đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș nicholas-thoburn-bakunin-s-lumpenproletariat.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:05:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Bakunin’s lumpenproletariat
Author: Nicholas Thoburn
Date: 2002
Language: en
Topics: Mikhail Bakunin, Lumpenproletariat, marxism
Source: Retrieved on 21st August 2021 from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/03085140220151882
Notes: Excerpt from Difference in Marx: the lumpenproletariat and the proletarian unnamable. Published in Economy and Society, 31(3), 434–460. doi:10.1080/03085140220151882

Nicholas Thoburn

Bakunin’s lumpenproletariat

In these three manifestations of lumpenproletarian practice (in relation

to history – as comic repetition of past identities, production – as a

self-separation from social productive activity, and politics – as a

vacillating spontaneity) we see a category which is marked by its

externality to capitalist social relations and its inability to engage

with the potential becoming of history. The political importance of this

account comes to the fore in the unfolding of the First International –

the emerging split between Marxism and anarchism – in Marx’s dispute

with Michael Bakunin, the man Engels dubbed as ‘the lumpen prince’

(cited in Bovenkerk 1984: 25)[1]

Though the conventional presentation of the split between Marx and

Bakunin centres on a statism/anti-statism conflict over the

‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, a far more important distinction (for

all else emerges from it) resides in their differences on the question

of the revolutionary agent.[2] Whereas Marx sees the emergence of the

revolutionary proletariat as immanent capitalist social relations,

Bakunin considers workers’ integration in capital as destructive of more

primary revolutionary forces. For Bakunin, the revolutionary archetype

is found in a peasant milieu (which is presented as having long-standing

insurrectionary traditions, as well as a communist archetype in its

current social form – the peasant commune), and among educated

unemployed youth, assorted ‘marginals’ from all classes, brigands,

robbers, the impoverished masses, and those on the margins of society

who have escaped, been excluded from, or not yet subsumed in the

discipline of emerging industrial work – in short, all those whom Marx

sought to include in the category of the lumpenproletariat (cf. Pyziur

1968: ch. 5). Thus, as the people capable of uniting ‘private peasant

revolts into one general all-people’s revolt’, Bakunin focuses on

free Cossacks, our innumerable saintly and not so saintly tramps

(brodiagi), pilgrims, members of ‘beguny’ sects, thieves, and brigands –

this whole wide and numerous underground world which from time

immemorial has protested against the state and statism.

(Bakunin n.d.: 19)

Such people, Bakunin (n.d.: 20) argues in a fashion not so different

from Marx’s account of lumpen ‘spontaneity’, are red with a

transhistorical instinctual rage, a ‘native movement’ of a ‘turbulent

ocean’, and it is this revolutionary fervour, immanent to their

identities, not class composition within capitalism, which elects them

for their political role:

Marx speaks disdainfully, but quite unjustly of this Lumpenproletariat .

For in them, and only in them, and not in the bourgeois strata of

workers, are there crystallised the entire intelligence and power of the

coming Social Revolution.

A popular insurrection, by its very nature, is instinctive, chaotic, and

destructive, and always entails great personal sacrifice and an enormous

loss of public and private property. The masses are always ready to

sacrifice themselves; and this is what turns them into a brutal and

savage horde, capable of performing heroic and apparently impossible

exploits, and since they possess little or nothing, they are not

demoralised by the responsibilities of property ownership ... they

develop a passion for destruction. This negative passion, it is true, is

far from being sufficient to attain the heights of the revolutionary

cause; but without it, revolution would be impossible. Revolution

requires extensive and widespread destruction, a fecund and renovating

destruction.

(Bakunin 1973: 334)

Though Bakunin’s category of the lumpenproletariat may have a broader

catchment than Marx’s,[3] it is clear that they both largely agree on

its components as an identity removed from capitalist social relations.

While for Marx the lumpenproletariat is a tendency – vis-à-vis history,

production and political action – towards identity, for Bakunin the

lumpenproletariat embodies in its present identity a kind of actually

existing anarchism.[4] The centrality of present identity to Bakunin’s

formulation is such that, when he does venture into theory, he places a

premium on abstract humanist concepts like freedom and equality.[5]

Bakuninist anarchism – for all its emphasis on the marginalized,

down-trodden and rebellious – is thus subject to the same critique Marx

raised against Utopian Socialism, as that which posits a transcendent

idea of a perfect social form and deploys historically decontextualized

‘eternal truths’ of ‘Human Nature’ and ‘Man in General’, rather than

engage with the expansive ‘fluid state’ of material life in specific

sociohistorical relations (Marx and Engels 1973: 69, 67; Marx 1976:

103).[6]

Selected Bibliography

Bakunin, M. (n.d.) Bakunin on Violence: Letter to S. Nechayev June 2

1870, New York: Anarchist Switchboard.

Bakunin, M. (1973) Bakunin on Anarchy: Selected Works by the

Activist-Founder of World Anarchism, trans. and ed. S. Dolgoff, London:

Allen & Unwin.

Bovenkerk, F. (1984) ‘The rehabilitatio n of the rabble; how and why

Marx and Engels wrongly depicted the lumpenproletariat as a reactionary

force’, Netherlands Journal of Sociology 20(1): 13–41.

Marx, K. and Engels, F. (1973) Manifesto of the Communist Party,

Beijing: Foreign Languages Press.

Marx, K. (1976) Capital: A Critical Analysis of Capitalist Production,

Vol. 1, trans. B. Fowkes, London: Penguin.

Pyziur, E. (1968) The Doctrine of Anarchism of Michael A. Bakunin,

Chicago: Gateway.

[1] The rationale behind the exclusion of Bakunin’s Alliance of Social

Democracy from the International is explained in some 120 pages (Marx

and Engels 1988), but begins by stating that the danger of a broad

banner workers’ movement, as the International’s explicit concern, was

always in letting in déclassé (lumpen) elements.

[2] The argument that Bakunin perceives in Marx the seeds of statism –

that he, in a sense, predicts the Soviet Union – is not uninteresting,

but it can be made only by ignoring the centrality of Bakuninist notions

of organization and ‘invisible dictatorship’ to Leninist politics (cf.

Blissett and Home n.d.).

[3] Bakunin seems to practise what Marx and Engels (1988: 520) refer to

as a ‘law of anarchist assimilation’, whereby a whole series of groups

(from religious sects to students and brigands) are brought under the

banner of a spontaneist ‘anti-authoritarian’ movement. Marx’s critique

is not just that the collective ‘community’ of these formations is often

little more than a product of Bakunin’s imagination, but that it is also

a cynical deployment of a populist rhetoric that disguises a tapestry of

secret societies and ‘invisible dictatorship’ (cf. Marx and Engels

1988).

[4] This is not to suggest that Bakunin was not an advocate of

revolutionary change, but simply that his change was to be the

expression of the identity of his political agent.

[5] In Revolutionary Catechism, for example, Bakunin writes: ‘Replacing

the cult of God by respect and love of humanity, we proclaim human

reason as the only criterion of truth; human conscience as the basis of

justice; individual and collective freedom as the only source of order

in society’ (1973: 76).

[6] Debord (1983) presents one of the most concise and incisive Marxist

critiques of utopian socialism and anarchism in these terms (albeit a

critique which could apply to the humanist and Hegelian tendencies in

the Situationist International itself (cf. Ansell Pearson 1997: 155–60;

Debray 1995)). Having argued that Marx’s ‘science’ is an understanding

of forces and struggle rather than transcendent law (Debord 1983: §81),

Debord writes:

The utopian currents of socialism, although themselves historically

grounded in the critique of the existing social organization, can

rightly be called utopian to the extent that they reject history –

namely the real struggle taking place, as well as the passage of time

beyond the immutable perfection of their picture of a happy society.

(Debord 1983: §83)

Debord then continues to consider anarchism:

The anarchists have an ideal to realize.... It is the ideology of pure

liberty which equalizes everything and dismisses the very idea of

historical evil.... Anarchism has merely to repeat and to replay the

same simple, total conclusion in every single struggle, because the

first conclusion was from the beginning identified with the entire

outcome of the movement.... [I]t leaves the historical terrain by

assuming that the adequate forms for th[e] passage to practice have

already been found and will never change. (Debord 1983: §92)