💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › maurice-brinton-capitalism-and-socialism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:29:42. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Capitalism and Socialism
Author: Maurice Brinton
Date: December 1968
Language: en
Topics: socialism; libertarian socialism; capitalism; anti-capitalism; criticism and critique; critique of the left; Marxism; authoritarian left; workers’ self-management
Source: https://www.marxists.org/archive/brinton/1968/12/capitalism-socialism.htm
Notes: Published in Solidarity, V, 6

Maurice Brinton

Capitalism and Socialism

What is basically wrong with capitalism? Ask a number of socialists and

you will get a number of different answers. These will depend on their

vision of what socialism might be like and on their ideas as to what

political action is all about. Revolutionary libertarian socialists see

these things very differently from the trad “left”. This article is not

an attempt to counterpoise two conceptions of socialism and political

action. It is an attempt to stress a facet of socialist thought that is

in danger of being forgotten.

When one scratches beneath the surface, “progressive” capitalists,

liberals, Labour reformists, “communist” macro-bureaucrats and

Trotskyist mini-bureaucrats all see the evils of capitalism in much the

same way. They all see them as primarily economic ills, flowing from a

particular pattern of ownership of the means of production. When

Khrushchev equated socialism with “more goulash for everyone” he was

voicing a widespread view. Innumerable quotations could be found to

substantiate this assertion.

If you don’t believe that traditional socialists think in this way, try

suggesting to one of them that modern capitalism is beginning to solve

some economic problems. He will immediately denounce you as having

“given up the struggle for socialism”. He cannot grasp that slumps were

a feature of societies that state capitalism had not sufficiently

permeated and that they are not intrinsic features of capitalist

society. “No economic crisis” is, for the traditional socialist,

tantamount to “no crisis”. It is synonymous with “capitalism has solved

its problems”. The traditional socialist feels insecure, as a socialist,

if told that capitalism can solve this kind of problem, because for him

this is the problem, par excellence, affecting capitalist society.

The traditional “left” today has a crude vision of man, of his

aspirations and his needs, a vision moulded by the rotten society in

which we live. It has a narrow concept of class consciousness. For them

class consciousness is primarily an awareness of “non-ownership”. They

see the “social problem” being solved as the majority of the population

gain access to material wealth. All would be well, they say or imply, if

as a result of their capture of state power (and of their particular

brand of planning) the masses could only be ensured a higher level of

consumption. “Socialism” is equated with full bellies. The filling of

these bellies is seen as the fundamental task of the socialist

revolution.

Intimately related to this concept of man as essentially a producing and

consuming machine is the whole traditional “left” critique of

laissez-faire capitalism. Many on the “left” continue to think we live

under this kind of capitalism and continue to criticize it because it is

inefficient (in the domain of production). The whole of John Strachey’s

writings prior to World War II were dominated by these conceptions. His

Why You Should Be a Socialist sold nearly a million copies — and yet the

ideas of freedom or self-management do not appear in it, as part of the

socialist objective. Many of the leaders of today’s “left” graduated at

his school, including the so-called revolutionaries. Even the usual

vision of communism, “from each according to his ability, to each

according to his needs”, usually relates, in the minds of “Marxists”, to

the division of the cake and not at all to the relations of man with man

and between man and his environment.

For the traditional socialist “raising the standard of living” is the

main purpose of social change. Capitalism allegedly cannot any longer

develop production. (Anyone ever caught in a traffic jam, or in a

working class shopping area on a Saturday afternoon, will find this a

strange proposition.) It seems to be of secondary importance to this

kind of socialist that under modern capitalism people are brutalized at

work, manipulated in consumption and in leisure, their intellectual

capacity stunted or their taste corrupted by a commercial culture. One

must be “soft”, it is implied, if one considers the systematic

destruction of human beings to be worth a big song and dance. Those who

talk of socialist objectives as being freedom in production (as well as

out of it) are dismissed as “Utopians”.

Were it not that misrepresentation is now an established way of life on

the “left”, it would seem unnecessary to stress that as long as millions

of the world’s population have insufficient food and clothing, the

satisfaction of basic material needs must be an essential part of the

socialist programme (and in fact of any social programme whatsoever,

which does not extol the virtues of poverty.) The point is that by

concentrating entirely on this aspect of the critique of capitalism the

propaganda of the traditional “left” deprives itself of one of the most

telling weapons of socialist criticism, namely an exposure of what

capitalism does to people, particularly in countries where basic needs

have by and large been met. And whether Guevarist or Maoist friends like

it or not, it is in these countries, where there is a proletariat, that

the socialist future of mankind will be decided.

This particular emphasis in the propaganda of the traditional

organizations is not accidental. When they talk of increasing production

in order to increase consumption, reformists and bureaucrats of one kind

or another feel on fairly safe ground. Despite the nonsense talked by

many “Marxists” about “stagnation of the productive forces”,

bureaucratic capitalism (of both the Eastern and Western types) can

develop the means of production, has done so and is still doing so on a

gigantic scale. It can provide (and historically has provided) a gradual

increase in the standard of living — at the cost of intensified

exploitation during the working day. It can provide a fairly steady

level of employment. So can a well-run gaol. But on the ground of the

subjection of man to institutions which are not of his choice, the

socialist critiques of capitalism and bureaucratic society retain all

their validity. In fact, their validity increases as modern society

simultaneously solves the problem of mass poverty and becomes

increasingly bureaucratic and totalitarian.

It will probably be objected that some offbeat trends in the “Marxist”

movement do indulge in this wider kind of critique and in a sense this

is true. Yet whatever the institutions criticized, their critique

usually hinges, ultimately, on the notion of the unequal distribution of

wealth. It consists in variations on the theme of the corrupting

influence of money. When they talk for instance of the sexual problem or

of the family, they talk of the economic barriers to sexual

emancipation, of hunger pushing women to prostitution, of the poor young

girl sold to the wealthy man, of the domestic tragedies resulting from

poverty. When they denounce what capitalism does to culture they will do

so in terms of the obstacles that economic needs puts in the way of

talent, or they will talk of the venality of artists. All this is

undoubtedly of great importance. But it is only the surface of the

problem. Those socialists who can only speak in these terms see man in

much less than his full stature. They see him as the bourgeoisie does,

as a consumer (of food, of wealth, of culture, etc.). The essential,

however, for man is to fulfil himself. Socialism must give man an

opportunity to create, not only in the economic field but in all fields

of human endeavour. Let the cynics smile and pretend that all this is

petty-bourgeois utopianism. “The problem”, Marx said, “is to organize

the world in such a manner that man experiences in it the truly human,

becomes accustomed to experience himself as a man, to assert his true

individuality”.

Conflicts in class society do not simply result from inequalities of

distribution, or flow from a given division of the surplus value, itself

the result of a given pattern of ownership of the means of production.

Exploitation does not only result in a limitation of consumption for the

many and financial enrichment for the few. This is but one aspect of the

problem. Equally important are the attempts by both private and

bureaucratic capitalism to limit — and finally to suppress altogether —

the human role of man in the productive process. Man is increasingly

expropriated from the very management of his own acts. He is

increasingly alienated during all his activities, whether individual or

collective. By subjecting man to the machine — and through the machine

to an abstract and hostile will — class society deprives man of the real

purpose of human endeavour, which is the constant, conscious

transformation of the world around him. That men resist this process

(and that their resistance implicitly raises the question of

self-management) is as much a driving force in the class struggle as the

conflict over the distribution of the surplus. Marx doubtless had these

ideas in mind when he wrote that the proletariat “regards its

independence and sense of personal dignity as more essential than its

daily bread”.

Class society profoundly inhibits the natural tendency of man to fulfil

himself in the objects of his activity. In every country of the world

this state of affairs is experienced day after day by the working class

as an absolute misfortune, as a permanent mutilation. It results in a

constant struggle at the most fundamental level of production: that of

conscious, willing participation. The producers utterly reject (and

quite rightly so) a system of production which is imposed upon them from

above and in which they are mere cogs. Their inventiveness, their

creative ability, their ingenuity, their initiative may be shown in

their own lives, but are certainly not shown in production. In the

factory these aptitudes may be used, but to quite different and

“non-productive” ends! They manifest themselves in a resistance to

production. This results in a constant and fantastic waste compared with

which the wastage resulting from capitalist crises or capitalist wars is

really quite trivial!

Alienation in capitalist society is not simply economic. It manifests

itself in many other ways. The conflict in production does not “create”

or “determine” secondary conflicts in other fields. Class domination

manifests itself in all fields, at one and the same time. Its effects

could not otherwise be understood. Exploitation, for instance, can only

occur if the producers are expropriated from the management of

production. But this presupposes that they are partly expropriated at

least from the capacities of management — in other words from culture.

And this cultural expropriation in turn reinforces those in command of

the productive machine. Similarly a society in which relations between

people are based on domination will maintain authoritarian attitudes in

relation to sex and to education, attitudes creating deep inhibitions,

frustrations and much unhappiness. The conflicts engendered by class

society take place in every one of us. A social structure containing

deep antagonisms reproduces these antagonisms in variable degrees in

each of the individuals comprising it.

There is a profound dialectical interrelationship between the social

structure of a society and the attitudes and behaviour of its members.

“The dominant ideas of each epoch are the ideas of its ruling class”,

whatever modern sociologists may think. Class society can only exist to

the extent that it succeeds in imposing a widespread acceptance of its

norms. From his earliest days man is subjected to constant pressures

designed to mould his views in relation to work, to culture, to leisure,

to thought itself. These pressures tend to deprive him of the natural

enjoyment of his activity and even to make him accept this deprivation

as something intrinsically good. In the past this job was assisted by

religion. Today the same role is played by “socialist” and “communist”

ideologies. But man is not infinitely malleable. This is why the

bureaucratic project will come unstuck. Its objectives are in conflict

with fundamental human aspirations.

We mention all this only to underline the essential identity of

relations of domination — whether they manifest themselves in the

capitalist factory, in the patriarchal family, in the authoritarian

upbringing of children or in “aristocratic” cultural traditions. We also

mention these facts to show that the socialist revolution will have to

take all these fields within its compass, and immediately, not in some

far distant future. The revolution must of course start with the

overthrow of the exploiting class and with the institution of workers’

management of production. But it will immediately have to tackle the

reconstruction of social life in all its aspects. If it does not, it

will surely die.