or consciousness of traditional Idealism. They

are, in contrast to the latter, pure abstractions from which the

personal characteristics of thought have been eliminated. But they are

ideas, nonetheless.

That science is, at least in some sense, Idealist is not really as

surprising as it might seem at first. After all, human beings conceive

of the world in terms of our ideas – our concepts, our categories, our

rules of logic (including mathematics), and our theories – and insofar

as we think about it, or about anything in it, we do not, and cannot,

get beyond them. Our thinking is, in a sense, trapped within the realm

of our ideas. And this is true both of our thinking about the natural

world and of our thinking about our thinking, that is, about philosophy.

This leads to an ironic conclusion that was most concisely raised by

Hegel. He said that all philosophies, including materialism, are really

forms of Idealism. What differentiates materialism from other types of

Idealism is that its fundamental category is matter, which is, as Hegel

saw it, a dull (uninteresting) and dead (undialectical) one. Yet, it is

still a category, an idea.

If this conclusion is correct, then Marxist “dialectical materialism” is

also a type of Idealism. Intriguingly, Engels seems to sense the

problematic nature of matter. In his Dialectics of Nature, he writes:

“Matter as such is a pure creation of thought and an abstraction. [My

emphasis – RT] We leave out of account the qualitative difference of

things in comprehending them as corporally existing things under the

concept matter. Hence matter as such, as distinct from definite existing

pieces of matter, is not anything sensuously existing.” (Dialectics of

Nature, op. cit., pp. 322–323.)

He goes on to try to rescue himself from this (not entirely welcome)

conclusion by drawing a distinction between the concept of matter itself

and specific material entities.

“If natural science directs its efforts to seeking out uniform matter as

such, to reducing qualitative differences to merely quantitative

differences in combining identical smallest particles, it would be doing

the same thing as demanding to see fruit instead of cherries, pears,

apples, or the mammal as such instead of cats, dogs, sheep, etc., gas as

such, metal, stone, chemical compound as such, motion as such.”

(Dialectics of Nature, pp. 322–323.)

But this is precisely what science does do; that is, it reduces

qualitative differences to more abstract quantitative ones (hence the

mathematical treatment, the scientific “laws,” the equations), leaving

aside the fact that categories such as “cherries, pears, apples,” and

“cats, dogs, sheep, etc.,” are just as much abstractions (ideas,

categories, products of human thought) as are “fruit” and “mammals”;

they are just somewhat narrower.

If, then, underneath the appearances, science is Idealist, what

distinguishes science from philosophy? As I see it, science is

distinguishable from philosophy by three things: (1) The categories,

equations, and “laws” of science are totally depersonalized, that is,

they are mindless, spiritless; they are not, and do not represent, the

minds, consciousness or spirits (God or the Ego) of the explicit forms

of Idealism; (2) As depersonalized thought, the categories, equations,

and “laws” do not embody or represent any sense of meaning or purpose,

any teleology. In other words, the universe has no underlying purpose;

it is not evolving toward some humanly meaningful historical or ethical

goal; (3) The conclusions of science – the concepts, hypotheses,

theories, and equations – are subjected to precise testing and hence to

corroboration or falsification (loosely, proof or disproof), while those

of philosophy are not. This insistence on testing is what lies behind

the fact that different realms of science and different scientific

theories often represent different and even contradictory philosophical

principles. In physics, for example, the macro world as described by the

theory of relativity is fully determined and, at least in principle,

predictable, while the micro world of quantum mechanics is

non-deterministic and probabilistic. Thus, most scientists (and hence,

one might say, science itself) assume that there is a realm “out there”

that is (more or less) independent of our theorizing that science is

attempting to explain.

(The precise nature and meaning of the process of corroboration and/or

falsification of scientific hypotheses and theories, and of the very

nature and meaning of the hypotheses and theories themselves, have long

been subjects of intense discussion and debate among scientists and

philosophers of science. Beyond the general notion that scientific

hypotheses and theories are, through some type of [often messy]

intellectual, cultural, social, and historical process, corroborated or

refuted, there is no general agreement on what this precisely means. In

light of this, one might add a fourth distinction between science and

philosophy. This is that science, unlike philosophy, is not reflexive;

it does not generally subject itself to analysis and takes it own

methods and procedures for granted. When scientists do attempt to

analyze science, they enter the realm of philosophy.)

Where, then, does this leave us? It leaves us, I think, with several

conclusions: (1) Science is not, in fact, materialist, despite its

appearance of being so. (2) What distinguishes science from philosophy

is not science’s supposedly materialistic nature but the extremely

abstract and depersonalized nature of its categories and concepts, its

denial that natural phenomena embody purposes or goals, and the fact

that it subjects its conclusions to systematic testing (along with the

implication of this – that it is attempting to explain a reality that is

independent of it); (3) Materialism, in the sense of a class of

philosophy counterposed to Idealism, is an illusion; it, like the rest

of philosophy, is a form (a subset) of Idealism. Materialism is a form

of Idealism that denies that it is Idealistic. (4) Marxism’s claim to be

materialist, to be based on a materialist philosophy, is false;

moreover, as per (1), such a claim, by itself, does not make it

scientific.

DIALECTICS

With this said, let’s turn to the question of dialectics.

To Marx and Engels, “dialectics,” in the most basic sense of the term,

refers to the fact that, in their view (and, they believed, in the view

of modern science), all natural and historical/social reality is and can

only be understood as a process, or more precisely, as a complex of

processes.

“[T]he world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made

things, but as a complex of processes....” (Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach and

the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, op. cit., p. 44.)

In this conception, everything in the world is in motion, and everything

reacts and interacts in an extremely complex way that cannot be fully

grasped by static, mechanical modes of thoughts. For Engels and Marx,

dialectics is a way to more effectively conceptualize and understand the

process-like nature of reality.

Dialectics (or better said, dialectical ideas and methods) has a long

history in Western philosophy, especially in Idealism. (It also appears

very early in Asian philosophy, most notably, in the interpenetrating,

mutually generating relations of “yin” and “yang.” But since Marx and

Engels describe their own philosophical development exclusively in terms

of Western philosophy, I will limit my discussion to that tradition.)

Although Engels, in Anti-DĂĽhring, cites some of the Greek pre-Socratic

materialist philosophers, particularly Heraclitus, as early sources of

dialectics, to get a deeper understanding of what dialectics is one must

look to the Idealists, first off to Plato. As those who have read some

philosophy know, Plato elaborated his outlook in the form of dialogues,

specifically, dialogues involving his mentor, Socrates. Socrates, an

eccentric citizen of ancient (5^(th) century B.C.) Athens, went around

the agora (the market place/public square) of the city questioning those

men who claimed to be philosophers and to know something about the

world. In contrast to these individuals, Socrates insisted that he

himself knew nothing. But through a series of probing questions, he

would get those he interrogated to contradict themselves, thus

demonstrating that, despite their claims to be knowledgeable, they, too,

did not know anything. (At least Socrates knew that he knew nothing.)

All Socrates claimed to know (but to know not quite in the same sense as

those he questioned claimed to know) was what his “daemon” – a little

voice in his head – told him, particularly, by raising doubts about

specific ideas. (Today, we would recognize this voice as Socrates’

conscience.) Because of his annoying habits, and even more, because he

set his individual conscience above the ancient, venerated laws and

customs of Athens, Socrates was tried (essentially, for treason),

convicted, and sentenced to death, which sentence he willingly, even

cheerfully, carried out by drinking the poisonous hemlock.

Although Socrates insisted that he knew (almost) nothing, and as a

result, never articulated a fully developed, logically coherent

philosophy, Plato used the “Socratic dialogues” to do just that.

Ironically, then, Plato utilized the modest, skeptical figure of

Socrates to elaborate a philosophy of absolute knowledge, a metaphysical

point of view that asserted not only that absolute knowledge was

possible but also that his (Plato’s) philosophy represented just that

knowledge.

In a nutshell, Plato argued that the world consists of two distinct but

interconnected realms. One is the world of everyday objects, events,

processes, and ideas that we feel/perceive through our five bodily

senses and think about with our untrained minds. The other, behind and

beyond this world, is a realm of Ideal forms that are the basis for and

determine the everyday world, not only the physical things – inanimate

objects, plants, animals, human beings – but also the values Athenians

held to, such as beauty, honor, virtue, valor, filial piety, patriotism,

and truth. Although most people only recognize the sensible, physically

perceivable world and the world of common-sense ideas, the realm of the

Ideal forms was, in Plato’s view, the more fundamental, the more real,

one, and it is only a very few individuals (true philosophers, such as

himself) who have the ability – indeed, the privilege – to recognize and

understand it, which they do through philosophical contemplation. It was

because of this that Plato believed that the only people capable of

governing society in a truly rational manner are those very

philosophers, and he elaborated a vision of an ideal society, governed

by “philosopher-kings” (who would be reared and educated via Plato’s

curriculum and methods), in what is perhaps his most famous dialogue,

The Republic. He actually tried to set up such a society in a couple of

places, becoming an adviser to what were then known as “tyrants”

(essentially, political strongmen) to do so. Fortunately, these efforts

to establish what were, in effect, totalitarian states were not

successful.

Although Plato does not use the term, we might say that for him,

“dialectics” is a logical process involving a confrontation of ideas.

Impelled by this conflict or dialogue, this process moves toward, and

eventually arrives at, the Truth, which, for Plato, meant absolutely

certain knowledge.

This conception of dialectics was summed up by a later Greek, Diogenes

Laertius, in his book on the Greek philosophers:

“The dialectic is the art of discourse by which we either refute or

establish some proposition by means of question and answer on the part

of interlocutors.” (Cited in Matteo Motterlini, editor’s introduction,

For and Against Method, by Imre Lakatos and Paul Feyerabend, The

University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1999, p. 1.)

Aside from dialectics and the notion of absolute truth, there can also

be seen in Plato’s thought a division of the cosmos into two distinct

realms. One is that of appearances, the world of everyday and natural

objects, events, and processes, of phenomena. The other, behind and/or

beyond the world of phenomena, is the more fundamental realm of the

noumena, or essences. To Plato and to most philosophers after him, it

was the ultimate purpose of philosophy to penetrate behind the phenomena

in order to discern the nature, structure, and dynamics of the noumena,

which is where the truth lies.

A much later version of dialectical thinking can be seen in the

philosophy of the 18^(th) century German, Immanuel Kant, as put forward

in his masterpiece, The Critique of Pure Reason. Kant saw the reasoning

faculty of the human mind as compartmentalized into distinct spheres;

one of these he termed the “understanding;” another, “pure reason.” The

understanding is that part of the mind that perceives and analyzes the

world of phenomena, which, for Kant, includes both the world of everyday

people, places, and things, and the world of science. Built into the

understanding are certain fundamental “laws” and structures, such as the

notion of cause and effect and the three-dimensional (Euclidean) nature

of space. To Kant, these laws and structures are not characteristics of

physical reality itself but serve to shape what we ultimately cognize

with our minds, specifically, by our understanding. One way to

understand this is to see these structures as constituting a kind of

framework, or filter, through which we sense, but do not fully and

precisely perceive, the ultimate reality. This ultimate reality is the

world of the noumena, the world of essences, or what Kant called the

“thing-in-itself.” This latter realm can be conceived only through pure

reason, by which he meant philosophic contemplation or speculation.

Although in this sense Kant was in agreement with Plato, in contrast to

Plato, Kant felt that pure reason was not capable of arriving at

philosophic (as opposed to scientific) truth. On all the great

metaphysical questions of his day, in fact, of the entire history of

philosophy – such as, Does God exist?, Is the universe finite or

infinite?, Did the universe have a beginning in time or has it existed

forever?, Are human actions determined or is there free will? – Kant

felt that pure reason was capable of arguing both sides (pro and con)

equally well. One result of this is an endless dialogue – idea

contending with idea, philosopher arguing with philosopher, each

philosopher debating with himself, in effect, reason arguing with itself

– that never actually arrives at the truth. Kant’s dialectic is thus

infinite and eternal. For Kant, certainty and true (scientific)

knowledge were possible only in the realm of phenomena, not in the realm

of the noumena, which was the more fundamental reality. Here, then, we

have a form of the dialectic that, unlike Plato’s, goes on forever and

never arrives at a conclusion, a synthesis, or (philosophical or

metaphysical) truth.

Understandably, many philosophers after Kant were dissatisfied with this

conclusion. Among these was Hegel. In many respects, Hegel’s philosophy,

and particularly his conception of the dialectic, can best be seen as a

reply to Kant’s. Where Kant left the dialectic inconclusive, forever

debating with itself but never reaching the truth, Hegel tried to

demonstrate that if left to itself, the dialectic, the dialogue of

consciousness or mind with itself, does in fact lead to

philosophic/metaphysical truth. In his Phenomenology of Mind, Hegel

starts with what is apparently the most certain type of knowledge, what

he called “sense certainty” (the seeming assurance that when one touches

something, one knows that it is there), and shows how, at each level of

thinking, one thought generates its opposite, and how the conflict

between these two ideas leads to the recognition that each thought is

both true and false, that each thought contains some truth but is also

limited and one-sided. The result of this conflict/dialogue is a kind of

synthesis of both ideas, a new idea that preserves what is true in each

thought, discards what is false, and ultimately transcends the debate

between them. This synthesis – this new idea, which represents a new and

higher level of thinking – then splits in two and undergoes the same

dialogical process, but at a still higher level. This process is

repeated at ever higher, broader, and more sophisticated planes of

thought, until consciousness eventually arrives at the absolute truth.

As we have seen, for Hegel, this truth is that God does exist, that God

is ultimately mind, consciousness, or spirit, and that our

minds/consciousnesses/spirits partake of and are the embodiments of the

cosmic mind/consciousness/spirit that is God. In this dialectical

process, we start out with perceptions of phenomena but wind up with

knowledge of the noumena, what Kant had called the “thing-in-itself,”

thus, breaking down the barrier Kant and other philosophers had erected

between these two realms and between the “understanding” and “pure

reason.” For Hegel, this process is simultaneously the journey of the

thought of each philosophical inquirer, of the consciousness (and hence,

for Hegel, the philosophy and history) of all humanity, and of the

spirit of God. While for us humans, as individuals and as a collective

entity, this journey takes place in time, for God (as Hegel explains in

the semi-mystical final section of the Phenomenology that has baffled

some readers [see Merold Westphal, History and Truth in Hegel’s

Phenomenology, Humanities Press, New Jersey, 1982.]), this process

occurs repeatedly and continually, in a truly dialectical fashion, in a

realm beyond time.

In contrast to Kant’s conception, in Hegel’s view there is no unsolvable

problem of knowledge or truth. Truth – real truth, Absolute Truth – is

obtainable through the dialectical process of philosophical thought,

what Hegel called speculation. All one has to do is to allow the process

to work itself out, to go along with it, so to speak, to follow where it

leads. The fundamental reason why, for Hegel, there is no insurmountable

problem of knowledge of the noumena is that our minds partake of the

same substance – ultimately they are the same substance – as that of the

cosmos and of God. As a result, the laws of our thinking, of our

consciousness (that is, our logic), are precisely the same as those laws

(and the logic) that underlie and determine the evolution of the cosmos,

the laws (the logic, the mind or spirit) of God. (This logic is

extensively – indeed, exhaustively – laid out in Hegel’s most impressive

work, The Science of Logic.)

The above examples of the dialectic relate exclusively to the realm of

ideas; to the thinkers I’ve discussed, the dialectic is an ideal

process; it characterizes only thought/consciousness and processes based

on it. Since the purely natural world does not entail meaning or

consciousness, the dialectic, in these versions, does not apply.

However, Hegel’s philosophy, whose Idealism is not subjective, but

objective (he believed the world exists independently of the

consciousness of any given individual), provides a transition to a

conceivable materialist dialectic. Although Hegel did not consider the

natural world to be governed by dialectical processes or logic, he did

think, as we have seen, that human history was. Thus, in contrast to

Plato and Kant, where the dialectic is a purely subjective process (a

dialogue of ideas in minds or consciousness), for Hegel, the dialectic

has an objective reality; it exists “out there”; it actually exists in,

underlies and impels, the objective reality of history. Basing oneself

on this, it is possible to assert the existence of an objective

dialectic in the material universe. This, in essence, is what Marx and

Engels do.

MARXIAN DIALECTICS

The dialectic of Marx and Engels, as they admit, takes its point of

departure from Hegel’s but claims to be different, and this in three

ways. First, Marx and Engels insist that their dialectic is

materialistic: in contrast to Hegel, they believe material reality,

including natural processes and nature itself, is dialectical; this

includes the notion that the material universe has a history, that it

evolves. Second, they contend that their dialectic is a “method” and

not, as it is in Hegelian philosophy, a “system.” Third, Marx and Engels

believe (although they never say this explicitly) that their conception

of the dialectic has predictive value, that is, it allows its

practitioners to project past trends into the future. This, too, is in

contrast to Hegel, who felt that the dialectic is ex post facto: it only

enables one to understand/explain/interpret events after they have

occurred. As he put it, “The owl of Minerva (the Roman goddess of wisdom

– RT) only flies at night.” In short, as Marx and Engels see it, their

dialectic is not an Idealist construct but a scientific method of

analyzing material reality that enables one to make accurate predictions

about the future.

Here is Engels’ explication:

“It is, therefore, from the history of nature and human society that the

laws of dialectics are abstracted. For they are nothing but the most

general laws of these two aspects of historical development, as well as

of thought itself.”

“And indeed they can be reduced in the main to three:

“All three are developed by Hegel in his idealist fashion as mere laws

of thought: the first, in the first part of his Logic, in the Doctrine

of Being; the second fills the whole of the second and by far the most

important part of his Logic, the Doctrine of Essence; finally the third

figures as the fundamental law for the construction of the whole

system.”

Engels then describes what he sees as Hegel’s fundamental error:

“The mistake lies in the fact that these laws are foisted on nature and

history as laws of thought, and not deduced from them. This is the

source of the whole forced and often outrageous treatment; the universe,

willy-nilly, is made out to be arranged in accordance with a system of

thought which itself is only the product of a definite stage of

evolution of human thought. If we turn the thing around, then everything

becomes simple, and the dialectical laws that look so mysterious in

idealist philosophy at once become simple and clear as noonday....

“We are not concerned here with writing a handbook of dialectics, but

only with showing that the dialectical laws are really laws of

development of nature, and therefore are valid also for theoretical

natural science.” (All of these citations are from Engels, Dialectics of

Nature, International Publishers, op. cit., pp. 26–27.)

(The rest of Dialectics of Nature consists of Engels’ attempts to

demonstrate the dialectical nature of material reality as it is revealed

in the discoveries of the science of his and Marx’s day.)

Despite Engels’ insistence that his and Marx’s notion of dialectics is

materialist, their conception is just as much of an Idealist construct

as is Hegel’s. This is because:

(1) The “laws” of dialectics that Engels claims have been abstracted

from nature and history have never been corroborated and accepted by the

scientific community. Specifically, they have not been established as

scientific laws in the same sense as have, say, the laws of modern

physics or the Darwinian theory of evolution through natural selection.

At the time Marx and Engels were writing, it might have appeared

reasonable to believe that these laws would eventually be accepted as

scientific by the community of scientists, and Marx and Engels seemed to

have shared this idea. As Engels put it,

“For the revolution which is being forced on theoretical natural science

by the mere need to set in order the purely empirical discoveries, great

masses of which are now being piled up, is of such a kind that it must

bring the dialectical character of natural events more and more to the

consciousness even of those empiricists who are most opposed to it.

(Engels, Anti-DĂĽhring, op. cit., p. 17.)

But despite their beliefs (and hopes), the laws of dialectics have not

been accepted by the scientific community and are not likely ever to be

so accepted. This is because they are too broad, too vague, and too

general to be systematically tested in a scientific fashion: they can be

subjected to many different interpretations; they apply to some

phenomena but not to others; they apply to some phenomena some of the

time but not all the time, etc. Above all, Marx and Engels’ laws do not

make predictions specific enough so they can be held to account; as a

result, there is no way they can be judged as true or false

(corroborated or falsified) in the scientifically-accepted meaning of

these terms. In the absence of such corroboration, the Marxian “laws of

dialectics” remain logical constructs, not scientific truths. (For

whatever it’s worth, if the theories of relativity and of quantum

mechanics had not been empirically corroborated, they, too, would be

nothing but logical – in this case, mathematical – constructs.)

(2) Although Engels contends that the laws of dialectics were abstracted

from the history of nature and human society, this is not so. Where?

When? How? By whom? Certainly not by any significant number of

scientists. As I’ve said, these laws have never been accepted by

mainstream science. Moreover, they were not even abstracted from the

history of nature and society by Marx and Engels. Marx and Engels were

introduced to dialectics through their academic backgrounds in

philosophy, specifically, through their study of Hegel and Hegel’s

disciples, and through their involvement in the postHegelian

philosophical milieu of their youth. It was this study and debate, along

with their participation in radical politics in the early and mid-1840s,

that led them to their mature political outlook, which was most

succinctly articulated in the Communist Manifesto. And it was only after

they had formulated this outlook that they began the systematic study of

capitalism (as Marx himself admits), and much later, of natural

phenomena. In other words, rather than abstracting the laws of

dialectics from the history of nature and human society, as Engels

insists, Marx and Engels, under the influence of the materialism of

Ludwig Feuerbach, first recast the Hegelian schema in materialist terms

(in effect, synthesizing the Hegelian and Feuerbachian philosophies),

and then looked to human society/history and nature to confirm the

validity of the construct. Dialectics of Nature was part of this

program. It was an attempt to prove the validity of the dialectical

schema by demonstrating that it manifests itself in natural, material

reality.

(Insofar as anybody can be said to have “abstracted” dialectics

[although not from nature but from the history of ideas], it was the

Idealist philosophers who did so, particularly Hegel and his once-friend

and later rival, F.W.J. Schelling, who actually claimed priority in the

development of the concept.)

(3) Despite Engels’ contention that his (and Marx’s) dialectics

constitutes a method, he does not really use it that way. To be utilized

as a method, the dialectical “laws” would have to be understood as, at

best, rules of thumb, general notions to be kept in mind as one

investigates natural and social phenomena. I think it is true, as Engels

says, that natural and human reality are best understood as a complex of

processes that cannot be fully understood by our usual habits of

thought. This is because our normal ideas – our concepts, categories,

and rules of logic – are abstract, and as a result, simplify and hence

distort reality. Specifically, they isolate phenomena from each other in

space, looking at each one, or at most a few, as distinct entities

abstracted from the rest of reality. They also stop time, viewing

entities as static, inert, and as non-evolving. But if all of reality

(including things that appear to be solid, permanent objects) is in fact

a process, if everything is in motion, then these traditional modes of

thought distort our understanding of that reality. From this standpoint,

the purpose of dialectics would be to remind us that reality does

consist of a complex of processes, that things that appear to be unitary

and stable may, in fact, be constituted by antagonistic forces, and that

they may be evolving into something else. If understood in this sense,

dialectics would serve to remind us to look at natural and economic,

social, and historical events in ever broader contexts of space and

time.

But this is not how Engels presents and utilizes these laws. He does not

use them as part of a general mode of procedure that serves to remind us

that nature is, as he puts it, a complex of processes. Instead, when he

looks at natural phenomena, he analyzes them with the intent of finding

the specific “laws of dialectics” in them, in other words, with the

purpose of proving the validity of the dialectical laws, that is,

proving that the “laws of dialectics” determine the development of

natural reality. But all he does, in fact, is to find what he is looking

for: certain phenomena at certain times do exhibit behavior that is

consistent with those “laws.” Rather than serving as a method, Engels’

laws of dialectics function in much the same way as they do in Hegel’s

system: they describe a structure or logic which is assumed (but never

proven) to underlie, form the basis of, and determine the evolution of

all natural and social reality. All that is different is how the two

dialectical schemas are conceived and presented. Hegel describes his

dialectical method and system explicitly as Idealistic, as laws of

thought/consciousness. In contrast, Engels presents his dialectics as

materialistic, specifically, as determining the development of material

reality (natural and historical) and its reflection in the human mind as

thought. But Marxian dialectics remains just as much of an abstract

logical schema, just as much of an Idealist construct, as does the

Hegelian. What Engels has in fact done is to take a very specific notion

of dialectics – one borrowed directly from the Idealists, particularly,

Hegel – and to surreptitiously amalgamate it with a much more general

(and generally acceptable) conception, and to put these forward as if

they were one and the same. But this is not the case. One can readily

agree that nature (and human society) is best understood and analyzed as

a “complex of processes” without accepting any of the dialectical “laws”

that Engels describes.

Engels’ ultimate motive behind this maneuver, and behind his elaboration

of “dialectical materialism” as a whole, is to establish the ontological

basis, and thus the validity, of the Marxian conception of history, and

through this, to substantiate the claim that the Marxian program is

scientific, specifically, that socialism, to be achieved through the

dictatorship of the proletariat, is inevitable. If material reality, the

world of matter of the natural sciences, is dialectical, that is,

conforming to and obeying a dialectical structure, then so, too, must be

the material reality of human history, the world of the forces and

relations of production, which is ontologically based on the material

world of nature and, at least in the view of Marx and Engels, follows

the same laws; in other words, human history must also conform to and

obey a dialectical structure. And, if we recognize that, for Marx and

Engels, an essential aspect of this dialecticality is that the future is

predictable (as the outcome of the “laws” of dialectics, particularly,

the “law” of the negation of the negation), the supposed dialectical

structure of history seems to prove that the laws of motion of

capitalism and all prior history inevitably lead to the proletarian

revolution, the establishment of the dictatorship of the proletariat,

and the creation of a socialist/communist society through that

institution. That this is Engels’ purpose can be seen more clearly if we

look at the three “laws” of dialectics that he discusses. Not

surprisingly, each one serves to justify one of the key precepts of

Marxism.

The first law, the “transformation of quantity into quality,” is

essential to the Marxian claim that social development occurs through

periodic revolutions. As we saw in the discussion of historical

materialism, for Marxism, the (quantitative) growth in the forces of

production within specific socio-economic formations leads to periodic

social revolutions (qualitative changes) that lead to new forms of

economic production, specifically, when the forces of production come

into conflict with the relations of production. As a result, capitalism,

which develops the forces of production at a far more rapid rate than

previous economic formations, is destined to bring about a (working

class) revolution.

The second law, the “interpenetration of opposites,” substantiates the

Marxian contention that each mode of production, each form of society,

must be understood as a dynamic unity of contradictory forces, first and

foremost, social classes, and that, as a result, all history is the

history of class struggles.

The third law, the “negation of the negation,” justifies the Marxian

insistence that the inevitable outcome of human history will be the

establishment of a collectivist, egalitarian society, a return to the

principles of primitive communism but on the far more technologically

advanced basis bequeathed by history, particularly by capitalism.

According to the dialectical schema, primitive communism is the starting

point, the first positive standpoint. This type of society is “negated”

by the establishment of class society, which is thus the first negation.

At the end of history, this first negation is negated by the proletarian

revolution, which eventually leads to the establishment of (classless)

communism, the negation of class society, the negation of the negation.

That this is the case can be seen in Engels’ own presentation. In

discussing his and Marx’s “rescue” of the Hegelian dialectic, he writes:

“We comprehended the concepts in our heads once more materialistically –

as images of real things instead of regarding the real things as images

of this or that stage of development of the absolute concept. Thus

dialectics reduced itself to the science of the general laws of motion –

both of the external world and of human thought – two sets of laws which

are identical in substance, but differ in their expression in so far as

the human mind can apply them consciously, while in nature and also up

to now for the most part in human history, these laws assert themselves

unconsciously in the form of external necessity in the midst of an

endless series of seeming accidents. Thereby the dialectic of the

concept itself became merely the conscious reflex of the dialectical

motion of the real world and the dialectic of Hegel was placed on its

head; or rather, turned off its head, on which it was standing before,

and placed upon its feet.”

“...the world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made

things, but as a complex of processes, in which the things apparently

stable no less than their mind-images in our heads, the concepts, go

through an uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing away,

in which, in spite of all seeming accidents and of all temporary

retrogression, a progressive development asserts itself in the end [my

emphasis – RT]....” (Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical

German Philosophy, op. cit., p. 44.)

In other words, according to Engels, the dialectic underlies and drives

the evolution of external reality (both natural and historical). In so

doing, it ensures, despite all apparent accidents and reverses, that

this evolution will be progressive. But this is nothing but the Hegelian

schema dressed up in materialist garb! Despite his claim, for Engels

(and, I believe, for Marx), the dialectic is a logical structure that is

immanent in material reality, both natural and historical, and propels

the evolution of that reality toward an inevitable, progressive

conclusion. This is philosophy (and Hegelian philosophy, at that), not

science, because, as I’ve stressed, there is no scientific proof that

the dialectic, in the sense of the dialectical “laws,” inheres in

material (or, for that matter, in social) reality.

Beyond his questionable procedure, Engels’ position reveals (at least)

three fundamental misconceptions. One is the belief that nature evinces

a progressive development. This is a profound misinterpretation of

science, in general, and of the Darwinian theory of evolution, in

particular. Modern science does recognize evolution in the cosmos. In

contrast to Hegel and the French materialists of the 18^(th) century,

modern cosmology believes that the universe evolves, that it has a

history, that it does not merely evince a purely mechanical repetition,

forever returning to the same state. But modern cosmology does not see

this as in any sense “progressive”; it does not assert that nature is

evolving toward a pre-existing end or goal; it is not teleological.

Similarly with the Darwinian understanding of evolution in the plant and

animal worlds. While Darwin and modern evolutionary biologists recognize

that the organic world has undergone an evolution from very simple

life-forms to more complex ones, this is not understood to be

“progressive.” For the contemporary neoDarwinian synthesis,

currently-existing species all reveal equally successful adaptations to

their environments. There are no “higher” or “lower” species – viruses,

bacteria, singlecell parasites, molds, fungi, worms, and insects are

just as successful as human beings (arguably more so) – and,

consequently, there is no “progress” in evolution, no immanent, let

alone “progressive,” goal.

Engels’ position rests on yet another misunderstanding. This is the

belief that laws that are found to apply/operate in the realm of nature

also apply/operate, and in the same manner, in the world of human social

life, specifically, as Engels says, that the laws of dialectics are laws

of nature and of history (and human thought). But this is not

necessarily so. Each realm of existence, the inorganic, the organic, and

the human/social, expresses different dynamics and is described by

different “laws”; each realm has its own, unique (“emergent”)

characteristics which cannot mechanically be reduced to, or deduced

from, the laws of the other levels. Thus, even if the Marxian “laws of

dialectics” were to be corroborated as being valid (and operating) in

the natural world, this, by itself, would not mean that they necessarily

apply to, or operate in, human society. This would have to be

independently demonstrated, which has never been done. Although Marx and

Engels claim to have demonstrated it, they only appear to do so by

assuming it from the outset.

Lastly, Engels seems to believe that evolutionary theory enables one to

predict the future, to be able to determine at least the broad outlines

of future developments. But this, too, is not true. Neither Darwin nor

modern evolutionary biologists have ever contended that the theory of

natural selection enables one to predict future forms of plant and

animal life, beyond the general claim that they will be more or less

adapted to their environments. Yet, the belief in the predictability of

the future is central to Engels’ (and, I believe, Marx’s) project.

Although Engels insists, in Anti-DĂĽhring, that dialectics cannot be used

to prove anything, this is what he is in fact trying to do. Why else

spend so much time and effort (in Dialectics of Nature, Anti-DĂĽhring,

and elsewhere) attempting to demonstrate that nature is dialectical,

that the “laws” of dialectics inhere in nature? The whole point of

Engels’ procedure is to establish these laws as universal laws of nature

and, hence, of all reality, not only natural, but economic, social, and

political, as well. And if, as Engels believes, they are the laws of

development of all reality, they can be used to prove something,

specifically, that, as he puts it, “in spite of all temporary

retrogression, a progressive development asserts itself in the end.”

But, given the lack of scientific demonstration of the dialectical laws,

they cannot, scientifically, be used to prove anything at all. And they

certainly cannot be used to predict the future of human society, which

is what Marx and Engels claim to be able to do. Yet, without that

ability – without the prediction that the (dialectical) logic of nature

and history necessarily results in socialism through the establishment

of the dictatorship of the proletariat – the Marxian claim to have

established the scientific basis of socialism collapses. And with that,

it is revealed that Marxian “scientific socialism” is a fraud. Like all

other forms of utopian ideology, the Marxian program rests on a moral or

ethical claim, not a scientific one.

In light of this, we can now see that the Marxist conception of

dialectics encompasses several versions that are, in fact, qualitatively

distinct but not clearly differentiated from each other. One is the

broad insistence that the world is to be comprehended as a “complex of

processes.” This is something that can be accepted by every scientist

(and in fact by every intelligent observer) and is thoroughly compatible

with a scientific outlook. If this is what dialectics consists of, then

dialectics is (almost obviously) true. An additional, but closely

related, meaning of dialectics is the traditional philosophical/Idealist

one; that is, it describes processes that are best understood as

involving opposing forces or ideas that mutually influence and generate

each other. Under this variant we can include the Marxist conception of

historical praxis, as well as the notion that philosophical ideas and

scientific theories often develop via an ongoing discussion or debate

between opposing viewpoints, without this implying that the outcome is

progressive, predictable or ordained. This conception of dialectics I

also believe is relatively unobjectionable.

But, in addition to these unexceptionable notions of dialectics, Engels

puts forward an additional one. This is the dialectics of the three

“laws” – the unity of opposites, the transformation of quantity into

quality, and the negation of the negation. These laws, which, as I’ve

stressed, have not been established as scientific, in fact represent a

philosophic construct, specifically, an Idealist system of logic

borrowed from Hegel and presented as materialistic. This construct is

then utilized to justify a particular ideological claim, specifically,

that human history entails a progressive development whose inevitable

outcome is communism, or, to put it in philosophic terms, that history

is the phenomenological expression of a noumenological telos whose goal

is human freedom, as Marx and Engels conceive it. In Marxist literature,

including and in particular the writings of Engels, this last,

philosophic, version of dialectics has not been delineated from the

others. As a result, the unobjectionable variants serve to justify, and

to legitimate, the philosophical construct and so to enable Marxists to

present it as scientific.

MARXISM AND SCIENCE

Given all this, it should not be surprising that Marxism has had an

ambiguous relationship with, and an ambivalent attitude toward, science.

On the surface, of course, Marxism admits of no such ambiguity or

ambivalence. It touts science as among the highest achievements of

humanity and strongly insists on its own scientific character. Thus, in

his oration at Marx’s funeral, Engels contended that Marx had done for

human history what Darwin had done for natural history. In addition,

Marxism claims that the discoveries of modern science confirm both the

details of its outlook and the truth of its philosophical standpoint,

dialectical materialism. Yet, as I’ve said, science does not have or

embody a specific, unified philosophy, aside from some very general

axioms, such as that the phenomena of nature reveal regular patterns,

that these can be discovered and expressed as “natural laws,” that

consistent empirical corroboration (or lack of falsification) of these

laws suggests that these laws are “true” (whatever that precisely

means), and that such laws apply, or can be said to be valid, throughout

the extent of space and time. Beyond this, a variety of philosophic

standpoints are consistent with science, and over the centuries,

individual scientists have held to a broad range of philosophical

outlooks – materialist and Idealist, rationalist and empiricist, realist

and instrumentalist, atheist and religious, logical and even mystical.

Within the accepted realms of science, scientists accept the basic

axioms of science, including the (very broadly defined) scientific

method, but beyond that, and in interpreting the methods and conclusions

of science, they embrace a variety philosophic positions.

As a result of this, despite its claims to be scientific (even to be

science itself), Marxism is in at least potential conflict with science

insofar as it insists that its philosophic standpoint, dialectical

materialism, is the true and only proper philosophy of science. As it

sees it, science is inherently dialectical and materialist, whatever

individual scientists may think, and only those scientists who hold to

dialectical materialism are truly and consistently scientific.

Conversely, it insists that those scientists who do not accept

dialectical materialism are inconsistent; their outlooks are in conflict

with the true philosophy and methods of science. In addition, Marxism,

by insisting that dialectical materialism is the proper philosophy of

science, implicitly claims the right to judge the discoveries,

hypotheses, and theories of science, a priori, on philosophical grounds.

That is, it claims the right to judge whether a given scientific

explanation or theory is right or wrong, correct or incorrect, true or

false, based on the theory’s supposed agreement or disagreement with the

tenets of dialectical materialism, regardless of the actual scientific

status of that theory, regardless, in other words, of whether or not the

theory has been empirically corroborated. Thus, even if, according to

the consensus of scientists working in a given field, a scientific

theory has been consistently corroborated, it may still be deemed

“incorrect” and “false” by Marxists if it is seen to violate the tenets

of dialectical materialism.

While Marx and Engels were alive, the conflict between Marxism and

science was largely dormant. But with the developments in physics in the

early years of the 20^(th) century, particularly the theories of

relativity and of quantum mechanics, it burst into the open. Although

the theory of relativity, by establishing the variability of time, led

to physical descriptions of the universe based on four dimensions

(mathematical representations of space-time involving four variables,

three for space, one for time), while modern cosmological theories, such

as string theory, entail ten or more, Lenin, in his Materialism and

Empirio-Criticism, mocked as absurd the idea that reality could have

more than three dimensions. Somewhat later, quantum mechanics came under

attack by Marxists as anti-materialist, because the standard,

Copenhagen, interpretation of the theory posits the inseparability of

observer and observed in the subatomic realm, and thus denies the

existence of a reality independent of observation. (See The Crisis in

Physics, by the British Marxist, Christopher Caudwell [pen name of

Christopher St. John Sprigg].) Still later, the science of genetics was

denounced by the Stalin-backed agronomist, Trofim D. Lysenko, in the

Soviet Union, because it emphasized the inherited nature of biological

traits rather than stressing the paramount role of the environment,

which Lysenko deemed the truly Marxist standpoint. Under Stalin’s

protection, Lysenko drove hundreds of scientists out of their jobs (many

were jailed and exiled; some died), and helped set back Soviet genetics

and agriculture many years. And in the 1970s, the now generally-accepted

theories of ethno-biologist Edward O. Wilson and others, who argued that

much of animal (and human) behavior is innate and genetically

determined, came under attack by Marxists and other leftists, including

Stephen Jay Gould (who would later criticize his role in this), for

pretty much the same reason.

Thus, despite its claims to be scientific and to stand on a scientific

ontology, Marxism has shown that it is often in conflict with science

and, in fact, quite hostile to it. Some Marxists try to explain this

away by criticizing modern science as “bourgeois.” After all, since,

according to Marxism, social being determines consciousness, modern

science, developing as it has under capitalism and generally serving its

interests, must also be bourgeois, a variety of “false consciousness,”

in fact a form of, or at the very least, influenced by, bourgeois

ideology. This implies the future existence of a “proletarian,” or

“socialist” science radically distinct from its current “bourgeois”

form. Although I think it likely that science under a truly liberated –

democratic, cooperative, and libertarian – society will differ in many

respects from its current incarnation, to posit the future existence of

a radically distinct version of science at this point in time and to use

this to oppose the discoveries of science is little more than a cover

for dismissing current science because some of its conclusions do not

conform to one’s personal philosophy.

Of course, Marxists have the right to their own opinions. But their

attacks on science reveal the purely philosophical nature of

“dialectical materialism.” Rather than being the only true and proper

philosophy of science, as it claims to be, dialectical materialism is a

philosophical construct whose scientific pretensions have not been

established, but which insists, nonetheless, on its right to judge

science on the basis of its own (dialectical materialism’s) precepts.

MARXISM AND PHILOSOPHY

In spite of the obviously philosophic nature of dialectical materialism,

Engels denies that it is a philosophy in the same sense as other

philosophies. Just as Hegel claimed that all past philosophy culminated

in his, so Engels insists that all prior philosophy (including Hegel’s)

culminates in the Marxist standpoint.

He writes (and it is worth quoting the entire passage):

“The realization of the entire incorrectness of previous German idealism

led necessarily to materialism, but, it must be noted, not to the simple

metaphysical and exclusively mechanical materialism of the eighteenth

century. Instead of the simple and naively revolutionary rejection of

all previous history, modern materialism sees history as the process of

the evolution of humanity, and its own problem as the discovery of laws

of motion of this process. The conception was prevalent among the French

of the eighteenth century, as well as with Hegel, of Nature as a whole,

moving in narrow circles and remaining immutable, with its eternal

celestial bodies, as Newton taught, and unalterable species of organic

beings, as Linnaeus taught. In opposition to this conception, modern

materialism embraces the more recent advances of natural science,

according to which Nature also has its history in time, the celestial

bodies, like the organic species which under favorable circumstances

people them, coming into being and passing away, and the recurrent

circles, in so far as they are in any way admissible, assuming

infinitely vaster dimensions. In both cases modern materialism is

essentially dialectical, and no longer needs any philosophy standing

above the other sciences. As soon as each separate science is required

to get clarity as to its position in the great totality of things and of

our knowledge of things, a special science dealing with this totality is

superfluous. What still independently survives of all former philosophy

is the science of thought and its laws – formal logic and dialectics.

Everything else is merged in the positive science of Nature and

history.” (Engels, Anti-Dühring, op. cit., p. 31.)

Thus, according to Engels, after the emergence of the Marxist standpoint

(“modern materialism”), philosophy (that is, all other philosophies)

becomes obsolete. What remains of philosophy is the “science of thought

and its laws,” that is, formal logic and (the Marxist conception, the

three “laws,” of) dialectics. In other words, dialectical materialism

survives; all other philosophies are superfluous and therefore wrong.

Marxism is not alone in its philosophical arrogance, its insistence that

it is right and that all other philosophies are wrong; most other

philosophies contend the same. But Marxism differs from these other

philosophical standpoints in two crucial ways. First, it denies that its

philosophy, dialectical materialism, is philosophy at all; it is, it

contends, coterminous with the methods and conclusions of science.

Second, consistent with its materialist self-conception, Marxism calls

on those who believe in it (that is, its practitioners) to seize

political power and establish a dictatorial state as the inevitable

outcome of the (dialectical) laws of nature and history. From this

vantage point, Marxists are then in a (very material) position from

which to establish Marxism’s correctness – its truth – in practice, that

is, to impose the Marxist standpoint by force, while suppressing all

other philosophic outlooks as unscientific, counterrevolutionary, and

false. And, in those countries where Marxists have come to power through

revolutions or military occupation, this is exactly what they’ve done.

PART II. MARXISM, KNOWLEDGE, AND TRUTH

Integrally involved with the issues discussed in the last chapter is the

question of Marxism’s attitude toward the nature of truth and the

veracity of human knowledge. What is truth? What is knowledge? How much

can we know? Is our knowledge certain or probable, precise or

approximate? Does our knowledge give us an accurate picture of reality,

does it somehow just enable us to manipulate it, or is it merely an

illusion? Is reality independent of all observers or is it connected to

the act of observation? Is reality even real? These are some of the

questions philosophers, scientists, and other thinkers have asked and

debated over the centuries. And the answers they have offered range from

the supremely confident (Lenin believed that our knowledge represents an

accurate reflection, or copy, of reality) to the extremely skeptical

(the ancient Sceptics questioned the validity of all knowledge claims,

even their own). Despite this, Marxism, like most other philosophies,

insists that it is true, that it knows what the truth is and of what our

knowledge consists.

The Marxist position starts with the assertion that knowledge flows out

of practice, or praxis. In contrast to some philosophies (such as those

of Descartes, Hume, Locke, Kant, and Berkeley) that describe human

knowledge in terms of the mind of a single and passive (generic)

individual at a given moment of time, Marxism insists that knowledge is

social, that it is active, and that it occurs over time. Specifically,

Marxism contends that the acquisition of knowledge is part of a process

in and through which the human species actively interacts with nature,

changing it and itself by means of labor. As human beings engage with

and act on nature, this activity generates ideas in our brains about it.

The adequacy of these notions is continually tested through our ongoing

interaction with an increasingly human-altered natural world. Those

ideas that are shown, through practice, to be wrong are discarded or

modified, while those that are demonstrated to be valid are adopted.

This is a dialectical process involving a complex reflexive relation

between humanity and nature, and between theory (our ideas about nature)

and practice (our practical engagement with nature), a process Marxists

refer to as the “unity of theory and practice.” Not only does practice —

that is, humans’ dialectical engagement with the world through labor

generate ideas in our brains, it also serves as the proof of the

validity of these ideas. Ultimately, it is the on-going social result of

this practice, the ever-increasing ability of the human species to

change the world — specifically, to subordinate it to our purposes —

that proves the validity, the truth value, of our thought. In the

Marxist view, it is through this interactive engagement with nature that

humanity, over the millennia, builds up an increasingly large,

increasingly sophisticated, and increasingly true, body of thought: a

conception of nature, what it is, how it is structured, how it

functions. For Marxism, it is this ever larger, ever more ramified, and

ever more accurate, corpus of thought — categories, ideas, concepts,

logic, hypotheses, theories, and facts — that constitutes our knowledge.

This praxis is not limited to humanity’s interaction with the natural

world; it also occurs on the societal level, so that, over time, we

develop an increasingly elaborate conception of the social world. As

human society evolves, and as it develops an ever-more ramified division

of labor, new realms of endeavor appear — agriculture, crafts,

manufacture, industry, art, music, dance, literature, drama, politics,

science, medicine, mathematics, philosophy, religion. Each of these

fields develops its own praxis — its own realm of practical activity and

knowledge — that is both dialectical in its own structure and

dialectically interrelated with the other realms of praxis. As a result,

human society can be understood as an increasingly elaborate complex of

interwoven dialectical practices, or, taken together, one gigantic,

tremendously ramified praxis.

For Marxism, what is true of our species as a whole, of groups of people

in specific areas of endeavor, and of individuals, is true of social

classes. On the one hand, the ruling classes throughout the ages have

had their own specific praxis, as they have engaged in the task of

managing their societies and protecting them and themselves from threats

from outside and from below. And, in and through such praxis, these

classes have developed their own conceptions of the world, of their

societies, and of their roles in those societies, in other words, their

myths, religions, philosophies — in short, their own ideologies — that

explain and justify their social roles and which they seek to foist on

the classes subject to them through various means. Yet, because of their

class position — as ruling, non-producing, and exploiting classes — and

because of their interest in maintaining that position, the social

knowledge of the ruling classes throughout history has been biased,

limited, and ultimately false. In other words, such classes have not

truly understood the natures of the socio-economic systems over which

they have ruled. This, for example, can be seen quite clearly in the

fantastic and ultimately apologetic theories of mainstream economics.

On the other hand, and most important from the Marxist standpoint, the

oppressed classes — slaves, serfs, crafts-persons, small farmers,

workers — also engage in praxis. This praxis includes that involved in

their own work, but at least as important, it includes the class

struggle. In and through such struggle, each class (with the exception

of the peasants, who, because they are isolated from each other and

because the division of labor among them is not well developed, do not

develop an independent outlook and therefore tend to follow the

leadership of other classes) develops its own conception of society, its

own understanding of its social position, and its own ideas of its

interests. This is particularly true of the working class, which by dint

of its location and role at the center of capitalist production, is in a

position to develop accurate knowledge of the world, and specifically,

of the capitalist society in which it lives and works. It is this

growing body of knowledge, embodied and theoretically elaborated in

Marxism, that will enable the working class to overthrow capitalism and

liberate itself and all humanity.

Consonant with this analysis, Engels, in Anti-Duhring, insists that at

any moment, human knowledge is relative or approximate; at any given

time, our knowledge does not give us absolute truth, an absolutely

certain picture of the world, but only limited and partial truths. This

is consistent with the (at least implied) view of science, which, given

its evolution, particularly the “scientific revolutions,” the radical

changes in our scientific theories and conceptions, that have occurred

periodically throughout the millennia, cannot claim that at any specific

point its theories are (or were) absolutely true.

Engels writes:

“Each mental image of the world system is and remains in actual fact

limited, objectively through the historical stage and subjectively

through the physical and mental constitution of its maker.” (Engels,

Anti-Duhring, p. 44.)

“The perception that all the phenomena of Nature are systematically

connected drives science on to prove this systematic connection

throughout, both in general and in detail. But an adequate, exhaustive

scientific statement of this interconnection, the formulation in thought

of an exact picture of the world system in which we live, is impossible

for us, and will always remain impossible.” (Engels, Anti-Duhring, op.

cit.,p. 44.)

And:

“But as for the sovereign validity of the knowledge in each individual’s

mind, we all know that there can be no talk of such a thing, and that

all previous experience shows that without exception such knowledge

always contains much more that is capable of being improved upon than

that which cannot be improved upon or is correct.”

“It is just the same with eternal truths. If mankind ever reached the

stage at which it could only work with eternal truths, with conclusions

of thought which possess sovereign validity and an unconditional claim

to truth, it would then have reached the point where the infinity of the

intellectual world, both in its actuality and in its potentiality had

been exhausted, and this would mean that the famous miracle of the

infinite series which has been counted would have been performed.

(Engels, Anti-Duhring, op. cit. pp. 96–97.)

Despite this, Engels also makes another, more far-reaching claim:

“(N)ow we come to the question whether any, and if so which, products of

human knowledge ever can have sovereign validity, and an unconditional

claim to truth....

“Is human thought sovereign? Before we can answer yes or no we must

first enquire: what is human thought? Is it the thought of the

individual human being? No. But it exists only as the individual thought

of many billions of past, present and future men. If then, I say that

the total thought of all these human beings, including future ones,

which is embraced in my idea, is sovereign, able to know the world as it

exists, if only mankind lasts long enough and in so far as no limits are

imposed on its knowledge by its perceptive organs or the objects to be

known, then I am saying something which is pretty banal and, in

addition, pretty barren.” [But true — RT]

And:

“In other words, the sovereignty of thought is realised in a number of

extremely unsovereignly-thinking human beings; the knowledge which has

an unconditional claim to truth is realised in a number of relative

errors; neither the one nor the other can be fully realised except

through an endless eternity of human existence.

“Here once again we find the same contradiction as we found above,

between the character of human thought, necessarily conceived as

absolute, and its reality in individual human beings with their

extremely limited thought. This is a contradiction which can only be

solved in the infinite progression, or what is for us, at least from a

practical standpoint, the endless succession, of generations of mankind.

In this sense human thought is just as much sovereign as not sovereign,

and its capacity for knowledge just as much unlimited as limited. It is

sovereign and unlimited in its disposition, its vocation, its

possibilities and its historical goal; it is not sovereign and it is

limited in its individual expression and its realisation at each

particular moment.” (Engels, Anti-Duhring, op. cit., pp. 96–97.)

These two sets of quotations reveal a contradiction (which Engels

himself admits). In the first set, Engels calls into question the

absolute validity (“sovereignty”) of human thought and hence of human

knowledge in general. But in the second set, he hedges his bets,

asserting that, in some sense, human thought/knowledge is, or at least

one day will be, “sovereign.” Engels seems to be contending that, while

at any given moment, human knowledge is not absolutely — but only

relatively or approximately — true, eventually, if humanity lives long

enough, our knowledge, the combined knowledge of many, many humans over

eons of time, will approach absolute truth. To express this in a

mathematical analogy, Engels here appears to be contending that our

knowledge, if given enough time, will approach absolute truth

asymptotically, getting ever closer to it without ever quite reaching

it.

Pursuing this question further, Engels goes on to divide human knowledge

into three areas, each of which has its own level of truth claim:

“Are there then nevertheless eternal truths, final and ultimate truths?

“Certainly there are. We can divide the whole realm of knowledge into

three great departments. The first includes all sciences which are

concerned with inanimate Nature and are to a greater or less degree

susceptible of mathematical treatment: mathematics, astronomy,

mechanics, physics, chemistry. If it gives anyone any pleasure to use

mighty words for very simple things, it can be asserted that certain

results obtained by these sciences are eternal truths, final and

ultimate truths; for which reason these sciences are also known as the

exact sciences. But very far from all their results have this validity.”

(Engels, AntiDuhring, op. cit., pp. 97–98.)

“The second department of science is the one which covers the

investigation of living organisms. In this field there is such a

multitude of reciprocal relations and causalities that not only does the

solution of each question give rise to a host of other questions, but

each separate problem can usually only be resolved piecemeal, through a

series of investigations which often requires centuries to complete; and

even then the need for a systematic presentation of the interrelations

makes it necessary again and again to surround the final and ultimate

truths with a luxuriant growth of hypotheses.... Anyone who wants to

establish really pure and immutable truths in this science will

therefore have to be content with such platitudes as: all men are

mortal, all female mammals have lacteal glands, and the like....”

(Engels, Anti-Duhring, op. cit., pp. 98–99.)

“But eternal truths are in an even worse plight in the third, the

historical group of sciences.... (K)nowledge is here essentially

relative, inasmuch as it is limited to the perception of relationships

and consequences of certain social and state forms which exist only at a

particular epoch and among particular people and are of their very

nature transitory. Anyone therefore who sets out on this field to hunt

down final and ultimate truths, truths that are pure and immutable, will

bring home but little, apart from platitudes and commonplaces of the

sorriest kind.... (Engels, Anti-Duhring, pp. 99–100.)

To understand what is at stake in Engels’ treatment of these questions,

it is worth noting several things about his discussion. First, Engels’

comments suggest that he sees human knowledge, including and in

particular, scientific knowledge, as additive: that is, he seems to

believe that while at any given moment our scientific theories may be

only approximately true, each new scientific discovery adds

incrementally and quantitatively to our knowledge, bringing us ever

closer to the absolute truth. While this may have been an understandable

belief in the 19^(th) century, during which science appeared to be

making great strides, building logically and consistently on the

foundations of the scientific revolution of the 16^(th) and 17^(th)

centuries, today this view can no longer be sustained. As the

discoveries of 20^(th) century physics have shown, major scientific

breakthroughs often involve significant qualitative changes (what the

historian and philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn called “paradigm

shifts,”) in scientists’ conceptions. As a result, it cannot be claimed

that the theories of modern science are simply incremental improvements

upon, merely quantitative additions to, the science of earlier epochs.

Thus, for example, modern physics is not a linear extension of the

“classical” physics developed by Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, and Newton

(while theirs is not a linear extension of the cosmology of the ancient

Greeks). Although the mathematical results of Newtonian mechanics can be

seen as a subset of the mathematical conclusions of the theory of

relativity (specifically, when the relative speeds of material bodies

are slow compared to the speed of light), and while relativity continues

to use some of the same categories and definitions as the earlier

theory, the two theories are conceptually very different. In Newtonian

physics, time and space are conceived as absolute, while gravity is

understood to be a force of attraction that (somehow) acts

instantaneously between two or more bodies at whatever distance they may

be from each other. In contrast, for relativity, there is no absolute

space and time, and gravity is no longer seen as a force acting at a

distance. Instead, gravity is seen as the expression of the very shape

of space itself, which is said to be more or less curved in proportion

to the massiveness of the bodies present in any given vicinity. As a

result, bodies under the influence of gravity are said to be following

their “natural paths in space-time.” More broadly, Newton’s physics

considers the universe to be mechanical, analogous to a machine. In

contrast, relativity understands the universe geometrically, as a kind

of varyingly curved “space-time continuum.” How, then, can we say that

the later theory represents simply a quantitative addition to the

earlier one? In a very real sense, the two theories are, as some

philosophers of science have put it, incommensurable. (For an excellent

discussion of these and related issues, see Perception, Theory and

Commitment, by Harold I. Brown, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

and London, 1979.)

The same situation can be seen in other areas of science. Prior to

Darwin, mainstream biology thought that the different species of plants

and animals were static; each species was immutable, and there was no

evolution. Since Darwin, the vast majority of scientists no longer

believe in the unchanging nature of species. Instead, species are seen

as mutable, changing over time, some of them evolving into new species.

In what sense, then, can modern evolutionary theory be seen as just a

quantitative addition to the earlier conception? In geology, to extend

this discussion, the surface of the Earth was also once thought to be

static; now we understand that the continents sit atop “tectonic plates”

that are continually in motion: moving apart from each other, sliding

past each other, colliding with each other, and “subducting,” one plate

being forced under another. As most people know, this is what causes

earthquakes and volcanoes. Can the modern theory accurately be

understood as a quantitative addition to earlier one? We can extend

these examples to virtually every other area of science. As a result,

Engels’ idea — that our scientific knowledge, which at any given moment

is relative, will, over time, ever more closely approach absolute truth

— cannot be reasonably sustained.

Second, Engels appears to vacillate between two distinct, and ultimately

incompatible, theories of knowledge (epistemologies), in one of which

our knowledge is limited, partial, or approximate (what he calls

“relative”), while in the other our knowledge is, or at least at some

point will be, absolute (what he calls “sovereign”). This is perhaps the

clearest reflection of the fact that, as I’ve insisted throughout this

book, Marxism is a form of Idealist philosophy that believes itself, and

claims to be, materialistic and scientific. But the two epistemologies

Engels embraces cannot be combined, even via the gymnastics of Marxian

(or Hegelian) dialectics. The two notions of truth come from two

distinct sources and mean qualitatively different things.

But with materialist and empiricist philosophies, this is not the case.

According to these philosophies, our knowledge is formed not simply

through abstract contemplation or reasoning, but primarily through the

impact of material particles and processes upon our bodies,

specifically, on those parts of our bodies that are responsible for

sensation and, through them, on our brains. And since the connection

between the outside world and our brains is so mediated and because our

sense organs, neurons, and brains, as material entities, are limited in

crucial ways, there is no way to be certain that the ideas which our

brains create out of our sensations (and from combining these with each

other and with whatever innate ideas our brains might contain) fully and

accurately reflect or represent the reality outside.

Marxism attempts to evade the conundrum by insisting that the proof of

the truth of our ideas is practice, specifically, our actual ability to

manipulate nature, to mold it to suit our purposes, and by its claim

that this practice, over an infinite amount of time, dialectically

resolves the contradiction between relative and absolute truth. But this

does not solve the problem. The fact that human beings can manipulate

nature suggests that our ideas about it have some validity (although

precisely what this means is not clear and is still controversial), but

it does not mean that our knowledge is or will ever be absolutely true.

Among other things, this is one of the things revealed by the history of

science. And there is no way, within a materialist or empiricist

framework, that we can get to absolute truth, even over an infinite

amount of time.

As this reveals, Marxism simultaneously holds to two contradictory

notions of truth. One is the claim that since our knowledge results from

praxis, human grasp of the truth can be only approximate. (This facet of

Marxian epistemology is very close to some versions of pragmatism, such

as John Dewey’s, [although Marxists usually deny this]: what is true is

what works, that is, what enables us to manipulate and transform

nature.) The other is the opposite claim that eventually, if humanity

lives long enough, our praxis will ultimately arrive at the absolute

truth. This facet of the Marxist theory of knowledge is a reflection of

the Idealist, specifically, Hegelian, origins of Marxism. In much the

same way as Hegel believed he had overcome Kant’s “antinomies,”

(reason’s unresolved debate over the fundamental questions of

philosophy), Marxism assumes that it has overcome the contradiction

between these two incompatible conceptions of the truth through a

dialectical synthesis. But like the other contradictions in the Marxian

world view, this is merely assumed and asserted but never proved. And,

as with those other aspects of Marxist theory, the ambiguity of Marxian

epistemology serves Marxism’s purposes. The explicit admission that our

knowledge is only approximate or relative gives the underlying Idealist

claim of Marxism, that it has discovered The Truth, a scientific cover.

But the fundamental claim of Marxism is that it has discovered, and in

fact embodies, the truth.

That the Idealist facet of Marxist epistemology is the fundamental

theory is suggested by the number of times Engels and Marx use the terms

“inevitable,” inexorable,” “necessary,” and “historical necessity”

throughout their writings. Although Engels explicitly states that

historical knowledge is relative (of all the fields of knowledge,

history is least able to claim that it has discovered absolute, eternal

truths), he never even tries to square this with his and Marx’s repeated

assertions that socialism is “inevitable” and that it will “necessarily”

occur through the dictatorship of the proletariat. In fact, throughout

Anti-Duhring itself, Engels uses the terms “inevitable,”

“inevitability,” or their equivalents repeatedly. For example (all

emphases mine — RT):

On page 33: “But what had to be done was to show this capitalist mode of

production on the one hand in its historical sequence and in its

inevitability for a definite period, and therefore also the

inevitability of its downfall....” On page 147, (nota bene that here

Engels is quoting Marx): “The capitalist mode of production and

appropriation, and hence capitalist private property, is the first

negation of individual private property founded on the labours of the

proprietor. But capitalist production begets, with the inexorability of

a law of Nature, its own negation. It is the negation of the negation.”

On page 165: “Modern capitalist production, on the contrary, which is

hardly three hundred years old and has only become predominant since the

introduction of large-scale industry, has in this short time brought

about contradictions in distribution — concentration of capital in a few

hands on the one side and concentration of the propertyless masses in

the big towns on the other — which must of necessity bring about its

downfall.”

On page 311: “To Herr Duhring, socialism in fact is not in any sense a

necessary product of historical development....” (In other words, Engels

thinks socialism is a “necessary product of historical development.”)

For those who believe that this is just the “positivist” Engels writing

this, it is worth remembering that this type of language occurs

throughout the works of both Marx and Engels, as well as in the material

they wrote in collaboration.

For example, in the Communist Manifesto, perhaps the fundamental

programmatic text of Marxism:

“What the bourgeoisie, therefore, produces, above all, is its own

gravediggers. Its fall and the victory of the proletariat are equally

inevitable.” [Manifesto of the Communist Party, in Lewis S. Feuer, ed.,

Marx and Engels: Basic Writings on Politics and Philosophy, Anchor

Books, Doubleday & Company, Inc., Garden City, New York, 1959, p. 20.]

And from Marx himself (in a passage I cited in Chapter V):

“And now as to myself, no credit is due me for discovering the existence

of classes in modern society or the struggle between them. Long before

me bourgeois historians had described the historical development of this

class struggle and bourgeois economists the economic anatomy of the

classes. What I did that was new to prove: 1) that the existence of

classes is only bound up with particular historical phases in the

development of production, 2) that the class struggle necessarily (my

emphasis; all other emphases in the original — RT) leads to the

dictatorship of the proletariat, that this dictatorship itself only

constitutes the transition to the abolition of all classes and to a

classless society. (Letter from Marx to J. Weydemeyer, March 5, 1852, in

Karl Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, International

Publishers, New York, 1963, p. 139.)

In fact, I know of only one place where Marx and Engels issue an

explicit caveat concerning their theory of historical inevitability.

This is also in the Manifesto:

“Free man and slave, patrician and plebian, lord and serf, guild master

and journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant

opposition to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now

open fight, a fight that each time ended either in a revolutionary

reconstitution of society at large or in the common ruin of the

contending classes.” [Manifesto of the Communist Party, ibid., p. 7.]

And note that this just refers to the past, not to the future.

Much later, during the First World War, Rosa Luxemburg, in her Junius

Pamphlet, introduced the expression “Socialism or Barbarism” into the

phrasebook of revolutionary Marxism, expressing her belief that either

the working class will overthrow capitalism and establish international

socialism or the world will be plunged into barbarism. This, too, is

often cited as proof that Marxists do not believe in historical

determinism. Yet, how can one weigh these two caveats [perhaps there a

few others] against the myriad references from the pens of the founders

of “scientific socialism” that say the exact opposite? (And if one were

to admit that socialism is not inevitable, what becomes of the Marxian

claim that its socialism, in contrast to others’, is “scientific?”)

That communism is inevitable is, and has always been, the fundamental

claim of Marxian “scientific socialism.” But if historical knowledge

(including the Marxian “materialist conception of history” ) is, as

Engels insists, relative and not absolute, on what grounds can he (or

Marx) assert the inevitability of anything historical? To say that

something is inevitable is to say that it must or has to happen, that

history cannot happen differently than it has, or is going to. Yet, this

is to base oneself on the grounds of absolute knowledge, for only if our

knowledge is absolute can we say that something is “inevitable.” If, on

the other hand, our knowledge is not absolute, if it is merely relative

or approximate, we have no grounds on which to assert the inevitability,

inexorability, or necessity of anything. We can, at best, assert that

something is probable, even highly probable, but we cannot assert that

it is inevitable or historically necessary. (Present-day science, even

physics, which Engels believed had discovered some “eternal truths”,

does not insist upon the inevitability of anything; at most, it asserts

that something is highly probable, even extremely probable. Yet, Marxism

has never actually demonstrated, let alone proved, that socialism is

even probable.)

Intriguingly, Engels seems not to be aware of the contradiction between

his (scientific) admission that knowledge, and particularly historical

knowledge, is relative, and his repeated (and Idealist) insistence that

socialism, to be achieved through a proletarian revolution and the

dictatorship of the proletariat, is inevitable. But recognition of this

contradiction is essential to understanding the historical, practical

results of Marxism.

MARXISM AND MORALITY

When looked at from the standpoint of morality, the history of the

Marxist/Communist movement presents a paradox. On the one hand,

individual Marxists, from its founders on, have often, even usually,

been motivated by the loftiest of ethical ideals. They have dedicated

their lives, sacrificed familial and material comforts, traditional

careers, and possible renown, and have often suffered exile,

imprisonment, and death, in their struggle to promote the interests of

the working class, to win the rights of women and oppressed minorities

and nationalities, and ultimately to win the liberation of all humanity.

On the other hand, when they have seized state power, Marxist

organizations, and the individual Marxists who have comprised them, have

established regimes that have been among the most brutal and oppressive

ever seen in history, governments that have trampled on the rights and

persons of the very people whom they previously championed. It has been

the purpose of this book to try to explain this.

In light of this paradox, Marxism, and Marxists, have often been accused

of being immoral, or at least amoral, since they reject traditional

morality and, supposedly, substitute for it the belief that the “ends

justify the means.” This charge rests on two foundations.

One is the fact that Marxism is openly (indeed, militantly) atheistic,

and as such, explicitly denies the validity of all traditional, that is,

religiously based, moral or ethical codes. To Marx, Engels, and the vast

majority of Marxists, ethics and morality flow out of and reflect

material conditions, specifically, the distinct socio-economic

formations, the modes of production, that humanity has created

throughout its history: ancient slave society, feudalism, the Asiatic

mode of production, capitalism. Each of these social formations

generates its own ethical or moral code, which is an essential part of

the “superstructure” and which hypostatises each socio-economic system

as eternal and God-ordained. These codes simultaneously justify and

defend the ruling classes’ right to rule by exalting as holy modes of

behavior that support, while condemning as evil modes of behavior that

threaten, the specific forms of society that generate them. Thus, for

Marxism, there is no absolutely true, eternal, God-given morality or

code of ethics. As evidence of this, Marxists point out that ruling

classes throughout history have flagrantly violated the very codes of

morality they have held up as God-given, in order to defend themselves

and the oppressive, exploitive societies over which they have ruled.

The other foundation of the charge that Marxism is immoral or amoral is

the palpable reality that Marxists have, during and after the

revolutions they have carried out, committed horrendous crimes — mass

incarcerations, in prisons and labor camps, mass executions, and mass

famines purposely or inadvertently caused by Marxist-inspired social

engineering (e.g., forced collectivization in the Soviet Union, the

“Great Leap Forward” in China), along with the crass lies, slanders, and

distortions characteristic of Communist propaganda.

Despite the fact that these two claims have some validity, the standard

accusation against Marxism is a considerable simplification and,

therefore, a distortion.

In the first place, as I suggested in an earlier chapter, Marxism,

despite its claims and its self-image, is in fact deeply grounded in the

fundamental tenets of the JudeoChristian tradition. The Marxist

conception of history — that history has a meaning, that it is

progressing toward a final goal, that this goal will be a state of

ultimate goodness (an Earthly paradise), that this will come about

through a cataclysmic transformation — is just a modern, secular version

of the messianic/apocalyptic visions of ancient Judaism and early

Christianity. Moreover, Marx and Engel were both obviously motivated by

the conviction that capitalism is a brutal and unjust social system, one

that condemns the majority of people to short lives of hard work and

suffering, while a tiny majority lives in extravagant luxury off the

fruits of others’ labor. Although Marx and Engels insisted that their

opposition to capitalism was based solely on their “scientific”

understanding that the capitalist system was historically obsolete and

destined to disappear, this does not explain their sense of outrage at

the injustices of the system. Their passion, which leaps out of almost

every page of their writings, speaks of their own grounding in

traditional notions of the moral worth and equality of all human beings

and the conceptions of right and wrong, justice and injustice, that flow

from this. Why else devote one’s whole life so fanatically to the cause

of socialism? Marx spent hours in the British Museum carrying out the

most exhaustive research on the nature of capitalism and the theories of

the economic thinkers who preceded him, while he and his family, whom he

loved, lived in poverty. One might criticize his choices (and his

conclusions), but his devotion to the cause was clearly based on a

fierce sense of justice, rather than a cool, detached interest in

investigating a neutral scientific fact. For his part, Engels passed a

significant period of his life managing his family’s textile business

(in other words, being a capitalist, which must have been distasteful to

him), while giving considerable amounts of money to the Marx family over

many years so that his friend and comrade could continue his research

and writing. Thus, although Marx and Engels would have vehemently denied

it, both their personalities and their politics were deeply grounded in

traditional, in this case, Judeo-Christian, ethics and morality.

In the second place, while it is certainly true that Marx and Engels,

and most Marxists after them, believed that, at least to some extent,

the “end justifies to means,” this is not the unambiguous moral

indictment that it is often assumed to be. The reality is that most

people (except perhaps saints) believe, on some level and at some times

and in some places, that the ends do in fact justify the means. We could

not live in the world as it is if we didn’t. Most of us believe that it

is wrong to lie, yet most of us do it, quite probably, rather often. If

a good friend (or perhaps a spouse or companion) approaches us with a

new set of clothes or a new haircut and asks us, “How do I look?”, most

of us will tell him/her that he/she looks fine, even if we believe the

outfit or haircut is not particularly flattering. How many of us have

worked under bosses or supervisors we have not cared for (or even

positively detested), yet have refrained from articulating how we felt

about them (let alone cussing them out)? And at a meeting at which a

boss or supervisor argues for a proposal that we think is poor, even

stupid, do we always express our opinion clearly and forthrightly? No,

not if we want to keep our jobs. In each of these cases, and in many

more like them, when we act this way, we are acting under the dictum

that the “end justifies the means.” It is worth telling a “white lie”

rather than unnecessarily hurting the feelings of, and complicating our

relationship with, someone we care about. Likewise, it is not worth

losing one’s job to be absolutely forthright with a boss. And this is

not to mention circumstances in which we have good reasons to believe

that much more is at stake. For example, most of us, except absolute

pacifists, accept the notion that when we are assaulted and threatened

with physical injury and possible death, we are justified in responding

with counter-violence, even to the extent of killing the attacker, in

order to defend ourselves. In other words, in some circumstances,

killing is justified. The end — saving your life — justifies the means —

killing another human being.

For individuals who have authority or power — economic, political,

legal, bureaucratic — in our society, the stakes become higher than for

those at the bottom of the hierarchy. Capitalist politicians, even those

that are relatively honest, uncorrupt, and concerned about the interests

of their constituents and their country, will lie, evade, cheat, and

steal, if they deem it necessary, whether to get elected or re-elected,

to get a law passed, or to carry out some policy they feel is important.

Looking at the top of the US political hierarchy, we can note many

examples. Abraham Lincoln, by most accounts a decent human being,

plunged the United States into, and presided over, the largest mass

slaughter in the country’s history, because he thought it was in the

interests of the nation and of humanity as a whole to do so. During

World War II, Franklin D. Roosevelt approved the fire bombings of

Dresden, Hamburg, and other German cities, actions that resulted in the

cruel deaths and burning of thousands of civilians, because he thought

it was necessary to win the war against the Nazis. In his opinion, the

end — winning the war and saving perhaps a greater number of lives down

the road — justified the means, which were, in fact, violations of the

Geneva Conventions, attacks on unarmed non-combatants, in other words,

war crimes. Likewise, when Harry Truman decided to drop atomic bombs on

Hiroshima and Nagasaki, he was operating under the same dictum. Similar

choices, not usually so dire, confront virtually every individual in a

position of authority or power over other people. The CEOs of powerful

corporations allow or encourage their outfits to pollute the

environment, resulting in illness and/or death for many people, in the

interests of profitability. They also lay off people and close entire

plants with the same end in mind or merely to raise the price of their

companies’ stocks. Heads of national intelligence agencies direct their

underlings to torture and murder in order to defend “national security.”

As these examples suggest, such individuals, and, in fact, most of us,

make decisions based, whether we like it or not, on the notion that the

“end justifies the means.” The nature of the end — how important it is,

what is at stake, e.g., how many lives may be saved — helps to determine

what means we are willing to consider under the concrete circumstances

in which we find ourselves. In the case of Lincoln, Roosevelt, and

Truman, in each situation, the stakes were deemed to be so high, the

ends were seen as so important, that extraordinary means, in these

situations, actions involving the deaths of tens of thousands of people,

were justified, even required. So, in this sense, Marxists are no

different from anybody else.

But Marxists do differ from most non-Marxists in how they approach their

moral/ethical decisions, and this in several ways. Probably most

important, for Marxists, the stakes, the “ends,” are almost always set

at the highest level. From their point of view, what is at issue in

many, if not most, of their actions is the fate of humanity. After all,

they believe their goal, socialism/communism, the end for which they are

fighting, ultimately entails the liberation of the entire human species,

human freedom. When the stakes are believed to be as high as this, means

that would otherwise be considered immoral, for example, measures that

might result in the deaths of thousands, even millions, of innocent

people, become acceptable. What are the deaths of a few (tens, hundreds,

thousands, hundreds of thousands, millions?) individuals when the fate

of all humanity is at stake?

Secondly, because Marxists believe that the road to human freedom

involves violent social transformations, when they have come to power,

they have usually done so in circumstances under which society, as it

normally is, has broken down, including and in particular, its norms of

ordinary, moral human behavior, what might be called “common decency.”

When the Bolsheviks seized state power in October 1917, they did so

after more than three years of the most frightful slaughter, when

millions of workers, peasants, and middle class people, on both sides of

the conflict, soldiers and civilians alike, were killed or maimed or

died of starvation or illness. So, when the Bolsheviks resorted to

brutal, repressive measures to consolidate their rule, they were not

inventing extreme violence. They were merely acting in the context of

the general breakdown of social norms that had been caused, as they saw

it, by the very social system they were attempting to overthrow. It is

also worth remembering that for Marxists (and not only for Marxists),

normal, supposedly peaceful society is itself founded on cruelty and

violence, such as that perpetrated daily by the state and its agencies

on the exploited and oppressed classes, particularly on those

individuals and groups who dare to resist, along with the poverty and

oppression, hunger and outright starvation that the millions of people

at the bottom of international capitalist society experience. In this

context, Marxists’ commitment to cruel and violent means does not

appear, at least to them, to be very extreme at all.

Beyond this, revolutionary Marxists are more prone to resorting to

violent and coercive means because of the very content of their theory,

the fundamental tenets of Marxism.

(1) Most obvious of these is Marxists’ commitment to the use of the

state as the main social instrument by which to implement their program.

As we have seen, they call this state the “dictatorship of the

proletariat” and claim that it is truly democratic, that it is the

“proletariat organized as the ruling class,” a “state that is in the

process of becoming a non-state,” a state that it is “withering away.”

But, it is crucial to remember, it is still a state, the most powerful

instrument of social coercion ever created by human beings. By the

state’s very nature, almost everything involving it is going to entail

mass coercion. And since, from the Marxist standpoint, the essence of

the state, as an institution, is violence and its fundamental role

repressive, the essence of the dictatorship of the proletariat, too, is

violence, while its social role and ultimate purpose likewise is

repressive. In addition, Marxists describe this state as a revolutionary

dictatorship, a state that is established in the course of a revolution

and one that is not bound by ordinary, peace-time norms and procedures

of legality and justice; in other words, such a state (for example, the

French state under the Jacobins during the French Revolution) takes

whatever steps it deems necessary to secure victory. To make matters

worse, this supposedly proletarian state is one that has taken over, or

aims to take over, all of the means of production, all of the economic

apparatus of society, or as much of it as is feasible at any given time.

This renders this particular state extraordinarily powerful, since it is

faced with no, or at least very few, countervailing institutions that

might serve to limit its power. Finally, as I argued in the chapter on

the question, the very notion of a dictatorship of the proletariat, in

the sense of a centralized state run directly and democratically by the

entire or even by the majority of the proletariat, is a contradiction in

terms and impossible to achieve. When, during the course of a

revolution, Marxist revolutionaries establish what they believe to be

the dictatorship of the proletariat, what they actually create is a

dictatorship of revolutionaries (and other individuals) over the

proletariat that claims to act in the proletariat’s name and interests.

So, here we have an extraordinarily powerful state, unfettered by

countervailing institutions and not bound by ordinary norms of law and

justice, whose fundamental role is repression. Is it any wonder that,

based on such a theory, Marxists have created, not “dictatorships of the

proletariat,” but monstrous Jacobin-style dictatorships, armed with the

advanced technology of their day.

(2) An additional facet of Marxian theory that renders Marxists prone to

extremely violent means is their version of dialectics, particularly

their understanding of the nature of contradiction. Since, according to

Marxism, all reality, including history, develops through contradiction,

freedom is to be brought about through un-freedom, through coercion; in

fact, it can be brought about only through coercion. In contrast to

Idealist conceptions of dialectics (such as Hegel’s), for Marxists, when

it comes to the class struggle, there is no synthesis; the end result,

logically speaking, of the struggle between social classes is not a

synthesis of the opposing classes, some sort of creative amalgamation of

the two contending classes that preserves what is positive in both. On

the contrary, the logical conclusion of the class struggle, the point

toward which the class struggle in any given historical epoch tends, is

the complete annihilation of one of the contending classes. In the

context of the proletarian revolution, therefore, one of the

proletariat’s main goals must be the complete and total destruction of

the old, reactionary ruling classes, and the more thoroughly those

classes and their agents and followers are eliminated, the more certain

and more secure will be the victory of socialism/communism, the realm of

freedom. When this is combined with the Marxian commitment to the use of

a dictatorial state, the logic of Marxism is to impel Marxists, when

they do gain control of a state, toward an ever-intensifying escalation

of state-sponsored violence against all social forces that are perceived

to be the enemies of the proletariat, aiming toward their complete

social, and even physical, annihilation. According to the Marxist

version of dialectics, then, the new world of socialism — a realm of

peace, freedom, equality, cooperation, comradely affection (dare I say

“love”?) — is to be established through methods that entail the very

opposite of these values: violence, coercion, hierarchy, and (class)

hatred.

(3) Marxists’ conscious rejection of traditional, religiouslybased,

moral/ethical codes also contributes to their willingness to utilize and

justify brutal and dishonest methods. It does so because it means they

are less likely to have, or at least to articulate and act upon, second

thoughts or scruples about engaging in what most people would consider

to be morally questionable acts. In fact, the case is rather to the

contrary. To put it differently, a commitment to Marxist theory usually

entails attempts on the part of Marxists, certainly those who have

seized state power, to suppress their moral consciences, to repress

their feelings of distaste, disgust, or even horror over the

consequences of their actions, since these consciences and feelings are

perceived to be products of their “bourgeois” upbringings, legacies of a

corrupt and decadent capitalist society, which are bound to be

eliminated and supplanted by the superior morality of communism. As a

result, particularly in a hierarchical setting, such as a Leninist-style

party, there will likely — indeed, almost inevitably — be extreme social

pressure directed against those who question the wisdom or morality of

using brutal, violent, and dishonest tactics. Such individuals will be

accused of being insufficiently liberated from traditional religious

beliefs and bourgeois social conventions (“soft”, “weak-kneed”,

suffering from “bourgeois sentimentalism”), if not downright

counterrevolutionary, and will tend to be marginalized within the party,

if not actually victimized by state repression. Since, according to

Marxism, the victory of the proletarian revolution requires coercion —

violence and repression — the logic of the theory is for Marxists to

strive to inure themselves against — that is, to try to suppress, their

moral compunctions about, even revulsion over — the violent, often

gruesome, acts they commit. The other side of this process is that it

tends to bring to the fore, within the Marxist party and the state,

those individuals who are most adept at doing this. Even more, once they

have gained power, Marxist organizations tend to attract to their side

and promote, particularly in the ranks of the police apparatuses,

individuals who have very poorly developed moral consciences or even no

moral consciences at all, in other words, extremely brutalized

individuals and outright sociopaths (such as Stalin and Beria).

(4) Marxists’ belief in historical necessity and in the progressive,

immanent logic of history leads them to believe, as did Hegel, that

everything that has happened in history, no matter how horrible, has

been necessary and therefore justified. Engels, for example, justified

the establishment of ancient slavery as progressive, in part because he

believed it to be a necessary and inevitable step in a history that will

eventually lead to human freedom. Hegel said it: What is real is

rational, and what is rational is real. With this belief, anything that

happens — no matter how brutal or barbaric it may be — that can be

convincingly explained by Marxist theory as promoting or representing

the historic process can be rationalized and justified as “progressive.”

Thus, Stalin’s policy of forced collectivization and the mass starvation

it caused and the vast purges he carried out in the Soviet Union in the

late 1920s and 1930s that resulted in the imprisonment and deaths of

millions of people, can be, and were, justified as “historically

necessary” steps leading to the full victory of socialism. Mao’s “Great

Leap Forward”, a policy that also led to widespread famine and the

deaths of many millions, was justified on the same basis, as was the

very violent “Cultural Revolution” of the 1960s.

(5) Marxists’ conviction that morality is a purely historic product and

that it can never be higher than the specific historical stage in which

humanity finds itself at any given time encourages them to denigrate

morality and ethical norms in general, seeing them primarily as aspects

of the political and ideological superstructures of exploitive societies

and, more narrowly, as religious myths designed to maintain subjugated

classes in their subordinate positions. In Anti-Duhring, for example,

Engels argues that the notion of human equality, and hence ideas of

justice and injustice, arose only during the epoch of feudalism,

nurtured among and eventually championed by the nascent bourgeoisie. In

contrast to this view, however, recent scientific discoveries suggest

that crucial aspects of our moral and ethical ideals, including our

ideas of justice and injustice, are, in fact, deeply grounded in human

biology, essential parts of our evolved human nature: human beings, and

it appears, other mammals, have a hard-wired moral sense, an intuitive

conception of justice and fair play, and therefore, some notion of moral

equality. If this is so, then many of the ideals and norms embodied in

ancient religious traditions, such as the Ten Commandments and the

Golden Rule, are not just tricks on the part of ruling elites to

inculcate thoughts and behavior that serve to sustain their rule, but

represent, however crudely and mechanically, something very basic to our

(biologically-evolved) human nature. It is certainly true that moral and

ethical codes are historically conditioned, that they adapt themselves

and make themselves appropriate to specific forms of society. It is also

true that they have been utilized by ruling elites to justify and

sustain their own rule. But these moral/ethical codes and norms have

been something more than merely passive reflections of the class

structures of particularly societies and ideological weapons in the

hands of specific ruling classes; they represent more than simple

apologia for those societies. These codes and norms have also contained

norms for criticizing these societies on moral and ethical grounds,

which is why they have periodically lent themselves to radical and even

revolutionary purposes. In fact, human morality appears to have a

history, an underlying tendency to evolve, that is independent of the

specific modes of production through which human society has evolved.

This history entails the gradual enlargement of the realm of the

mandated application of the moral norms (the ideas of justice and fair

play) to ever wider circles of the human species, from family to clan,

to tribe, to region, to race, to gender, to nation, and (hopefully) to

all of humanity. But Marxism does not see this. Failing to recognize the

deep-seated foundation of our moral sense, and hence of our traditional

moral and ethical codes, the Marxian conception of morality and ethics

leads Marxists to denigrate those traditional moral strictures and both

facilitates and justifies their willingness to use methods that violate

them.

(6) Marxism’s underlying but unconscious Idealism, its belief that

categories and other abstractions, such as social classes, are what is

ultimately real, often leads them to devalue concrete individual human

beings and to subordinate them to the “higher” needs of the class

struggle. For example, the working class, the proletariat, is more

important than individual workers, who can and should be sacrificed —

exiled, jailed, or executed — if the necessities of the class struggle

and the revolution, as the Marxists judge them, demand it. Even more,

members of non-proletarian social classes, such as peasants, small

business people, artisans, artists, professionals, and intellectuals,

tend to be defined and judged by Marxists primarily by their

(non-proletarian) class position and only secondarily by their concrete

attitudes and behavior. Thus, unless they are members of the Marxist

revolutionary party, they are usually conceived to be intrinsically less

important — less valuable as human beings — than members of the working

class and therefore much more readily “expendable,” that is, subject to

repressive measures, including physical elimination.

(7) Finally, Marxists’ belief in the truth of their theory, their

(nearly absolute) conviction that Marxism is right, underlies and

reinforces their willingness to resort to extremely violent and brutal

methods. Individuals who fervently believe that their theory is

absolutely (or nearly absolutely) correct, that this theory obliges them

to utilize state-sponsored violence against entire social classes, and

that the outcome of their theory-inspired actions is the liberation of

the human species are likely to be far more willing to be brutal than

those who have strong doubts about their world view. Although Marx wrote

that his personal credo was “Doubt Everything,” this doubt is not an

intrinsic part of his system; much like Descartes’ “methodological

doubt,” it is not logically integrated into the theory. On the contrary,

it is a methodological stricture that is necessarily external to the

resultant theoretical conception. Specifically, it is a crucial tool in

the philosopher’s search for absolute truth, for certainty, the very

opposite of doubt. And it is the certainty, not the doubt, that becomes

an essential aspect of the theory/ideology and that gets conveyed to the

disciples. Whatever doubts Marx and Engels may have entertained about

their worldview, they certainly did not discuss them publicly. As a

result, what got communicated, and what continues to get communicated,

is the sense of absolute conviction, the “scientific” certainty, that

their theory is true, that socialism is inevitable and that it must be,

and can only be, achieved through the dictatorship of the proletariat.

And this is what is picked up, embraced, and aggressively propagated by

the vast majority of Marxists. To Marxists, they, and only they,

understand the nature and direction of history. They, and only they,

represent — in fact, embody — the historic consciousness of the working

class, whatever the workers may think at any given time. When they act,

in other words, they represent history. It is likely, however, that for

many, if not most, Marxists, their doubts about the validity of their

theory are not totally suppressed; such doubts probably still exist in

the form of a kernel, a gnawing worm, somewhere deep in their minds. But

as long as they remain Marxists, this sentiment, if anything, serves to

reinforce their fervor, as they struggle privately to suppress their

doubt. In this sense of (near )certainty (along with the dialectic of

certainty versus doubt) about the correctness and righteousness of their

cause, Marxists are merely continuing in the tradition of religious

fanatics throughout the millennia, whether they have been Jewish,

Christian, Hindu, Moslem or the followers of any other religion. The

main difference between explicitly religious fanatics and Marxists is,

obviously, that Marxists claim to be atheists; but they embrace their

atheism and their dogma with the same fervor, and via the same dynamic,

as religious fanatics hold to their beliefs. And like so many religious

fanatics, in the past and in the present, and for the same reasons, they

have been willing to utilize, justify, and excuse, the most brutal and

barbaric means to reach their (holy) goals.

DETERMINISM AND FREEDOM

The explicit goal of Marxism, what Marxists claim to be fighting for, is

human freedom. Marx and Engels believed that communism, to be achieved

through a proletarian revolution and the establishment of the

dictatorship of the proletariat, would be a truly free society. This is

in contrast to capitalism, under which individual human beings are free

in only a formal, legal sense (that is, they are neither slaves nor

serfs), while they remain subject to exploitation by the capitalists, to

the destructive effects of the dynamics of capitalist production and

particularly of capitalist crises, and to the overall domination of the

forces of production which they themselves have produced. Under

communism, the former proletarians will be free substantially. They will

be the “associated producers,” who, because of their classless and

collective organization and their control over the means of production

and society as a whole, will no longer be exploited and will no longer

be the victims of the blind, inexorable workings of the laws of

capitalism (and of nature). Instead, they will subject these laws and

the forces of production to their conscious control, manage society

collectively and democratically through a conscious plan, and via these

means, overcome relative scarcity, shorten the workday, end the

subjection of the individual to the division of labor, and usher in the

realm of true freedom.

“In making itself the master of all the means of production, in order to

use them in accordance with a social plan, society puts an end to the

former subjection of men to their own means of production. It goes

without saying that society cannot itself be free unless every

individual is free. The old mode of production must therefore be

revolutionised from top to bottom, and in particular the former division

of labor must disappear. Its place must be taken by an organization of

production in which, on the one hand, no individual can put on to other

persons his share in productive labor, this natural condition of human

existence; and in which on the other hand, productive labor, instead of

being a means to the subjection of men, will become a means to their

emancipation, by giving each individual the opportunity to develop and

exercise all his faculties, physical and mental, in all directions; in

which, therefore, productive labor will become a pleasure instead of a

burden.”(Engels, Anti-Duhring, op. cit., p. 320.)

“The seizure of the means of production by society puts an end to

commodity production, and therewith to the domination of the product

over the producer. Anarchy in social production is replaced by conscious

organisation on a planned basis. The struggle for individual existence

comes to an end. And at this point, in a certain sense, man finally cuts

himself off from the animal world, leaves the conditions of animal

existence behind him and enters conditions which are truly human. The

conditions of existence forming man’s environment, which up to now have

dominated man, at this point pass under the dominion and control of man,

who now for the first time becomes the real conscious control of Nature,

because and insofar as he has become master of his own social

organisation. The laws of his own social activity, which have hitherto

confronted him as external, dominating laws of Nature, will then be

applied by man with complete understanding, and hence will be dominated

by man. Men’s own social organisation which has hitherto stood in

opposition to them as if arbitrarily decreed by Nature and history, will

then become the voluntary act of men themselves. The objective, external

forces which have hitherto dominated history, will then pass under the

control of men themselves. It is only from this point that men, with

full consciousness, will fashion their own history; it is only from this

point that the social causes set in motion by men will have,

predominantly and in constantly increasing measure, the effects willed

by men. It is humanity’s leap from the realm of necessity into the realm

of freedom.” (Engels, Anti-Duhring, ibid., pp. 309–310.)

Despite this apparently libertarian vision, Marxists, where they have

had the opportunity to implement their program, have not created free

societies or even societies moving toward freedom. Instead, they have

created social systems that have been among the most brutal and

tyrannical of any seen in history. This, I believe, is not an accident.

Although a variety of factors contributed to these outcomes, a crucial

responsibility for these results lies with Marxists themselves,

specifically, with the actions they have taken and the policies they

have pursued upon their victories in social revolutions. And central to

the motivation behind these actions has been Marxist theory, the

consciously-held views of Marxists, along with the logical implications

of these views, of which Marxists have not always been aware. Throughout

this book, I have attempted to trace some of the totalitarian

implications of Marxist theory. Here I would like to focus on the

Marxian theory of freedom.

In Anti-Duhring, Engels explains his conception:

“Hegel was the first to state correctly the relation between freedom and

necessity. To him, freedom is the appreciation of necessity. “Necessity

is blind only in so far as it is not understood.” Freedom does not

consist in the dream of independence of natural laws, but in the

knowledge of these laws, and in the possibility this gives of

systematically making them work toward definite ends. This holds good in

relation both to the laws of external nature and to those which govern

the bodily and mental existence of men themselves — two classes of laws

which we can separate from each other at most only in thought but not in

reality. Freedom of the will therefore means nothing but the capacity to

make decisions with real knowledge of the subject. Therefore the freer a

man’s judgment is in relation to a definite question, with so much

greater necessity is the content of this judgment determined; while the

uncertainty, founded on ignorance, which seems to make an arbitrary

choice among many different and conflicting possible decisions, shows by

this precisely that it is not free, that it is controlled by the very

object it should itself control. Freedom therefore consists in control

over ourselves and over external nature which is founded on knowledge of

natural necessity; it is therefore a product of historical development.”

(Engels, Anti-Duhring, ibid., p. 125.)

It is in passages such as these that the Hegelian nature of Marxism is

perhaps most clearly revealed. Hegel did not believe in freedom in the

commonly-accepted meaning of the term. To him, history is the working

out of an immanent logic that has existed eternally in the mind

(actually, as the mind) of God. All that happens, everything that

everybody does, every thought that every individual human and humanity

as a whole has had or will have, reflects the working out of that logic.

In the Hegelian view, in other words, history is determined and

“necessary,” everything that happens is ordained. Conversely, there is

no contingency, no chance; that some things appear to be contingent or

the result of chance merely reflects our inability to recognize the

(dialectical) chain of causation that has led (in fact, inexorably) to

the apparently chance event. As a result, freedom, as Hegel defines it,

is the conscious recognition, the conscious understanding, appreciation,

of that necessity or logic; it is having one’s mind in conscious

conformity with God’s. To Hegel, an apparent “refusal” to align one’s

consciousness with that of God is not freedom; it is, in fact, ordained,

determined, a reflection of the dialectical “cunning of reason.” As a

result, for Hegel, there is no freedom, in the sense that most people

understand the word.

As Engels’ remarks suggest, he — and Marx — shared this conception of

freedom. In the Marxist view, all of reality, natural and social,

develops according to natural and social laws. These laws are not just

representations — analogies or models — in the human mind of the way the

world might work, but are structures that actually inhere in the natural

and social/historical worlds and determine what happens. This is why

Marx and Engels’ writings abound with references to “inevitability,”

“inexorability,” and “necessity.” And this is why they called their

conception of socialism “scientific”; they believed they had discovered

the historical logic that will make the overthrow of capitalism and its

replacement by socialism/communism (through the dictatorship of the

proletariat) inevitable. As in the Hegelian world view, in Marxism,

there is no freedom to resist the historic process. Both support for and

resistance to the cause of the proletariat are determined, along with

the illusion that this is a matter of choice (remember, “social being

determines social consciousness”). Both “choices” represent the concrete

working out of the (Marxian) dialectic of the class struggle. In sum,

rather than believing in freedom, as most people conceive of it, Marx

and Engels, like Hegel, were determinists.

There are many versions of determinism. One, held by the ancient Greeks,

sees the world and human beings as being ruled by an overarching,

external Destiny or Fate. To be subject to this Fate can be likened to

being in an invisible cage that determines the outcome of events,

including the lives of individuals, regardless of people’s subjective

intentions. This conception of determinism can be clearly seen in

Sophocles’ drama, Oedipus Rex. At the beginning of the play, we will

remember, an oracle foresees that Oedipus will kill his father and marry

his mother. And this is what happens at the end of the story, although

this was never Oedipus’s conscious intent; circumstances, abetted by

ignorance, virtually impel Oedipus to carry out these heinous crimes. In

this variant of determinism, Fate is external, working apart from, and

even against, individuals’ conscious wills. The great Russian writer,

Leo Tolstoy, had a similar conception, which is elaborated at some

length toward the end of his epic novel, War and Peace. To Tolstoy,

history is like a massive river that sweeps up everybody and everything

in its mighty flow, regardless of individual wills. Based on this

conception, Tolstoy saw the “great men” of history, such as Napoleon and

the Russian general Kutuzov, as being less, not more, free than the rank

and file soldiers in the French and Russian armies.

In partial contrast to this view are those that see the determinist

logic working through the wills of individuals, not against them. Thus,

for Hegel, the dialectical logic of history determines the consciousness

and the individual wills, the conscious intentions, of all the

participants, even though, consistent with the dialectic, these wills

often and even usually appear to be at cross purposes to each other and

even counterposed to the direction of history. In this way, the logic of

history, what Hegel called the “cunning of reason,” does its work,

operating through the wills of the historical participants, including

and in particular (at least for Hegel) those of history’s “great men.”

The Dutch-Jewish philosopher, Baruch/Benedict Spinoza, whom Hegel

consistently praises, held to a similar, though non-dialectical,

standpoint. He argued that if a stone that has been thrown through the

air were conscious, it would believe that it was being propelled by its

own free will. For these determinists, the laws of history do not

eliminate freedom but are, in some sense, responsible for it. Freedom is

being aware of, and consciously willing, the course of history; freedom

is having one’s conscious will in line with the laws of nature and of

history. Hence, for these thinkers, freedom is the recognition (or

appreciation) of necessity.

(There is yet another variant of determinism that is worth noting at

this point, something that might be called “structural determinism.”

This is the belief that the large-scale structures of any process [I am

thinking here primarily of social, economic, and historical processes]

are determined, but that within the bounds of these structures, specific

events and the consciousness of individuals are not fully determined.

Engels seems to approach this standpoint when he writes that “in the

long run” or “in the last analysis” the material structures of social

life determine human consciousness.)

Now, the question of determinism is, like many of the other questions

addressed in this and the previous chapter, one of those that have been

discussed by philosophers for over twentyfive hundred years, and it has

never been resolved. Is everything in nature and human life determined?

Has everything that has happened been inevitable — did it have to happen

just when, where, and how it did — or might it have happened

differently? Are all facets of reality determined, some of them, or none

of them? Nobody knows the answers to these questions, and there has

never been agreement, among philosophers and others who have concerned

themselves with the issue, about the answers.

At the time Marx and Engels wrote, however, it appeared as if science

had, in fact, answered the questions. In the 19^(th) century, scientists

were making (and had been making since the mid 16^(th) century)

discoveries that seemed to confirm the view that everything that happens

in the apparently material world happens of necessity, occurs

inevitably; that all physical events are connected in one vast chain of

causation that cannot be broken and that leaves no room for chance. (The

fact that during this period, scientific knowledge did appear to be

additive; that scientists were increasingly discovering what appeared to

be absolute, empirically verified truths about nature, seemed to confirm

this belief.) Marx and Engels (along with many other 19^(th) and early

20^(th) century champions of science, including leading figures in the

anarchist tradition), accepted this view and believed they had extended

it, via their materialist conception of history, to the social realm,

the realm of human society and its history.

But, as we’ve seen, more recent developments in science have rendered

this conclusion doubtful. While in much of the macro world of physics

(especially those phenomena addressed by the theory of relativity),

events seem to be determined, in the subatomic dimension, this appears

not to be the case. In that world, according to most interpretations of

quantum physics, events are not understood to be determined but are

deemed to be more or less probable. (In other words, there is no

inevitability, no inexorability, no necessity.) Moreover, this is not a

result of the insufficiency of our knowledge but reflects the very

nature of reality itself. In addition to these two realms, there are

areas that lie, in a sense, between them in which the question of

determinism/inevitability vs. probability is undecided. For example,

recent discoveries have suggested that the uncertainties of the quantum

world express themselves on the molecular level, including in the

behavior of relatively large molecules, such as DNA and RNA, and even on

the level of entire organisms. If these findings are confirmed, it will

mean that some of the realms of chemistry and molecular biology are

also, like the world of sub-atomic particles, probabilistic, rather than

determined, in character. If the seemingly random mutations of genetic

material that are responsible for evolution are truly random, then

biological evolution, too, is indeterminate. Then there are the areas of

scientific investigation in which the phenomena involved are now

conceived to be determined but in which the theories and conceptions we

use to understand and explain them are statistical and only give results

in terms of probabilities. Thus, while in theory, the processes involved

in creating our weather, as phenomena of the macro world, are thought to

be determined, in practice, our ability to predict the weather is

limited; meteorologists cannot give us certainties but only

probabilities, and these get ever lower as the time frame is lengthened.

Is this merely the result of our limited knowledge, or are the phenomena

of the weather actually indeterminate? Similarly with certain processes

studied by geologists, such as earthquakes and volcanic eruptions; while

they may be fully determined, we are currently unable to make precise

predictions about when and where these events will occur. In like

manner, the laws of thermodynamics and the scientific laws that describe

the behavior of gases are not absolute but statistical and therefore

probabilistic in their conclusions. Are these realms determined or is

contingency at work? We really don’t know. So, what we see when we

peruse the different realms of science is a patch-work of theories, some

of whose implicit philosophical implications are inconsistent with

others.

There are various possibilities here. One is that all of natural reality

(including the subatomic realm) is determined; it is only limitations of

our knowledge and/or of our brains that prevent us from seeing this and

from making accurate predictions. (This was Albert Einstein’s position.)

Another is that some aspects of reality (e.g., the realm of relativity)

are determined, while others (e.g., the subatomic realm) are not. (This

is the practical standpoint of perhaps most working physicists today.)

Still another is the conception that all of natural reality is

probabilistic (like the subatomic world), but this is not (yet)

accurately grasped in scientific theory. This is why some scientists do

not believe the theory of relativity, which is deterministic, is truly

correct and are searching for a theory of “quantum gravity.” Finally, it

might be the case that the different realms of reality lie on a kind of

spectrum; in some realms, everything is determined, while in others,

there may be more or less space for contingency.

The problem is even more complicated when we look at the social world,

in which what are commonly called the “social sciences” have made very

little progress in developing theories that can accurately predict human

behavior and/or historical development. Aside from the problem of

multiple causation there are so many factors at work in any given social

or historical situation that it is virtually impossible to predict

outcomes — the question is made much more difficult by the fact that

humans have a definite subjective sense of freedom or nondeterminism. We

believe we are free. While it is possible that all of our actions and

all of our thoughts (including this sense of free will) are, in fact,

fully determined — that is, that they are the inevitable and inexorable

result of who we are genetically, along with how we’ve been shaped by

our environment and by our own actions — we certainly do not feel that

this is the case. We believe that at any given moment, we are capable of

deciding to do one thing rather than another, to turn left instead of

right, to eat the sweet, fatty ice cream we know we shouldn’t or to

forego it, to do the chore that’s on our “to do” list or to be lazy and

leave it for another day. Perhaps all of our conscious decisions are

strictly determined but we just don’t realize this. Obviously, our

choices are not totally undetermined. We are, for example, limited by

the nature of our bodies and, more broadly, by the physical “laws of

nature”: we cannot fly, run faster than a certain speed, breathe under

water, go without water and food for more than a few days or weeks, live

forever, etc. We are also hemmed in by the social world in which we live

— we need to go to work (or have an alternate source of income), we

cannot do certain things with impunity, and are otherwise limited by

decisions we have made and the other circumstances in our lives, e.g.,

how much education we have received and the kinds of skills we possess,

where we live, our immediate social arrangements, whether we are

married, have children. But within these strictures, we do feel that we

have real freedom to make choices. Among other things, this belief

stands behind our conceptions of ethics and morality; we believe people

have a choice about whether to do right or wrong, good or evil, and that

they therefore both can and should be held responsible for their acts.

Does this subjective sense of freedom reflect reality or is it just an

illusion? Do we really have free will, and if so, how much, or are our

wills completely determined?

There are some modern theorists who argue that our sense of freedom, our

belief in “freedom of the will,” is an illusion. This is the thesis of

The Illusion of Conscious Will, by Daniel M. Wegner (The MIT Press,

Cambridge, Massachusetts, London, England, 2002). Basing himself on

research that shows that when we make a conscious decision to, say, lift

a finger, the neurological processes that result in raising that finger

begin measurably before¬ we are conscious of making the decision to

raise the finger, Wegner denies that we have freedom of the will.

Instead, he argues that our conscious will does not determine our

decision but is itself a result of other processes that have, in fact,

made us lift the finger. As Wegner interprets these experiments, then,

consciousness is an epiphenomenon, a surface reflection of some other

processes and not in itself determinant. As a result, to him, our sense

of conscious will is an illusion; we believe we have consciously decided

to lift our finger and that this is what caused our finger to go up,

but, in fact, some other, e.g., neurological, process really made us do

so and then created the subjective sense that we have made the decision.

It is worth noting, however, that Wegner’s interpretation of the

research upon which he bases his conclusion is not universally accepted

within the field. (Significantly, the man who carried out the

experiments did not agree with it. [See Benjamin Libet, “Do We Have Free

Will?,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, No. 8–9, 1999, pp. 47–57.])

Moreover, there is plenty of research that suggests that consciousness

is, in fact, essential to much of our decision-making and behavior.

Lastly, if conscious will is an illusion, as Wegner contends, why did it

arise? Why do we have the sense that our conscious decisions determine

(at least some of) our actions? Evolutionary theory would imply that

consciousness, and therefore our ability to make decisions, is adaptive,

enabling species that are conscious, or more conscious than others, to

survive better in environments that are changing, challenging, and

ultimately hostile. But if conscious decision-making is an illusion, it

seems like a tremendously costly and wasteful (caloricallyspeaking) one

that the process of evolution would have quickly eliminated as a dead

end.

I do not propose to try to answer the question of

determinism/contingency here. In fact, I don’t think it can be answered,

at least not given the present state of our knowledge. And it may well

be one of those questions that never will get answered, one of the great

mysteries of our existence that will be pondered for as long as human

beings survive. Although some people may find this worrisome or even

frightening, it need not be so, because it would then mean that freedom,

in the sense that most people understand it, is at least possible. And

if it is, it will mean that we, both as individuals and as a species,

may have the power to control our fates and are not condemned to be

merely passive and ultimately deluded products and objects of fully

determinate scientific “laws.”

But leaving this question aside, I wish to return to a point I made in

an earlier chapter. This is that what one believes will have an impact

on what one does, that is, how one behaves, how one acts in the world.

Specifically, people who do not believe that freedom (in the commonly

accepted meaning of the term) truly exists, will not, should they be in

a position to establish new societies, create ones that are truly free.

(If true autonomy does not exist, why allow for?) It is not an accident

that Hegel, with his fully deterministic world-view, admired and

glorified the state, in general, and supported the reactionary Prussian

monarchy of his day, in particular; or that Plato attempted to set up

real versions of his ideal society by making alliances with dictators.

Marx and Engels are followers of this determinist tradition. They

believed that all processes, natural and social, are governed by

inexorable laws. Consequently, they did not believe that freedom, in the

sense that most people understand it, really exists. To them, freedom is

the “appreciation of necessity”; it is merely a question of recognizing

what will inevitably happen and being on the side of, consciously

supporting the emergence of, that inevitability, an apparent “decision”

that is, in fact, determined. And it is this inevitability that is

recognized by — indeed, is embodied — in Marxist theory. Although

Marxism does not claim to be able to predict all the details of future

historical development, it does claim to know, as we have seen, that

socialism is inevitable and that it can only be created through the

establishment of the dictatorship of the proletariat.

In light of this, it should be no surprise that the social systems

Marxists have set up have not been free in any meaningful sense of the

term. To Marxists, freedom is understanding history as they understand

it and acting on this understanding in the manner Marxists decide is

correct: it is the “appreciation of necessity.” As a result, the

Marxists who have managed to seize state power have never intended the

workers, peasants, and other oppressed people to actually decide on the

types of societies they wished to build, to determine what their goals

might be and what measures and methods they might use to reach those

goals. On the contrary, Marxist revolutionaries have believed that these

questions have already been answered; they (the Marxists) know, at least

in general, what needs to be done, because this is described in and

prescribed by Marxist theory, which they understand to be true. To them,

the inevitable outcome of history is a (Marxist-led) revolution that

establishes a dictatorial state, based on nationalized means of

production, that suppresses the old ruling classes and their agents.

This “dictatorship of the proletariat” paves the way for the first stage

of socialism (whose motto is “from each according to his abilities to

each according to his work”), which will eventually lead to the second

stage of socialism, or communism (whose motto is “from each according to

his ability to each according to his needs”). From the Marxist point of

view, all this has been delineated by Marxist theory, and it is totally

superfluous for the workers (let alone the peasants or middle class

people) to have any determining role in the matter. Insofar as specific

decisions need to be made that are not explicitly outlined in Marxist

theory, Marxists believe that they can decide what needs to be done, not

democratically, but theoretically, by deducing it from the general

tenets of Marxism, as they might be applied in the concrete

circumstances in which Marxists find themselves.

This is why Marxist-led revolutions, wherever they have taken place,

have never entailed allowing the actual makers of those revolutions, the

workers and/or peasants, to make the substantive decisions about what

their revolutionary societies are going to look like, but have quickly

devolved into attempts to impose Marxism-derived models by persuasion,

if possible, and by force, if necessary. At best, the mass democratic

institutions that have been created in revolutionary upheavals have been

viewed by Marxists as levers or transmission belts through which to

carry out, and ultimately to impose, their decisions. As a corollary,

this is why the central economic planning that Marxists have established

in the societies over which they have ruled has never entailed the

members of those societies, the supposed “associated producers,”

actually doing the planning themselves (based on a democratic discussion

of their needs and of their differing perspectives about the direction

of society). On the contrary, Marxist planning has always meant planning

by economic “experts,” operating under the political direction of a

Marxist elite. (This, in turn, helps to explain why such planning was

ultimately a failure. While achieving considerable successes in the

early stages of industrialization — although at the cost of tremendous

waste, of both material resources and human lives — it proved totally

incapable of managing a technologically advanced society — incapable,

specifically, of generating new technology and of providing a broad

variety of high quality consumer goods. It did prove quite capable,

however, of despoiling the environment to an unbelievable degree.)

Finally, this is why Marxists see all other leftists, both non-Marxists

and those Marxists with whom they disagree (and who are therefore not

true Marxists), as opponents who must ultimately come to agree with them

or be suppressed. Although from the Marxist (and Hegelian) standpoint,

such Marxist dictatorships might be conceived to be free, they are not

free from the standpoint of anybody else.

THE TYRANNY OF THEORY

At bottom, the totalitarian thrust of Marxism resides in its belief that

the universe in all its facets — inorganic, organic, and human/social —

can be encompassed within, and accurately represented by, one logically

coherent worldview or philosophy. This view is based on the conception

that the universe, at bottom, is logical, that it conforms to and

embodies a unified logical structure, and that this logic is discernible

to and understandable by human beings. The philosophies of Hegel, on one

hand, and of Marx and Engels, on the other, are attempts by these

thinkers to describe this logical structure. Hegel’s philosophy is

explicit; to him, the underlying reality of the cosmos is logical,

Ideal, although the logic it embodies is not the mechanical, syllogistic

logic of ordinary human understanding, but a dialectical one. Marx and

Engels were not satisfied with the explicitly Idealist nature of Hegel’s

theory and recast it in superficially materialist and scientific terms.

But beneath the materialist facade, the Hegelian Idealist structure

remains. It is this combination of Hegelian structure and materialist

cover that explains why Marx and Engels saw socialism/communism as

arising inevitably out of the internal (dialectical) contradictions of

capitalism, and why they described their socialism as “scientific.”

Hegel, Marx, and Engels were certainly not alone in attempting to

achieve this philosophical, and ultimately rationalist, project; many

philosophers, certainly those in the Western tradition, have shared the

same assumption and have attempted to solve the same puzzle. And,

consistent with this view, most of them consider their philosophies to

be true and all other philosophies to be false. In this sense, these

philosophies are totalitarian. But the question of whether this

assumption — that the universe is ultimately logical and can be

accurately represented by a unified, logically coherent philosophy — is

correct and whether any of these philosophies are true or not, cannot be

answered. It is certainly not answerable by science, contrary to what

Marx and Engels may have thought, since science operates on and within

its own philosophical assumptions, which themselves are not subject to

proof. I personally believe the assumption is incorrect and that these

philosophies are false. (There is also good reason to think that no

system of logic is itself fully logical or consistent. According to the

theorem of mathematician Kurt Godel, all systems of logic, those of

mathematics or any other, will always be inconsistent, incomplete, or

both.) I also believe that philosophies that purport to encompass all of

reality within a logically consistent system can result only in attempts

to conceptually cram all aspects of reality into their logically

coherent structures even if some aspects do not comfortably fit. And

when holders of such philosophies attempt to carry them out in practice,

to apply them in the real world on a society-wide scale through the use

of the state, such attempts lead to totalitarian results. When, given

the opportunity and the means, e.g., control of dictatorial states, to

try to carry out their program, these totalitarian rationalists attempt

to force reality, including human beings, with their competing interests

and their infinitely varied consciousnesses and personalities, to

conform to the logic of their theories and to suppress, exterminate or

otherwise eliminate all aspects of reality that do not so conform. This,

to my mind, explains the actual, practical, results of Marxist-led

revolutions.

In contrast to such a view, I believe the universe is too complicated,

too vast in its dimensions (from the very small to the immense, from the

inorganic to the human) and too complex in its workings to ever be fully

understandable by human beings, let alone reduced to one

logically-consistent picture. Moreover, I think it is the height of

arrogance to believe it can. Despite this, I expect many, even most,

scientists, philosophers, and religious thinkers will continue to search

for, or believe they have found, the supposedly final, ultimately true,

world view (some physicists are currently looking for the “theory of

everything”). Perhaps this is inevitable. Perhaps it is the

(dialectical) nature of human thought to continue to search for

certainty, and to believe, at any given moment, that it has found it,

only to be doomed eventually to discover that this is not the case. This

certainly seems to describe the history of science. But it is a

philosophical position that, under certain circumstances, can become

extremely dangerous.

Marxism’s totalitarian monism is obscured and motivated by a glorified,

and ultimately inaccurate, view of science. It simultaneously elevates

the natural sciences, particularly physics, to the status of model for

all the sciences and conceives of the “laws of nature” as iron-clad

structures that inhere in reality and strictly determine the behavior of

everything in the universe. When applied to the social realm — economic,

politics, history — such a faulty conception implies that social reality

is subject to similar laws, and that, as a result, social reality — the

behavior and consciousness of all human beings — is, at bottom, totally

determined and hence predictable.

It is because of this that Marxism insists that it has discovered,

scientifically, the ultimate structure, meaning, and goal of history. It

contends that this goal is the establishment of a certain kind of

society, communism, which can only be established through a form of the

state it calls the “dictatorship of the proletariat.” It insists that

this communist society, based on the nationalized means of production

and economic planning, will be a truly free society, a society in which

humanity, both as a species and as individuals, will be free to

determine their destinies. Finally, it insists that this is the

inevitable — logical and necessary — outcome of what it calls the “laws

of history,” in other words, that communism — and therefore, freedom

itself — is determined.

But if communism is, in fact, determined, if it is the inevitable

necessary and logical — outcome of history, then, as I see it, it will

not and cannot be a truly free society. Freedom, to me, must include the

freedom to choose, both on the part of human individuals and on the part

of the human species as a whole. Consequently, a truly free society can

be only one that human beings truly choose and truly create. In other

words, human beings must be able to decide not only the precise

structure and forms of such a society, but also whether even to

establish such a society. In other words, if such a society is to be

free, humanity must have the freedom not to create it, if it so decides.

To put this negatively, a truly free a society cannot be determined; it

cannot be inevitable; it cannot be the necessary and logical end result

of history. A society that is the inevitable — logical and necessary —

outcome of history (if history is, in fact, determined) may have the

forms, the outer shell, the accoutrements, of a free society, but it

will not be a free society.

Contrary to Marxism’s claim, we do not know what will happen in history.

We do not know if humanity will create a free — a truly egalitarian,

cooperative, and democratic — society. We do not even know whether

humanity is capable of creating such a society. And we do not know

whether history is determined (and if it is determined, what it is

precisely that is determined) or open. Nobody knows the answers to these

questions; they have never been answered scientifically, and they never

will be answered scientifically. What we can say is that if there is to

be even the possibility of humanity creating a truly free society, then

freedom must exist, as a potential — that is, ontologically — in history

and in the cosmos. But we do not, and cannot, know that this is the

case. For those of us who advocate a free society, we have to hope that

it is, to act on this assumption, and to take responsibility for our

actions.

A truly free society, then, cannot be inevitable, the result of

inexorable laws; it cannot be “scientifically” ordained. If it is to

happen, a free society must be a choice, a choice facing all of

humanity, the entire human species. In other words, it must be a

consciously willed decision, a moral or ethical goal. Or, as another

great Russian writer, Fyodor Dostoyevsky, put it in his Winter Notes on

Summer Impressions, “There must be a change of heart.”