đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș nicholas-thoburn-bakunin-s-lumpenproletariat.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:05:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Bakuninâs lumpenproletariat Author: Nicholas Thoburn Date: 2002 Language: en Topics: Mikhail Bakunin, Lumpenproletariat, marxism Source: Retrieved on 21st August 2021 from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/03085140220151882 Notes: Excerpt from Difference in Marx: the lumpenproletariat and the proletarian unnamable. Published in Economy and Society, 31(3), 434â460. doi:10.1080/03085140220151882
In these three manifestations of lumpenproletarian practice (in relation
to history â as comic repetition of past identities, production â as a
self-separation from social productive activity, and politics â as a
vacillating spontaneity) we see a category which is marked by its
externality to capitalist social relations and its inability to engage
with the potential becoming of history. The political importance of this
account comes to the fore in the unfolding of the First International â
the emerging split between Marxism and anarchism â in Marxâs dispute
with Michael Bakunin, the man Engels dubbed as âthe lumpen princeâ
(cited in Bovenkerk 1984: 25)[1]
Though the conventional presentation of the split between Marx and
Bakunin centres on a statism/anti-statism conÂflict over the
âdictatorship of the proletariatâ, a far more important distinction (for
all else emerges from it) resides in their differences on the question
of the revolutionary agent.[2] Whereas Marx sees the emergence of the
revolutionary proletariat as immanent capitalist social relations,
Bakunin considers workersâ integration in capital as destructive of more
primary revolutionary forces. For Bakunin, the revolutionary archetype
is found in a peasant milieu (which is presented as having long-standing
insurrectionary traditions, as well as a communist archetype in its
current social form â the peasant commune), and among educated
unemployed youth, assorted âmarginalsâ from all classes, brigands,
robbers, the impoverished masses, and those on the margins of society
who have escaped, been excluded from, or not yet subsumed in the
discipline of emerging industrial work â in short, all those whom Marx
sought to include in the category of the lumpenproletariat (cf. Pyziur
1968: ch. 5). Thus, as the people capable of uniting âprivate peasant
revolts into one general all-peopleâs revoltâ, Bakunin focuses on
free Cossacks, our innumerable saintly and not so saintly tramps
(brodiagi), pilgrims, members of âbegunyâ sects, thieves, and brigands â
this whole wide and numerous underground world which from time
immemorial has protested against the state and statism.
(Bakunin n.d.: 19)
Such people, Bakunin (n.d.: 20) argues in a fashion not so different
from Marxâs account of lumpen âspontaneityâ, are red with a
transhistorical instinctual rage, a ânative movementâ of a âturbulent
oceanâ, and it is this revolutionary fervour, immanent to their
identities, not class composition within capitalism, which elects them
for their political role:
Marx speaks disdainfully, but quite unjustly of this Lumpenproletariat .
For in them, and only in them, and not in the bourgeois strata of
workers, are there crystallised the entire intelligence and power of the
coming Social Revolution.
A popular insurrection, by its very nature, is instinctive, chaotic, and
destructive, and always entails great personal sacrifice and an enormous
loss of public and private property. The masses are always ready to
sacrifice themselves; and this is what turns them into a brutal and
savage horde, capable of performing heroic and apparently impossible
exploits, and since they possess little or nothing, they are not
demoralised by the responsibilities of property ownership ... they
develop a passion for destruction. This negative passion, it is true, is
far from being sufficient to attain the heights of the revolutionary
cause; but without it, revolution would be impossible. Revolution
requires extensive and widespread destruction, a fecund and renovating
destruction.
(Bakunin 1973: 334)
Though Bakuninâs category of the lumpenproletariat may have a broader
catchment than Marxâs,[3] it is clear that they both largely agree on
its components as an identity removed from capitalist social relations.
While for Marx the lumpenproletariat is a tendency â vis-Ă -vis history,
production and political action â towards identity, for Bakunin the
lumpenproletariat embodies in its present identity a kind of actually
existing anarchism.[4] The centrality of present identity to Bakuninâs
formulation is such that, when he does venture into theory, he places a
premium on abstract humanist concepts like freedom and equality.[5]
Bakuninist anarchism â for all its emphasis on the marginalized,
down-trodden and rebellious â is thus subject to the same critique Marx
raised against Utopian Socialism, as that which posits a transcendent
idea of a perfect social form and deploys historically decontextualized
âeternal truthsâ of âHuman Natureâ and âMan in Generalâ, rather than
engage with the expansive âfluid stateâ of material life in specific
sociohistorical relations (Marx and Engels 1973: 69, 67; Marx 1976:
103).[6]
Selected Bibliography
Bakunin, M. (n.d.) Bakunin on Violence: Letter to S. Nechayev June 2
1870, New York: Anarchist Switchboard.
Bakunin, M. (1973) Bakunin on Anarchy: Selected Works by the
Activist-Founder of World Anarchism, trans. and ed. S. Dolgoff, London:
Allen & Unwin.
Bovenkerk, F. (1984) âThe rehabilitatio n of the rabble; how and why
Marx and Engels wrongly depicted the lumpenproletariat as a reactionary
forceâ, Netherlands Journal of Sociology 20(1): 13â41.
Marx, K. and Engels, F. (1973) Manifesto of the Communist Party,
Beijing: Foreign Languages Press.
Marx, K. (1976) Capital: A Critical Analysis of Capitalist Production,
Vol. 1, trans. B. Fowkes, London: Penguin.
Pyziur, E. (1968) The Doctrine of Anarchism of Michael A. Bakunin,
Chicago: Gateway.
[1] The rationale behind the exclusion of Bakuninâs Alliance of Social
Democracy from the International is explained in some 120 pages (Marx
and Engels 1988), but begins by stating that the danger of a broad
banner workersâ movement, as the Internationalâs explicit concern, was
always in letting in déclassé (lumpen) elements.
[2] The argument that Bakunin perceives in Marx the seeds of statism â
that he, in a sense, predicts the Soviet Union â is not uninteresting,
but it can be made only by ignoring the centrality of Bakuninist notions
of organization and âinvisible dictatorshipâ to Leninist politics (cf.
Blissett and Home n.d.).
[3] Bakunin seems to practise what Marx and Engels (1988: 520) refer to
as a âlaw of anarchist assimilationâ, whereby a whole series of groups
(from religious sects to students and brigands) are brought under the
banner of a spontaneist âanti-authoritarianâ movement. Marxâs critique
is not just that the collective âcommunityâ of these formations is often
little more than a product of Bakuninâs imagination, but that it is also
a cynical deployment of a populist rhetoric that disguises a tapestry of
secret societies and âinvisible dictatorshipâ (cf. Marx and Engels
1988).
[4] This is not to suggest that Bakunin was not an advocate of
revolutionary change, but simply that his change was to be the
expression of the identity of his political agent.
[5] In Revolutionary Catechism, for example, Bakunin writes: âReplacing
the cult of God by respect and love of humanity, we proclaim human
reason as the only criterion of truth; human conscience as the basis of
justice; individual and collective freedom as the only source of order
in societyâ (1973: 76).
[6] Debord (1983) presents one of the most concise and incisive Marxist
critiques of utopian socialism and anarchism in these terms (albeit a
critique which could apply to the humanist and Hegelian tendencies in
the Situationist International itself (cf. Ansell Pearson 1997: 155â60;
Debray 1995)). Having argued that Marxâs âscienceâ is an understanding
of forces and struggle rather than transcendent law (Debord 1983: §81),
Debord writes:
The utopian currents of socialism, although themselves historically
grounded in the critique of the existing social organization, can
rightly be called utopian to the extent that they reject history â
namely the real struggle taking place, as well as the passage of time
beyond the immutable perfection of their picture of a happy society.
(Debord 1983: §83)
Debord then continues to consider anarchism:
The anarchists have an ideal to realize.... It is the ideology of pure
liberty which equalizes everything and dismisses the very idea of
historical evil.... Anarchism has merely to repeat and to replay the
same simple, total conclusion in every single struggle, because the
first conclusion was from the beginning identified with the entire
outcome of the movement.... [I]t leaves the historical terrain by
assuming that the adequate forms for th[e] passage to practice have
already been found and will never change. (Debord 1983: §92)