💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › bob-black-anarchy-after-leftism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:54:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchy after Leftism
Author: Bob Black
Date: 1997
Language: en
Topics: anti-work, critique, ideology, individualism, marxism, municipalism, Murray Bookchin, organization, post-left, primitivism, science, scientism, technology
Source: Retrieved on 17 March 2011 from http://www.scribd.com/doc/37185997/Anarchy-After-Leftism.
Notes: Anti-copyright @ 1997 Bob Black This book may be freely pirated and quoted. The author and publisher would like to be informed at:    C.A.L. Press Columbia Alternative Library POB 1446 Columbia, MO 65205–1446 USA    Bob Black POB 3142 Albany, NY 12203–0142 USA

Bob Black

Anarchy after Leftism

Preface

Leaving the twentieth century, leftism of every stripe is in disarray

and defeat — anarcho-leftism included. And Murray Bookchin’s Social

Ecology is certainly no exception to this trend.

Bookchin, one of the best known of contemporary North American

anarchists, has spent much of his life staking out his own personal

eco-anarchist ideological territory under the banners of Social Ecology

and Libertarian Municipalism. He is the author of a steady stream of

books from the sixties to the present, including his classic collection

of essays titled Post-Scarcity Anarchism published in 1971, his

excellent volume on the history of the Spanish anarchist movement

written in the seventies, and his failed attempt in the eighties at

constructing a philosophical magnum opus in The Ecology of Freedom.

Bookchin has never been content with merely constructing one more

radical ideology in competition with all the others. His dream has

always been to lead a coherent left-wing ecological radical grouping

into a serious contest with the powers that be. However, his attempts at

constructing such a grouping (from the Anarchos journal group in the New

York of the sixties to the recent Left Green Network within the Greens

milieu) have never met with much success.

In his latest book, Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism, Bookchin

aims to pin the blame for his lifetime of frustration (despite his

decades of valiant effort!) on an evil anti-socialist conspiracy which

has subverted his dreams at every turn: the dreaded specter of

“Lifestyle Anarchism.” For Bookchin, lifestyle anarchism is a

contemporary manifestation of the individualist anarchist currents which

have always bedeviled the world anarchist movement proper. The fact that

the anarchist “movement” itself has always been more of a polymorphous

insurrectionary milieu encompassing everything from

anarcho-syndicalists, anarcho-communists and anarcho-futurists to

anarchist feminists, anarchist primitivists and anarcho-situationists

doesn’t really matter to him. The important thing is that he has finally

been able to name the anti-organizational cabal which opposes him and to

explain the esoteric links between its often seemingly unrelated or even

mutually contradictory efforts!

Enter Bob Black.

Now a lot of people don’t like Bob Black. Many anarchists would be

alarmed if he moved in next door. Anyone with good sense would probably

be upset if he started dating her younger sister. Most everyone is

loathe to provoke his anger or face it head on.

And not without reason. Bob may be a brilliant critic and hilarious wit,

but he’s not a nice guy. His infamous reputation isn’t built on fair

play or good sportsmanship.

Maybe this is why Murray Bookchin’s latest rant, Social Anarchism or

Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm, never criticizes Bob Black

directly. In fact it never so much as mentions Bob’s name. Even though

it’s obvious from the book’s contents that by all rights Bob should have

received the same type of attempted (though ultimately feeble) thrashing

Bookchin reserved for George Bradford, John Zerzan, Hakim Bey, et al.

Obviously, Murray knows better than to challenge Bob to a duel, even a

rhetorical one. But that hasn’t stopped Bob, in an uncharacteristically

generous spirit, from giving Bookchin his due anyway.

Bob’s defense of anarchy in Anarchy after Leftism isn’t meant to express

solidarity with those targeted in the latest attacks framed by

Bookchin’s pidgin dialectics. Nor is Bob really interested in rescuing

anarchist ideology from itself. He just wants to set the record straight

by clearing away worse than useless polemics. Defending the potential

for anarchy is merely an unpleasant task of menial anti-ideological

labor that Bob has performed because no one else volunteered to wash

these particular dirty dishes, [1] while he wants to get on with cooking

another meal.

But that’s by no means all that’s going on here. Disposing of Murray

Bookchin’s ideological and rhetorical rubbish gives Bob the chance to

develop the grounds for a more general attack on the remaining vestiges

of leftism while he’s at it. Cleaning house of leftism is a much bigger

task than dealing with one man’s leftist career. So in one sense, by

drawing attention to his ineffectual polemic, Bookchin has made himself

an excuse for the beginning of a much larger process of critique, a

process that will undoubtedly continue to unfold with increasing

militance into the coming century. It will require awareness and effort

from all of us to finish this task, but it will be done.

Bob’s double critique in Anarchy after Leftism only gains incisiveness

from the attitude of lumpen noblesse oblige he has adopted for his task.

Rather than letting his own sordid past (and present) get in the way,

the lack of any revenge motive (seemingly Bob’s favorite muse) allows

him to unleash his pen with just as much wit, but with fewer red

herrings, obscure put-downs and tortured self-justifications than ever.

The result is a modest feast made up of consistently entertaining prose,

an immanent critique of a would-be eminent social critic, and one more

nail in the coffin of obsolete leftism, anarchist-style.

You might not want to invite Bob into your house. I certainly wouldn’t.

But at least thank him for doing the dishes. And let’s get on with the

next feast!

Jason McQuinn

Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed

Alternative Press Review

Introduction

This small book is nothing more than a critique of another small book,

Murray Bookchin’s Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An

Unbridgeable Chasm. [2] His consists of the title essay plus “The Left

That Was: A Personal Reflection.” Published in 1995, it was an

unexpected intervention in an intramural debate which had been going on

for at least twenty years between traditionalistic anarchists — leftist,

workerist, organizational, and moralist — and an ever more diverse (and

an ever more numerous) contingent of anarchists who have in one way or

another departed from orthodoxy, at least in Bookchin’s eyes.

Bookchin caught a lot of us heterodox anarchists by surprise. Most of us

have read some of Bookchin’s books and many of us, myself included, have

learned from them, especially the earlier books from the 1970s.

Bookchin’s subsequent and ever-intensifying preoccupation with municipal

politics we were mostly inclined to ignore as an idiosyncrasy. He seemed

to take no notice of what we were up to. He was absent from publications

like the Fifth Estate, Popular Reality, Front Line, The Match!, and

Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed. It was as if he took the anarchists

for granted. They didn’t know that Bookchin thought they were sinking

swiftly into ideological and moral decay.

They do now. Bookchin views-with-alarm almost every new tendency in

anarchism except his own specialty, ecology. What’s more, the nefarious

novelties exhibit malign thematic affinities. Not only are they

pernicious, they are pernicious in essentially the same way. They

represent a recrudescence of an old heresy, “individualism,” decked out

in trendy post-modernist fashions in a configuration Bookchin calls

“lifestyle anarchism.” Much worse than a falling-away from some aspects

of classical left-wing anarchism, lifestyle anarchism is (he insists)

fundamentally opposed to the defining tenets of anarchism. (How this

could have happened on his watch he does not explain.)

For Bookchin, then, lifestyle anarchists are not just errant comrades,

they are traitors. As such they are even worse than avowed opponents of

anarchism. He mistreats them accordingly. His jeremiad is downright

nasty. There aren’t many epithets he doesn’t work in somewhere or

another, and never mind if they sometimes contradict each other (for

instance, “individualism” and “fascism” applied to the same people).

They don’t have to be true to be effective. Bookchin started out as a

Stalinist, and it sure shows in the abusive style and unscrupulous

content of his polemic. He wants no dialogue with his self-appointed

enemies, only their irreparable discredit.

I get the distinct impression that Bookchin, an elderly man said to be

in ill health, is cashing in his chips as a prominent anarchist theorist

and staking all his influence and reputation on demolishing all possible

alternatives to his own creed, what he calls “social anarchism.” A

parting shot.

He missed the target. He had to miss the target, since there is none.

There’s no such thing as “lifestyle anarchism.” There are only a lot of

anarchists exploring a lot of ideas — a lot of different ideas — that

Bookchin disapproves of. It follows that this book is not a defense of

“lifestyle anarchism.” There’s no such unicorn, so I couldn’t defend it

even if I wanted to. The very phrase is Bookchin’s invention, much as

Stalin invented a nonsense category, the “bloc of Rights and

Trotskyists,” to collect all his political enemies for their more

convenient disposal. At the time, Bookchin believed this, and everything

else, the Party told him to believe. He hasn’t changed much; or, if he

did, he’s changed back.

If I were only taking Bookchin to task for his incivility, I’d be a

hypocrite, for I’ve penned plenty of blunt critiques of various

anarchists and anti-authoritarians. A Dutch anarchist, Siebe Thissen,

has described me — not as a criticism — as the severest critic of

contemporary anarchism (1996: 60). Maybe I am, although criticism of

anarchists takes up only a fraction of the content of my previous three

books. But I’ve often been tough on anarchists I considered

authoritarian, dishonest or stupid.

Often harsh but, I like to think, rarely unfair. Some people, especially

those I’ve criticized, mistake my being articulate for my being rude, or

mistake my noticing them for being obsessed with them. Be that as it

may, for me to set myself up as the Miss Manners of anarchism would not

be appropriate. I do think Murray Bookchin needs a lesson in manners,

and I’m going to give him one, but incivility is the least of what’s

wrong with his dyspeptic diatribe. It’s what he says, far more than how

he says it, that I mean to have done with.

I am not, except incidentally, defending those whom Bookchin targets as

“lifestyle anarchists.” (For the record, I’m not one of his identified

targets.) I am debunking the very category of lifestyle anarchism as a

construct as meaningless as it is malicious. And I am coming down with

crushing force on “an ugly, stupid style and substance of doctrinal

harangue” (Black 1992: 189), the worst survival of Bookchin’s original

Marxism. I’ve done it before and, frankly, I rather resent having to do

it again. Bookchin has made the cardinal author’s mistake of falling for

his own jacket blurbs. Otherwise he could never write such a wretched

screed and hope to get away with it. His previous contributions to

anarchism, even if they were as epochal as he likes to think, are no

excuse for this kind of gutter-gabble. His swan-song sounds nothing but

sour notes. And sour grapes.

Which is why I think there’s a place for my polemic. If even the great

Bookchin can’t get away with talking trash, maybe less eminent

anarchists will be less tempted to talk trash. If even the

quasi-academic Bookchin’s quasi-scholarship doesn’t hold up under even

modest scrutiny, maybe some unduly impressionable anarchists will learn

to question the authority of footnotes and jacket blurbs. Better

scholars than Bookchin live in dread of somebody someday looking up

their footnotes. I’ll be getting around to several of them, too. But,

worst things first.

Most people will take no interest in what Bookchin and I have to say

about anarchism. These books aren’t destined for the best-seller lists.

Even some feel-good anarchists will dismiss the ruckus as “in-fighting.”

But on one point at least I think Bookchin would agree with me:

in-fighting can be as important as out-fighting. Indeed it’s impossible

to tell them apart. The fighting has a lot to do with determining who is

in and who is out. But anybody who thinks that anarchism is, or might

be, important should consider this controversy important. I admit I’m

almost as vain as Bookchin, but maybe I am the “lifestyle anarchist” to

call him out for a showdown at high noon out at the Circle-A Ranch.

A throwback to vulgar Marxism in more than one sense, Social Anarchism

or Lifestyle Anarchism may turn out to be the last tract of its kind, at

least the last one with anarchist pretensions. Soon there will be nobody

left in North America with the requisite Leninist background to practice

this highly stylized genre of defamation. Debunking it may assist

anarchists in letting go of the leftism they have outgrown, some of them

without realizing it. Cleansed of its leftist residues, anarchy —

anarchism minus Marxism — will be free to get better at being what it

is.

Chapter 1: Murray Bookchin, Grumpy Old Man

Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism may well be the worst book about

anarchists that any of them has ever written.

According to the cover blurb, Murray Bookchin, born in 1921, has been “a

lifelong radical since the early 1930s.” “Radical” is here a euphemism

for “Stalinist”; Bookchin was originally “a militant in the Young

Pioneers and the Young Communist League” (Clark 1990:102; cf. Bookchin

1977:3). Later he became a Trotskyist. At one time Bookchin himself, “as

one who participated actively in the ‘radical’ movements of the

thirties” (1970: 56), put the word “radical,” considering the context,

in quotation marks, but now he is nostalgic about that milieu, what he

calls the Left That Was (66–86).

About 25 years ago, Murray Bookchin peered into the mirror and mistook

it for a window of opportunity. In 1963 he wrote, under a pseudonym, Our

Synthetic Society (Herber 1963), which anticipated (although it seems

not to have influenced) the environmentalist movement. In 1970, by which

time he was pushing 50 and calling himself an anarchist, Bookchin wrote

“Listen, Marxist!” — a moderately effective anti-authoritarian polemic

against such Marxist myths as the revolutionary vanguard organization

and the proletariat as revolutionary subject (Bookchin 1971:171–222). In

this and in other essays collected in Post-Scarcity Anarchism (1971),

Bookchin disdained to conceal his delight with the disarray of his

Marxist comrades-turned-competitors. He thought he saw his chance. Under

his tutelage, anarchism would finally displace Marxism, and Bookchin

would place the stamp of his specialty, “social ecology,” on anarchism.

Not only would he be betting on the winning horse, he would be the

jockey. As one of his followers has written, “if your efforts at

creating your own mass movement have been pathetic failures, find

someone else’s movement and try to lead it” (Clark 1984: 108).

Bookchin thereupon set out to conquer the anarchists for the

eco-radicals (the Greens), the Greens for the anarchists, and all for

one — the great one — Murray Bookchin himself. He would supply the

“muscularity of thought” (Bookchin 1987b: 3) that they lacked. By now

he’s been “a prophetic voice in the ecology movement for more than

thirty years,” if he does say so himself (Institute for Social Ecology

1996: 13) (Bookchin co-founded the ISE). He cranked out several

well-padded, largely repetitious books. The Ecology of Freedom (1982;

rev. ed. 1991) is the one he apparently regards as his magnum opus. At

any rate, one of his jacket blurbs (Bookchin 1987a) quotes a

revolutionary anarchist weekly, the Village Voice, to that effect (cf.

Clark [1984]: 215).

The material base for these superstructural effusions was Bookchin’s

providential appointment as a Dean at Goddard College near Burlington,

Vermont, a cuddle-college for hippies and, more recently, punks, with

wealthy parents (cf. Goddard College 1995). He also held an appointment

at Ramapo College. Bookchin, who sneers at leftists who have embarked

upon “alluring university careers” (67), is one of them.

Something went awry. Although Dean Bookchin was indeed widely read by

North American anarchists — one of his acknowledged sycophants (Clark

1984: 11) calls him “the foremost contemporary anarchist theorist”

(Clark 1990: 102; cf. Clark 1982: 59) — in fact, not many anarchists

acknowledged him as their dean. They appreciated his ecological

orientation, to be sure, but some drew their own, more far-reaching

conclusions from it. The Dean came up against an unexpected obstacle.

The master-plan called for anarchists to increase in numbers and to read

his books, and those parts came off tolerably well. It was okay if they

also read a few anarchist classics, Bakunin and Kropotkin for instance

(8), vetted by the Dean, with the understanding that even the best of

them afford “mere glimpses” of the forms of a free society (Bookchin

1971: 79) subsequently built upon, but transcended by, the Dean’s own

epochal discovery, social ecology/social anarchism. Bookchin does not

mind standing on the shoulders of giants — he rather enjoys the feel of

them under his heel — so long as he stands tallest of all.

He must have had no doubt that he would. He seemed to have no

competition intramurally. Paul Goodman, “the most widely known

anarchist” (De Leon 1978:132), untimely died. Tweedy British and

Canadian anarchist intellectuals like Herbert Read, Alex Comfort and

George Woodcock shuffled off into the literary world. Aging

class-struggle fundamentalists like Sam Dolgoff and Albert Meltzer could

be counted on to just keep doing what they were doing, whatever that

was, and with their usual success. “We all stand on the shoulders of

others,” as the Dean generously allows (1982: Acknowledgements). Dean

Bookchin could stand on the shoulders of midgets too. The footing was

even surer there.

What the Dean did not expect was that anarchists would start reading

outside his curriculum and, worse yet, occasionally think for

themselves, something that — in all fairness — nobody could have

anticipated. They read, for instance, about the ethnography of the only

societies — certain of the so-called primitive societies — which have

actually been operative anarchist societies on a long-term basis. They

also read about plebeian movements, communities, and insurrections —

Adamites, Ranters, Diggers, Luddites, Shaysites, Enrages, Carbonari,

even pirates (to mention, to be brief, only Euro-American, and only a

few Euro-American examples) — seemingly outside of the

Marxist-Bookchinist progressive schema. They scoped out Dada and

Surrealism. They read the Situationists and the pro-situs. And, yes,

like earlier generations of anarchists, they were receptive to currents

of cultural radicalism. Indeed, instead of listening to “decent music”

(64 n. 37), they often preferred punk rock to Pete Seeger and Utah

Philips (“the folk song,” he has explained, “constitutes the emotional,

aesthetic, and spiritual expression of a people” [Bookchin 1996: 19]).

And usually their hair was either too long or too short. Who sent them

down this twisted path?

In some cases it was the “self-styled anarchist” (1, 2,9) — this is a

favorite Bookchin slur — who wrote:

The graffiti on the walls of Paris — “Power to the Imagination,” “It is

forbidden to forbid,” “Life without dead times” [sic], “Never work” —

represent a more probing analysis of these sources [of revolutionary

unrest in modern society] than all the theoretical tomes inherited from

the past. The uprising revealed that we are at the end of an old era and

well into the beginning of a new one. The motive forces of revolution

today, at least in the industrialized world, are not simply scarcity and

material need, but also the quality of everyday life, the demand for the

liberation of experience, the attempt to gain control over one’s destiny

[emphasis in the original].

This was not a solemn revolt, a coup d’etat bureaucratically plotted and

manipulated by a “vanguard” party; it was witty, satirical, inventive

and creative — and therein lay its strength, its capacity for immense

self-mobilization, its infectiousness.

The lumpen-bohemian crazy who penned this paean to “neo-Situationist

‘ecstasy’” (26) is the prelapsarian Murray Bookchin (1971: 249–250,

251), These are all, in fact, situationist slogans. Some of us believed

him then. Now he tells us we were wrong, although he never tells us he

ever was. Why should we believe him now?

The Hard Right Republicans like Newt Gingrich along with the

Neo-Conservative intellectuals (most of the latter, like the Dean, being

high-income, elderly Jewish ex-Marxists from New York City who ended up

as journalists and/or academics) blame the decline of Western

civilization on the ‘60s. Bookchin can’t credibly do that, since it was

in the ‘60s that he came out as an anarchist, and built up the

beginnings of his reputation as a theorist. In his golden years, he has

to tread very carefully on this dark and bloody ground:

For all its shortcomings, the anarchic counterculture during the early

part of the hectic 1960s was often intensely political and cast

expressions like desire and ecstasy in eminently social terms, often

deriding the personalistic tendencies of the later Woodstock generation

(9).

By definition “the early part of the hectic 1960s” is presumably the

years 1960–1964. This is the first time I’ve heard tell of an “anarchic

counterculture” during the Kennedy Administration. As manifested in —

what? the Peace Corps? the Green Berets? And while there were

personalistic tendencies in the early 1960s, no one then anticipated,

and so no one derided, the specific “personalistic tendencies of the

later Woodstock generation.” Not Bookchin, certainly, who concluded

prematurely that “Marxian predictions that Youth Culture would fade into

a comfortable accommodation with the system have proven to be false”

(1970: 60).

What did the all-seeing Dean do to combat these nefarious trends in the

20-odd years they have been infecting anarchism? Nothing. He had better

things to do than come to the rescue of the anarchist ideology he

considers the last best hope of humankind. On the one hand, he was

consolidating his alluring academic career; on the other, he was making

a play for ideological hegemony over the Green movement. Were we all

supposed to wait up for him?

There were those who actually tried to implement the Dean’s directive to

formulate “a coherent program” and “a revolutionary organization to

provide a direction for the mass discontent that contemporary society is

creating” (1). Note that Bookchin demands one organization, although he

does not say if he wants an American CNT, an American FAI, or an

American symbiote of both such as formed in Spain, with less than

entirely positive consequences (Bookchin 1994: 20–25; cf. Brademas

1953).

During the recent decades of decadence, there were several opportunities

for the Dean to participate in this important work. He claims that his

parents were Wobblies (2–3) — I wonder what they thought when he became

a Communist? — but he did not himself join the Industrial Workers of the

World although it still, after a fashion, exists. In the late 1970s,

some class-struggle anarchists formed the Anarchist Communist

Federation, which collapsed in acrimony after a few years. The Dean did

not join. One ACF faction set up the syndicalist Workers Solidarity

Alliance; Bookchin didn’t join that one either. And finally, in the last

few years the direct-actionist newspaper Love & Rage has tried to turn

its support groups into the nuclei of a national anarchist organization.

Once again, Bookchin held himself aloof.

Why? No doubt all these organizations fell somewhat short of his

requirements, but as my mother says, “what do you want, an egg in your

beer?” The CNT and the FAI were also imperfect. Everything is imperfect.

If your fundamental critique of contemporary North American anarchists

is that they have failed to assemble in a continental federation, surely

you should have told them what is to be done, and how, a long time ago.

The involvement of so distinguished a militant as Bookchin might

energize an organization which might otherwise appear to be a sect of

squabbling, droning dullards, perhaps because, in each and every

instance, it is a sect of squabbling, droning dullards.

The only possible justification is that — to do justice to the Dean (and

do I ever want to do exactly that!) — he laid down two requirements, not

just one. A directive organization, yes — but with “a coherent program.”

Such time as remained after the performance of his administrative and

academic responsibilities (and the lecture circuit) the Dean has devoted

to providing the coherent program. No doubt Bookchin can organize the

masses (he must have had a lot of practice, and surely great success, in

his Marxist-Leninist days). So can many other comrades — but no other

comrade can concoct a coherent program the way Bookchin can. It is,

therefore, only rational for a division of labor to prevail. Less

talented comrades should do the organizational drudge-work, freeing up

Dean Bookchin — after hours — to theorize. It’s an example of what

capitalist economists call the Law of Comparative Advantage. All of that

Kropotkinist-Bookchinist talk about rotation of tasks, about superseding

the separation of hand-work and brain-work — time enough for that after

the Revolution.

The Dean’s booklet thunders (in a querulous sort of a way) that

“anarchism stands at a turning point in its long and turbulent history”

(1). When didn’t it? In the time-honored sophist manner, the Dean offers

an answer to a nonsense question of his own concoction. “At a time when

popular distrust of the state has reached extraordinary proportions in

many countries,” etc., etc., “the failure of anarchists — or, at least,

many self-styled anarchists — to reach a potentially huge body of

supporters” is due, not entirely of course, but “in no small measure to

the changes that have occurred in many anarchists over the past two

decades... [they] have slowly surrendered the social core of anarchist

ideas to the all-pervasive Yuppie and New Age personalism that marks

this decadent, bourgeoisified era” (1).

Now this is a curious claim. Anarchism is unpopular, not because it

opposes popular ideological fashions, but because it embraces them? It’s

unpopular because it’s popular? This isn’t the first time I’ve

identified this obvious idiocy (Black & Gunderloy 1992).

Simple logic aside (where Dean Bookchin cast it), the Dean’s empirical

assumptions are ridiculous. North American anarchism is not “in retreat”

(59), it has grown dramatically in the last twenty years. The Dean might

have even had a little to do with that. It is leftism which is in

retreat. That this growth of anarchism has coincided with the eclipse of

orthodox anarcho-leftism by more interesting varieties of anarchy

doesn’t conclusively prove that the heterodox anarchies are the growth

sector, but it sure looks that way. For instance, the North American

anarchist publication with the highest circulation, Anarchy: A Journal

of Desire Armed, is on Bookchin’s enemies list (39, 50).

As for the supposition that “Yuppie and New Age personalism” are

“all-pervasive” in our “decadent, bourgeoisified era,” this says more

about Dean Bookchin and the company he keeps than it does about

contemporary society. If you are an upper middle class academic in an

affluent leftist enclave like Burlington or Berkeley, you might well

think so, but to generalize those impressions to the general society is

unwarranted and narcissistic (“personalistic,” as it were). America (or

Canada) is still much more like Main Street than Marin County. If the

Dean really thinks the brat-pack collegians in his Burlington ashram are

representative North American youth, he doesn’t get out enough.

Berating “Yuppies” for their self-indulgence, something Bookchin carries

to the point of obsession (1 & passim), doesn’t defy media-managed

popular opinion, it panders to it. As is typical of progressives,

Bookchin is behind the times. Not only are the ‘60s over, as he has

finally figured out, so are the ‘70s and the ‘80s. The Old Left that he

nostalgically recalls, what he calls the Left That Was (66–86), extolled

discipline, sacrifice, hard work, monogamy, technological progress,

heterosexuality, moralism, a sober and orderly if not downright

puritanical lifestyle, and the subordination of the personal

(“selfishness”) to the interest of the cause and the group (be it the

party, the union or the affinity group):

The puritanism and work ethic of the traditional left stem from one of

the most powerful forces opposing revolution today — the capacity of the

bourgeois environment to infiltrate the revolutionary framework. The

origins of this power lie in the commodity nature of man under

capitalism, a quality that is almost automatically translated to the

organized group — and which the group, in turn, reinforces in its

members.

This passage might have been written by Jacques Camatte, whose essay “On

Organization” has exerted an anti-organizational influence on a lot of

us “lifestyle anarchists” (Camatte 1995: 19–32). By now the reader will

be on to my game (one of them, anyway): the above-quoted author is once

again Bookchin the Younger (1971: 47; cf. Bookchin 1977: ch. 11). Again:

In its demands for tribalism, free sexuality, community, mutual aid,

ecstatic experience, and a balanced ecology, the Youth Culture

prefigures, however inchoately, a joyous communist and classless

society, freed of the trammels of hierarchy and domination, a society

that would transcend the historic splits between town and country,

individual and society, and mind and body (Bookchin 1970: 59).

Bookchin the Elder’s values, in contrast, are precisely those of the New

Right and the neo-conservatives who have set the country’s current

political and ideological agendas — not the New Age bubbleheads Bookchin

may meet in Vermont’s socialist Congressman Bernie Saunders’ hot tub.

“Yuppie” is, on the Dean’s lips, an ill-chosen epithet. It is (lest we

forget) a neologism and semi-acronym for “young urban professional.” To

which aspects of this conjuncture does Dean Bookchin object? To

urbanism? Bookchin is the apostle of urbanism (1987): he thinks that

“some kind of urban community is not only the environment of humanity:

it is its destiny” (1974: 2). To professionalism? A college

professor/bureaucrat such as Bookchin is a professional. The high

technology Bookchin counts on to usher in post-scarcity anarchism (1971:

83–135; 1989: 196) is the invention of professionals and the fever-dream

of techno-yuppies. So if Dean Bookchin, an old urban professional,

disparages young urban professionals, what is it about them that he

hates so much? By a process of elimination, it cannot be that they are

urban and it cannot be that they are professional. It must be that they

are young, as the Dean is not. Actually, a lot of them aren’t all that

young — most are baby boomers entering middle age — but to a Grumpy Old

Man of 75 like Dean Bookchin, that’s young enough to resent. But it’s

not their fault, after all, that most of them will live on long after

Murray Bookchin is dead and forgotten.

And one more thing: Now that we know why the heretical anarchists have

“failed to reach a potentially huge body of supporters,” what’s his

excuse? One of his editors calls him “arguably the most prolific

anarchist writer” (Ehrlich 1996: 384). (Although he has yet to

outproduce the late Paul Goodman, who “produced a stream of books

containing some of his enormous output of articles and speeches” (Walter

1972: 157) and he is likely to be soon surpassed by Hakim Bey — a far

better writer — which may account for some of the insensate hatred the

Dean displays for Bey.) So the truth is out there. Where, after all

these years, are the Bookchinist masses?

The Dean’s vocabulary of abuse evokes what he calls the Left That Was

(66) but hardly the fondness he feels for it. His epithets for

unorthodox anarchists are the standard Stalinist epithets for all

anarchists. He berates anarchist “decadence” over and over, to which he

often appends abstract denunciations of “bourgeois” or “petty bourgeois”

tendencies. “Decadence” is an epithet so indiscriminately applied that a

spirited case has been made for retiring it from responsible discourse

(Gilman 1975). Even without going quite so far, undeniably “’decadent’

as a term of political and social abuse has a generous range of

applications,” especially as deployed by Marxists and Fascists (Adams

1983: 1).

To speak of the Dean’s denunciations of le bourgeois as “abstract” is my

characteristically courteous way of hinting that he of all people had

better pick his words more carefully. I say “abstract” because a college

dean is a member of the bourgeoisie if, in any objective sense, anybody

is. Bookchin surely has a higher income than anybody he’s targeted. Dean

Bookchin has to be deploying the word in a subjective, moralistic,

judgmental sense which, however, he isn’t defining.

It never used to bother the Dean that “many militant radicals tend to

come from the relatively affluent strata” (Bookchin 1971: 25) — as his

student disciples still do. Who else can afford to sit at his feet? For

1996–1997, the two-semester masters’ program in Social Ecology costs

$10,578 (Goddard College 1996). Back then he considered it a “historic

breach” that it was “relatively affluent middle class white youth” who

created the implicitly revolutionary Youth Culture (Bookchin 1970:

54–55).

No one can possibly pronounce with any confidence upon the class

position of present-day North American anarchists in general, much less

the class positions of “individualists,” Bookchinists, etc. (Although my

impression is that most anarcho-syndicalists are campus-based and none

of them are factory workers. Work is much easier to glorify than it is

to perform.) Nor does it bother the Dean that almost the only luminaries

unconditionally admitted to his anarchist pantheon, Bakunin and

Kropotkin, were hereditary aristocrats. Class-baiting is evidently a

weapon to be deployed with fine discrimination.

For Bookchin, as for Stalinists, class is not a category of analysis,

only an argot of abuse. Long ago he dismissed “workeritis” as

“reactionary to the core” rendered meaningless by the trans-class

decomposition of contemporary society (1971: 186–187). So completely did

class disappear from Bookchin’s ideology that a review of one of his

goofier books (Bookchin 1987) exclaimed that “it is what is missing

altogether that renders his book terminally pathetic. Nowhere does he

find fault with the most fundamental dimension of modern living, that of

wage-labor and the commodity” (Zerzan 1994: 166). He now reverts to the

hoary Marxist epithets — “bourgeois,” “petit-bourgeois” and “lumpen” —

but with no pretense that they have, for him, real social content.

Otherwise, how could he apply all these words to the same people? In

their relations to the means of production (or lack thereof), lifestyle

anarchists cannot be both bourgeois and lumpens. And how likely is it

that out of these “thousands of self-styled anarchists” (1), not one is

a proletarian?

Where Bookchin accuses rival anarchists of individualism and liberalism,

Stalinists accuse all anarchists of the same. For example, there was

that Monthly Review contributor who referred to Bookchinism as “a crude

kind of individualistic anarchism” (Bookchin 1971: 225)! In other words,

...capitalism promotes egotism, not individuality or

“individualism.”...The term “bourgeois individualism,” an epithet widely

used today against libertarian elements, reflects the extent to which

bourgeois ideology permeates the socialist project —

— these words being, of course, those of Bookchin the Younger (1971:

284). That the Dean reverts to these Stalinist slurs in his dotage

reflects the extent to which bourgeois ideology permeates his project.

Fanatically devoted to urbanism, the Dean was being complimentary, not

critical, when he wrote that “the fulfillment of individuality and

intellect was the historic privilege of the urban dweller or of

individuals influenced by urban life” (1974: 1). Individuality’s not so

bad after all, provided it’s on his terms.

As for “decadence,” that is an eminently bourgeois swear-word for people

perceived to be having more fun than you are. By now the word has lost

whatever concrete meaning it ever had. Calling post-leftist anarchists

“decadent” is just Dean Bookchin’s way of venting his envy and, as

Nietzsche would say, ressentiment that they are not afflicted with the

hemorrhoids, tax audits, or whatever it is that’s raining on his Mayday

parade.

Chapter 2: What is Individualist Anarchism?

Dean Bookchin posits an eternally recurring “tension” within anarchism

between the individual and the social (4). As this is none other than

the central conundrum of Western political philosophy, the Dean is

neither original nor — more important — has he identified a specifically

anarchist tension. He goes on to identify the antitheses within

anarchism as “two basically contradictory tendencies: a personalistic

commitment to individual autonomy and a collectivist commitment to

social freedom” (4). This is the “unbridgeable chasm” his book title

refers to.

If the Dean is right — that individual autonomy and social liberation

are not just in tension but basically contradictory — then anarchy is

impossible, as anti-anarchists have always maintained. Bookchin here

rejects out of hand what he used to espouse, “a society that would

transcend the historic splits between...individual and society” (1970:

59).

Not all of us share his conservative fatalism. We too have our

apprehensions and our times of despair. But to surrender to them

entirely (which I condemn nobody for doing, if he’s honest about it) is

to renounce any affiliation with anarchism. The Dean won’t fish, neither

will he cut bait. He won’t shit, neither will he get off the pot.

Some of those with impeccable, Bookchin-approved credentials, such as

Kropotkin, had a more tolerant take on this genuinely tragic dilemma:

Anarchist Communism maintains that most valuable of all conquests —

individual liberty — and moreover extends it and gives it a solid basis

— economic liberty — without which political liberty is delusive; it

does not ask the individual who has rejected god, the universal tyrant,

god the king, and god the parliament, to give unto himself a god more

terrible than any of the preceding — god the Community, or to abdicate

upon its altar his independence, his will, his tastes, and to renew the

vow of asceticism which he formerly made before the crucified god. It

says to him, on the contrary, “No society is free so long as the

individual is not so!” (Kropotkin 1890: 14–15)

Bookchin is the veritable high priest of what Kropotkin calls “god the

Community,” “more terrible than any of the preceding,” the most vicious

and oppressive god of all.

“Social freedom” is like the “free market” in the sense that the freedom

referred to has to be metaphorical. It makes no literal sense to

attribute freedom to behavioral interaction systems, even feedback

systems, lacking the necessarily individual qualities of consciousness

and intention. It’s like saying an anthill or the solar system or a

thermostat is free. Free from, and for, what? What else could a society

or a market possibly be free of if not autonomous individuals?

If one assigns any value to individual autonomy, logically there are

only two possibilities for it to even exist, much less flourish, in

society. (Contrary to what the Dean implies [58], not even Max Stirner

thought it was possible outside of society [1995: 161, 271–277].) The

first is a compromise: liberalism. The individual exchanges part of his

precarious natural liberty for society’s protection of the rest of it,

and also for the practical opportunities for advancing his interests

only opened up in a social state. This was the position of Thomas

Hobbes, John Locke, Adam Smith and William Blackstone. In the public

sphere, freedom means democracy; In the private sphere, it means

individual rights.

The second resolution of the quandary, the radical one, is anarchism.

Anarchism rejects the dichotomy as false — maybe not false as existing

society is constituted, but false in its supposed fatality. In an

anarchist society the individual gains freedom, not at the expense of

others, but in cooperation with them. A person who believes that this

condition — anarchy — is possible and desirable is called an anarchist.

A person who thinks it is not possible or not desirable is a statist.

As I shall have no difficulty demonstrating later on, it so happens that

the Dean himself is not an anarchist, merely, in his own terminology, a

“self-styled anarchist.” But that’s no reason for those of us who

(albeit unenthusiastically, if I may speak for myself) are anarchists

not to heed his critique. From George Bernard Shaw to Guy Debord,

anti-anarchists who took anarchism seriously have often supplied crucial

critiques the anarchists were unable or unwilling to construct

themselves. Unfortunately, Bookchin’s isn’t one of them.

What is remarkable about Dean Bookchin’s posturing as the Defender of

the Faith, aside from the fact that he doesn’t share it, is how many of

the Church Fathers (and Mothers) he has excommunicated as

“individualists.” Predictably, William Godwin (5), Max Stirner (7, 11)

and Benjamin Tucker (8) Bookchin summarily dismisses as individualists,

although that hardly does justice to the richness of their insights and

their relevance to any anarchism. (Although even Kropotkin acknowledged

that Godwin espoused communism in the first edition of Political

Justice, only “mitigating” that view in later editions [Kropotkin 1995;

238], and the anarcho-syndicalist Rudolf Rocker acknowledged that Godwin

“was really the founder of the later communist Anarchism” [1947: 7].) 1

But that’s only the beginning of the purge. The Dean condemns even

Proudhon as an individualist (5), although he elsewhere pays tribute to

“Proudhon’s emphasis on federal-ism [which] still enjoys considerable

validity” (Bookchin) 1996: 24). When Bookchin says that something from a

classical anarchist still enjoys considerable validity, this is his way

of saying that’s whom he filched it from. The federalism of Proudhon’s

later years (1979) is virtually identical to Bookchin’s call for a

“confederation of decentralized municipalities” (60). Which is

tantamount to saying that in the end Proudhon was not an anarchist, as I

am not the only one to have noticed (Steven 1984). Indeed, the Dean has

come close to admitting it himself (Bookchin 1977: 21).

The Dean now claims that the prominent Spanish anarchist Federica

Montseney was a “Stirnerite” [sic] in theory if not in practice (8). In

his The Spanish Anarchists she is “one of the FAI’s luminaries”

(Bookchin 1977: 243). The FAI was a “vanguard” (the word is Bookchin’s)

anarcho-communist secret society (Bookchin 1994: 21–22; cf. Brademas

1953).

Even Emma Goldman is under a cloud. Although she was an avowed

anarcho-communist, she also displayed a disqualifying affinity with

Nietzsche (8), and she was, after all, “by no means the ablest thinker

in the libertarian pantheon” (13). Bookchin has a muscular, masculine

disdain for anarchist women such as Emma Goldman, Federica Montseney and

L. Susan Brown. Only his innate modesty kept the Dean from naming who is

the ablest thinker in the libertarian pantheon, but then again, who,

having read him, needs to be told?

Paul Goodman, a “communitarian anarchist” (Stafford 1972: 112), Bookchin

calls “an essentially individualistic anarchist” (12), although Goodman

was essentially an urban-oriented, humanistic anarcho-collectivist

(Goodman & Goodman 1961: ch. 6 & 220; cf. Stafford 1972: 112–113) from

whom Bookchin has cribbed many ideas without admitting it. Notice, for

instance, the remarkable absence of any inferences to the by then

deceased Goodman in Bookchin’s The Limits of the City (1974) or The Rise

of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship (1987), although he did

let slip the name in Crisis in Our Cities (Herber 1965: 177) at a time

when Goodman was in his prime whereas the future Dean was so far from

foreseeing his own celebrity that he wrote under a pseudonym. He’ll soon

wish he’d written this trashy had under a pseudonym.

“Individualist” anarchists in the original sense — people like Max

Stirner (1995) and John Henry Mackay — were never numerous, as Bookchin

observes with too much satisfaction (6–8). And they were always few and

far between, strange to say, in decadent, bourgeois North America,

supposedly their natural breeding-ground. Stirner did not identify

himself as an anarchist, probably because the only (indeed, the very

first) “self-styled” anarchist in the 1840s when he was writing was

Proudhon, for whom moralism, as Stirner noticed, served as a surrogate

for religion (ibid.: 46) — as it does for the Dean. The rather few

individuals who at later times considered themselves Stirnerists have,

however, usually considered themselves anarchists as well, such as the

Italian peasant guerrilla Renzo Novatore (Black & Parfrey 1989: 92–93)

It is worth mentioning — because so many people who toss his name around

have never read him — that Stirner had no social or economic program

whatsoever. He was no more pro-capitalist than he was pro-communist,

although Marxists like Marx, Engels and Bookchin have routinely and

mindlessly castigated him as an apologist for capitalism. Stirner was

just not operating at that level. He was staking a claim, the most

radical claim possible, for the individual as against all the ideologies

and abstractions which, purporting to liberates him in general and in

the abstract, left the individual as personally, practically subordinate

as ever: “In principle... Stirner created a utopistic vision of

individuality that marked a new point of departure for the affirmation

of personality in an increasingly impersonal world” (Bookchin 1982:

159). From Stirner’s perspective — which on this point is also mine —

ideologies like liberalism, humanism, Marxism, syndicalism, and

Bookchinism have all too much in common (cf. Black 1994: 221–222).

Nobody the Dean denounces as a “Stirnerite,” not Michael William (50),

not Hakim Bey (23) is a Stirnerist if this implies that he affirms

amoral egoism and is indifferent to or entirely agnostic about social

and economic formations. Both obviously assume as axiomatic the need for

a social matrix for individual efflorescence. What distinguishes them,

in more than one sense, from the Dean is their appreciation of the

epistemic break in bourgeois thought wrought by the likes of Stirner and

Nietzsche:

A sense of incompleteness haunts Western philosophy after Hegel’s death

and explains much of the work of Kierkegaard, Schopenhauer, Stirner,

Nietzsche, the surrealists and the contemporary existentialists. For the

Marxians merely to dismiss this post-Hegelian development as “bourgeois

ideology” is to dismiss the problem itself.

You guessed it: Bookchin the Younger again (1971: 276). For Bookchin to

dismiss this post-Hegelian development as “bourgeois ideology” is to

dismiss the problem itself.

In a more recent, still narrower sense, “individualism” designates those

who combine rejection of government with espousal of an absolutely

unlimited laissez-faire market system. Such ideologues do exist, but

Bookchin never even mentions a contemporary example, although he cannot

be unaware of their existence, since he made use of one of their

publishers, Free Life Books (Bookchin 1977). Considerable contact with

some of them over the years has persuaded me that most

anarcho-capitalists are sincere in their anarchism, although I am as

certain that anarcho-capitalism is self-contradictory as I am that

anarcho-syndicalism is. Unlike the Dean, I’ve on occasion taken the

trouble to confute these libertarians (Black 1986:141–148; Black 1992:

43–62). But the point is, nobody the Dean targets in this screed is by

any stretch of the imagination (not that he has one) an “individualist”

anarchist in the usual contemporary sense of the term. He never even

claims that any of them are.

The Dean makes the bizarre allegation that those he calls lifestyle

anarchists, decadent successors to the individualist anarchists, claim

(the quotation marks are his) their “sovereign rights” (12):

Their ideological pedigree is basically liberal, grounded in the myth of

the fully autonomous individual whose claims to self-sovereignty are

validated by axiomatic “natural rights,” “intrinsic worth,” or, on a

more sophisticated level, an intuited Kantian transcendental ego that is

generative of all knowable reality (11).

A digression on the, for lack of a better word, ethics of punctuation

marks is in order here. “Quotation marks,” wrote Theodor Adorno,

...are to be rejected as an ironic device. For they exempt the writer

from the spirit whose claim is inherent in irony, and they violate the

very concept of irony by separating it from the matter at hand and

presenting a predetermined judgment on the subject. The abundant ironic

quotation marks in Marx and Engels are the shadows that totalitarian

methods cast in advance upon their writings, whose intention was the

opposite: the seed from which eventually came what Karl Kraus called

Moskauderwelsch [Moscow double-talk, from Moskau, Moscow, and

Kauderwelsch, gibberish or double-talk]. The indifference to linguistic

expression shown in the mechanical delegation of intention to a

typographic cliché arouses the suspicion that the very dialectic that

constitutes the theory’s content has been brought to a standstill and

the object assimilated to it from above, without negotiation. Where

there is something which needs to be said, indifference to literary form

almost always indicates dogmatization of the content. The blind verdict

of quotation marks is its graphic gesture (Adorno 1990: 303).

As a tenured academic, the Dean is presumably aware that in scholarly

discourse — and surely his magisterial essay is such — quotation marks

identify quotations, yet his 45 footnotes fail to reference any use of

these expressions by anybody. That is because no such quotations exist.

So-called lifestyle anarchists (meaning: non-Bookchinists) don’t usually

think or write that way. They tend not to go in for rights-talk because

it is just an ideological, mystifying way of saying what they want,

something better said honestly and directly.

By this maladroit misrepresentation, the Dean inadvertently exposes his

original misunderstanding of the so-called individualist anarchists. Max

Stirner was an amoral egoist or individualist. Godwin and Proudhon were,

if they were individualists at all, moralistic individualists

preoccupied with what they called justice. Lysander Spooner was an

example of a clearly moralistic, natural-rights individualist anarchist.

But when the prominent individualist publisher Benjamin Tucker went over

to Stirnerist egoism in the late nineteenth century, he split the

American individualists. (This, as much as the competition from

collectivists credited by Bookchin [6- 7], brought about the decline of

the tendency.) Although there were exceptions, the moralistic

natural-rights individualists — which were most of them — usually ended

up as essentially advocates of pure free-market capitalism. Those

attracted to the amoralist, egoist or (if you please) “Stirnerist”

position necessarily shared with Stirner a whole-sale rejection of

moralism, that being what Stirner, and Nietzsche after him, absolutely

exploded as a tenable point of view. But no more than Stirner did they

exhibit any interest in laissez-faire (or any) economics. Capitalism, as

Max Weber noticed, has its own moralism, often if not always expressed

as the “Protestant ethic.” The egoists/amoralists and the free-market

natural-rightists parted over precisely this point. The

egoist/amoralists have contributed something to the “lifestyle

anarchists,” the natural-rightists have not.

For instance, take L. Susan Brown (please! — no, just kidding), who’s

attempted, says the Dean, “to articulate and elaborate a basically

individualist anarchism, yet retain some filiations with

anarcho-communism” (13), In a footnote he’s more candid: “Brown’s hazy

commitment to anarcho-communism seems to derive more from her own

preference than from her analysis” (62). In other words, maybe she means

well but she’s just a ditzy dame, like Emma Goldman. Just believing in

anarcho-communism isn’t good enough to acquit you of the charge of

individualism. You have to emote a politically correct,

anti-individualist “analysis” too. I wonder how many Makhnovists, and

how many Spanish rank-and-file insurrectionaries fighting for comunismo

libertario would have passed whatever final exam our pedant might assign

to them to test their “analysis.” I have a pretty good idea how they

would have received such an insolent inquisition. Post-situationist that

I am, I am far from sure that “the revolution will not be televised,”

but I am quite sure it will not be on the final exam, not if teacher

knows what’s good for him. As Marx so truly said, the educator himself

needs educating. And as Diogenes said, why not whip the teacher when the

student misbehaves?

The Dean has brought “down to date” (as Mark Twain would say) the New

England Puritan exercise known as the “relation of faith.” In order to

join the Congregational Church, the applicant not only had to affirm

each and every tenet of Calvinism, he had to demonstrate that he had

gone through a standardized sequence of spiritual experiences.

(Alcoholics Anonymous is the only Protestant cult which still imposes

this requirement.) Most believers never made it that far. What the Dean

means by an inadequate “analysis” is obvious enough: any analysis other

than Bookchinism is no analysis at all. The “disdain for theory” he

ascribes to “individualist” anarchism (11) is really disdain for, or

rather indifference to, his theory. Nowadays, anarcho-communism is

Bookchinism or it is nothing — according to Bookchin (60).

Like it or not — personally (and “personalistically”), I like it —

there’s an irreducible individualistic dimension to anarchism, even

social anarchism, as L. Susan Brown is hardly heretical in pointing out

(1993: ch. 1). According to Kropotkin, Anarcho-Communism says that “No

society is free so long as the individual is not!” (1890: 15). If it

sounds as if anarchism has, as the Dean might say, “filiations” with

liberalism, that’s because anarchism does have filiations with

liberalism. What else could the Dean possibly mean when he writes that

social anarchism is “made of fundamentally different stuff” than

lifestyle anarchism, it is “heir to the Enlightenment tradition” (56)?

As anarcho-syndicalist Rudolf Rocker wrote (and he was only summarizing

the obvious):

In modern Anarchism we have the confluence of the two great currents

which during and since the French Revolution have found such

characteristic expression in the intellectual life of Europe: Socialism

and Liberalism....

Anarchism has in common with Liberalism the idea that the happiness and

the prosperity of the individual must be the standard in all social

matters. And, in common with the great representatives of Liberal

thought, it has also the idea of limiting the functions of government to

a minimum. Its supporters have followed this thought to its ultimate

logical consequences, and wish to eliminate every institution of

political power from the life of society (1947: 16, 18–19).

If he hadn’t seen these words before, the Dean would have come across

part of these passages as quoted by Brown (1993:110). Naturally he’d

rather debunk Brown, an obscure young academic (Jarach 1996), than the

illustrious anarchist elder Rocker. Bookchin’s a playground bully who

doesn’t mind hitting a girl with glasses, but he’d be off his Rocker to

mess with Rudolf.

Nobody chooses his ancestors. Rationally, no one should be ashamed of

them. Visiting the sins of the fathers on the children, even unto the

fourth generation (Exodus 34:7) — as the Dean is doing, pretty much on

schedule — hardly comports with the Enlightenment rationalism he claims

as his ancestry (21, 56).

The Left That Was which provided Bookchin’s original politics,

Marxism-Leninism, also supplied him with a muscular polemical praxis and

a versatile vocabulary of abuse. I’ve already drawn attention to one of

these gambits, denigration-by-quotation-marks. Its “filiations” include

Lenin’s “Left-Wing” Communism, an Infantile Disorder (1940) and

countless texts by Marx and Engels, as Adorno (1990) noticed. John

Zerzan, reviewing Bookchin (1987), noted a related way that the Dean

abused quotation marks: “Another device is to ignore the real history of

urban life, as if illusory; he resorts at times to putting such terms as

‘elected’ representatives, ‘voters’ and ‘taxpayers’ in quotes as though

the terms really don’t, somehow, correspond to reality” (Zerzan 1994:

165). As if to confirm that he’s incorrigible, Bookchin refers to this

review, not as a review, but as a “review” (59). Bookchin was doing the

same thing almost 40 years ago when the first chapter of The Limits of

the City (1974: ix) was written: Tenochtitlan was the “capital,” not the

capital, of the urban, imperialistic, cannibalistic Aztec empire (ibid.:

7, 9).

Bookchin just doesn’t know when to shut up. Having lambasted

individualists as liberals, he turns around and insinuates that they are

fascists! Critics of industrial technology (specifically, George

Bradford of the Fifth Estate) who argue that it determines, as well as

being determined by, social organization are, opines the Dean, “deeply

rooted in the conservative German romanticism of the nineteenth century”

which “fed into National Socialist ideology, however much the Nazis

honored their antitechnological ideology in the breach” (29). This would

be a sophisticated version of guilt-by-association if it were

sophisticated. The Dean doesn’t bother to even identify these

“conservative German” romantics — he hasn’t read them, probably couldn’t

even name them — much less substantiate their unlikely influence on

contemporary “lifestyle” anarchists. Retro-leftist that he is, Bookchin

must suppose that bracketing the hate-words “conservative” and “German”

is a one-two punch nobody recovers from. One page later (30), he admits

that “there is no evidence that Bradford is familiar with Heidegger or

Jünger,” the twentieth-century German intellectuals he j’accuses as

carriers of nineteenth-century conservative German romantic ideology.

McCarthyism is the political strategy of guilt by association. If you

know a Communist, or if you know someone who knows someone who is a

Communist, presumptively you are a Communist and you’ll have to talk

your way out of it, preferably by ratting somebody out. The ex-Communist

Bookchin has outdone Senator McCarthy. The Senator sought to uncover

association as evidence of guilt. The Dean affirms guilt as evidence of

association. That’s really all there is to his dirty little diatribe. To

be even less fair than Joe McCarthy is quite an accomplishment, what

Nietzsche used to call a “downgoing.”

And another thing, nineteenth-century romanticism was neither

exclusively conservative nor exclusively German. What about the liberal

or radical German romanticism of Beethoven and Büchner and Schiller and

Heine? And what about the non-German radical romanticism of Blake and

Burns and Byron and Shelley?

The Dean relates that the Nazis honored their romantic,

anti-technological ideology “in the breach.” “Honored in the breach” is

Bookchin’s poor try at heading off the obvious, and decisive, objection

that the Nazis didn’t have an anti-technological ideology. The Autobahn

was as much a monument to technology as were its contemporaries the

Moscow subway and the New York World’s Fair (which, I suspect, thrilled

the 18 year old Murray Bookchin). So was the V-2. Almost openly erotic

references to iron and steel recur with monotonous and pathological

frequency in Nazi rhetoric. As John Zerzan remarked in a book the Dean

claims to have read (39–42, 62 n. 19);

Behind the rhetoric of National Socialism, unfortunately, was only an

acceleration of technique, even into the sphere of genocide as a problem

of industrial production. For the Nazis and the gullible, it was, again

a question of how technology is understood ideally, not as it really is.

In 1940 the General Inspector for the German Road System put it this

way: “Concrete and stone are material things. Man gives them form and

spirit. National Socialist technology possesses in all material

achievement ideal content” (Zerzan 1994: 140).

I’m not one of those who cries out in horror at the slightest whiff of

anti-Semitism. But the Dean sees fit to insinuate that even the

promiscuously pluralistic Hakim Bey is ideologically akin to Hitler

(22), and that the primitivist quest to recover authenticity “has its

roots in reactionary romanticism, most recently in the philosophy of

Martin Heidegger, whose völkisch ‘spiritualism,’ latent in Being and

Time, later emerged in his explicitly fascist works” (50). So let’s

consider whether Bookchin-vetted classical anarchists are ideologically

kosher. Proudhon was notoriously anti- Semitic (Silbener 1948), but

since Bookchin dismisses him, however implausibly, as too much the

individualist (4–5), let’s set Proudhon aside. Bakunin, the Russian

aristocrat who “emphatically prioritized the social over the individual”

(5) had a notion what was wrong with his authoritarian rival, Karl Marx.

Bakunin considered Marx, “the German scholar, in his threefold capacity

as an Hegelian, a Jew, and a German,” to be a “hopeless statist”

(1995:142). A Hegelian, a Jew, a sort-of scholar, a Marxist, a hopeless

(city-) statist — does this sound like anybody familiar?

The Dean approvingly quotes Lewis Mumford on “the esthetic excellence of

the machine form” (32), a phrase which might have been turned by

Marinetti or Mussolini or anyone else on the ill-defined frontier

between Futurism and Fascism (cf. Moore 1996: 18). In War, the Worlds

Only Hygiene, Marinetti elaborated on the Bookchin/Mumford aesthetic:

We are developing and proclaiming a great new idea that runs through

modern life: the idea of mechanical beauty. We therefore exalt love for

the machine, the love we notice flaming on the cheeks of mechanics

scorched and smeared with coal. Have you never seen a mechanic lovingly

at work on the great powerful body of his locomotive? His is the minute,

loving tenderness of a lover caressing his adored woman (Flint 1972:

90).

The Germans conquered Europe with Panzers and Stukas not by

blood-and-soil hocus-pocus. Nazi ideology is far tool incoherent to be

characterized as either pro- or anti-technological. The Dean in

bewailing our “decadent, bourgeoisified era” (1) and our “decadent

personalism” (2) is himself echoing Nazi and Stalinist rhetoric, as he

surely remembers, and it’s as empty as ever. The point is that the

ideology didn’t have to make sense to matter. It was vague and

inconsistent so as to appeal to as many people as possible who

desperately needed something to believe in, something to free them from

freedom, something to command their loyalty. It didn’t have to be the

same come-on for everyone. The Nazis, fishers of Menschen, understood

that you need different bait to hook different fish, that’s all.

And finally, individualist anarchists are terrorists — or rather,

anarchist terrorists are individualists.

The inseparable association of anarchism with terrorism commenced for

Americans with a specific event: the Haymarket tragedy in Chicago in

1886. As the police were breaking up a peaceable workers’ rally, someone

threw a bomb into their midst, killing or wounding several of them.

Eight prominent anarchists involved in the union movement, but

indisputably innocent of the bombing, were convicted of murder and four

of them hanged (one committed suicide) on the basis of their anarchist

agitation and beliefs. If there is one fact about the history of

anarchism known to everyone who knows at least one fact about the

history of anarchism, it is this: “Thereafter, anarchism, in the public

mind, was inseparably linked with terrorism and destruction” (Avrich

1984: 428; cf. Schuster 1932: 166; Woodcock 1962: 464). And the

anarchism with which the link was forged was the collectivist anarchism

of the Haymarket defendants. That they were, as individuals, innocent is

irrelevant to the genesis of the mad-bomber legend. Innocent in act but

not necessarily in intention: “One of them, [Louis] Lingg, had the best

alibi: he wasn’t there... he was home, making bombs. He was thus

convicted of a crime he would have liked to commit” (Black & Parfrey

1989: 67). In contrast, one historian refers to “the peaceful philosophy

of Individualist Anarchism” (Schuster 1932: 159).

The anarchists’ terrorist reputation was not, however, entirely

fabricated by their enemies (Black 1994: 50–55). In the 1880s, left-wing

European anarchists had already begun to preach, and practice,

“propaganda by the deed,” such as bombings — “chemistry,” as they

sometimes put it — and assassinations. Even the beatific Kropotkin was

originally a supporter of “the new tactic” (Bookchin 1977: 115). Some

thought it the most effective way to dramatize anarchism and disseminate

it to the masses. According to what the Dean calls “the best account of

Spanish Anarchism from 1931 to 1936” (Bookchin 1977: 325), “the last

decade of the [nineteenth] century was one in which the anarchists

really were engaged in the bomb-throwing which is popularly thought to

exhaust their range of activities” (Brademas 1953: 9).

These anarchist terrorists were, to apply Bookchin’s terminology

anachronistically, usually social anarchists, rarely individualist

anarchists. August Vaillant, who bombed the French Chamber of Deputies,

was a leftist (Tuchman 1966: 91) and a member of an anarchist group

(Bookchin 1977: 114). Of the French bombers of the 1890s, Ravachol

alone, so far as anybody knows, was “almost but not quite” a Stirnerist

(Tuchman 1964: 79).

The Spanish anarchists whom the Dean esteems above all others (1977,

1994) had perhaps the longest terrorist tradition of all. The index

reference to “Terrorism, anarchist” in his history of Spanish anarchism

covers dozens of pages (1977: 342). There were sporadic bombings in the

1880s which became chronic, at least in the anarchist stronghold of

Barcelona, in the 1890s (Bookchin 1977: ch. 6). 1918–1923, period of

violent class struggle in Spain, was the time of the pistoleros — gunmen

— a term which applies to both employer-hired goons and anarcho-leftist

militants. Among hundreds of others, “a premier, two former civil

governors, an Arch-bishop, nearly 300 employers, factory directors,

foremen, and police, and many workers and their leaders in the sindicato

libre [a company union], fell before the bullets and bombs of Anarchist

action groups” (Bookchin 1977: 191).

The pistolero phase subsided as the anarchists, who were getting the

worst of the violence anyway, were driven underground by the Primo de

Rivera dictatorship at the same time that a measure of prosperity took

the edge off the class struggle. But anarcho-terrorism never ceased.

During the ‘2Os and ‘3Os, “the FAI’s most well-known militants —

Durruti, the Ascaso brothers, Garcia Oliver — included terrorism in

their repertory of direct action: ‘Gunplay, especially in

“expropriations” and in dealing with recalcitrant employers, police

agents, and blacklegs, was not frowned upon’” (Bookchin 1994: 23). Their

heists “sustained Ferrer-type schools, Anarchist printing presses, and a

large publishing enterprise in Paris which produced the Anarchist

Encyclopedia, as well as many books, pamphlets, and periodicals”

(Bookchin 1977: 199).

I adduce these facts — and reference most of them, deliberately, to

Bookchin — not to condemn or condone what “social anarchists” have

sometimes done but to show up the Dean’s duplicity. Terrorism has been,

for better or for worse, a recurrent anarchist tactic for more than a

century. And the anarcho-terrorists have almost always been “social,”

not individualist, anarchists. I’ve had occasion to rebut leftist

falsifications to the contrary (Black 1994: 50–55). Bookchin justifies

Spanish anarcho-pistolero terrorism as legitimate self-defense (1977:

201–202), an opinion I share, but the fact remains that it was terrorism

— in Bookchinese, “social anarchist” terrorism — not the activity of

individualist anarchists.

Chapter 3: Lifestyle Anarchism

As fast-and-loose as the Dean plays with the word “individualism,”

extrapolating it to something he calls “lifestyle anarchism” is, to

borrow a phrase from Jeremy Bentham not just nonsense, it is nonsense on

stilts. Here is how he does the stretch:

In the traditionally individualist-liberal United States and Britain,

the 1990s are awash in self-styled [that word again!] anarchists who —

their flamboyant radical rhetoric aside — are cultivating a latter-day

anarcho-individualism that I will call lifestyle anarchism.... Ad hoc

adventurism, personal bravura, an aversion to theory oddly akin to the

antirational biases of postmodernism, celebrations of theoretical

incoherence (pluralism), a basically apolitical and anti-organizational

commitment to imagination, desire, and ecstasy, and an intensely

self-oriented enchantment of [sic] everyday life, reflect the toll that

social reaction has taken on Euro-American anarchism over the past two

decades (9).

In a classic tale of cerebral fantasy, Jorge Luis Borges related that in

Tlön, “the dominant notion is that everything is the work of one single

author”: “Criticism is prone to invent authors. A critic will choose two

dissimilar works — the Tao Te Ching and the 1001 Nights, let us say —

and attribute them to the same writer, and then with all probity explore

the psychology of this interesting homme de lettres....” (Monegal & Reid

1981: 118).

That is exactly the Dean’s modus operandi, except that Borges was joking

in a very sophisticated way whereas Bookchin is serious in a very dumb,

dull way. Those he has designated “lifestyle anarchists” are essentially

alike because, well, he has designated them as lifestyle anarchists. The

label is self-verifying. He’s cobbled together all his self-selected

enemies who are also “self-styled” anarchists as “lifestyle anarchists.”

In an essay only recently published, but written In 1980, the Dean

cogently observed that

...anarchism [has] acquired some bad habits of its own, notably an

ahistorical and entrenched commitment to its own past. The decline of

the New Left and the transformation of the sixties counter-culture into

more institutionalized cultural forms compatible with the status quo

created among many committed anarchists a longing for the ideological

security and pedigree that also afflicts the dwindling Marxist sects of

our day (1996: 23).

In the Middle Ages, what the Dean’s doing — but they did it better back

then, and in good faith — was known as Realism. There cannot be a name

(goes the argument) unless there is something real which that name

designates. St. Anselm’s ontological argument for the existence of God,

for instance, by defining God as that which nothing could be greater

than, implies that God is the greatest possible being, and since

something must be the greatest possible being, God must exist. The

reflective reader will probably spot at least some of the flaws in this

line of argument which almost all philosophers have long since

recognized.

I am amazed to learn that the present epoch is “awash in self-styled

anarchists.” Maybe I should awash more often. I hadn’t thought any place

has been awash in self-styled anarchists since certain parts of Spain

were in the 1930s. Maybe Burlington is awash in Bookchinists — a

veritable Yankee Barcelona — but this conjecture is as yet unconfirmed.

“Lifestyle” wasn’t always a dirty word for the Dean. Recalling what was

wrong with the Stalinist ‘30s, he’s written:

“Life-style?” — the word was simply unknown. If we were asked by some

crazy anarchists how we could hope to change society without changing

ourselves, our relations to each other, and our organizational

structure, we had one ritualistic answer: “After the revolution....”

(Bookchin 1970: 57).

Back then the Dean was calling for “communist life-styles” as integral

to the revolutionary project (ibid.: 54). Today, the Dean alleges that

lifestyle anarchism is “concerned with a ‘style’ rather than a society”

(34), but the “crazy anarchists” he formerly identified with, but now

maligns, agree with Bookchin the Younger that social revolution is

lifestyle revolution, the revolution of everyday life: “It is plain that

the goal of revolution today must be the liberation of daily life”

(Bookchin 1971: 44).

Most of this gibberish is pejorative and content-free. If the dizzy Dean

is saying anything substantive, he is claiming that those he has lumped

(lumpened?) together as lifestyle anarchists are (1) anti-theoretical,

(2) apolitical, (3) hedonistic and (4) anti-organizational. The question

of organization is so large as to require a chapter in itself (Chapter

5). I’ll take up the other charges here.

Anti-Theoretical. As to this the Dean is nothing less than grotesque.

When is a theorist not a theorist? When his theory is not the theory of

Dean Bookchin. That disqualifies Guy Debord, Michel Foucault, Jacques

Camatte, Jean Baudrillard and, to all intents and purposes, everybody

published by Autonomedia. Bookchinism is not just the only true theory,

it is the only theory. (Marxism, of course, is not theory, it is

bourgeois ideology [Bookchin 1979].) Like Hegel and Marx before him,

Bookchin likes to think that he is not only the finest but the final

theorist. As they were wrong, so is he.

Apolitical. This is, if anything, even zanier. How can a political

philosophy like anarchism — any variety of anarchism — be apolitical?

There is, to be sure, a difference between Bookchinism and all

anarchisms. Anarchism is anti-political by definition. Bookchinism is

political (specifically, it is city-statist, as shall shortly be shown).

It follows as a matter of course that Bookchinism is incompatible with

anarchism, but it doesn’t follow that lifestyle anarchism is apolitical,

only that lifestyle anarchism is, at worst, anarchism, and at best,

contrary to Bookchinism.

Hedonistic. Sure, why not?

The Dean is right about one thing: it’s the truth (if no longer the

whole truth) that anarchism continues the Enlightenment tradition. As

such, it stands for life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness in a much

more radical way than liberalism ever did. Godwin, for instance, argued

that anarchism was the logical implication of utilitarianism. Kropotkin

was convinced that “’the greatest happiness of the greatest number’ is

no longer a dream, a mere Utopia. It is possible” (1924: 4). His

adoption of the utilitarian maxim was neither ironic nor critical.

Hedonism in some sense of the word has always been common ground for

almost all anarchists. Rudolph Rocker attributed anarchist ideas to the

Hedonists and Cynics of antiquity (1947: 5). Back before he lost his

groove, the Dean praised the utopian socialist Charles Fourier for

“envision[ing] new communities that would remove restrictions on

hedonistic behavior and, almost embarrassingly to his disciples, sought

to harmonize social relations on the basis of pleasure” (1974: 112). As

that “most unsavory” (20) of lifestyle anarchists, Hakim Bey, put it,

“your inviolable freedom awaits to be completed only by the love of

other monarchs” (22 [quoting Bey 1991: 4]) — “words that could be

inscribed on the New York Stock Exchange,” grumps the Dean, “as a credo

for egotism and social indifference” (22). Decadent degenerates that we

are, lifestyle anarchists tend to favor “a state of things in which each

individual will be able to give free rein to his inclinations, and even

to his passions, without any other restraint than the love and respect

of those who surround him.” Presumably this credo, a more overtly

hedonistic version of Bey’s socially indifferent egotism, is even better

suited to decorate the Stock Exchange — which would probably surprise

its author, the anarcho-communist Kropotkin (1890:15). We think love and

respect could be forces as powerful as they are wonderful. Even Bakunin

on occasion sounded more like Raoul Vaneigem than Jean-Jacques Rousseau,

as when he wrote that the anarchist is distinguished by “his frank and

human selfishness, living candidly and unsententiously for himself, and

knowing that by doing so in accordance with justice he serves the whole

of society” (quoted in Clark 1984: 68).

The plebeian radical William Benbow originated the idea of the General

Strike — the “Grand National Holiday” of the working classes — in 1832

(Benbow n.d.). (The Dean is wrong when he writes that

anarcho-syndicalism “can be traced back, in fact, to notions of a ‘Grand

Holiday’ [sic] or general strike proposed by the English Chartists” (7).

Although Benbow went on to become a Chartist, there was no Chartist

movement in 1832, the Chartists never espoused the general strike, and

there was never anything remotely syndicalist about the Chartists’

purely political program centered on universal male suffrage [Black

1996c].) Benbow called upon the direct producers “to establish the

happiness of the immense majority of the human race” — namely,

themselves — to secure their own “ease, gaiety, pleasure and happiness.”

If it’s hedonistic or decadent for impoverished, exploited, overworked

people to stage a revolution for generalized case, gaiety, pleasure and

happiness, long live hedonism and decadence!

The Dean’s yapping about “Yuppie” self-indulgence is, even aside from

its gross hypocrisy, misdirected. The problem is not that Yuppies, or

unionized factory workers, or small businessmen, or retirees, or

whomever, are selfish. In an economy orchestrated by scarcity and risk,

where almost anybody might be “downsized” (Black 1996b), only the

super-rich can afford not to be selfish (but they usually are anyway:

old habits die hard). The problem is the prevailing social organization

of selfishness as a divisive force which actually diminishes the self.

As society is now set up, individual selfishness is collectively, and

literally, self-defeating.

The Dean recoils in horror from a coinage he attributes to Hakim Bey,

“Marxism-Stirnerism” (20) — actually, as Bookchin probably knows, Bey

borrowed it from me (Black 1986: 130). It comes from my Preface to the

Loompanics reprint of a pro-situationist text, The Right to Be Greedy

(For Ourselves 1983), which argued for “communist egoism.” I made it

clear that I didn’t think the essay offered any ultimate resolution of

the tension between the individual the social. No theory will ever

accomplish that a priori, although theory might inform its resolution in

practice. But the essay is acute in distinguishing the self-sacrificing

militant from the selfish revolutionary: “Any revolutionary who is to be

counted upon can only be in it for himself — unselfish people can always

switch loyalty from one projection to another” (For Ourselves 1983) —

for example, from Stalinism to Trotskyism to Anarchism to....

We need, not for people to be less selfish, but for us to be better at

being selfish in the most effective way, together. For that, they need

to understand themselves and society better — to desire better, to

enlarge their perceptions of the genuinely possible, and to appreciate

the real institutional (and ideological) impediments to realizing their

real desires. By “real desires” I don’t mean “what I want people to

want,” I mean what they really want, severally and together, as arrived

at — as Benbow so presciently put it — by unconstrained, general,

unhurried reflection, “to get rid of our ignorant impatience, and to

learn what it is we do want.” And also what we “do not need” (Bookchin

1977: 307).

In typical retro-Marxist fashion, the Dean purports to resort, on this

point as on others, to the ultimate argument from authority, the

argument from History:

The Austrian workers’ uprising of February 1934 and the Spanish Civil

War of 1936, I can attest [emphasis added], were more than orgiastic

“moments of insurrection” but were bitter struggles carried on with

desperate earnestness and magnificent elan, all aesthetic epiphanies

notwithstanding (23).

As a preliminary quibble — I can sometimes be as petty as lit. Dean

usually is — I object to the word “attest” here. To “attest” to

something — the signing of a will, for instance — means to affirm it as

a witness, from personal knowledge. Bookchin was 13 in 1934 and 15 in

1936. He has no more personal knowledge of either of these revolts than

my six year old niece does. Similarly, the Dean “would like to recall a

Left That Was,” “the Left of the nineteenth and early twentieth century”

(66), and rattles away as if he were doing exactly that — although that

is, for someone born in 1921, a chronological impossibility. Another old

man, Ronald Reagan, remembered the moving experience of liberating

German concentration camps, although he spent World War II making

propaganda films in Hollywood. What the uprising of the Austrian workers

(state socialists, incidentally, not anarchists), savagely suppressed in

only three days, has to do with present-day revolutionary anarchist

prospects, I have no more idea than Bookchin seems to. Abstaining from

“orgiastic” insurrection, if they did, must not have improved their

military situation much.

Spain, where anarchists played so prominent a role in the revolution,

especially in its first year, is a more complicated story. Of course it

was a bitter struggle. It was a war, after all, and war is hell. Hey! —

this just occurred to me — did Bookchin fight the Fascists when he had

the chancy in World War II? Not that I’ve ever heard. He would have been

draft-age military material, at age 21, in 1942 when they were drafting

almost everybody, even my spindly, nearsighted 30 year old father.

Waving the bloody shirt at lifestyle anarchists might be more impressive

if Bookchin had ever worn it.

The fact that an experience is one thing doesn’t necessarily entail that

it is only that one thing. This is the sort of metaphysical dualism

which vitiates almost everything the Dean has to say (Jarach 1996).

There was a great deal festivity and celebration even in the Spanish

Revolution, despite the unfavorable conditions. In Barcelona, “there was

a festive enthusiasm in the streets” (Fraser 1979:152). Some couples,

“‘believing the revolution made everything possible’ began living

together and splitting up with too much ease (ibid.: 223). George

Orwell, who fought with them, reported that the Catalan militiamen on

the Aragon front were badly armed and even water was scarce, but “there

was plenty of wine” (1952: 32). Indeed, “Orwell’s description of the

city [of Barcelona] during this phase is still intoxicating: the squared

and avenues bedecked with black-and-red flags, the armed people, the

slogans, the stirring revolutionary songs, the feverish enthusiasm of

creating a new world, the gleaming hope, and the inspired heroism”

(Bookchin 1977: 306). In Barcelona, young anarchists commandeered cars —

motoring was a thrill hitherto beyond their means — and careened through

the streets on errands of dubious revolutionary import (Seidman 1991: 1,

168; Borkenau 1963: 70): mostly they were just joyriding. Bookchin

reviles the romanticism of the lifestyle anarchists, forgetting his own

statement that “Spanish Anarchism placed a strong emphasis on

life-style” (1977: 4). As José Peirats remembered the Spanish

Revolution, “we regarded ourselves as the last romantics” (Bolloten

1991: 769 n. 17). May they not be the last!

Consider the Paris Commune of 1871, which the Situationists referred to

as the greatest rave-up of the nineteenth century:

The Communards of the Belleville district in Paris, who fought the

battles of the barricades and died by the tens of thousands under the

guns of the Versaillais, refused to confine their insurrection to the

private world described by symbolist poems or the public world described

by Marxist economics. They demanded the eating and the moral, the filled

belly and the heightened sensibility. The Commune floated on a sea of

alcohol — for weeks everyone in the Belleville district was

magnificently drunk. Lacking the middle-class proprieties of their

instructors, the Belleville Communards turned their insurrection into a

festival of public joy, play and solidarity (Bookchin 1971: 277).

Revolutionaries make love and war.

Chapter 4: On Organization

Well, finally, the Dean has identified a concrete “programmatic”

difference between him and his appointed enemies. Most, maybe all of

those he criticizes as “lifestyle anarchists” indeed oppose the

establishment of some sort of authoritative anarchist organization, as

well they should (Black 1992:1 181–193). It is something North American

anarchists have always shied away from, even in the heyday of the Left

That Was. The Dean, as previously noted, has spent his entire anarchist

life going out of his way not to involve himself with any such

organization — not from principle, apparently, but because he was

preoccupied, personalistically, with his own career. Some of us think

the enterprise is ill-advised, even counterproductive, even apart from

our suspicion that it wouldn’t advance our careers. A lot of us don’t

even have careers.

Jacques Camatte (1995: 19–38) and, before him, the disillusioned

socialist Robert Michels (1962) with whom the Dean is not entirely

unfamiliar (1987: 245), provided some theoretical reasons for us to

think so. Dean Bookchin himself (1977,1996) recounts the bureaucratic

degeneration of what he considers the greatest anarcho-syndicalist

organization of them all, the Spanish CNT-FAI. Even Kropotkin, one of

the few anarchists to enjoy the Dean’s imprimatur, thought that a

syndicalist regime would be far too centralized and authoritarian: “As

to its Confederal Committee, it borrows a great deal too much from the

Government that it has just overthrown” (1990: xxxv).

With organizations, especially large-scale ones, the means tend to

displace the ends; the division of labor engenders inequality of power,

officially or otherwise; and representatives, by virtue of greater

interest, experience, and access to expertise, effectively supplant

those they represent. We agree with the Dean that “the words

‘representative democracy,’ taken literally, are a contradiction in

terms” (1987: 245). In other words, “delegated authority entails

hierarchy” (Dahl 199O: 72). Thus in Spain the 30,000 faistas quickly

came to control one million cenetistas, whom they led into policies —

such as entering the government — to which the FAI militants should have

been even more fiercely opposed than the rank-and-file CNT unionists. In

a crisis — which might be of their own creation — the leadership

generally consults its “personalistic” interests and the maintenance

requirements of the organization, in that order; only then, if ever,

their announced ideology; not the will of the membership (although the

leaders will invoke it if it happens to coincide with their policies

and, for that matter, even if it doesn’t). This has happened too often

to be an accident.

We do not reject organization because we are ignorant of the history of

anarchist organizations. We reject it, among other reasons, because we

know that history only too well, and Bookchin is one of those who has

taught it to us. Nobody is surprised that business corporations,

government bureaucracies, hieratic churches and authoritarian political

parties are in practice, as in theory, inimical to liberty, equality and

fraternity. (Also incompetent: as Paul Goodman put it [1994: 58],

central organization “mathematically guarantees stupidity.”) What at

first surprises, and what cries out for explanation, is that egalitarian

and libertarian organizations sooner or later — usually sooner — end up

the same way.

Robert Michels (himself a socialist) studied the German Social

Democratic Party — a Marxist party programmatically committed to social

equality — a few years before the First World War, and found it to be

thoroughly hierarchic and bureaucratic. Vindicating Michels, the vast

majority of German socialists, contrary to their official antiwar

position, promptly followed their leaders in supporting the war.

Anarchists might congratulate themselves that Marxism, unlike anarchism,

was a “bourgeois ideology” (Bookchin 1979) — like the Pharisees,

thanking God that they are not as other men. (Although that would be

“idealism,” another bourgeois ideology.) Michels, writing at a time when

syndicalism seemed to be an important social movement, noted:

Here we find a political school, whose adherents are numerous, able,

well-educated, and generous-minded, persuaded that in syndicalism it has

discovered the antidote to oligarchy. But we have to ask whether the

antidote to the oligarchical tendencies of organization can possibly be

found in a method which is itself rooted in the principle of

representation.... Syndicalism is... mistaken in attributing to

parliamentary democracy alone the inconveniences that arise from the

principle of delegation in general (1962: 318).

Times have changed: North American syndicalists aren’t numerous, aren’t

able, and least of all are they generous-minded, although most may be

“well-educated” if you equate a good education with college — something

that I, having taught American college students, don’t do.

The Spanish experience suggests that Michels was right about

“organization” at least in the sense of large-scale organizations whose

higher reaches consist of representatives, such as the Spanish CNT or

the confederal “Commune of communes” (57) the Dean desires. Even if

these organizations are only minimally bureaucratic — a precious, and

precarious, accomplishment — they are nonetheless inherently hierarchic.

The CNT pyramid had at least six levels (and some outbuildings):

Section → Syndicate → Local federation of syndicates → Comercal

federation → Regional confederation → National confederation (congress)

(Brademas 1953: 16–17)

This leaves out, for instance, several intermediary bodies such as the

Regional Plenum, the Plenum of Regionals (no, I’m not joking) and the

National Committee (Bookchin 1977: 170). What happened was just what

might have been expected to happen had anybody anticipated the CNT’s

abrupt rise to power. When their turn came, in Spain, the organizational

anarchists blew it too. It is not only that the most vociferous FAI

militants, like Montseney and García Oliver, joined the Loyalist

government — that could be explained away, albeit implausibly, as

“personalistic” treachery — but that most of the CNT-FAI rank-and-file

went along with it (Brademas 1953: 353). Even more startling than the

leaders’ support for what they were supposed to be against (the state)

was their opposition to what they were supposed to be for — social

revolution — which swept over much of Republican Spain without the

support, and in most cases over the objections, of the leaders (Bolloten

1991; Broué & Témime 1972). The leaders placed the war ahead of the

revolution and managed, at the cost of a million lives, to lose both

(Richards 1983).

The Spanish experience was not unique. The Italian syndicalists mostly

went over to Fascism (Roberts 1979). The sham industrial democracy of

syndicalist corporatism only needed a little fine-tuning and a touch of

cosmetics to be finessed into the sham syndicalism of Fascist

corporatism.

For North Americans, no example — not even the Spanish example — is more

important than the Mexican Revolution. Had it turned out differently, it

would have recoiled upon the United States with incalculable force.

Because the revolution was contained south of the border, in America the

Federal and state governments (and the vigilantes they encouraged) had a

free hand to crush the anarchists, syndicalists and socialists so

thoroughly that they’ve never recovered.

During the Mexican Revolution, the organized anarcho- syndicalists

supported the liberals — the Constitutionalists — against the Zapatista

and Villista social revolutionaries (Hart 1978: ch. 9). As urban

rationalist progressives (like Bookchin), they despised peasant

revolutionaries still clinging to Catholicism. Besides, they thought

that Pancho Villa — here’s an uncanny precursor to Bookchinist jargon —

acted too much like a “personalist”! (ibid.: 131). On behalf of the

Constitutionalist regime — the one President Wilson sent the U.S. Army

in to prop up — the anarcho-syndicalists raised “Red Battalions,”

perhaps 12,000 strong, “a massive augmentation of commanding general

Obregon’s Constitutional army” (ibid.: 133, 135). They soon reaped the

reward — repression — that they’d earned. By 1931 the government had the

Mexican working class under control (ibid.: 175–177, 183), as it still

does. If revolution resumes it will be the Neo-Zapatistas, the Mayan

peasants of Chiapas, who set it off (Zapatistas 1994).

Without attempting a comprehensive critique of the Dean’s

municipal-confederal socialism, I’d like to raise a couple of prosaic

points of fact which do not depend upon, although they are consistent

with, the anti-organizational critiques of Michels, Camatte, Zerzan,

myself and, by now, many others. Direct democracy is not, and for all

anybody knows, never was, all it’s cracked up to be by the Dean. Most of

the extant authors from classical antiquity, who knew the working system

better than we ever will, were anti-democratic (Finley 1985: 8–11), as

Bookchin elsewhere admits (1989: 176). The word “democracy” was almost

always used pejoratively before the nineteenth century — that is, when

it referred only to direct democracy: “To dismiss this unanimity as a

debasement of the currency, or to dismiss the other side of the debate

as apologists who misuse the term, is to evade the need for explanation”

(Finley 1985: 11; cf. Bailyn 1992: 282–285).

The Athenian polis, the most advanced form of direct democracy ever

practiced for any extended period, was oligarchic. It’s not only that,

as Bookchin grudgingly concedes (59), the polity excluded slaves,

numerous other noncitizens (one-third of free men were technically

foreigners [Walzer 1970: 106]), and women, i.e., the polis excluded the

overwhelming majority of adult Athenians. Even the Dean acknowledges,

but attaches no importance to, the fact that maybe three-fourths of

adult male Athenians were “slaves and disenfranchised resident aliens”

(1987: 35). It could not have been otherwise:

These large disenfranchised populations provided the material means for

many Athenian male citizens to convene in popular assemblies, function

as mass juries in trials, and collectively administer the affairs of the

community (Bookchin 1989: 69).

“A modicum of free time was needed to participate in political affairs,

leisure that was probably [!] supplied by slave labour, although it is

by no means true that all active Greek citizens were slave owners”

(Bookchin 1990: 8). Greek culture, as Nietzsche observed, flourished at

the expense of the “overwhelming majority”: “At their expense, through

their extra work, that privileged class is to be removed from the

struggle for existence, in order to produce and satisfy a new world of

necessities” (1994: 178).

There are two more points to ponder.

The first is that the vast majority of the Athenian citizen minority

abstained from participation in direct democracy, just as the majority

of American citizens abstain from our representative democracy. Up to

40,000 Athenian men enjoyed the privilege of citizenship, less than half

of whom resided in the city itself (Walzer 1970: 17). “All the policy

decisions of the polis,” according to Bookchin, “are formulated directly

by a popular assembly, or Ecclesia, which every male citizen from the

city and its environs (Attica) is expected to attend” (1974: 24). In

reality, the facility provided for the assembly accommodated only a

fraction of them (Dahl 1990: 53–54), so most must have been expected not

to attend, and didn’t. Attendance probably never exceeded 6,000, and was

usually below 3,000. The only known tally of the total vote on a measure

is 3,461 (Zimmern 1931: 169). And this despite the fact that many

citizens were slaveowners who were thereby relieved, in whole or in

part, of the need to work (Bookchin 1990: 8). And despite the fact that

the prevalent ideology, which even Socrates subscribed to, “emphatically

prioritized the social over the individual,” as the Dean approvingly

asserts that Bakunin did (5): “as a matter of course,” the Athenians

“put the city first and the individual nowhere” (Zimmern 1931: 169–170

n. 1). Even most Athenians with the time to spare for public affairs

avoided political involvement.

In this respect they resembled the remnants of direct democracy in

America, the New England town meetings. These originated in the

Massachusetts Bay colony when the dispersal of settlements made a

unitary central government impractical. At first informally, but soon

formally, towns exercised substantial powers of self-government. The

original form of self-government was the town meeting of all freemen,

which took place anywhere from weekly to monthly. This system still

prevails, formally, in some New England towns, including those in

Bookchin’s adopted state Vermont — but as a form without content. In

Vermont the town meeting takes place only one day a year (special

meetings are possible, but rare). Attendance is low, and declining: “In

recent years there has been a steady decline in participation until in

some towns there are scarcely more persons present than the officials

who are required to be there” (Nuquist 1964: 4–5). The Dean has thrown a

lot of fairy-dust on present-day Vermont town meetings (1987:268–270;

1989: 181) without ever claiming that they play any real role in

governance. Indeed, Bookchin hails the town meeting’s “control”

(so-called) precisely because “it does not carry the ponderous weight of

law” (1987: 269): in other words, it’s just a populist ritual. By

failing to either “carry the ponderous weight of law” or jettison it —

tasks equally beyond its illusory authority — the town meeting

legitimates those who do carry, willingly, the ponderous weight of law,

the practitioners of what the Dean calls statecraft.

In modern Vermont as in ancient Athens, most people think they have

better things to do than attend political meetings, because most people

are not political militants like the Dean. Several sorts of, so to

speak, special people flock to these get-togethers. These occasions tend

to attract a person (typically a man) who is an ideological fanatic, a

control freak, an acting-out victim of mental illness, or somebody who

just doesn’t have a life, and often someone favored by some combination

of the foregoing civic virtues.

Face-to-face democracy is in-your-face democracy. To the extent that the

tireless typicals turn up, they discourage those not so afflicted from

participating actively or returning the next time. The Dean, for

instance, speaks glowingly of “having attended many town meetings over

the last fifteen years” (1987: 269) — they aren’t even held where he

lives Burlington — who but a political pervo-voyeur could possibly get

off on these solemn ceremonies? Some people like to watch autopsies too.

The same types who’d get themselves elected in a representative

democracy tend to dominate, by their bigmouthed bullying, a direct

democracy too (Dahl 1990: 54). Normal non-obsessive people will often

rather appease the obsessives or even kick them upstairs than prolong an

unpleasant interaction with them. If face-to-face democracy means having

to face democrats like Bookchin, most people would rather execute an

about-face. And so the minority of political obsessives, given an

institutional opportunity, tend to have their way. That was how it was

in Athens, where direction came from what we might call militants, what

they called demagogues: “demagogues — I use the word in a neutral sense

— were a structural element in the Athenian political system [which]

could not function without them” (Finley 1985: 69).

In “A Day in the Life of a Socialist Citizen,” Michael Walzer (1970: ch.

11) sent up muscular, direct democracy before Bookchin publicized his

version of it. Walzer’s point of departure was what Marx and Engels

wrote in The German Ideology about how the post-revolutionary communist

citizen is a fully realized, all-sided person who “hunts in the morning,

fishes in the afternoon, rears cattle in the evening, and plays the

critic after dinner” without ever being confined to any or all of these

social roles (ibid.: 229). Bookchin has endorsed this vision (1989: 192,

195). Sounds good, but a muscular municipal socialist has further

demands on his time:

Before hunting in the morning, this unalienated man of the future is

likely to attend a meeting of the Council on Animal Life, where he will

be required to vote on important matters relating to the stocking of the

forests. The meeting will probably not end much before noon, for among

the many-sided citizens there will always be a lively interest even in

highly technical problems. Immediately after lunch, a special session of

the Fishermen’s Council will be called to protest the maximum catch

recently voted by the Regional Planning Commission, and the Marxist man

will participate eagerly in these debates, even postponing a scheduled

discussion of some contradictory theses on cattle-rearing. Indeed he

will probably love argument far better than hunting, fishing, or rearing

cattle. The debates will go on so long that the citizens will have to

rush through dinner in order to assume their role as critics. Then off

they will go to meetings of study groups, clubs, editorial boards, and

political parties where criticism will be carried on long into the night

(ibid.: 229–230).

In other words, “Socialism means the rule of the men with the most

evenings to spare” (ibid.: 235). Walzer is far from being my favorite

thinker (Black 1985), but what he sketched here is as much paradigm as

parody. It scarcely exaggerates and in no way contradicts Rousseau’s —

his fellow Genevan Calvin’s — ascetic republican civism, which in turn

is disturbingly close to Bookchin’s muscular, moralistic municipalism.

The Dean has long insisted upon the potential of what he calls

“liberatory technology” to free the masses from toil and usher in a

post-scarcity society (1971: 83–139). “Without major technological

advances to free people from toil,” anarchy — especially “primitivistic,

prerational, antitechnological, and anticivilizational” anarchy — is

impossible (26). No part of his Marxist heritage is more vital to

Bookchin than its notion of humanity passing from the realm of necessity

to the realm of freedom by way of the rational, socially responsible

application of the advanced technology created by capitalism.

The Dean is furious with “lifestyle anarchists” who doubt or deny this

postulate of positivist progressivism, but for present purposes, let’s

assume he’s right. Let’s pretend that under anarcho-democratic, rational

control, advanced technology would drastically reduce the time devoted

to production work and afford economic security to all. Technology would

thus do for the upright (and uptight) republican Bookchinist citizenry

what slavery and imperialism did for the Athenian citizenry — but no

more. Which is to say, not nearly enough.

For even if technology reduced the hours of work, it would not reduce

the hours in a day. There would still be 24 of them. Let’s make-believe

we could automate all production-work away. Even if we did, technics

couldn’t possibly do more than shave a few minutes off the long hours

which deliberative, direct democracy would necessitate, the “often

prosaic, even tedious but most important forms of self-management that

required patience, commitment to democratic procedures, lengthy debates,

and a decent respect for the opinions of others within one’s community”

(Bookchin 1996: 20; cf. Dahl 1990: 32–36, 52). (I pass over as beneath

comment Bookchin’s avowal of “a decent respect for the opinions of

others.”) Having to race from meeting to meeting to try to keep the

militants from taking over would be even worse than working, but without

the pay.

That was the first practical objection. The second is that there is no

reason to believe that there has ever been an urban, purely direct

democracy or even a reasonable approximation of one. Every known

instance has involved a considerable admixture of representative

democracy which sooner or later usually subordinated direct democracy

where it didn’t eliminate it altogether. In Athens, for instance, a

Council of 500, chosen monthly by lot, set the agenda for the meetings

of the ekklesia (there was no provision for new business to be brought

up from the floor [Bookchin 1971: 157; Zimmern 1931: 170 n. 1]) and

which, in turn, elected an inner council of 50 for governing between

assemblies, which in turn elected a daily chairman. Sir Alfred Zimmern,

whose sympathetic but dated account of Athenian democracy the Dean has

referred to approvingly (1971: 159, 288 n. 27), observed that the

Council consisted of paid officials (Zimmern 1931: 165), a detail the

Dean omits. In general, “the sovereign people judged and administered by

delegating power to representatives” (ibid,: 166). Generals, for

instance — very important officials in an imperialist state frequently

at war — were elected annually (Dahl 1990: 30; cf. Bookchin 1971: 157).

These were remarkably radical democratic institutions for their day, and

even for ours, but they are also substantial departures from Bookchinist

direct democracy. Nonetheless the Dean only grudgingly admits that

Athens was even a “quasi-state” (Bookchin 1989: 69), whatever the hell a

“quasi-state,” is. Unbelievably, the Dean claims that “Athens had a

‘state’ in a very limited and piecemeal sense... the ‘state’ as we know

it in modern times could hardly be said to exist among the Greeks”

(1987: 34). Just ask Socrates. What’ll you be having? Hemlock, straight

up. The Dean has elsewhere explained that in his municipal Utopia,

face-to-face assemblies would set policy but leave its administration to

“boards, commissions, or collectives of qualified, even elected

officials” (Bookchin 1989: 175) — the experts and the politicians.

Again: “Given a modest but by no means small size, the polis could be

arranged institutionally so that it could have its affairs conducted by

well-rounded, publicly-engaged men with a minimal, carefully guarded

degree of representation” (Bookchin 1990: 8). Meet the new boss, same as

the old boss!

Consider Switzerland, a highly decentralized federal republic which for

the Dean is a fascinating example of “economic and political

coordination within and between communities that render[s] statecraft

and the nation-state utterly superfluous” (1987: 229). Alexis de

Tocqueville, as astute a student of democracy as ever was, wrote in

1848:

It is not sufficiently realized that, even in those Swiss cantons where

the people have most preserved the exercise of their power, there does

exist a representative body entrusted with some of the cares of

government. Now, it is easy to see, when studying recent Swiss history,

that gradually those matters with which the people concern themselves

are becoming fewer, whereas those with which their representatives deal

are daily becoming more numerous and more important. Thus the principle

of pure democracy is losing ground gained by the opposing principle. The

former is insensibly becoming the exception and the latter the rule

(1969b: 740).

Even in the Swiss cantons there were representative bodies

(legislatures) to which the executive and the judiciary were strictly

subordinate (ibid.: 741). Civil liberties were virtually unknown and

civil rights entirely so, a much worse situation than in most European

monarchies at the time (ibid.: 738). De Tocqueville considered the Swiss

Confederation of his day “the most imperfect of all the constitutions of

this kind yet seen in the world” (ibid.: 744). Earlier, John Adams had

also made the point that the Swiss cantons were aristocratic republics

as well as observing that their historical tendency was for hereditary

elites to entrench themselves in office (Coulborn 1965: 101–102).

As for the “economic and political coordination” which renders the Swiss

“nation-state utterly superfluous” (Bookchin 1987: 229), if the Swiss

nation-state is utterly superfluous, why does it exist at all? As it

does, as surely as exist the Swiss banks whose numbered accounts

safeguard so much of the loot of the world’s dictators and gangsters

(Ruwart 1996: 4). Is there possibly a connection? Might Switzerland’s

rakeoff from loan-sharking and money-laundering underwrite its direct

democracy (such as it is) just as slavery and imperialism underwrote the

direct democracy of Athens? A Swiss parliamentarian once referred to his

country as a nation of receivers of stolen goods.

Those of us who are somewhat older than most North American anarchists,

although much younger than the Dean, also recall the history of efforts

to form an all-inclusive anarchist organization here. Never did they

come close to success. (To anticipate an objection — the Industrial

Workers of the World is not now, and never has been, an avowedly

anarchist organization. It is syndicalist, not anarchist [and not

Bookchinist]). Not until about 1924, when most of the membership had

fallen away, joined the Communist Party, or in some cases gone to

prison, was the little that was left of the One Big Union essentially,

if unofficially, an anarchist organization.) Much later the Anarchist

Communist Federation made an effort to unify the

workerist/organizational anarchists, and most recently the ex- (or maybe

not so ex-) Marxists around Love & Rage, whose anarchist bona fides are

widely doubted, flopped too.

At this time there seems to be no interest in a continental anarchist

federation. The only apparent purpose for one is to legislate standards

of anarchist orthodoxy (Black 1992: 181–193), an objective

understandably unwelcome to the unorthodox majority of anarchists,

although that now appears to be the Dean’s belated goal. While the

anarchist ranks have greatly grown during the decades of decadence, we

are far from numerous and united enough to assemble in a fighting

organization. But no cult is ever too small for its own little

Inquisition.

So, yes, we “lifestyle anarchists” tend to be anti-organizational, in

the sense that we know that anarchist organizations have a poor track

record and also that, given our numbers, our resources, and our

differences, North American anarchists have no compelling reason to

believe that what’s never worked for us before would work if we tried it

now. It is not as if these organizing efforts are indispensable to

accomplish even what little we are already accomplishing. Mostly what we

are accomplishing is publishing. After the ACF fell apart, the

collective which had been responsible for producing its newspaper

Strike! continued to do so on its own for some years. An organization

may need a newspaper, but a newspaper may not need an organization

(Black 1992: 192). In the case of Love & Rage, the newspaper preceded

what little there is to its continental organization. Self-reports and

other reports of anarchist burnout within leftist anti-authoritarian

collectives abound (No Middle Ground, Processed World, Open Road, Black

Rose Books, Sabotage Bookstore, etc.). These are, for anarchists,

usually ideological killing-fields. Ironically, the allegedly

anti-organizational collectives, such as Autonomedia and the Fifth

Estate, have outlasted most of the organizational ones. Could it be that

the organizer-types are too individualistic to get along with each

other?

Chapter 5: Murray Bookchin, Municipal Statist

There is no putting off the inevitable any longer. It has to be said:

Dean Bookchin is not an anarchist. By this I do not mean that he is not

my kind of anarchist, although that too is true. I mean he is not any

kind of anarchist. The word means something, after all, and what it

means is denial of the necessity and desirability of government. That’s

a bare- bones, pre-adjectival definition anterior to any squabbling

about individualist, collectivist, communist, mutualist, social,

lifestyle, ecological, mystical, rational, primitivist, Watsonian,

ontological, etc. anarchisms. An anarchist as such is opposed to

government — full stop. Dean Bookchin is not opposed to government.

Consequently, he is not an anarchist.

What! “The foremost contemporary anarchist theorist” (Clark 1990: 102)

is not an anarchist? You heard me. He’s not — really and truly, he’s

not. And not because he flunks some abstruse ideological test of my own

concoction. He’s not an anarchist because he believes in government. An

anarchist can believe in many things, and all too often does, but

government is not one of them.

There’s nothing heinous about not being an anarchist. Some of my best

friends are not anarchists. They do not, however, claim to be

anarchists, as the Dean does.

I could take some cheap shots at the Dean — come to think of it, I think

I will! How many of his Red-and-Green disciples know that he was

formerly in favor of a modest measure of nuclear power? Solar, wind, and

tidal power should be exploited to the max, but “it would be impossible

to establish an advanced industrial economy based exclusively on solar

energy, wind power, or even tidal power” (Herber 1965: 193), and we must

have an advanced industrial economy, that goes without saying. So,

though we shouldn’t “overcommit ourselves to the use of nuclear fuels,”

the clean energy sources will not suffice: “These gaps will be filled by

nuclear and fossil fuels, but we will employ them judiciously, always

taking care to limit their use as much as possible” (ibid.). That’s a

comfort.

And it would be scurrilous of me to report that this same Bookchin book

(Herber 1965: ix) includes — this must be an anarchist first — a plug

from a Cabinet member, then-Secretary of the Interior Stewart L. Udall:

“Crisis in Our Cities sets forth in one volume vivid evidence that the

most debilitating diseases of our time are a result of our persistent

and arrogant abuse of our shared environment.... We cannot minimize the

investments necessary to pollution control, but as Mr. Herber [Bookchin]

documents, the penalties for not doing so have become unthinkable.” This

is, be it noted, a call for legislation and taxation which a closet

anarchist allowed to adorn one of his books. There’s also an afterword

from the Surgeon General of the United States.

As embarrassing to the Dean as these reminders must be, they are not

conclusive against him. It is his own explicit endorsements of the state

which are decisive. Not, to be sure, the nation-state of modern European

provenance. He doesn’t like that sort of state very much. It allows for

too much individual autonomy. But he is enamored of the city-state of

classical antiquity and the occasionally, semi-self- governing “commune”

of pre-industrial western Europe. In this he is reminiscent of

Kropotkin, who propounded the absurd opinion that the state did not

exist in western Europe prior to the sixteenth century (cf. Bookchin

1987: 33–34). That would have surprised and amused William the Conqueror

and his successors, not to mention the French and Spanish monarchs and

the Italian city-states familiar to Machiavelli — whose Il Principe was

clearly not directed to a mandated and revocable delegate responsible to

the base, but rather to a man on horseback, somebody like Caesare

Borgia.

Although it is the most unremarkable of observations, the Dean carries

on as if he’s genuinely incensed that John Zerzan, reviewing his The

Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship (1987), pointed out

that the romanticized classical Athenian polis has “long been Bookchin’s

model for a revitalization of urban politics,” a “canard” to which the

Dean indignantly retorts, “In fact, I took great pains to indicate the

failings of the Athenian polis (slavery, patriarchy, class antagonisms,

and war)” (59). He may have felt great pains at getting caught, but he

took very few. The Dean made, “in fact,” all of two references — not

even to slavery as a mode of production, as a social reality, but to

attitudes toward slavery (1987: 83, 87), as if the fact that classical

cities had mostly subject populations (Dahl 1990: 1) was the accidental

result of some collective psychic quirk, some strange thousand-year

head-trip. What Zerzan said is only what one of the Dean’s admirers put

in stronger terms: “Bookchin continually exhorts us to hearken back to

the Greeks, seeking to recapture the promise of classical thought and to

comprehend the truth of the Polis” (Clark 1982: 52; Clark 1984:

202–203).

Every historian knows that large-scale slavery was a necessity for the

classical city (Finley 1959), although the Dean has issued the fiat that

“the image of Athens as a slave economy which built its civilization and

generous humanistic outlook on the backs of human chattels is false”

(1972: 159). (M.I. Finley — like the Dean, an ex-Communist [Novick 1988:

328] — is a Bookchin-approved historian [1989: 178].) Some of what

Zerzan writes about paleolithic society may be conjectural and

criticizable, but what he writes about Bookchin is pure reportage. The

Dean plainly says that “later ideals of citizenship, even insofar as

they were modeled on the Athenian, seem more unfinished and immature

than the original — hence the very considerable discussion I have given

to the Athenian citizen and his context” (1987: 83). That is perhaps

because the even more unfinished and immature realizations of “later

ideals” lacked the combination of the immense slave infrastructure and

the tributary empire possessed by classical Athens. Similar paeans to

Athenian citizenship pepper the Dean’s early books too (1972: 155–159;

1974: ch. 1). Manifestly what’s put a bee in Bookchin’s beret is that

Zerzan has had the temerity to read Bookchin’s books, not just revere

their distinguished author, and Zerzan has actually kept track of what

the Dean’s been reiterating all these years. The down side of being

“arguably the most prolific anarchist writer” (Ehrlich 1996: 384) is

that you leave a long paper trail.

Bookchin is a statist: a city-statist. A city-state is not an

anti-state. Contemporary Singapore, for instance, is a highly

authoritarian city-state. The earliest states, in Sumer, were

city-states. The city is where the state originated. The ancient Greek

cities were all states, most of them not even democratic states in even

the limited Athenian sense of the word. Rome went from being a

city-state to an empire without ever being a nation-state. The

city-states of Renaissance Italy were states, and only a few of them,

and not for long, were in any sense democracies. Indeed republican

Venice, whose independence lasted the longest, startlingly anticipated

the modern police-state (Andrieux 1972: 45–55).

Taking a worldwide comparative-historical perspective, the

pre-industrial city, unless it was the capital of an empire or a

nation-state (in which case it was directly subject to a resident

monarch) was always subject to an oligarchy. There has never been a city

which was not, or which was not part of, a state. And there has never

been a state which was not a city or else didn’t incorporate one or more

cities. The pre-industrial city (what Gideon Sjoberg calls — a poor

choice of words — the “feudal city”) was the antithesis of democracy,

not to mention anarchy:

Central to the stratification system that pervades all aspects of the

feudal city’s social structure — the family, the economy, religion,

education, and so on — is the pre-eminence of the political

organization.... We reiterate: the feudal, or preindustrial civilized,

order is dominated by a small, privileged upper stratum. The latter

commands the key institutions of the society. Its higher echelons are

most often located in the capital, the lower ranks residing in the

smaller cities, usually the provincial capitals (Sjoberg 1960: 220).

Sjoberg anticipated the objection, “What about Athens?” He wrote,

“although the Greek city was unique for its time, in its political

structure it actually approximates the typical preindustrial city far

more than it does the industrial-urban order” (ibid.: 236). Only a small

minority of Athenians were citizens, and many of them were illiterate

and/or too poor to be able to participate effectively, if at all, in

politics (ibid.: 235). Then and there, as always in cities everywhere,

politics was an elite prerogative. The “latent” democracy of any and

every urban republic (59) is something only Bookchin can see, just as

only Wilhelm Reich could see orgones under the microscope.

The distinction the Dean tries to draw between “politics” mid

“statecraft” (1987: 243 & passim) is absurd and self-serving, not to

mention that it’s a major mutilation of ordinary English. Even if local

politics is a kinder, gentler version of national politics, it is still

politics, which has been well if cynically defined as who gets what,

when, where, how (Lasswell 1958).

It’s not just that the Dean uses an idiosyncratic terminology to

reconcile (in a ramshackle sort of a way) anarchy with democracy, he’s

more apoplectic than anybody could have ever thought otherwise:

Even democratic decision-making is jettisoned as authoritarian.

“Democratic rule is still rule,” [L. Susan] Brown warns.... Opponents of

democracy as “rule” to the contrary notwithstanding, it describes the

democratic dimension of anarchism as a majoritarian administration of

the public sphere. Accordingly, Communalism seeks freedom rather than

autonomy in the sense that I have counterpoised them (17, 57).

Moving along from his mind-boggling deduction that democracy is

democratic, Bookchin further fusses that “pejorative words like dictate

and rule properly refer to the silencing of dissenters, not to the

exercise of democracy” (18). Free speech is a fine thing, but it’s not

democracy. You can have one without the other. The Athenian democracy

that the Dean venerates, for instance, democratically silenced the

dissenter Socrates by putting him to death.

Anarchists “jettison” democratic decision-making, not because it’s

authoritarian, but because it’s statist. “Democracy” means “rule by the

people.” “Anarchy” means “no rule.” There are two different words

because they refer to (at least) two different things.

I don’t claim — and to make my point, I don’t have to claim — that the

Dean’s characterization of anarchism as generalized direct democracy has

no basis whatsoever in traditional anarchist thought. The anarchism of

some of the more conservative classical anarchists is indeed along these

lines — although Bookchin’s version, right down to such details as its

philhellenism, is instead an unacknowledged appropriation from the

avowedly anti-anarchist Hannah Arendt (1958). Ironically, it is the

anarchists Bookchin disparages as individualists — like Proudhon and

Goodman — who best represent this anarchist theme. It was the

individualist egoist Benjamin Tucker who defined an anarchist as an

“unterrified Jeffersonian democrat.” But another theme with as least as

respectable an anarchist pedigree holds that democracy is not an

imperfect realization of anarchy but rather statism’s last stand. Many

anarchists believe, and many anarchists have always believed, that

democracy is not just a grossly deficient version of anarchy, it’s not

anarchy at all. At any rate, no “direct face-to-face democracy” (57)

that I am aware of has delegated to comrade Bookchin (mandated,

revocable, and responsible to the base) the authority to pass or fail

anarchists which he enjoys to pass or fail college students.

It is by no means obvious, and the Dean nowhere demonstrates, that local

is kinder and gentler — not where local refers to local government. It

is equally as plausible that, as James Madison argued, a large and

heterogeneous polity is more favorable to liberty than the “small

republic,” as then local minorities can find national allies to

counteract local majoritarian tyranny (Cooke 1961: 351–353). But after

all, as he says himself, the Dean isn’t interested in liberty (in his

jargon, autonomy [57],) but only in what he calls social freedom, the

participatory, self-ratified servitude of indoctrinated moralists to the

petite polity in which they function as self-effacing citizen-units.

My present purpose is not to take the full measure of Bookchinism, only

to characterize it as what it manifestly is, as an ideology of

government — democracy — not a theory of anarchy. Bookchin’s “minimal

agenda” — this hoary Marxist word “minimal” is his, not mine (1987: 287)

— is unambiguously statist, not anarchist. The “fourfold tenets,” the

Four Commandments he requires all anarchists to affirm, although most of

them do not, and never did, are:

...a confederation of decentralized municipalities; an unwavering

opposition to statism; a belief in direct democracy; and a vision of a

libertarian communist society (60).

By some quirk of fate, Bookchin’s minimal, believe-it-or-else anarchist

creed just happens to be his creed. It also happens to be deliriously

incoherent. A “confederation of decentralized municipalities”

contradicts “direct democracy,” as a confederation is at best a

representative, not a direct, democracy. It also contradicts “an

unwavering opposition to statism” because a city-state or a federal

state is still a state. And by requiring, not “a libertarian communist

society,” only the vision of one, the Dean clearly implies that there is

more to such a society than obedience to the first Three Commandments —

but exactly what more, he isn’t saying. The Dean is relegating

higher-stage anarchy (the real thing) to some remote future time, just

as the Marxists relegate what they call higher-stage communism to some

hazy distant future which seems, like a mirage, forever to recede.

Amazingly, the Dean considers a city like New York (!) to be “largely

made up of neighborhoods — that is to say, largly organic communities

that have a certain measure of identity” (1987: 246). (He has elsewhere

and inconsistently written that the modern world “lacks real cities”

[Bookchin 1974: viii].) But community “obviously means more than, say,

neighborhood” (Zerzan 1994: 157) — more than mere propinquity. And

obviously Bookchin’s been away from his home town for an awfully long

time, especially if civility and civic virtue play any part in his

conception of an organic community. I wouldn’t recommend he take a

midnight stroll in some of these “organic communities” if he values his

own organism. If the criterion of an organic community is “a certain

measure of identity,” many wealthy all-white suburbs qualify, although

Bookchin blames them for the central city’s problems (1974: 73–74).

Jealously territorial and violent youth gangs are the most conspicuous

manifestations of community in many impoverished and otherwise atomized

New York neighborhoods, his “colorful ethnic neighborhoods��� (1974: 72)

of childhood memory. If racial-caste and social-class residential

segregation is the Dean’s idea of what defines organic communities, then

organic communities certainly exist in New York City, but not many

people who live in them, except the very rich, are very happy about it.

While the word “anarchism” appears on almost every page of the Dean’s

diatribe, the word “anarchy” rarely if ever does. The ideology, the ism,

is what preoccupies him, not the social condition, the way of life, it’s

presumably supposed to guide us toward. It may not be an inadvertent

choice of words that what Bookchin lays down, as one of his Four

Commandments of orthodox anarchism, is “an unwavering opposition to

statism” (60: emphasis added), not an unwavering opposition to the

state. As a democrat, the Dean is at best capable of only a wavering

opposition to the state, whereas an abstract rejection of an

abstraction, “statism,” is easy enough to issue. And I’m sure it’s no

accident that his shot at the mainstream marketing of Bookchinism

(Bookchin 1987a) nowhere identifies the Dean as an anarchist or his

teachings as any kind of anarchism.

A further Bookchinist fiddle — this one a blatant regression to Marxism

(indeed, to St.-Simonianism) — is the distinction between “policy” and

“administration” (ibid.: 247–248). Policy is made, he says, by the

occasional face-to-face assembly which pushy intellectuals like Bookchin

are so good at manipulating. Administration is for the experts, as in

higher-stage Marxist Communism, where the “government of men” is

ostensibly replaced by the “administration of things.” Unfortunately it

is men (and it usually still is men) who govern by administering things,

and by administering people as if they were things, as governors have

always governed. Policy without administration is nothing.

Administration with or without policy is everything. Stalin the General

Secretary, the administrator, understood that, which is why he triumphed

over Trotsky, Bukharin and all the other policy-preoccupied politicians

who perhaps possibly believed in something. “Policy” is a euphemism for

law, and “administration” is a euphemism for enforcement.

Just what political practice does the eximious elder prescribe to

anarchists? We know how higher-stage confederal municipalism looks —

muscular mentating men massed in meetings — but what is to be done in

the here and now? The Dean despises existing anarchist efforts:

The sporadic, the unsystematic, the incoherent, the discontinuous, and

the intuitive supplant the consistent, purposive, organized, and

rational, indeed any form of sustained or focused activity apart from

publishing a “zine” or pamphlet — or burning a garbage can (51).

So we are not to publish zines and pamphlets as Bookchin used to do, nor

are we to burn garbage cans. Nor are we to experience freedom in the

temporary collective fraternizations Hakim Bey calls Temporary

Autonomous Zones (20–26). We’re supposed to get organized, but Bookchin

has not indicated, not even by example, what organization we’re supposed

to join. What then? I

On this point the Dean, usually so verbose, is allusive and elusive. I

have been unable to locate in any of his writings any formulation of the

“programmatic as well as activist social movement” he now demands (60).

What I think he is hinting at, with nods and winks, is participation in

local electoral politics:

The municipality is a potential time bomb. To create local networks and

try to transform local institutions that replicate the State [emphasis

added] is to pick up a historic challenge — a truly political one — that

has existed for centuries.... For in these municipal institutions and

the changes that we can make in their structure — turning them more and

more into a new public sphere — lies the abiding institutional basis for

a grassroots dual power, a grassroots concept of citizenship, and

municipalized economic systems that can be counterpoised to the growing

power of the centralized Nation-State and centralized economic

corporations (Bookchin 1990: 12).

When the Dean speaks of transforming existing local institutions, when

he speaks of “the changes we can make in their structure,” he can only

be referring to participation in local politics as it is actually

conducted in the United States and Canada — by getting elected or by

getting appointed by those who’ve gotten themselves elected. That is

exactly what the world’s only Bookchinist political movement, Black Rose

boss Dimitri Roussopoulos’ Ecologie Montreal groupuscule (Anonymous

1996:22) has attempted, and, fortunately, failed at. You can call this

anything you want to — except anarchist.

To sum up: Dean Bookchin is a statist.

Chapter 6: Reason and Revolution

The Dean denounces lifestyle anarchists for succumbing to the

reactionary intellectual currents of the last quarter century, such as

irrationalism (1–2, 9, 55–56 & passim). He laments the Stirnerist

“farewell to objective reality” (53) an the disdain for “reason as such”

(28). With his usual self-absorption sans self-awareness, Bookchin fails

to notice that he is echoing the right-wing rhetoric which since the

60’s has denounced the treason of the intellectuals, their betrayal of

reason and truth. There was a time when Bookchin “dismissed out of hand”

the way the “bourgeois critics” condemned 60’s youth culture as

“anti-rational” (1970: 51). Now he joins the neo-conservative chorus:

The sixties counterculture opened a rupture not I only with the past,

but with all knowledge of the past, including its history, literature,

art, and music. The young people who arrogantly refused to “trust anyone

[sic] over thirty,” to use a popular slogan of the day, severed all ties

with the best traditions of the past (Bookchin 1989: 162).

(“Trust no one over thirty” (to get the slogan right) — imagine how much

that must have irked Ye Olde Dean!)

Essentially identical elegiac wails well up regularly from the

conservative demi-intelligentsia, from Hilton Kramer, Norman Podhoretz,

Midge Dechter, James Q. Wilson, Irving Kristol, William F. Buckley,

George Will, Newt Gingrich, Thomas Sowell, William Safire, Clarence

Thomas, Pat Buchanan and the Heritage Foundation crew. Every generation,

once it senses that it’s being supplanted by the next one, forgets that

it was once the upstart (the right-wing version) or insists that it

still is (the left-wing version).

The lifestyle anarchists are afflicted, charges the Dean, with mysticism

and irrationalism. These are words he does not define but repeatedly

brackets as if they had the same meaning (2, 11, 19 & passim). They

don’t.

Mysticism is the doctrine that it is possible, bypassing the ordinary

methods of perception and cognition, to experience God/Ultimate Reality

directly, unmediatedly. In this sense, it is likely that Hakim Bey

qualifies as a mystic, but I can’t think of anybody else on the Dean’s

enemies list who even comes close. There is nothing innately rational or

irrational about mysticism. Reason-identified philosophers such as Kant,

Hegel and Aristotle (the latter cited 30 times in the Dean’s magnum opus

[1982: 376]) maintained that there is an Ultimate Reality. If they’re

right, for all I know it may be accessible to what Hakim Bey calls

non-ordinary consciousness (1991: 68). The “epistemological anarchist,”

as philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend calls himself, takes great

interest in experiences “which indicate that perceptions can be arranged

in highly unusual ways and that the choice of a particular arrangement

as ‘corresponding to reality’ while not arbitrary (it almost always

depends on traditions), is certainly not more ‘rational’ or more

‘objective’ than the choice of another arrangement” (1975: 189–190). All

I can say for myself is that, for better or for worse, I have never had

a mystical experience and, furthermore, that I do not consider the

notion of ultimate or absolute reality meaningful. As I once jibed,

mystics “have incommunicable insights they won’t shut up about” (Black

1986: 126). Mysticism is arational, not necessarily irrational.

The Dean’s fervent faith in objective reality (53) has more in common

with mysticism than it does with science. As mystics do, Bookchin

believes there is something absolute “out there” which is accessible to

direct apprehension — by “reason as such” (28) on his account, by other

means according to theirs. Scientists have been disabusing themselves of

such simplism for about a century. The hard sciences — starting with

physics, the hardest of them all — were the first to abandon a

metaphysical positivism which no longer corresponded to what scientists

were really thinking and doing. The Dean was at one time vaguely I aware

of this (1982: 281). The not-quite-so-scientific soft sciences with

lower self-esteem were slower to renounce scientism, but by now, they

have, too — they have too, because they have to. The rejection of

positivism in social thought is no post-modernist fashion. This too

began a century ago (Hughes 1961: ch. 3). The glossary to a classic

contemporary textbook on social science research methods could not be

more blunt: “objectivity. Doesn’t exist. See intersubjectivity” (Babbie

1992: G6). Settling for intersubjective verifiability within a community

of practicing scientists is actually the most conservative

post-objectivist position currently within the range of scientific

respectability (e.g., Kuhn 1970).

History, the maybe-science which has always had the most ambiguous and

dubious claim to objectivity, held out the longest, but no longer

(Novick 1988: ch. 13). Objectivity in any absolute sense is illusory, a

cult fetish, a childish craving for an unattainable certitude.

Intellectuals, neurotics — i.e., in a political context, ideologues —

“have to do with the invisible and believe in it,” they have “always

kept before their eyes again an intrinsically valid importance of the

object, an absolute value of it, as if the doll were not the most

important thing to the child, the Koran to the Turk” (Stirner 1995:

295). In contrast, the anarchist “does not believe in any absolute

truth” (Rocker 1947: 27). Nor does the scientist. Nor does the mature

adult. In the novel Seven Red Sundays, the anarchist Samar says, “This

effort to stop thinking is at base religious. It represents a faith in

something absolute” (Sender 1990: 253).

If Stirner bid “farewell to objective reality,” if Nietzsche held “that

facts are simply interpretations” (53), they were far ahead of their

times. It is by now almost trite to remark that there is “no

theory-independent way to reconstruct phrases like ‘really there’” (Kuhn

1970: 206; cf. Bradford 1996: 259–260). Scientists dispense with

objective reality for the same reason the mathematician Laplace, as he

told Napoleon, dispensed with God: there’s no need for the hypothesis

(cf. Bookchin 1979: 23). Reviewing two recent anthologies, Rethinking

Objectivity (Megill 1994) and Social Experience and Anthropological

Knowledge (Hastrup & Hervik 1994), anthropologist Jay Ruby relates that

no contributor to either volume argues that “an objective reality exists

outside of human consciousness that is universal” (1996: 399). Intending

no humor, but unwittingly providing some at Bookchin’s expense, he

continues: “It is unfortunate that Megill did not seek out proponents of

this position, for they can easily be found among journalists — print

and broadcast, documentary filmmakers, Marxists, and the political and

religious right” (ibid.).

Bookchin is not the first left-wing rationalist to be outraged by this

idealist, subjectivist (etc., etc.) betrayal of muscular rationalism by

what one Marxist lawyer called “fideism.” But this polemical predecessor

of Bookchin’s — a certain Lenin — had at least a nodding acquaintance

with the content of the then-new physics which was undoing

fundamentalist materialism (Lenin 1950). There is no indication that

Bookchin has any real grounding in science, although thirty years ago he

did an adequate job of popularizing information about pollution (Herber

1963, 1965). The true believers in objectivist, matter-in-motion

rationalism are usually, like Lenin and Bookchin, wordmongers — lawyers,

journalists (Ruby 1996: 399), or ideologues (Black 1996a) — not

scientists. They believe the more fervently because they do not

understand. They cling to objective reality “with the same fear a child

clutches his mother’s hand” (ibid.: 15). As Clifford Geertz says, the

objectivists are “afraid reality is going to go away unless we believe

very hard in it” (quoted in Novick 1988: 552). Lenin could hardly be

more indignant: “But this is all sheer obscurantism, out-and-out

reaction. To regard atoms, molecules, electrons, etc., as an

approximately true reflection in our mind of the objectively real

movement of matter is equivalent to believing in an elephant upon which

the world rests!” (1950: 361). Either these impenetrable particles are

bouncing around off each other down there like billiard balls on a pool

table (what a curious model of objective reality [Black 1996a]) or they

are fantasy beings like unicorns, leprechauns and lifestyle anarchists.

It’s appropriate that the lawyer Lenin’s critique of the physics of

scientists like Mach (Lenin 1950) was answered by a scientist, a

prominent astronomer who was also a prominent libertarian communist:

Anton Pannekoek (1948).

Ecology is a science, but Social Ecology is to ecology what Christian

Science is to science. Bookchin’s academic affiliations, undistinguished

as they are, and his scholarly pretensions have made some impression on

some anarchists, but then again, some anarchists are all too easy to

impress. According to the (Bookchinist) Institute for Social Ecology,

its co-founder is an “internationally acclaimed author and social

philosopher” (1995: 6). The Ecology of Freedom (Bookchin 1982),

according to a Bookchinist, is “a work of sweeping scope and striking

originality” which is “destined to become a classic of contemporary

social thought” (Clark 1984: 215). How is Bookchin’s scholarship

regarded by actual scholars? I decided to find out.

I looked up all reviews of the Dean’s books listed in the Social

Sciences Index from April 1981 to date (June 1996). I appreciate that

this is a crude and incomplete measure of his reception — it fails to

pick up, for instance, two notices in the academically marginal journal

Environmental Ethics (Watson 1995; Eckersley 1989) — but it canvasses

every important journal and most of the less important ones.

There were all of two reviews of the first edition of The Ecology of

Freedom, his Das Kapital, “the most important book to appear so far in

the history of anarchist thought” (Clark 1984:188 n. 2). The one-page

review in the American Political Science Review, after summarizing

Bookchin’s contentions, asked: “Can humanity simply be integrated into

the whole [i.e., Nature] without losing its distinctiveness, and can

solutions to the problems of the modern world emerge in the relatively

spontaneous fashion Bookchin anticipates (pp. 316–317), much as problems

are dealt with by ants, bees, and beavers?” (Smith 1983: 540). There’s

nothing on the pages cited which has anything to do with the relatively

spontaneous solution of social problems which Smith claims that Bookchin

espouses. The reviewer could hardly have misunderstood Bookchin more

profoundly. The Dean is frantically insistent on distinguishing humans

from animals and “animality” (47–48, 50, 53, 56), especially

“four-legged animality” (39) — four legs bad, two legs good! Smith —

whoever he is — clearly had no clue that he was reviewing a giant work

of political theory.

The seven-paragraph review in the American Anthropologist was

surprisingly favorable. Reviewer Karen L. Field wrote:

The Ecology of Freedom unites materials from many disciplines, and no

doubt specialists from each one will take Bookchin to task for

occasional lapses of rigor. But despite its shortcomings, the work

remains the kind of wide-ranging and impassioned synthesis that is all

too rare in this age of scholarly specialization (1984: 162).

In other words, the best thing about the book — and I agree — is that it

thinks big. On the other hand, “the scenario he constructs is not wholly

persuasive”:

The description of “organic” society draws largely on materials by Paul

Radin and Dorothy Lee, and paints an overly homogenized — even sanitized

— picture of preliterate peacefulness and egalitarianism; it evokes

!Kung and Tasaday, but not Yanomamo and Kwakiutl. Attempting to distance

himself from traditional Marxian versions of the emergence of class

society, Bookchin downplays the importance of technoeconomic factors,

but the corresponding emphasis he places on age stratification as the

key to domination is unconvincing and suffers from such a paucity of

empirical evidence that it reads at times like a “Just-So” story (ibid.:

161).

That the Dean is taken to task for romanticizing the primitives by an

anthropologist is truly matter for mirth. Nowadays he takes the

anthropologists to task for romanticizing the primitives (Chapters 8 &

9). Either the Dean has reversed himself without admitting it, or else

the most favorable review he’s ever received from a non-anarchist, bona

fide scholar rested on a serious misreading of Bookchin’s magnum opus.

And it was all downhill from there.

The one specific point brought up by Field — the Dean’s unsubstantiated

contention that gerontocracy was the original form of hierarchy (and

still the best!) — was contested, not only by Field, but subsequently by

anarchist L. Susan Brown. As a feminist, she thinks it’s more plausible

that the sexual division of labor, whether or not it was necessarily

hierarchical, eventually turned out to be the origin of hierarchy (1993:

160–161). I tend to think so too. That she dared to criticize the Dean,

and in a book from his own main publisher Black Rose Books, probably

explains why she got rounded up with the unusual suspects (13–19)

although she doesn’t seem to have much else in common with them.

If the academic reception of The Ecology of Freedom was less than

triumphal, the Dean’s other books have fared worse. There were no

reviews in social science journals of Post-Scarcity Anarchism and The

Limits of the City when they were reprinted by Black Rose Books in 1986.

There were no reviews of The Modern Crisis (1987), or Remaking Society

(1989), or The Philosophy of Social Ecology (1990), or the revised

edition of The Ecology of Freedom (1991), or Which Way for the Ecology

Movement? (1993), or To Remember Spain (1995), or, for that matter,

Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism (1995).

There was exactly one notice of The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline

of Citizenship (1987a) in an social science journal, and everything

about it is odd. It appeared — all two paragraphs of it — in Orbis: A

Journal of World Affairs, a right-wing, spook-ridden foreign policy

journal, although the Dean’s book has nothing to do with international

relations. According to the anonymous, and condescending, reviewer,

Bookchin’s “method is to ransack world history — more or less at random

— first to show how the rise of cities has corresponded to the erosion

of freedom at different times and places, then to point out how some

communities have fought the trend.” It’s not scholarship, “scholarship,

though, is not his point, or his achievement.” (That’s for sure.) The

reviewer — as had Karen Field — expresses satisfaction at reading a book

with “a real idea” for a change, even if the idea is a “slightly twisted

one” (Anonymous 1988: 628). This falls somewhat short of a rave review,

and it reverses the Dean’s understanding of urbanism, although it

comports with the title of his book (later changed to Urbanization

Without Cities, not obviously an improvement). The reviewer takes

Bookchin to be arguing that the tendency of urbanism is to diminish

human freedom, although here and there communities have managed to buck

the trend for awhile. But what Bookchin really contends is the opposite:

that the tendency of urbanism is liberatory, although here and there the

elites have managed to buck the trend for awhile. The reviewer is right

about urbanization but wrong about Bookchin. He did the Dean the favor

of misrepresenting him.

The Dean’s own conception of reason — dialectical reason — would have

been dismissed “out of hand,” as he might say, as mystical by

objective-reasonists back when there were any. Like technophilia and

defamation, the “dialectical approach” (Bookchin 1987b: 3–40) is a

feature of Marxism to which he has always clung stubbornly. The late

Karl Popper, at one time the most prominent philosopher of science of

this century, denounced dialectical reasoning, not only as mystical

gibberish, but as politically totalitarian in tendency (1962). He

denounced “Hegelian dialectics; the mystery method that replaced ‘barren

formal logic’” (ibid: 1: 28). I bring this up, not because I endorse

Popper’s positivism — I don’t (Black 1996a) — but as a reminder that

people who live in the Crystal Palace shouldn’t throw stones.

I myself veto no mode of reasoning or expression, although I think some

are more effective than others, especially in specific contexts. There’s

no such thing, for instance, as the scientific method; important

scientific discovery rarely if ever results from following rules

(Feyerabend 1975). Religious forms of expression, for instance, I’ve

long considered especially distorting (Black 1986: 71–75), but I’ve also

insisted, as opposed to freethinker simpletons, that important truths

have been expressed in religious terms: “God is unreal, but [He] has

real but muddled referents in lived experience” (Black 1992:222).

Bookchin was formerly aware of this (1982: 195–214).

The Dean’s dialectic is more than a mode of reasoning: he has a

“dialectical notion of causality” (Bookchin 1989: 203). The Universe

itself exhibits “an overall tendency of active, turbulent substance to

develop from the simple to the complex, from the relatively homogeneous

to the relatively heterogeneous, from the simple to the variegated and

differentiated” (ibid.: 199). To evolve, that is, from primal glop to

us: “Humanity, in effect, becomes the potential voice of a nature

rendered self-conscious and self-creative” (ibid.: 201; cf. 1987b: 30).

We are one with nature — provided we follow his package directions — and

at the same time we are more natural than nature has hitherto been. Out

of the evolution of consciousness emerged the consciousness of evolution

and now, rational self-direction. By and through this social “second

nature” — conscious humanity — the dialectic actualizes the “immanent

self-directedness” (1987b: 28) of the cosmos. An “immanent world reason”

is the “inherent force,” “the logos — that impart[s] meaning and

coherence to reality at all levels of existence” (Bookchin 1982: 10).

Humanity’s duty and destiny is to inscribe the Word on the fabric of

reality. The Deanly dialectic represents the most advanced thought of,

say, the fourth century B.C.

In appearance, it’s the same old story of man’s God-given mission to

dominate nature (Genesis 9: 1–3): the directed evolution of an objective

“ecological ethics involves human stewardship of the planet” (Bookchin

1987b: 32). But in essence, second nature is a moment in the development

of

...a radically new “free nature” in which an emancipated humanity will

become the voice, indeed the expression, of a natural evolution rendered

self-conscious, caring, and sympathetic to the pain, suffering, and

incoherent aspects of an evolution left to its own, often wayward,

unfolding. Nature, due to human rational intervention, will thence

acquire the intentionality, power of developing more complex life-forms,

and capacity to differentiate itself (Bookchin 1989: 202–203).

(Query: Why is it a moral imperative to make the world more complicated

than it already is?) Even today, when an unemancipated humanity “is

still less than human” (ibid.: 202), we are well on our way to

rationalizing the “often wayward” course of evolution. Thanks to

biotechnology, “thousands of microorganisms and plants have been

patented as well as six animals. More than 200 genetically engineered

animals are awaiting patent approval at the Patent and Trademark Office”

(Rifkin 1995: 119). This would seem to he fully in keeping with

Bookchin’s program (Eckersley 1989: 111–112). Nature finds freedom at

long last in submission to its highest manifestation: us. Just as we

not-quite-humans find freedom in submission to rational direction from

the first fully human being: Murray Bookchin. To paraphrase Nietzsche,

not-quite-man is something to be surpassed: a rope stretched over the

abyss between all the rest of us and Murray Bookchin.

Is everybody with me? Bookchin is saying that nature isn’t actually free

when it’s really free (where really means “what it is”), when it’s out

of control. That’s just “negative freedom” — “a formal ‘freedom from’ —

rather than [positive freedom,] a substantive freedom to” (4). We are no

longer to let Nature take its course. Nature is actually free when it’s

really controlled by its highest manifestation, humans. Humanity is

essentially natural (nature for-itself), the rest of nature isn’t

(nature in-itself).

Perhaps a political analogy will help. Workers aren’t actually free when

they’re really free, i.e., uncontrolled. The working class in-itself is

actually free when it’s really controlled by the class for-itself, the

class-conscious vanguard — workers like Bookchin was, back when he was a

worker.

When he tells it the way it is, the way it “actually” is, Bookchin is

irrefutable. Insofar as the evidence supports him, he is “really” right.

Insofar as it does not, that is because he is, to that extent,

“potentially” right. (I am using these words throughout exactly as

Bookchin does [1987b: 27J.) Reality “is no less ‘real’ or ‘objective’ in

terms of what it could be as well as what it is at any given moment”

(ibid.: 203). Ancient Athens might not have been a genuine direct

democracy “at any given moment” or indeed in any of its moments, but if

it ever had the potential for direct democracy, then it was always

actually, objectively a direct democracy. To divine this mystery is “to

comprehend the truth of the Polis” (Clark 1982: 52; 1984: 202–203). The

fact that the potential was never realized when Athens was real doesn’t

matter. “An oak tree objectively inheres in an acorn” (Bookchin 1987b:

35 n. 22) — thus the acorn is actually an oak — even if a squirrel eats

it. To call this an “idiosyncratic use of the word I objective”

(Eckersley 1989: 101) is putting it mildly.

You can make this same trick work for the city in the I abstract, and

thus for any city: “Civilization, embodied in the city as a cultural

center, is divested of its rational dimensions [by

anti-civilizationists], as if the city were an unabated cancer rather

than the potential sphere for universalizing human intercourse, in

marked contrast to the parochial limitations of tribal and village life”

(34). No matter how devastating a case is made against civilization, “to

malign civilization without due recognition of its enormous

potentialities for self-conscious freedom” is “to retreat back into the

shadowy world of brutishness, when thought was dim and intellectuation

[sic] was only an evolutionary promise” (56). (At least the brutes

didn’t use big words that don’t exist.) Democracy “lies latent in the

republic” (59), any urban republic, as it has for thousands of years

(and for how many thousands more?).

With characteristic understatement, the Dean concedes that his is “a

fairly unorthodox notion of reason” (1982: 10). It’s Hegel’s philosophy

of history with an abstract Humanity replacing the World-Spirit, roughly

the point reached by Feuerbach. Murray Bookchin is the world’s oldest

Young Hegelian. God, taught Feuerbach, is merely the essence of Man, his

own supreme being, mystified. But abstract Man, countered Max Stirner,

is also a mystification:

The supreme being is indeed the essence of man, but just because it is

his essence and not he himself, it remains quite immaterial whether we

see it outside him and view it as “God,” or find it in him and call it

“essence of man” or “man.” I am neither God nor man, neither the supreme

essence nor my essence, and therefore it is all one in the main whether

I think of the essence as in me or outside me (1995: 34).

Hegel’s Christian philosophy is developing-humanity-as- supernatural.

Bookchin’s Marxist philosophy is developing-humanity-as-supranatural.

The difference is only terminological.

Whenever Stirner says “I” he refers to himself, Max Stirner, but only as

an example. Whenever he refers to the unique one or to the ego he

refers, not to an abstract individual, but to each and every individual,

to himself, certainly, but also to every Tom, Dick and Murray. This is

why accusing Stirner of elitism (7) is bogus. Bookchin thinks that real

Humanity is still less than actually human (1989: 202). Stirner thinks

that every real human is more than human(ity): “‘Man’ as a concept or

predicate does not exhaust what you are because it has a conceptual

content of its own and because it lets itself stipulate what is human,

what is a ‘man,’ because it can be defined... But can you define

yourself? Are you a concept?” (1978: 67).

Positing a human essence is unnecessary for the practice of any art or

science. The indwelling essence is not discoverable by observation,

experimentation, or any rational mode of inquiry. To be sure, there are

those who claim to have apprehended essence directly, by non-ordinary

consciousness. They’re called mystics, and Professor Bookchin professes

to despise them. More likely he envies the qualitative superiority of

their visions. Municipal socialism has got to be as mundane as mysticism

gets. As Hakim Bey writes: “In sleep we dream of only two forms of

government — anarchy & monarchy.... A democratic dream? a socialist

dream? Impossible” (1991: 64). The Dean is indignant at this supposed

denigration of “the dreams of centuries of idealists” (21) but neglects

to indicate by what muscular rationalist faculty he is privy to the

dreams of the dreamers of previous centuries — a ouija board perhaps?

But he may be right that Bey has underestimated how far the colonization

of the unconscious may have proceeded in the case of a lifelong, elderly

political militant. Bookchin may well be a counterexample to the claim

by a Nietzsche commentator that “there is no such thing as a dull

unconscious” (Ansell-Pearson 1994: 168). Do androids dream of electric

sheep? Or as Nietzsche put it: every “thing in itself’ is stupid (1994:

81).

Whether mystical or merely mystifying, Bookchin’s conception of reason

is as unreasonable as so many of its results. His latest polemic is so

foolish that it invites reexamination of his previous books which mostly

escaped critical attention from radicals. The accolades of liberal

journalists (and they’ll forget him soon enough) won’t avert the serious

devaluation he’s called down upon himself. I once defined dialectics,

unfairly, as “a Marxist’s excuse when you catch him lying” (1992: 149).

In this sense alone is Bookchin’s reasoning dialectical. After decades

of talking down to eco- hippies who disdain “all muscularity of thought”

(Bookchin 1987b: 3), his own mental musculature has atrophied. This time

he’s bitten off more than he can gum.

Chapter 7: In Search of the Primitivists Part I: Pristine Angles

Bashing the primitivist anarchists is probably Dean Bookchin’s highest

priority (Anonymous 1996), because they are the excommunicate anarchists

whose views are most likely to be confused with, and to compete

successfully with, his own. He revels in his self-image as ecology’s

apostle to the anarchists, and for once, there’s some truth to his

messianic machismo. It was the Dean, after all, who has for so long and

in so many books clamored for the restoration of “organic community,” as

he now shamefacedly admits (41; cf. Bookchin 1974, 1982, 1987a, 1989,

1991). Once again his embarrassment is that his readers took him at his

word — an error that this reader, for one, will not repeat. These

innocents never suspected that they were not supposed to learn anything

about primitive societies or pre-industrial communities except what

cleared Bookchinist censorship.

The Dean is so much the “irate petty bourgeois” (52) on this subject

that he lashes out at the primitivists in petty, peevish ways — even for

him. Several sources John Zerzan cites in Future Primitive (1994), he

huffs, are “entirely absent” from its bibliography, such as “‘Cohen

(1974)’ and ‘Clark (1979)’” (62 n. 19). Zerzan cites “Cohen (1974),” not

on any controversial point, but for the platitude that symbols are

“essential for the development and maintenance of social order” (1994:

24) — does the Dean disagree? He never says so. “Clark (1979)” may be a

misprint for “Clark (1977),” which does appear in Zerzan’s bibliography

(1994: 173). As the author of a book from the same publisher,

Autonomedia, in the same series, I know how sloppy the production values

of this amateur, all-volunteer nonprofit collective can be.

Additionally, Zerzan (1996: 1) in a letter to me admits to “faulty

record-keeping” and explains that the absence of the two references the

Dean carps about “goes back to switching to social science-type notes —

after FE [the Fifth Estate] refused to run footnotes to my articles, in

the ‘80s.”

The Dean refers to part 2, ch. 4, sec. 4 of Max Stirner’s The Ego and

His Own (64–65) although the book ends with part 2, ch. 3 (Stirner 1995:

viii, 320–324). My library copy of Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Bookchin

1971) from Ramparts Press has a list of fifteen errata taped into it

which presumably ought not to shatter the reader’s “faith in

[Bookchin’s] research” (62 n. 19), and it is far from complete: that

should be Jacques Ellul, for instance, not Jacques Elul (ibid.: 86). And

that should be Alfred Zimmern, not Edward Zimmerman (ibid.: 159, 288 n.

27; cf. Zimmern 1931). Bookchin was perhaps thinking of a

singer-songwriter who has interested him for decades, Bob Dylan (9), the

Artist Formerly Known as Zimmerman. In an especially maladroit move, the

Dean cites a favorable review of Hakim Bey’s T.A.Z. (1991) in the Whole

Earth Review as verifying that Bey’s anarchism is a decadent, “unsavory”

(20) “bourgeois form of anarchism” (22): the Whole Earth Review has,

after all, a “yuppie clientele” (23). The back jacket blurbs for just

one of the Dean’s books (1987) come from such arch-yuppie publications

as the Village Voice and The Nation. The inside back jacket blurb boasts

that he has contributed to “many journals” including CoEvolution

Quarterly. CoEvolution Quarterly was the original name of the Whole

Earth Review.

The Dean’s devotion to urbanism is an important part of his hatred of

the primitive. City-statism and primitive society are mutually

exclusive. What amazes is that the Dean assumes that it’s the

primitivists, not the city-statists, who are the presumptive heretics

from anarchism — that they, not he, have some explaining to do. There

has never been an anarchist city, not for more than a few months at the

most, but there have been many longlasting anarchist primitive

societies. Many anarchists have considered anarchy possible in urban

conditions — among them the Dean’s bete noir Hakim Bey (Black 1994: 106)

— but Bookchin is the first anarchist who ever posited that anarchy is

necessarily urban. That would have come as quite a surprise to the

Makhnovist peasant guerrillas in the Ukraine or the insurrectionary

anarchist villagers in the pueblos of Andalusia (Bookchin 1977: ch. 5).

My point is not that the efforts and experiences of urban anarchists are

irrelevant or unworthy of attention — after all, I’m an urban anarchist

myself — only that they are not the only anarchist experiences worthy of

attention. I fail to understand why anarchists should attend only to

their failures and ignore their only successes.

I don’t consider myself a primitivist. Genuine anarcho- primitivists

such as John Zerzan, George Bradford and Feral Faun probably don’t think

I’m one of them either, any more than Hakim Bey is, although the Dean

can’t quite figure out “is he is or is he ain’t” (62 n. 8). So it’s not

my purpose to defend the views of John Zerzan or George Bradford against

Bookchin (although, incidentally, I’ll do some of that): they are quite

capable of defending themselves and I’m sure they will. Bradford, in

fact, has written a lengthy rejoinder to be co-published by Autonomedia

and Black & Red. But it is my purpose to show that in the way he

denounces the primitivists, the Dean is, as usual, unscrupulous and

malicious. When he isn’t flat-out wrong he’s usually irrelevant.

In rebutting a right-wing libertarian critic, I made clear two of the

aspects of primitive societies (there are others) which ought to

interest anarchists:

Hunter-gatherers inform our understanding and embarrass libertarians

[and Bookchinists] in at least two ways. They operate the only known

viable stateless societies. And they don’t, except in occasional

emergencies, work in any sense I’ve used the word (Black 1992: 54).

Even the Dean earlier admitted the first point: “This organic, basically

preliterate or ‘tribal,’ society was strikingly nondomineering” (1989:

47). After all, Cultural Man is at least two million years old. He was

originally a hunter-gather. He was an anatomically modern human at least

50,000 years before he adopted any other mode of subsistence. As

recently as 10,000 years ago he was still only a forager (Lee & DeVore

1968c: 3). And he was still an anarchist.

Now it may well be that the life-ways of hunter-gatherers (also known as

foragers) are not, as a practical matter, available for immediate

adoption by disgruntled urbanites, as the Dean declaims (36). Some

primitivists have said as much; John Moore, for one, is exasperated to

have to keep saying so (1996: 18). Others, in my opinion, have

equivocated. But that’s not the point, or not the only point. A way of

life is much more than a “life-style.” Hunter-gatherers grow up in a

habitat and learn its secrets, they have “a marvelous understanding of

the habitat in which they lived; they were, after all, highly

intelligent and imaginative beings” (47), Most anarchists should

probably send for a lot of Loompanics books and practice up on a lot of

survival skills before they even think of venturing into the wilderness

on a long-term basis. Hardly any anarcho-primitivists propose to do so

(to my knowledge, only one). But the point is to learn from the

primitives, not necessarily to ape them.

Dean Bookchin, in contrast, doesn’t know and doesn’t want to know

anything about primitives which might suggest that low-tech, non-urban

anarchy is even possible — although it’s the only kind of anarchy

empirically proven to be possible. Since the whole point of the Dean’s

polemic is to pass judgment upon what counts as anarchism, you’d think

he’d try to indict primitives as statists. As that is impossible, he

changes the subject.

Repeatedly, the Dean throws what he apparently considers roundhouse

punches at primitivist myths, but he never connects, either because they

are not tenets of primitivism or else because they are not myths.

For instance, the Dean argues at length that hunter- gatherers have been

known to modify, and not merely adapt to, their habitats, notably by the

use of fire (42–43). Anthropologists, and not only the ones the Dean

cites, have known that for a long time. The Australian aborigines, the

quintessential foragers, set fires for various purposes which

transformed their landscape, usually to their advantage (Blainey 1976:

ch. 5 [“A Burning Continent”]). Shifting cultivators, such as most of

the Indians of eastern North America, also fired the brush with

important ecological consequences, as even historians know (Morgan 1975:

ch. 3). If any primitivist ever claimed otherwise, he is wrong, but the

Dean does not cite when and where he did. John Zerzan, “the

anticivilizational primitivist par excellence” (39), observes, without

apparent disapproval, that humans have been using fire for almost two

million years (1994: 22).

To take an ecological perspective means to hypothesize general

interaction among all species and between each and all species and the

inanimate environment. It implies dethroning humans as the lords of

nature appointed by a Judeo-Christian divinity, certainly, but it

doesn’t imply or presuppose that there was ever a time or a condition of

society in which humans never acted upon the rest of nature but were

only acted upon. Not even amoebas are that passive and quiescent

(Bookchin 1989: 200).

Amazingly, Bookchin explicitly embraces the Hobbesian myth that the

lives of primitive, pre-political people were nasty, brutish and short

(46). For him as for Hobbes (Black 1986: 24), the purpose of the myth is

to further a statist agenda.

“Our early ancestors,” he remarks with satisfaction, “were more likely

scavengers than hunter-gatherers” (46). How disgusting! They ate animals

which were already dead! Just as we do when we shop the meat section of

a supermarket. (Perhaps there are no meat sections in Burlington

supermarkets. Perhaps there are no supermarkets there, just food co-ops.

Why do I find it hard to summon up an image of Bookchin putting in his

four hours a month bagging groceries?) Bookchin probably picked up this

tidbit from Zerzan (1994: 19). Regardless, our still-prehistoric,

still-anarchic ancestors must have formed other tastes in food in

becoming big game hunters (42).

And these our animalistic ancestors were unhealthy too, claims the Dean.

The Neanderthals suffered high rates of degenerative bone disease and

serious injury (46). There is considerable controversy whether the

Neanderthals were among our ancestors. If your ancestors are from Europe

or the Levant, possibly; otherwise, almost certainly not. Admittedly,

our early ancestors were more likely to be eaten by leopards and hyenas

than we are (46), but for contemporary foragers, predation is a minor

cause of death (Dunn 1968: 224–225). On the other hand, our leading

killers, cancer and heart disease, appear infrequently among them

(ibid.: 224), and our thousands of occupational diseases never do.

Hunter-gatherers have never been afflicted by asbestosis, black lung

disease, Gulf War syndrome (as I write these words, the Pentagon is

finally admitting there might be such a thing) or carpal tunnel

syndrome. Band societies have very low population densities, and “viral

and bacterial infections cannot generally persist among small human

populations” (Knauft 1987: 98). Paleolithic foragers might suffer

serious or fatal injuries, but one million of them were not killed by

motor vehicles in just a hundred years.

According to the Dean, prehistoric mortality statistics are “appalling”:

“about half died in childhood or before the age of twenty, and few lived

beyond their fiftieth year” (46). Even taking these claims to be true,

the aggregate figures, their vagueness aside, are highly misleading.

Foraging peoples usually have a lot greater sensitivity to the carrying

capacities of their habitats than techno-urbanites do. The ones who

didn’t have paid the price. The ones who did, and do, adjust their

populations by the means at their disposal. Delayed marriage, abortion,

prolonged lactation, sexual tabus, even genital surgery are among the

cultural practices by which foragers hold down their birthrates

(Yengoyan 1968:1941). Low-tech does have its limitations. The condom,

the diaphragm, the IUD and the Pill have not been available to

hunter-gatherers. Foragers have often resorted to post-partum population

control as well: in other words, to infanticide and senilicide (Dunn

1968: 225).

Especially infanticide (although I suspect the Dean feels a lot more

threatened by senilicide). Infanticide was probably prevalent among

Pleistocene hunter-gatherers (Birdsell 1968: 236), so it’s ridiculous to

calculate an “average” lifespan in which the few minutes or hours some

neonates were allowed to live count for as much as all the years lived

by those who actually go on to have lives. It’s as if in measuring the

present-day American lifespan we included in the numerator, as 0, every

conception averted by contraception and every aborted fetus, while

adding each of them, scored as 1, to the denominator counting the entire

population. We’d come up with a startlingly low “average” lifespan for

the contemporary United States — 10 years? 20 years? — which would be

utterly meaningless. When contraceptive devices became available to

Nunamiut Eskimo women in 1964, there was “massive adoption” of them

(Binford & Chasko 1976: 77). At this point somebody might rise up in

righteous indignation — from the right, from the left, a trifling

distinction — to denounce my equation of contraception, abortion and

infanticide. I’m not even slightly interested in whether, or where, the

Pope or any other dope draws moral lines among these time-honored

practices. I don’t equate them morally because I’m not moralizing. I

equate them only with respect to the issue, the demographic issue, at

hand.

Gimmickry aside, the evidence suggests that foragers live relatively

long lives. The Dean’s claim that the average lifespan of the !Kung San

is 30 years (45) is unreferenced and misleading, Lee’s censuses showed

...a substantial proportion of people over the age of 60. This high

proportion (8.7 to 10.7 percent) by Third World standards contradicts

the widely held notion that life in hunting and gathering societies is

“nasty, brutish, and short.” The argument has been made that life in

these societies is so hard that people die at an early age. The Dobe

area [of Botswana], by contrast, had dozens of active older persons in

the population (Lee 1979: 44).

The population structure “looks like that of a developed country, for

example, like that of the United States around 1900” (ibid.; 47). This

is how two other anthropologists summarize the !Kung situation:

Although individuals who have reached maturity can expect to live into

their middle 50s, life expectancy at birth is approximately 32 years,

determined mainly by high infant mortality — between 10 and 20% in the

first year, almost all due to infectious disease. In the traditional

situation, infanticide made a small additional contribution to mortality

(Konner & Shostack 1987: 12).

It is true that foragers have always lacked the technology to perpetuate

the agony of their incapacitated elders as our insurance-driven system

arranges for some of ours. When I visit my father in the nursing home —

a stroke victim, a mentally confused cripple usually complaining of

pain, 85 years old — I find it hard to consider longevity an absolute

value. According to the Iliad, neither did Achilles:

For my mother Thetis, the goddess of the silver feet tells me I carry

two sorts of destiny towards the day of my death. Either if I stay here

and fight beside the city of the Trojans my return home is gone, but my

glory shall be everlasting; or if I return to the beloved land of my

fathers, the excellence of my glory is gone, but there will be a long

life (quoted in Feyerabend 1987: 138).

For an urbanist (if less than urbane) crusader like the Dean, the

relevant comparisons should be different. Primitivists like Zerzan and

Bradford compare the robust lives of Paleolithic foragers with the

stunted lives of those caught up in the urban/agricultural complex: “The

increasingly sophisticated interpretation of the archaeological record

suggests that the transition to the Neolithic was accompanied by a

fairly general decline in dietary quality, evidenced in stature and

decreased longevity” (Ross 1987: 12). And also a related decline in

health. Almost all archeological studies “conclude that infection was a

more serious problem for farmers than for their hunting and gathering

forebears, and most suggest that this resulted from increased sedentism,

larger population aggregates, and/or the well-established synergism

between infection and malnutrition” (Cohen 1987: 269–270). For one

thing, work — and when we arrive at agriculture we arrive,

unambiguously, at work — is hazardous to your health.

The fact that these are the findings of archeological studies of

prehistoric societies renders irrelevant, for present purposes, the

recent argument that the much-studied San are really just an

impoverished underclass within capitalism (Wilmsen 1989). This is a

controversial claim (Peters 1990) — vigorously rebutted by Richard B.

Lee and like-minded anthropologists (Solway & Lee 1990) — which,

predictably, Bookchin whoops up with uncritical abandon (44–45). But by

definition, prehistoric peoples cannot have been marginal to, or relics

of, or devolved from historical societies. What did they devolve from?

Atlantis? Lemuria? Mu? Are they the love-children of extraterrestrials

(“Earth girls are easy”) who, having had their exotic fun, revved up the

Chariots of the Gods and rocketed off to the next off-planet pick-up

scene? The artist Goya, as quoted by the Dean, once said that “the sleep

of reason begets monsters” (28). Does Bookchin think that the

sleeping-around of monsters begets reasonables?

And when we progress from mere agriculture to urbanism — one thing leads

to another — health deteriorates even more dramatically. Throughout

history, pre-industrial urban populations have usually reproduced at

less than replacement levels: “Ancient cities were like tar pits,

drawing country folk into their alluring but disease-ridden precincts”

(Boyd & Richerson 1993: 127). The Dean is fond of the slogan that “city

air makes you free” (1974: 1), but there is considerably more truth to

saying that city air makes you sick (ibid.: 66). Urban “internal

nonviability” has three sources: (1) high population density

“facilitates the genesis and communication of infectious diseases”; (2)

such cities “have almost invariably had poor sanitation and hygiene,

particularly with respect to water and sewage”; and (3) urbanites depend

on outside sources of food, on monocultural food production subject to

crop failures and difficulties of transportation, storage and

distribution (Knauft 1987: 98).

Industrial cities have only imperfectly coped with these unhealthy

influences. They are more overcrowded than ever, with, the Dean has

shown, adverse health consequences (Herber 1965). “Urban air is

seriously polluted and urban wastes are reaching unmanageable

proportions” — furthermore:

Nothing more visibly reveals the overall decay of the modern city than

the ubiquitous filth and garbage that gathers in its streets, the noise

and massive congestion that fills its thoroughfares, the apathy of its

population toward civic issues, and the ghastly indifference of the

individual toward the physical violence that is publicly inflicted on

other members of the community (Bookchin 1974:66,67).

Even the most conspicuous health accomplishment of industrialism, the

control of disease by antibiotics, is being rolled back, as resistant

strains of disease vectors evolve. Even the food situation is

unsatisfactory, if not for precisely the traditional reasons. Most

American urbanites have unhealthy diets, and more than a few are

malnourished.

The Dean mostly obsesses about details — why not oblige him? — such as

whether contemporary hunter-gatherer societies are “pristine” and

whether hunter-gatherers have invariably been the benign stewards of

their habitats. Although these propositions are largely irrelevant to

the species “primitivism” and entirely irrelevant to its supposed genus,

“lifestyle anarchism,” the ways the Dean deploys them are relevant to

his ulterior aims and exemplary of his unsavory methods.

By “pristine” (44, 45) the Dean seems to mean the supposition that all

contemporary hunter-gatherers are living fossils who have always lived

the way they do now. As usual, when the Dean puts a loaded word in

quotation marks it’s a dead giveaway that he’s not quoting anybody, just

talking to his favorite person, himself. (Just as his mockery of

primitive “reverence for life” (42) might have been amusing — a Bookchin

first — if he could only have pinned on the anarcho-primitivists a

phrase employed, not by them, but by that celebrated racist paternalist,

the late B’wana, Dr. Albert Schweitzer.) He might have learned that — he

probably did — from John Zerzan: “surviving hunter-gatherers, who have

somehow managed to evade civilization’s tremendous pressures to turn

them into slaves (i.e. farmers, political subjects, wage laborers), have

all been influenced by contact with outside peoples” (1994: 29–30). The

call for papers for the 1966 “Man the Hunter” conference — which the

Dean blames for romanticizing foragers (37) — stated “that there is no

assumption that living hunter-gatherers are somehow living relicts of

the Pleistocene” (quoted in Binford 1968: 274). Bookchin is beating a

dead horse or, better yet, an extinct eohippus: “It is widely recognized

that modern hunters are not pristine living relics of the Pleistocene”

(Hawkes 1987: 350).

The Dean cites with some satisfaction a fairly recent article by William

M. Denevan, “The Pristine Myth: The Landscape of the Americas in 1492”

(1992), but for several reasons, I doubt the Dean has even read it. In

the first place, the Dean only adverts to it as “cited in William K.

Stevens, ‘An Eden in Ancient America? Not Really,’ The New York Times

(March 30, 1993, p. CI” (63 n. 22). The newspaper story may well have

been how the Dean got wind of the article — nothing wrong with that, I

often follow up on tips that way — but having served that purpose,

there’s no reason to refer to a newspaper story which, at best, must

have oversimplified the article. Second, the Dean misquotes the name of

the journal. And finally, the title of the newspaper story, suggesting a

debunking of the myth of “an Eden in ancient America,” has absolutely

nothing to do with what Denevan was really writing about, although it

has everything to do with the Dean’s anti-primitivist ideological

agenda.

Denevan’s argument, which relates only to the Western Hemisphere, is

that when Europeans arrived in the New World, and for some time

afterwards, the landscape they encountered — Denevan is a cultural

geographer — was not “pristine” if this means it had been barely

affected by tens of thousands of years of indigenous human presence.

Indian hunting, horticulture, and especially the use of fire had wrought

important transformations in many stretches of the landscape. Many North

American grasslands, for instance, were produced by human action, and to

a lesser extent, so were the park-like woodlands of eastern North

America (Morgan 1975: ch. 3; Salisbury 1982: ch. 1). But by the time the

Euro-Americans moved west on a large scale, the once-numerous Indians

had been decimated and much of the landscape had reverted to a tangled,

pre-humanized “wilderness” the settlers mistook for pristine conditions.

Denevan plausibly argues for this conclusion but does not, as the Dean

does, consider it cause for celebration.

But what does this have to do with anything? A humanized landscape is

not necessarily a ravaged, depleted, denaturalized landscape because

there was a time when humans were natural.

The Dean, Professor of Social Ecology, also supposes he is saying

something important when he avers that primitives may have contributed

to the extinction of some species of the animals they hunted and that

they may have sometimes degraded their environments (42–43). As the

allegations are independent, let us address each count of the indictment

separately.

Even the Dean admits that the best-known claim for induced extinction,

so-called Pleistocene overkill, is “hotly debated” (63 n. 23). Rapid

climatic change was indisputably part of the cause, and possibly a

sufficient cause, for the extinction of overspecialized species like the

mastodon. But supposing that prehistoric hunters were responsible for

some extinctions — so what? Extinction has so far been the fate of

almost every species to appear on this planet, and may in time be the

fate of all of them. The continuation of natural life does not depend

upon the continuation of any particular species, including ours. What

difference does it make?

Anyway, to say that some prehistoric primitives could and did kill game

animals on a large scale (42, 62–63 n. 20), as all anthropologists are

well aware, does not entail that these primitives brought about the

extinction of their prey. Well into historic times, the Plains Indians

killed many buffalo and the Northwest Coast Indians netted many salmon

without coming close to extinguishing either species. The yield, though

enormous, was sustainable. It required the intrusion of industrial

society to pose a real risk of extinction with its high-tech,

mass-production life destruction.

An article which the Dean cites (Legge & Rowley-Conwy 1987), but must

not have read very carefully — even if we disregard his mistake as to

one co-author’s name (62–63 n. 20 [“Rowly”]) — actually tells against

his indictment of the foragers. Bookchin cites it for the conclusion

“that migrating animals could have been slaughtered with devastating

effectiveness by the use of corrals” (63 n. 20). Granting that — a point

of no present importance — the article tells a more interesting story.

The authors, archaeologists, are reporting on a site they excavated in

Syria. It was first occupied by hunter-gatherers in approximately 9000

B.C. and remained occupied, with one break, well into the Neolithic

(agricultural) period. The authors emphasize that this was a year-round

community, not a seasonal campsite. For about a thousand years after the

villagers domesticated plants, hunting — mainly gazelle hunting —

continued to supply them with animal protein. By then, the authors

believe, the farmers had hunted the gazelles into extinction, and only

then did they take up animal husbandry to replace the meat formerly

supplied by wild game.

There are two points of interest here, and each is adverse to the Dean.

Hunter-gatherers were not responsible for the extinction of the

gazelles: their agricultural descendants were. These villagers had long

since ceased to be foragers by the time they finished off the gazelles

(locally, that is: the animals survived elsewhere). More important,

they’d never really been hunter-gatherers in the sense in which hunter-

gatherers interest primitivists and ought to interest all anarchists.

Anthropologists have recently resolved an ambiguity in the expression

“hunter-gatherers” (cf. Murdock 1968: 13–15). It refers to two kinds of

society, not one: nonsedentary and sedentary. What they have in common

is that they hunt and/or gather rather than plant/and or herd. They do

not domesticate either plants or animals (in a few such societies, dogs

are domesticated, but not as a food source). What separates them is

whether they occupy locations on a long-term or short-term basis. The

occupants of the Syrian site were always “hunters” in the obvious

respect that, like many members of the National Rifle Association, they

hunted animals. But they more closely resembled such Northwest Coast

Indians as the Kwakiutl in that they were the permanent, year-round

occupants of favored, restricted locations which afforded them

sustenance. They were not the same sort of “hunter-gatherers” as the

Australian aborigines, the San/Bushmen, the Pygmies, the Great Basin

Shoshone and many others for whom frequent relocation was the condition

of successful adaptation to their habitats. Sedentary hunter-gatherers

are socially much more like sedentary agriculturalists and urbanites

than they are like foragers who are routinely on the move. Their

societies exhibit class stratification, hereditary chiefs, sometimes

even slavery (Kelly 1991; Renouf 1991: 90–91, 98, 101 n. 1; cf. Renouf

1989 for a prehistoric European example). It is from these societies

that the city and the state emerged — together.

Possibly more relevant is the claim that primitives are not necessarily

“ecologically benign” (42), and there’s no reason to suppose they always

are. As Denevan says, sometimes “Indians lived in harmony with nature

with sustainable systems of resource management” and sometimes they

didn’t (1992: 370). But Devevan was not generalizing about primitives,

he was generalizing about Indians. He nowhere adduces a single example

of Amerindian hunter-gatherers who degraded their environment, and

neither does Bookchin, although I wouldn’t lose a lot of sleep if it

turned out that there was one, or even more than one group like that. A

small-scale society which fouled its own nest would probably not

survive, but the environmental damage it did would be localized. A

small-scale society which by some combination of insight and accident

settled into a sustainable relationship with its ecosystem would be much

more likely to persist. Existing foraging societies may not all have

been around for millennia, but they’ve endured at least for centuries.

“Primitivism” is not “indigenism,” i.e., pan-Indian racial nationalism

with a left-wing spin such as Ward Churchill serves up. “Primitive” and

“Indian” are not synonyms. Most primitives were never Indians and many

pre-Columbian Indians weren’t primitives. The Dean reports that “forest

overclearing and the failure of subsistence agriculture undermined Mayan

society and contributed to its collapse” (43). One only has to refer to

his own footnote to identify his references (64 n. 25) from “The

Collapse of Classic Maya Civilization” in The Collapse of Ancient States

and Civilizations to The Collapse of Complex Societies in order to

notice that he’s not referring to foragers or primitives, he’s referring

to a civilization, the state-organized, urban-based, agricultural,

priest-ridden, class-stratified Mayan civilization. Civilizations have a

long history of occasioning environmental destruction whether the

civilized be red, white, black or yellow: they have belonged to all of

these races. Is this news to Professor Social Ecology?

Probably the most amusing aspect of the Dean’s campaign against the

primitivists is how blatantly self-contradictory it is (Jarach 1996).

While he wants to represent primitive life-ways as undesirable, the

decisive point is that they are, for us, simply impossible: “Anyone who

advises us to significantly, even drastically, reduce our technology is

also advising us, in all logic, to go back to the ‘stone age’ — at least

to the Neolithic or Paleolithic (early, middle, or late)” (36).

To digress for just a bit, consider how idiotic this assertion is. The

Dean says that any significant rollback of technology would reduce us

to, at best, the Neolithic, the New Stone Age. But obviously there was a

lot of technological progress, if that’s what it was, between the

Neolithic Revolution (agriculture) which commenced a few thousand years

ago and the Megamachine which dominates us now. The Dean’s beloved

Athenian polis, for instance, exploited a technology much inferior to

what we moderns command but far beyond what the Neolithic farmers, the

earliest farmers, had to work with. Early medieval Europe, an almost

entirely rural society, quickly developed new technology (such as the

mould-board plough) beyond anything that urban-oriented Greco-Roman

civilization ever did.

John Zerzan’s unspeakable heresy, as the Dean sees it, is that Zerzan

thinks that prehistoric hunter-gatherers did not just fail to “innovate

technological change” (38), they refused domestication and the division

of labor. For the Dean, progress is an offer you can’t refuse. But then,

sublimely oblivious to the inconsistency, he goes on to say that some

primitive societies have, in his value-laden word, “devolved” from more

complex societies (44). The Mayans devolved from civilization (43). The

Yuqui foragers of the Bolivian forest devolved from “a slave-holding

pre-Columbian society” which was horticultural (45). Even the San have

“literally devolved — probably very much against their desires — from

horticultural social systems” (44; cf. Wilmsen 1989).

We may “never have any way of knowing whether the lifeways of today’s

foraging cultures accurately mirror those of our ancestral past” (43) —

actually, archeology and paleoecology have come up with some ways — but

we have an easy way to find out if the San would rather be gardeners

than foragers. We can ask them. This would never occur to the Dean, for

whom contemporary foragers are little more than talking dogs, but it

occurred to Richard B. Lee when he lived with and studied the San in the

‘60s: “when a Bushman was asked why he hadn’t taken to agriculture he

replied: ‘Why should we plant, when there are so many mongongo nuts in

the world?”’ (Lee 1968: 33).

There are many examples of voluntary “devolution.” The ancestors of most

Plains Indian tribes were agriculturalists. There is absolutely no

reason to suppose they were forced off their farmlands and onto the

plains by environmental pressures or aggression from other tribes. When

the horse, introduced by the Spanish, found its way north, these Indians

seized upon this new technology to “devolve” from sedentary agriculture

to nomadic buffalo hunting. We’ll never know for sure why they made this

choice. Was buffalo meat tastier than corn? Was hunting more fun than

farming? Was a frequent change of scenery more interesting than being

stuck forever in Mudville-on-the-Missouri? Whatever it was, it was a

choice. Maybe we have a choice too.

Chapter 8: In Search of the Primitivists Part II: Primitive Affluence

According to the Dean, the notion of primitive affluence is some

silliness the hippies smoked up and put over on the anthropologists in

the ‘60s:

Much of [George Bradford’s] “critical anthropology” appears to derive

from ideas propounded at the “Man the Hunter” symposium, convened in

April 1966 at the University of Chicago. Although most of the papers

contributed to this symposium were immensely valuable, a number of them

conformed to the naive mystification of “primitivity” that was

percolating through the 1960s counter-culture — and that lingers on to

this day. The hippie culture, which influenced quite a few

anthropologists of the time, averred that hunting-gathering peoples

today had been bypassed by the social and economic forces at work in the

rest of the world and still lived in a pristine state, as isolated

remnants of Neolithic and Paleolithic lifeways. Further, as

hunter-gatherers, their lives were notably healthy and peaceful, living

then as now on an ample natural largess (37).

The chief villain of the piece was anthropologist Richard B. Lee, who

had “estimated that the caloric intake of ‘primitive’ peoples was quite

high and their food supply abundant, making for a kind of virginal

‘affluence’ in which people needed to forage only a few hours each day”

(37–38).

In the above-quoted passage, “it would take a full-sized essay in itself

to unscramble, let alone refute, this absurd balderdash, in which a few

truths are either mixed with or coated in sheer fantasy” (37). The Dean

refers to a passage he quotes from Bradford, but might have been

referring to his favorite subject — himself — except that there aren’t

even a few truths in his passage, not even mixed or coated with fantasy.

The revision of the Hobbesian postulate that primitive life is nasty,

brutish and short commenced, not at the “Man the Hunter” symposium in

1966 (Lee & DeVore 1968), but at the symposium on band societies in

Ottawa in 1965 (Damas 1969). The Chicago symposium only extended the

theses of the pioneering Ottawa gathering (Renouf 1991: 89–90). April

1965 and even April 1966 (Lee & DeVore 1968: vii) are implausibly early

dates to assume much hippie influence on academic scholarship, and the

Dean adduces no evidence in support of his self-serving conjecture.

There’s no trace of counterculture influence, for instance, in

Bookchin’s 1965 book Crisis in Our Cities (Herber 1965) or his 1965

essay “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought” (Bookchin 1971: 55- 82).

Indeed, back when his memories were more recent and his memory perhaps

better, Bookchin wrote that “the hippie movement was just getting

underway in New York when ‘Ecology and Revolutionary Thought’ was

published” (ibid.: 29). In contrast, the hippie movement bulks large in

his 1970 essay opportunistically lauding youth culture (Bookchin 1970:

51–63). The times they were a-changin’. To Bookchin’s annoyance, they

still are.

If there is any relationship between ‘60s hippie culture and the

anti-Hobbesian turn in anthropology, it is of the sort the statisticians

call a spurious relationship. That is, the variables are associated with

each other, not as cause and effect, but as consequences of a common

cause (Babbie 1992: 416). The common cause would have been the general

climate of distrust of authority and orthodoxy.

If you read the Dean’s passage with more care than it was written with,

it’s noticeable that he attributes most of the malign influence on the

primitivists, not to the anthropologists, but to the hippies. I am

drawing on my own distant memories here, but my recollection is that

what the hippies romanticized was tribal society on the model, usually

ill-understood, of certain pacific Native American tribes like the Hopi

and the Navajo. At the time, Bookchin apparently thought so too. “In its

demands for tribalism,” among others, “the Youth Culture prefigures,

however inchoately, a joyous communist and classless society” (Bookchin

1970: 59). Unless they were attending graduate school, few hippies would

have been acquainted with what Bookchin calls the “‘Man the Hunter’

timewarp” (39), which was expressly and only about revising the

Hobbesian view of hunter-gatherers.

For the most part, hunter-gatherers don’t even live in tribes, they live

in bands (Lee & DeVore 1968b: 7–8). In contrast, tribal peoples —

horticulturalists or herders — occupy a social space “between bands and

states” (Gregg 1991). Many of their societies are also anarchist and as

such are also interesting, as well as interesting in their own right,

but necessarily there are not as many valid generalizations about

primitives as there are about foragers. All foragers are primitives, but

not all primitives are foragers.

In a way, it’s Bradford’s fault for inviting the Dean to foment

confusion. If the Dean quotes him correctly — always a big if where the

Dean is concerned — Bradford wrote in 1991 that the “official”

anthropological view of foragers is the Hobbesian one. That was already

changing even when Marshall Sahlins made the same point in his 1968

essay “The Original Affluent Society” (Sahlins 1971: ch. 1). Today the

“current model” (Renouf 1991: 89–90) is the one advanced at the Ottawa

and Chicago conferences: “although the more idealized aspects of the Lee

and DeVore model are commonly acknowledged, I think it is fair to say

that no fundamental revision of it has been made” (ibid.: 90).

Similarly, another anthropologist refers to the continuing prevalence of

“the revised general version of hunter-gatherers of the mid- 1960s”

(Conkey 1984: 257). John Zerzan, not George Bradford, is correct in

saying that “a nearly complete reversal in anthropological orthodoxy has

come about, with important implications” (1994: 16). Bradford’s failure

to update the opinions he’s expressed since the 1970s — which is typical

of the Fifth Estate — afforded the Dean an undeserved opportunity to

claim scientific respectability for a viewpoint long since discredited.

Bradford’s other mistake, eagerly exploited by the Dean, is that he

allegedly wrote that the revisionist view is based on “greater access to

the views of primal people and their native descendants” (37). That gave

the Dean his chance to dismiss primitive affluence as the “edenic” myth

of nostalgic natives (36) feeding their fantasies, and perhaps their

peyote, to credulous white hippies.

This is all wrong. It was the earliest studies of hunter-gatherers,

including classic accounts by Kroeber, Boas and Radcliffe-Brown, which

relied on older informants’ memories of conditions 25–50 years before,

on “ethnographic reconstructions of situations which were no longer

intact” (Lee & DeVore 1968c: 5–6). The Man the Hunter symposium, far

from overlooking this method’s shortcomings, made that a “central theme”

(ibid.: 6). Contemporary anthropologists have lesser, not greater access

to the views of so-called primal people. In the first place, primal

people are disappearing almost as rapidly as leftists are. And secondly,

Western anthropologists no longer enjoy as much “access” as they did

when the people they studied were subject to Western colonial rule. Most

indigenous peoples now have more power to determine whether and on what

terms they will receive resident and even visiting ethnographers. Some

exclude them entirely. And the national governments of some former

colonial possessions which are now independent states restrict or

exclude foreign anthropologists for a variety of reasons (Beals 1969:

20–27).

More important, the affluence thesis is based on observation and

measurement, not myth and memory. Richard B. Lee concluded that the

!Kung San/Bushmen did remarkably little work compared to us — not by

sitting at the feet of the Old Wise Man like they do at Goddard College

— but by following the San around to see what they were doing and for

how long. He based his conclusions as to the sufficiency of their diet

on measuring the calories they ingested and expended (Lee 1969, 1979),

something rarely done previously. One of the resulting articles was

titled “!Kung Bushmen Subsistence: An Input-Output Analysis” (Lee 1969).

This is science at its most muscular, not free-form fantasy.

It doesn’t necessarily follow, of course, that if San society is in a

very tangible, measurable sense leisurely and affluent, then so are all

or most other foraging societies. But on the Hobbesian new, the San as

they lived in the 1960s were impossible, so the Hobbesian view in the

muscular form espoused by the Dean has to be qualified or, as the social

scientists say, “specified” (the scope of its validity narrowed) (Babbie

1992: 421–422) or else rejected altogether. And what’s so intriguing is

that the San live their affluence in the arid Kalahari Desert, not

someplace approximating the Garden of Eden (Zerzan 1994: 29). If

foraging life could be affluent there, it might have been affluent

almost everywhere — and almost everywhere is where pre-historic humans

lived, as foragers, for 99% of human existence (Lee & DeVore 1968c: 5).

The civilized, in contrast, find it very difficult to sustain an

affluent lifestyle in the desert outside of a few special locations like

Palm Springs and Kuwait (cf. Lévi-Strauss 1962: 5 [quoted in Feyerabend

(1987): 112 n. 14)]).

These implications have not only reoriented fieldwork, they have also

occasioned the reinterpretation of already available accounts of

hunter-gatherers, both historical sources and formal ethnographies.

Sahlins (1971: ch. 1) did some of both in “The Original Affluent

Society,” whose conclusions he’d previewed as a discussant at the Man

the Hunter symposium (Lee & DeVore 1968: 85–89). The abundant historical

accounts of the Australian aborigines, for all their misperceptions, if

carefully read, confirm the affluence thesis. And the earlier

ethnographers of hunter-gatherers, although they had often announced as

their conclusions the Hobbesian party line, report ample data which

contradict those conclusions. Anthropologists who once slighted written,

historical sources relating to foragers such as the San are now combing

them very carefully (e.g., Parkington 1984).

Unlike Bradford, the Man the Hunter anthropologists were not interested

in primitive animism, harmony with nature, or “ecstatic techniques,” a

phrase the Dean attributes to Bradford (36). Anthropologists had long

since documented beyond any reasonable possibility of refutation all

these aspects of many primitive cultures. What the Man-the-Hunter

revisionists added was precisely what the Dean claims is missing, the

social dimension: “Egalitarianism, sharing, and low work effort were

stressed, as was the importance of gathering foods and, by extension,

women’s direct role in the economy” (Renouf 1991: 89). The Dean’s entire

rhetorical strategy is as misdirected as it is malicious. Primitivists

contrast the orderly anarchy and the generous egalitarianism of foragers

with the chaotic statism and class hierarchy of urban civilization. The

Dean dredges up one foraging society, the Yuqui of Bolivia, which, he

claims, includes the institution of hereditary slavery — although he has

to admit that “this feature is now regarded as a feature of former

horticultural lifeways” (45).

You could hardly ask for a better example of the exception that proves

the rule. There were only 43 Yuqui at contact in the 1950s, far below

the minimum — usually put at about 500 — for social viability. They are

probably descended from a Guaraní raiding party of the late

pre-Columbian period which was unable to find its way back to Paraguay.

Remarkably, they maintained vestiges of slavery, something “difficult to

imagine, but it did exist.” The Dean neglects to mention that upon

falling into the clutches of the missionaries, this social splinter

abandoned both foraging and slavery (Stearman 1989). This example

proves, at the most, that foraging societies are not always anarchist

and egalitarian, leaving untouched the conclusion, which even the Dean

doesn’t deny, that they are almost always anarchist and egalitarian.

On the other hand, in thirty years of celebrating urbanism, the Dean has

yet to identify a stable, anarchic, egalitarian urban society. Perhaps

revolutionary Barcelona approximated one for a few months in 1936–1937,

and Paris in 1968 for several weeks. But at best these are only blips on

a social screen of almost unrelieved urban statism and class

stratification. These “outliers,” as the statisticians refer to rare

values of variables, far outside the range of all others, do remind us —

as do the Yuqui — of the human capacity for extreme social plasticity.

As such, they hearten me, but they fail to persuade me that “some kind

of urban community is not only the environment of humanity: it is its

destiny” (Bookchin 1974: 2). I don’t think anatomy is destiny and I

don’t think urbanity is destiny either.

Chapter 9: From Primitive Affluence to Labor-Enslaving Technology

One tendency which surely belongs on the Dean’s enemies short list is

zero-work, the critique of work as such, “the notion that the abolition

of work is possible and desirable: that genuine, unconditioned needs can

be met by voluntary playlike activity enjoyed for its own sake” (Black

1996d: 22). Zero-work may well be the only programmatic position shared

by everybody the Dean targets, even L. Susan Brown (1995). The Left That

Was not only posited work as a necessity, it regarded it as almost a

sacrament. And while zero-work is not the same thing as such Bookchin

bugbears as hedonism and primitivism, it complements them nicely. It is

an important Bookchin target, but he attacks it with potshots, not the

usual scattershot. There may be several reasons for his uncharacteristic

circumspection.

In his younger days (“younger” being, of course, a relative term),

Bookchin understood that dealing radically with what he called “toil”

was a crucial dimension of post-scarcity anarchism: “The distinction

between pleasurable work and onerous toil should always be kept in mind”

(1971: 92). Even 25 years ago, the productive forces had developed “to a

point where even toil, not only material scarcity, is being brought into

question” (Bookchin 1970: 53). For the traditional left, the answer to

the question of work was to eliminate unemployment, rationalize

production, develop the productive forces, and reduce the hours of work.

To this program the ultra-left, such as the council communists and the

anarcho-syndicalists, added workers’ control of production according to

one formula or another. These reforms, even if completely successful on

their own terms, fall short of any qualitative transformation of the

experience of productive activity. Why doesn’t the Dean just contradict

his former opinion without admitting it, as he does with so many others?

It may be because zero-work is one dimension of avant garde anarchism

which on Bookchin’s terms looks progressive not regressive — a double

irony, as heterodox anarchists tend to disbelieve in progress. Reduced

hours of work is an ancient demand of the left (and of the labor

movement [Hunnicutt 1988]). Marx considered it the precondition of

passage from the realm of necessity to the realm of freedom (1967: 820),

just like Bookchin (Clark 1984: 55). Anarchists agreed: “The eight-hour

day which we officially enjoy is the cause for which the Haymarket

anarchists of 1886 paid with their lives” (Black 1992: 29). Over a

century ago, Kropotkin argued that it was then already possible to

reduce the working day to four or five hours, with retirement by age 45

or 50 (1995: 96). What would his estimate be today: 40 or 50 minutes?

Since the Dean believes (however erroneously) that technological

progress reduces “toil,” at least potentially (26), he has to believe

that the abolition of work is an ever- increasingly practical

possibility. He can only criticize zero-workers, not as reactionaries,

but as ahead of their time. And that debunks the whole notion of

lifestyle anarchism as a surrender to the prevailing climate of

reaction.

The Dean might have other reasons not to be conspicuous or even explicit

in his rejection of zero-work. Lifestyle anarchists have supposedly

withdrawn “from the social domain that formed the principal arena of

earlier anarchists” (2) because lifestyle anarchism “is concerned with a

‘style’ rather than a society” (34). But for an old Marxist like

Bookchin, labor is the very essence of the social: “Labor, perhaps more

than any single human activity, underpins contemporary relationships

among people on every level of experience” (1982: 224). In the

importance they attach to the labor process, zero-workers resemble

traditional socialists, not “the growing ‘inwardness’ and narcissism of

the yuppie generation” (9). Work is about real life, not lifestyle or

hairstyle.

Finally, there might be a very personal source of the Dean’s relative

reticence. His usual method is to focus on one or two prominent

expositors of each malign aspect of lifestyle anarchism. Were he to deal

with zero-work that way he would probably have to deal with me. As the

author of “The Abolition of Work” (Black 1986: 17–33), a widely read

essay which has been published in seven languages, and other zero-work

writings (Black 1992: ch. 1; 1996b), I would be the single most

convenient whipping-boy. But Bookchin never refers to me with respect to

zero-work or anything else. What am I, chopped liver?

I can only speculate why I was spared, except by implication, the Dean’s

wrath. The flattering suggestion has been made that he feared my polemic

powers and hoped I’d ignore his diatribe unless personally provoked by

it (Jarach 1996: 3). If so, he miscalculated. I’m a better friend to my

friends than that, and besides, I like a good fight. I’m not the kind of

guy who says: “First they came for the anarcho-liberal individualists,

but I said nothing, for I was not an anarcho-liberal individualist; next

they came for the mystics, but I said nothing, for I was not a mystic;

next they came for the primitivists, but I said nothing, for I was not a

primitivist,” etc.

If anything, I am peeved to be overlooked. Bookchin’s enemies list looks

to be for the anarchists of the ‘90s what Nixon’s enemies list was for

the liberals of the ‘70s, an honor roll. I’ve previously flattened a

nobody — his name doesn’t matter — who pushed the same line as Bookchin

(Black 1992: 181–193; Black & Gunderloy 1992) although that one also

happened not to mention my name. For me, the political is the personal.

An attack upon all is an attack upon one. Solidarity forever — or make

my day! ¡No paserán — baby!

We have already seen (Chapter 9) how the Dean blithely misrepresents the

best current understanding of how, and how long, foragers work — if that

is even the word for what they do for a living, or rather, for the

living that they do. As I’ve summarized the situation in my book

Friendly Fire:

In addition to shorter hours, “flextime” and the more reliable “safety

net” afforded by food sharing, foragers’ work is more satisfying than

most modern work. We awaken to the alarm clock; they sleep a lot, night

and day. We are sedentary in our buildings in our polluted cities; they

move about breathing the fresh air of the open country. We have bosses;

they have companions. Our work typically implicates one, or at most a

few hyper-specialized skills, if any; theirs combines handwork and

brainwork in a versatile variety of activities, exactly as the great

Utopians called for (Black 1992: 33).

I’ve cited ample supporting references in that book (which the Dean is

surely familiar with, if less than happy with) as also in this one (cf.

Zerzan 1994: 171–185 [Bibliography]). All Bookchin can do is fulminate

that the primitive affluence thesis is hippie hokum, an ad hominem

insult which is irrelevant as well as untrue.

The Dean is equally wrong about work — and the relationship of

technology to work — in other forms of society. In Friendly Fire I

summarized some of the evidence (there’s lots more) that as technology

advances, the quantity of work increases and the quality of the work

experience declines (Black 1992: 19–41). In general, there’s no such

thing as labor-saving technology. There’s usually, at best, only labor-

rearranging technology, which from the worker’s perspective is sort of

like “emigrating from Romania to Ethiopia in search of a better life”

(ibid.: 13). Capitalists develop and deploy new technology, not to

reduce labor, but to reduce the price of labor. The higher the tech, the

lower the wages and the smaller the work-force.

When he descends from declamation to detail, the Dean exposes his

ignorance of the real history of work and technology. The two examples

he adduces are evidence enough. Here’s his cartoon history of Southern

agriculture:

In the South, plantation owners needed slave “hands” in great part

because the machinery to plant and pick cotton did not exist; indeed,

American tenant farming has disappeared over the past two generations

because new machinery was introduced to replace the labor of “freed”

black share-croppers (35).

In other words, Bookchin blames slavery on technological backwardness,

not on a capitalist world-system which assigned to the South the

function of export monoculture. But cotton was of minor importance in

the low-tech colonial economy of the seventeenth and eighteenth

centuries when slaves were raising other export crops such as tobacco,

rice and indigo (McCusker & Menard 1985). As every schoolchild knows,

technical progress strengthened slavery, which had been languishing,

with the conjunction of the cotton gin with the textiles-based

Industrial Revolution in Britain (Scheiber, Vatter & Faulkner 1976:

130–134).

If what Bookchin says about slaveholders makes sense, thenevery ruling

class is off the hook. The plantation owners “needed” slaves “in great

part” because they lacked machines to do their work for them. Presumably

industrialists “needed” child labor for the same reason. Athenian

citizens “needed” slaves because their technology was inadequate to peel

their grapes, give them blowjobs, and satisfy the many other needs of a

civic-minded citizenry with aims so lofty that they could not be

troubled with earning their own keep. “Need” is socially and

economically relative. No doubt the Southern planters and the Athenian

citizens needed slaves, but did the slaves need the Southern planters or

the Athenian citizens?

The Deans’s other example is also maladroit. It’s that classic

instrument of women’s liberation, the washing machine: “Modern working

women with children could hardly do without washing machines to relieve

them, however minimally, from their daily domestic labors — before going

to work to earn what is often the greater part of their households’

income” (49). In other words, the washing machine reinforces the

domestic sexual division of labor and enables women to be

proletarianized — to enter the paid labor force at the bottom (Black

1992: 29–30). Thanks to technology, modern working women get to do the

unpaid drudge-work, the “shadow work” (Illich 1981) of the patriarchal

household, plus the underpaid capitalist drudge-work of the office, the

restaurant and even the factory. The washing machine, and household

technology in general, never saved women any labor-time. It just raised

performance standards (with a Maytag, no excuse any more if your

laundry’s not brighter than white) or else displaced effort to other

tasks like child care (Cowan 1974, 1983). I doubt Bookchin does his own

laundry, and not only because he’s always airing his dirty linen in

public.

In Bookchin’s civic Utopia, “a high premium would be placed on

labour-saving devices — be they computers or automatic machinery — that

would free human beings from needless toil and give them unstructured

leisure time for their self-cultivation as individuals and citizens”

(1989: 197). To believe in that is, for someone as ignorant as Bookchin,

an act of faith. In recent decades productivity, driven by high

technology far beyond anything the Dean anticipated, has increased

prodigiously — more than doubling since 1948 (Schor 1991: 1–2, 5, 29).

Oddly enough, not even “material scarcity,” much less “toil,” has

diminished. Real income has fallen at the same time hours of work have

increased (Black 1994: 31–32; Black 1996b: 45). Even the Dean has

noticed, literally on page one, “the growing impoverishment of millions

of people” at the same time that “the intensity of exploitation has

forced people in growing numbers to accept a work week typical of the

last century” (1). What he hasn’t noticed is that the paradox of more

progress, more productivity, more poverty and more work calls his

essentially Marxist celebration of the development of the productive

forces, as he might say, “into question.”

The Dean admits that “many technologies are inherently domineering and

ecologically dangerous” (34), but he cannot imagine that they increase

and worsen work. Really he just doesn’t care. He hasn’t devoted any

sustained attention to work since Post-Scarcity Anarchism (1971). After

25 years as a college bureaucrat, the factory is a distant memory. His

1989 primer summarizing his views on remaking society devoted all of two

sentences to work with but a perfunctory affirmation of rotation of

tasks (1989: 195). All Bookchin cares about any more is politics and

ecology, in that order. Provided a technology is neither “domineering”

nor “dangerous,” its impact on work means nothing to him.

Nothing better dramatizes the Dean’s self-deception and irrelevance than

the contrast between his fervor for politics and his indifference to

work. He believes, because he wants to believe, that “seldom in recent

memory has there been a more compelling popular sentiment for a new

politics” (59). That contradicts his characterization of the epoch as

privatistic, personalistic and apolitical. The truth is that seldom in

recent memory has there been a more compelling sentiment for no

politics.

On the other hand, work is if anything more salient, if less liked, in

the lives of ordinary people than it’s been in decades. Longer hours,

lower real incomes, and employment insecurity have done nothing to

compensate for the joyless and often humiliating experience of the work

itself. In the 1960s Bookchin, ever alert to sniffing out potentially

revolutionary sources of social malaise, expressed approval of the

younger generation’s contempt for the work trap (Bookchin 1970: 54, 61;

1971: 175–176; cf. 1994: 30). But while other Bookchin-approved

tendencies, like youth culture, were recuperated, a widening revolt

against work became a persistent feature of the American workplace

(DeLeon 1996: 196–197; Zerzan 1988: 170–183). Spontaneous and

acephalous, it could neither be bought out by bosses nor organized by

leftists. The overworked and the unemployed — now there’s a potentially

revolutionary force (Black 1996a).

Chapter 10: Shut Up, Marxist!

As a matter of course, unless ideology withers away, it eventually

hardens into dogma. After Jesus comes Paul, and eventually some Pope,

Innocent in name only. That Bookchinism would calcify into a creed after

no very long time is no surprise. Even in its prime it was arthritic

with Rousseau, St.-Simon, Marx and Arendt. It was always ambiguous about

technology and scarcity. Its ecological content was always at odds with

its civism, to which, in retrospect, ecology seems to have always been

an accessory, an add-on. It’s marred by eccentricities as various as

primitive gerontocracy and Swiss anarchy. It’s unredeemed by irony, much

less humor. What’s amazing is that Bookchin isn’t leaving Bookchinism to

its Plekhanovs, Kautskys and Lenins. He’s vulgarizing his ideology

himself.

As the Green Anarchist reviewer observes, the Dean now “goes on to

crudely reduce or reject all that’s best in his Ecology of Freedom,”

forsaking dialectics for dualism (Anonymous 1996: 22). In fact he’s gone

back on the best of everything he’s written. This latest tract by the

author of “Listen, Marxist!” might have been titled “Listen to the

Marxist!” The author of “Desire and Need” (2) denounces desire as greed.

The benign, “conciliatory” animism of organic society (Bookchin 1982:

98) has become “an inexplicable, often frightening dream world that they

[the ignorant jungle bunnies] took for reality” (42). The author who

acclaimed the drop-out culture (Bookchin 1970: 63 n. 1) now vilifies

“lumpen lifeways” (56). The author who cannot spit out the word “zine”

without contemptuous quotation marks (51) used to publish a zine,

Comment, himself (Bookchin 1979: 28). There must be hundreds of these

contradictions. The Dean is oblivious to all of them.

“Certainly,” decrees the Dean, “it is already no longer possible, in my

view, to call oneself an anarchist without adding a qualifying adjective

to distinguish oneself from lifestyle anarchists” (61). That’s the most

reasonable proposal in the entire essay. I suggest he call himself a

“Bookchinist anarchist” or, if his overweening modesty forbids, an

“anti-lifestyle anarchist.” Nobody will know what he’s talking about, so

introducing himself that way might stimulate curiosity about his views,

much as would introducing oneself as a Two-Seed-in-the-Spirit Primitive

Baptist.

Fated to failure, however, is any attempt to standardize the terminology

on Bookchin’s tendentious terms. Most anarchists would already rather

answer to “social anarchist” than “lifestyle anarchist.” Reading the

Dean’s tract won’t turn any lifestyle anarchists — who number in the

“thousands” (1) — into social anarchists, but it might encourage them to

adopt protective coloration (red). We will all be social anarchists,

even if, like Bookchin, we aren’t anarchists at all. Bookchinists might

retaliate by calling themselves “very social anarchists,” but you see

where that would lead. They need a name nobody else wants. How about

“Marxist”?

Chapter 11: Anarchy after Leftism

In one respect, Murray Bookchin is right in almost the only way he’s

still capable of, i.e., for the wrong reasons. The anarchists are at a

turning point. For the first time in history, they are the only

revolutionary current. To be sure, not all anarchists are

revolutionaries, but it is no longer possible to be a revolutionary

without being an anarchist, in fact if not in name.

Throughout its existence as a conscious current, anarchism has been

shadowed and usually overshadowed by leftism in general, and Marxism in

particular. Especially since the formation of the Soviet Union,

anarchism has effectively (and therefore ineffectively) defined itself

with reference to Marxism. The reduction of anarchists to satellites of

the Communists, especially in revolutionary situations, is so regular a

feature of their modern history that it can’t be an accident. Fixated on

their great rival, the anarchists have competed with Marxists on their

own leftist terms and so the anarchists have always lost.

Marxism was already ideologically bankrupt by the time European

Communism collapsed. As ideology, Marxism is now merely a campus — and

mostly a faculty — phenomenon, and even as such its persistence is

mostly parasitic upon feminism and the racial nationalisms. As a state

system, what remains of Marxism is merely Oriental despotism,

unthinkable as a model for the West. Suddenly, seventy years of

anarchist excuses became irrelevant.

Although these developments caught the anarchists, like everybody else,

by surprise, they were not as unprepared as they would have been twenty

years earlier. Many of them had, if not by design, then by drift and

default, strayed from their traditional position as “the ‘left wing’ of

‘all socialisms’” (6) — but not by moving to the right. Like many other

North Americans, they were unable to discern any difference between left

and right of such importance that they felt compelled to declare for one

or the other. As the leftist veneer — or tarnish — they typically

acquired in college wore off, an indigenous anti-authoritarianism showed

through. The Marxists they encountered on campus were too ridiculous to

be taken seriously as rivals or reference points. (That some of them

were professors made them that much more ridiculous.) More than ever

before, some anarchists insisted on a “personalistic” grounding of

politics in the experience of everyday life, and they correspondingly

opened up to theorists like the situationists for whom the critique of

everyday life was a first principle. They took to dumpster-diving among

the discards of doctrines and cultures to fashion, like a collage,

recombinant world-pictures of their own. And if Nietzsche’s definition

is right — that man is the animal who laughs — then they recovered some

of their humanity too.

Now I admit this picture is too rosy because it’s not red enough. A

fraction of North American anarchists, mostly syndicalists, remain

out-and-out leftists. As such, they share the decline of the rest of the

left. They no longer include any first-rate or even second-rate

thinkers. Other pockets of anarchists act as auxiliaries of sub-leftist,

particularist ideologies like feminism and Third World nationalism

(including indigenism) — the larger hunks of wreckage from the New Left.

These too have produced their logorrheics but nobody with anything to

say. Many other anarchists retain vestiges of leftism (not always a bad

thing). What’s important is how many of them, whatever their lingering

influences, simply aren’t leftists any more. The Dean’s jeremiad

expresses his shock of recognition at this unprecedented state of

affairs.

The precondition for any substantial increase in anarchist influence is

for anarchists to make explicit and emphatic their break with the left.

This does not mean placing the critique of the left at the center of

analysis and agitation. On the contrary, that’s always been a symptom of

anarchism’s satellite status. It is enough to identify leftism, as the

occasion arises, as all it really is, a variant of hegemonic ideology —

a loyal opposition — which was formerly effective in recuperating

revolutionary tendencies. There’s no reason for anarchists to inherit an

accursed share of the left’s unpopularity. Let’s make our own enemies.

And our own friends. Since there really is something anarchist about

some popular tendencies, we should try to make some anarchist tendencies

popular. Certain anarchist themes both old and new resonate with certain

widespread attitudes. It isn’t necessarily elitist or manipulative to

circulate the proposition that anarchism explicates and elaborates

various inchoate anti-authoritarian tendencies. This can be done in an

imperialistic and opportunistic fashion, but I believe it can also be

done, judiciously, in good faith. If we’re mistaken, no harm done, we

just won’t go over very well, something we’re used to. Many people will

surely shrink, at least initially, from drawing the anarchist

conclusions we suggest their own attitudes and values tend toward. Then

again, some others may not, not even initially — especially the young.

Besides, making converts is not the only purpose of anarchist agitprop.

It may also enlarge the chokingly constricted range of North American

political discourse. We may never bring most of the intelligentsia over,

but we can soften them up. We can reduce some of them to sympathizers,

to what the Stalinists called fellow travellers, to what Lenin called

useful idiots. They will traduce our ideas but also, in some mutilated

form, send them around and legitimate them in the sense that they are to

be taken seriously. And in so doing they will weaken their own power to

counter them if and when these ideas are taken seriously enough to be

acted upon by those who understand them.

Americans (and undoubtedly others, but I’ll stick with the American

context Bookchin addresses) really are in a certain sense “anarchistic.”

I’m not going to pretend, like David De Leon (1978), that there is

something innately and immemorially anarchist about Americans. Our

beliefs and behavior have long been otherwise in important respects.

Most contemporary American anarchists and other radicals — and I include

myself here — have been consciously and conspicuously anti-American. In

college, I majored in history, but I took courses only in European

history, because Europeans had a revolutionary heritage which we

Americans (I assumed) did not. Much later I learned that Americans have

at times been much more revolutionary (and so, to me, more interesting)

than I originally supposed. While this discovery didn’t transform me

into a patriot, as my anti-Gulf War activities demonstrate (Black 1992:

ch. 9), it did kindle a sympathetic interest in American history which I

am still pursuing. Anarchy is at once very much an elaboration of

certain American values and at the same time antithetical to certain

others. So it makes no sense for American anarchists to be pro-American

or anti-American. They should be themselves — their one indisputable

area of expertise — and see what that leads to.

Post-leftist anarchy is positioned to articulate — not a program — but a

number of revolutionary themes with contemporary relevance and

resonance. It is, unlike Bookchinism, unambiguously anti-political, and

many people are anti-political. It is, unlike Bookchinism, hedonistic,

and many people fail to see why life is not to be lived enjoyably if it

is to be lived at all. It is, unlike Bookchinism, “individualistic” in

the sense that if the freedom and happiness of the individual — i.e.,

each and every really existing person, every Tom, Dick and Murray — is

not the measure of the good society, what is? Many people wonder what’s

wrong with wanting to be happy. Post-leftist anarchy is, unlike

Bookchinism, if not necessarily rejective, then at least suspicious of

the chronically unfulfilled liberatory promise of high technology. And

maybe most important of all is the massive revulsion against work, an

institution which has become less and less important to Bookchin at the

same time it’s become more and more important, and oppressive, to people

outside academia who actually have to work. Most people would rather do

less work than attend more meetings. Which is to say, most people are

smarter, and saner, than Murray Bookchin is. Post-leftist anarchists

mostly don’t regard our times one-dimensionally, as either a “decadent,

bourgeoisified era” (1) of “social reaction” (9) or as the dawning of

the Age of Aquarius. They tend toward pessimism, but not usually as much

as the Dean does. The system, unstable as ever, never ceases to create

conditions which undermine it. Its self-inflicted wounds await our salt.

If you don’t believe in progress, it’ll never disappoint you and you

might even make some progress.

In some particulars, — as I’ve come to appreciate, somewhat to my

surprise, in writing this essay, — traditional anarchist themes and

practices are more attuned to popular predilections than ever before.

Most Americans have joined them, for instance, in abstention from

elections, and they just might be interested in the anarchists’ reasons.

Class conflict at the point of production holds little interest for

campus-based Bookchinist-Arendtist civilogues, but means much to

post-college workers reduced, for the duration, to the degradation they

briefly thought they’d escaped by graduating from high school. Now they

must work to pay off the loans that financed an interval of relative

freedom (a Temporary Autonomous Zone, as it were) such as they may never

enjoy again, no matter how much they earn. They may have learned just

enough along the way to question whether life has to be this way.

But the new themes of the New Anarchism, or, better yet, the New

Anarchisms also have popular appeal — not because they pander to

prevalent illusions but because they pander (and why not?) to prevalent

disillusions. With technology, for instance. A political critique of

technology may make a lot of sense to the tenders of high technology who

have not experienced anything of its liberatory potential as so often

promised but never delivered by the progressives, by the Marxists,

syndicalists, Bookchinists and other technocrats. At the very least,

trickle-down techno-liberation is as fraudulent as trickle-down

enrichment through supply-side economics (make the already rich so much

richer that some crumbs are bound to fall from their table). Computer

programming is, if more interesting, little more liberatory than data

entry, and the hours are longer. There’s no light at the end of the

carpal tunnel.

With whatever elements the New Anarchisms are compounded and whatever

their fortunes will be, the old anarchism — the libertarian fringe of

the Left That Was — is finished. The Bookchinist blip was a conjunctural

quirk, an anomalous amalgam of the old anarchism and the New Left to

which the Dean-to-be fortuitously added a little pop ecology and (this

part passed unnoticed for far too long) his weird city-statist fetish.

Now Bookchin belatedly bumbles forth as the defender of the faith, that

old-time religion. Anarchism-as-Bookchinism was a confusionist episode

even he, its fabricator, seems to be in haste to conclude.

If the word “decadence” means anything, Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism is an exercise in decadence, not to mention an exercise in

futility. If the word means anything, it means a deterioration from a

previous higher level of accomplishment — it means doing worse what was

formerly done better. In that sense, the New Anarchisms of the

“lifestyle anarchists” cannot be decadent, for what they are doing is at

best, something better, and at worst, something different from what the

old-style left-wing anarchists did. Bookchin is not even doing what

Bookchin once did, if never very well, then at least a lot better.

Within anarchism, what is taking place resembles what, in science, is

known as a paradigm shift (Kuhn 1970). A paradigm is an overarching

frame of reference, something broader than a theory (or ideology), which

directs the development of thought for those belonging to a community of

those operating within the paradigm. That this is a somewhat circular

formulation its originator admits (ibid.: 176), but truth is circular,

an inescapable hermeneutic circle but one whose diameter we can widen

along with our perspectives. The details and, for that matter, the

deficiencies of Kuhn’s much-discussed model of scientific theory and

practice need not detain us here (although I commend them to anarchists

capable of more muscular thinking than Bookchin and most other

anarcho-eggheads are up for). Here I’m drawing attention to just two

aspects of this historical approach to explaining theoretical thinking

which I find suggestive.

The first is the notion of “normal science,” which refers to the

everyday practice of workaday scientists: the working-out of the

implications of the prevailing paradigm. Newton’s physics, for instance,

kept observational astronomers and experimental physicists happy, or at

least busy, for over two hundred years: it assigned them problems to

solve and criteria for what counted as solutions to those problems.

The classical anarchism of Godwin, Proudhon, Bakunin and especially

Kropotkin may be thought of as the original anarchist political

paradigm. For all their differences, together they furnished many

answers and a context for developing many more. Later figures like

Malatesta, Goldman, Berkman, the anarcho-syndicalists, and the

intellectuals writing for Freedom in effect engaged in “normal

anarchism” — in restating, elaborating, updating and in details amending

the paradigm. Men like Herbert Read, George Woodcock, Alex Comfort and

Paul Goodman worked within this tradition in the inclement climate of

the ‘40s and ‘50s. In characterizing their activity as derivative I am

by no means denigrating it, or them. Precisely because the classical

paradigm was rich in potential, intelligent anarchists have drawn fresh

insights from it by applying it to changing 20th-century developments.

But the developments have long since outstripped the paradigm. Too many

“anomalies,” as Kuhn calls them, have appeared to be reconciled with the

paradigm without increasing strain and a deepening sense of

artificiality. Classical anarchism, like leftism in general, is played

out. Murray Bookchin, whom some anarchists once mistook for the first

theorist of a new anarchist paradigm, has now come forth explicitly as

the last champion of the old one, the anarchist tail of what he calls

the Left That Was.

One other suggestive feature of Kuhn’s argument is his account of how,

on the ground, the supplanting of one paradigm by another actually takes

place:

When, in the development of a natural science, an individual or group

first produces a synthesis able to attract most of the next generation’s

practitioners [emphasis added], the older schools gradually disappear.

In part their disappearance is caused by their members’ conversion to

the new paradigm. But there are always some men who cling to one or

another of the older views, and they are simply read out of the

profession, which thereafter ignores their work (Kuhn 1970: 18–19).

Kuhn goes on to explain that this may involve intransigent individuals,

“more interesting, however, is the endurance of whole schools in

increasing isolation from professional science. Consider, for example,

the case of astrology, which was once an integral part of astronomy”

(ibid.: 19 n. 11).

Not to pretend that anarchism is a science — such a pretense is itself a

part of the obsolete paradigm — but the analogy is illuminating. As

Bookchin admits, and deplores, “thousands” of anarchists, “the next

generation’s practitioners” of anarchism, are increasingly abandoning

social anarchism for lifestyle anarchism. Some of the older school’s

practitioners convert, as has indeed happened. Other once-prominent

figures, as Kuhn noticed (ibid.), marginalize themselves as the Dean has

now done. And to clinch the comparison, what were once “integral parts”

of anarchism are on the verge of splitting off on their own as did

astrology from astronomy so as to have any hope of surviving at all.

Bookchinism, “social ecology,” was never an integral part of anarchism,

for all the Dean’s efforts to make it so. If it persists awhile after

the Dean’s demise, social ecology/anarchism will bear about the same

relationship to the new anarchism as astrology to astronomy.

As will, I expect, the dwindling anarcho-leftist fundamentalisms. Of

these there would seem to be only three. The first is the supposed

pure-and-simple anarchism of, say, Fred Woodworth of The Match! or the

late unlamented Bob Shea. The inherent improbability of a socially and

economically agnostic anarchism — let’s abolish the state and later sort

out the trifling details, such as our way of life — as well as the sheer

crackpotkinism of its vestigial devotees (Black 1994: 42–44) relegate

this fundamentalism to imminent oblivion. Even Bookchin would be

embarrassed to be associated with it. A Marxist is capable of many

errors and many horrors, and usually commits some, but one thing a

Marxist cannot be indifferent to is political economy and the social

relations of production.

The second obsolete anarcho-leftism is anarcho- syndicalism. Although it

is a workerist ideology, its few working-class adherents are elderly.

Although it is by definition a union-oriented ideology, there is no

perceptible syndicalist presence in any union. A syndicalist is more

likely to be a professor than a proletarian, more likely to be a folk

singer than a factory worker. Organizers on principle, syndicalists are

disunited and factionalized. Remarkably, this dullest of all anarchisms

attracts some of the most irrational and hysterical adherents. Only a

rather small minority of North American anarchists are syndicalists.

Syndicalism will persist, if at all, as a campus-based cult in

increasing isolation from the main currents of anarchism.

The third anarcho-leftism is anarcho-feminism. The category is, I admit,

questionable. So-called radical feminism is leftist in origin but

extreme right-wing in ideology (Black 1986: 133–138; Black 1992:

195–197). Separatist in tendency and sometimes in principle,

anarcho-feminism is oriented much more toward statist feminism than

anarchism. It is already well on its way toward encapsulation and

isolation from the anarchisms. The feminist presence in anarchism is

more apparent than real. Many anarchist women call themselves feminists

from force of habit or because they think that by not so identifying

themselves they somehow undermine those women who do. But there is

little if anything distinctively feminist, fortunately, in the anarchism

of most nominal anarcho-feminists. Feminism is so obviously an

Establishment ideology and so remote from its (largely mythical) radical

roots that its affirmation by anarchists will become ever more

perfunctory. Like leftism, feminism is a needless liability for

anarchists.

There is life after the left. And there is anarchy after anarchism.

Post-leftist anarchists are striking off in many directions. Some may

find the way — better yet, the ways — to a free future.

References

Adams, Robert M. (1983). Decadent Societies. San Francisco, CA: North

Point Press

Adorno, Theodor W. (1990). “Punctuation Marks.” The Antioch Review

(Summer): 300–305

Andrieux, Maurice (1972). Daily Life in Venice in the Time of Casanova.

New York & Washington, DC: Praeger Publisher

[Anonymous] (1988). Review of The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline

of Citizenship, by Murray Bookchin. Orbis: A Journal of World Affairs 32

(Fall): 628

[Anonymous] (1996). Review of Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism:

An Unbridgeable Chasm, by Murray Bookchin. Green Anarchist 42 (Summer):

22–23

Ansell-Pearson, Keith (1994).An Introduction to Nietzsche as Political

Thinker: The Perfect Nihilist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Apter, David E., & James Joll, eds. (1972). Anarchism Today. Garden

City, NY: Anchor Books

Arendt, Hannah (1958). The Human Condition. Chicago, IL & London:

University of Chicago Press

Avrich, Paul (1984). The Haymarket Tragedy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press

Babbie, Earl (1992). The Practice of Social Research. Sixth Edition.

Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company

Bailyn, Bernard (1992). The Ideological Origins of the American

Revolution. Enlarged Edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

Bakunin, Michael (1990). Statism and Anarchy. Edited by Marshall Shatz.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Beals, Ralph L. (1969). Politics of Social Research: An Inquiry into the

Ethics and Responsibilities of Social Scientists. Chicago, IL: Aldine

Publishing Company

Benbow, William (n.d.). Grand National Holiday and Congress of the

Productive Classes. Edited by SA. Bushell. London: Pelagian Press

Bey, Hakim (1991). T.A.Z.: The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological

Anarchism, Poetic Terrorism. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia

Binford, Lewis R., & W.J. Chasto, Jr. (1976). “Nunamiut Demographic

History: A Provocative Case.” In Zubrow (1976), pp. 63–143

Binford, Sally R. (1968). “Ethnographic Data and Understanding the

Pleistocene.” In Lee & DeVore (1968a), pp. 274–275

Black, Bob (1986). The Abolition of Work and Other Essays. Port

Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited

— (1992). Friendly Fire. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia

— (1994). Beneath the Underground. Portland, OR: Feral House

— (1996a). “Technophilia, An Infantile Disorder.” Green Anarchist 42

(Summer): 13–15

— (1996b). “What’s Wrong With This Picture?” Exquisite Corpse 57: 43–45

— (1996c). Unpublished review of Grand National Holiday and Congress of

the Productive Classes, by William Benbow

— (1996d). “Zero Work.” Small Magazine Review 28(6) (June): 22

— , & Mike Gunderloy (1992). “Neo-Individualism Reconsidered.” In Black

(1992), pp. 199–201

— , & Adam Parfrey, eds. (1989). Rants and Incendiary Tracts: Voices of

Desperate Illumination, 1558 to Present. New York: Amok Press & Port

Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited

Black, Robert C. [Bob Black] (1985). “The Heavenly City of the

20th-Century Political Philosopher: Walzer on Judging.” Legal Studies

Forum 9(3): 259–279

Blainey, Geoffrey (1976). Triumph of the Nomads: A History of Aboriginal

Australia. Woodstock, NY: Overlook Press

Bolloten, Burnett (1991). The Spanish Civil War. Chapel Hill, NC:

University of North Carolina Press

Bookchin, Murray (1970). “The Youth Culture: An Anarcho- Communist

View.” In Hip Culture: Six Essays on Its Revolutionary Potential (New

York: Times Change Press), pp. 51–63

— (1971). Post-Scarcity Anarchism. Berkeley, CA: The Ramparts Press

— (1974). The Limits of the City. New York: Harper & Row Colophon Books

— (1977). The Spanish Anarchists: The Heroic Years, 1868–1936. New York:

Free Life Editions, 1977

— (1979). “Marxism as Bourgeois Sociology.” Our Generation 13(3)

(Summer): 21–28

— (1982). The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of

Hierarchy. Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books

— (1987a). The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship. San

Francisco, CA: Sierra Club Books

— (1987b). “Thinking Ecologically: A Dialectical Approach.” 18(2) Our

Generation (March): 3–40

— (1989). Remaking Society. Montreal, Canada & New York: Black Rose

Books

— (1990). “Radical Politics in an Era of Advanced Capitalism.” Our

Generation 21(2) (June): 1–12

— (1991). Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of

Hierarchy. Revised Edition. Montreal, Canada: Black Rose Books

— (1994). To Remember Spain: The Anarchist and Syndicalist Revolution of

1936. Edinburgh, Scotland & San Francisco, CA: AK Press

— (1996). “Anarchism: Past and Present.” In Ehrlich (1996), pp. 19–30

Boyd, Robert, & Peter J. Richerson (1993). “Culture and Human

Evolution.” In Rasmussen (1993), pp. 119–134

Borkenau, Franz (1963). The Spanish Cockpit. Ann Arbor, MI: University

of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor Paperbacks

Brademas, Stephen John (1953). “Revolution and Social Revolution: A

Contribution to the History of the Anarcho-Syndicalist Movement in

Spain: 1930–1937.” Ph.D dissertation, University of Oxford

Bradford, George (1996). “Media: Capital’s Global Village.” In Ehrlich

(1996), pp. 258–271

Broué, Pierre, & Émile Témime (1972). The Revolution and the Civil War

in Spain. Cambridge: MIT Press

Brown, L. Susan (1993). The Politics of Individualism: Liberalism,

Liberal Feminism and Anarchism. Montreal, Canada: Black Rose Books

— (1995). “Does Work Really Work?” Kick It Over 35: 14- 17

Camatte, Jacques (1995). This World We Must Leave and Other Essays .

Edited by Alex Trotter. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia

Clark, John (1982). Review of Toward an Ecological Society, by Murray

Bookchin. Our Generation 18(2) (Summer): 52–59

— (1984). The Anarchist Moment: Reflections on Culture, Nature and

Power. Montreal, Canada: Black Rose Books

— (1990). “Bookchin, Murray (b. 1921).” Encyclopedia of the American

Left, ed. Mari Jo Buhle, Paul Buhle & Dan Georgakas. New York & London:

Garland Publications

Cohen, Mark N. (1987). “The Significance of Long-Term Changes in Human

Diet and Food Economy.” In Harris & Ross (1987), pp. 261–283

Cohen, M.N., & G.S. Armelagos, eds. (1984). Paleopathology at the Dawn

of Agriculture. New York: Academic Press

Colbourn, H. Trevor (1965). The Lamp of Experience: Whig History and the

Intellectual Origins of the American Revolution. Chapel Hill, NC:

University of North Carolina Press

Conkey, Margaret W. (1984). “To Find Ourselves: Art and Social Geography

of Prehistoric Hunter Gatherers.” In Schrere (1984), pp. 253–276

Cooke, Jacob E., ed. (1961). The Federalist. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan

University Press

Cowan, Ruth Schwartz (1974). “A Case Study of Technological Change: The

Washing Machine and the Working Wife.” In Hartman & Banner (1974), pp.

245–253

— (1983). More Work for Mother: The Irony of Household Technology from

the Open Hearth to the Microwave. New York: Basic Books

Dahl, Robert A. (1990). After the Revolution: Authority in a Good

Society. Revised Edition. New Haven, CT & London: Yale University Press

Damas, David, ed. (1969). Contributions to Anthropology: Band Societies.

Ottawa, Canada: National Museum of Canada

De Leon, David (1978). The American as Anarchist: Reflections on

Indigenous Radicalism. Baltimore, MD & London: The Johns Hopkins

University Press

— (1996). “For Democracy Where We Work: A Rationale for Self-Management”

In Ehrlich (1996), pp. 192–210

Denbow, James R. (1984). “Prehistoric Herders and Foragers of the

Kalahari: The Evidence for 1500 Years of Interaction.” In Schrire

(1984), pp. 175–193

Denevan, William (1992). “The Pristine Myth: The Landscape of the

Americas in 1492” Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82:

369–385

Dunn, Frederick L. (1968). “Epidemological Factors: Health and Disease

in Hunter-Gatherers.” In Lee & DeVore (1968a), pp. 221–228

Eckersley, Robyn (1989). “Divining Evolution: The Ecological Ethics of

Murray Bookchin.” Environmental Ethics 11(2) (Summer): 99–116

Ehrlich, Howard J., ed. (1996). Reinventing Anarchy, Again. Edinburgh,

Scotland & San Francisco, CA: AK Press

Feyerabend, Paul (1975). Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic

Theory of Knowledge. London: NLB & Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities

Press

— (1987). Farewell to Reason. London & New York: Verso

Finlay, M.I. (1959). “Was Greek Civilisation Based on Slave Labour?”

Historia 8: 145–164

— (1985). Democracy Ancient and Modern. Second Edition. London: The

Hogarth Press

Flint, R.W., ed. (1972). Marinetti: Selected Writings. New York: Farrer,

Straus & Giroux

For Ourselves (1983). The Right to Be Greedy: Theses on the Practical

Necessity of Demanding Everything. Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics

Unlimited

Fraser, Ronald (1979). Blood of Spain: An Oral History of the Spanish

Civil War. New York: Pantheon

Gilman, Richard (1975). Decadence. New York: Farrer, Straus & Giroux

Goddard College (1995). 1995 Off-Campus Catalog. Plainfield, VT: Goddard

College

— (1996). Addendum to Off Campus Catalog. Plainfield, VT: Goddard

College

Goodman, Paul (1994). Crazy Hope and Finite Experience: Final Essays of

Paul Goodman. Edited by Taylor Stoehr. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass,

Inc.

— , & Percival Goodman (1960). Communitas: Means of Livelihood and Ways

of Life. Second Edition, Revised. New York: Vintage Books

Gordon, Robert J. (1984). “The !Kung in the Kalahari Exchange: An

Ethnohistorical Perspective.” In Schrire (1984), pp. 195–224

Gregg, Susan, ed. (1991). Between Bands and States. Carbondale, IL:

Southern University of Illinois at Carbondale

Harris, Marvin, & Eric B. Ross, eds. (1987). Food and Evolution: Toward

a Theory of Human Food Habits. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press

Hart, John M. (1978). Anarchism and the Mexican Working Class,

1860–1931. Austin, TX & London: U. of Texas Press

Hartman, Mary S., & Lois Banner, eds. (1974). Clio’s Consciousness

Raised: New Perspectives on the History of Women. New York: Harper & Row

Hastrup, Kirsten, & Peter Hervik, eds. (1994). Social Experience and

Anthropological Knowledge. New York: Routledge

Hawkes, Kristen (1987). “How Much Food Do Foragers Need?” In Harris &

Ross (1987), pp. 341–355

Herber, Lewis [Murray Bookchin] (1963). Our Synthetic Environment

— [Murray Bookchin] (1965). Crisis in Our Cities. Englewood Cliffs,

N.J.: Prentice-Hall

Holton, Gerald (1993). Science and Anti-Science. Cambridge: Harvard

University Press

Hughes, H. Stuart (1961). Consciousness and Society: The Reorientation

of European Social Thought, 1890–1930. New York: Alfred A. Knopf

Hunnicutt, Benjamin Kline (1988). Work Without End: Abandoning Shorter

Hours for the Right to Work. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press

Illich, Ivan (1981). Shadow Work. Boston, MA: Marion Boyars

Institute for Social Ecology (1996). 1996 Catalog. Plainfield, VT:

Institute for Social Ecology

Jarach, Lawrence (1996). “Manichean Anarchism or Dishonest Anarchism;

Judging a Bookchin by His Cover-Ups.” Unpublished review of Social

Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism forthcoming in Anarchy: A Journal of

Desire Aimed

Kelly, Robert C. (1991). “Sedantism, Sociopolitical Inequality, and

Resource Fluctuations.” In Gregg (1991), pp. 135–158

Knauft, Bruce M. (1987). “Divergence Between Cultural Success and

Reproductive Success in Preindustrial Cities.” Cultural Anthropology

2(1) (Feb.): 94–114

Konner, Melvin, & Marjorie Shostak (1987). “Timing and Management of

Birth Among the !Kung: Biocultural Interaction in Reproductive

Adaptation.” Cultural Anthropology 2(1) (Feb.): 11–28

Kropotkin, Pierre (1890). The Place of Anarchism in Socialistic

Evolution. London: William Reeves

Kropotkin, Peter (1947). Ethics: Origin and Development. New York: The

Dial Press

— (1990). “Preface” to How We Shall Bring About the Revolution:

Syndicalism and the Cooperative Commonwealth, by Emile Pataud and Emile

Pouget. In Pataud & Pouget (1990), pp. xxxi-xxxvii

— (1995). The Conquest of Bread and Other Writings. Edited by Marshall

S. Shatz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Second

Edition, Enlarged. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press

Lasswell, Harold (1958). Politics: Who Gets What, When, How. With

Postscript. New York: Meridian Books

Lee, Richard Borshay (1968). “What Hunters Do for a Living, or, How to

Make Out on Scarce Resources.” In Lee & Devore (1968), pp. 30–48

— (1969). “!Kung Bushmen Subsistence: An Input-Output Analysis.” In

Vayda (1969), pp. 47–79

— (1979). The !Kung San: Men, Women and Work in a Foraging Society.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

— , & Irven DeVore, eds. (1968a). Man the Hunter. Chicago: Aldine

Publishing Company

— & Irven DeVore (1968b). “Preface.” in Lee & DeVore (1968a), pp. vii-ix

— , & Irven DeVore (1968c). “Problems in the Study of Hunters and

Gatherers.” In Lee & DeVore (1968a), pp. 3–12

Legge, Anthony J., & Peter A. Rowley-Conwy (1987). “Gazelle Killing in

Stone Age Syria.” Scientific American 257(2) (August): 88–95

Lenin, V.I. (1940). “Left-Wing” Communism, an Infantile Disorder: A

Popular Essay in Marxian Strategy and Tactics. (Little Lenin Library,

Vol. 20.) N.Y.: International Publishers

— (1950). Materialism and Empirio-Criticism: Critical Comments on a

Reactionary Philosophy. London: Lawrence and Wishart Ltd.

Lévi-Strauss, Claude (1962). The Savage Mind. Chicago, IL: University of

Chicago Press & London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson

Lowie, Robert H. (1963). Indians of the Plains. Garden City, NY: The

Natural History Press

Marx, Karl (1967). Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Edited by

Frederick Engels. Vol. III: The Process of Capitalist Production as a

Whole. New York: International Publishers

McCusker, John J., & Russell R. Menard (1985). The Economy of British

America, 1607–1789. Chapel Hill, NC & London: University of North

Carolina Press

Megill, Allan, ed. (1994). Rethinking Objectivity. Durham, NC:

University of North Carolina Press

Michels, Robert (1962). Political Parties: A Sociological Study of the

Oligarchical Tendencies of Modern Democracy. New York: The Free Press

Monegal, Emir Rodriguez, & Alastair Reid, eds. (1981). Borges: A Reader.

New York: E.P. Dutton

Moore, John (1996). “Commentary on the Anarcho-Futurist Manifesto.”

Green Anarchist 40/41 (Spring): 18–20

Morgan, Edmund S. (1975). American Slavery, American Freedom: The Ordeal

of Colonial Virginia. New York & London: W.W. Norton & Company

Murdoek, George Peter (1968). “The Current Status of the World’s Hunting

and Gathering Peoples.” In Lee & DeVore (1968a), pp. 13–20

Newcomb, W.W., Jr. (1961). The Indians of Texas. Austin, TX: University

of Texas Press

Nietzsche, Friedrich (1994). On the Genealogy of Morality. Edited by

Keith Ansell-Pearson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Novatore, Renzo (1989). “Iconoclasts, Forward!” In Black & Parfrey

(1989), pp. 92–93

Novick, Peter (1988). That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and

the American Historical Profession. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press

Nuquist, Andrew E. (1964). Town Government in Vermont. Burlington, VT:

University of Vermont Government Research Center

Orwell, George (1952). Homage to Catalonia. New York & London: Harcourt

Brace Jovanovich

Pannekoek, Anton (1948). Lenin as Philosopher: A Critical Examination of

the Philosophical Basis of Leninism. New York: New Essays

Parkington, John E. (1984). “Soaqua and Bushmen: Hunters and Robbers.”

In Schrire (1984), pp. 151–174

Pataud, Emile, & Emile Pouget (1990). How We Shall Bring About the

Revolution: Syndicalism and the Cooperative Commonwealth. London &

Winchester, MA: Pluto Press

Peters, Pauline (1990). “The San Historicized.” Science 248 (May 28):

905–907

Popper, Karl L. (1962). The Open Society and Its Enemies. 2 vols. Fourth

Edition, Revised. New York & Evanston, IL: Harper Torchbooks

Proudhon, P.-J. (1979). The Principle of Federation. Edited by Richard

Vernon. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press

Rasmussen, D. Tab, ed. (1993). The Origin and Evolution of Humans and

Humanness. Boston, MA & London: Jones and Bartlett Publisher

Renouf, MA.P. (1991). “Sedentary Hunter-Gathers: A Case for Northern

Coasts.” In Gregg (1991), pp. 89–107

Richards, Vernon (1983). Lessons of the Spanish Revolution, 1936–1939.

Revised, Enlarged Edition. London: Freedom Press

Rifkin, Jeremy (1995). The End of Work: The Decline of the Global Labor

Force and the Dawn of the Post-Market Era. New York: G.P. Putnam’s Sons

Roberts, David D. (1979). The Syndicalist Tradition and Italian Fascism.

Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press

Rocker, Rudolf (1947). Anarcho-syndicalism: Vieory and Practice. Indore,

India: Modern Publishers

Ross, Eric B. (1987). “An Overview of Trends in Dietary Variation from

Hunter-Gatherer to Modern Capitalist Societies.” In Harris & Ross

(1987), pp. 7–55

Ruby, Jay (1996). “Objectivity Revisited.” American Anthropologist 98(2)

(June): 398–400

Ruhart, Mary (1996). “Keeping Our Freedom in an Unfree World.”

Formulations 3(3) (Spring): 3–4, 13

Sahlins, Marshall (1972). Stone Age Economics. Chicago, IL: Aldine

Publishing Company

Salisbury, Neal (1982). Manitou and Providence: Indians, Europeans, and

the Making of New England, 1500–1643. New York & Oxford: Oxford

University Press

Scheiber, Harry N., Harold G. Vatter & Harold Underwood Faulkner (1976).

American Economic History. New York: Harper & Row

Schor, Juliet (1991). The Overworked American: The Unexpected Decline of

Leisure. New York: Basic Books

Schrire, Carmel, ed. (1984). Past and Present in Hunter Gatherer

Societies. Orlando, FL: Academic Press

Schuster, Eunice Minette (1932). Native American Anarchism: A Study of

Left-Wing American Individualism. (Smith College Studies in History,

Vol. XVII, Nos. 1–4.) Northampton, MA: Smith College Department of

History

Seidman, Michael (1991). Workers Against Work: Labor in Paris and

Barcelona During the Popular Fronts. Berkeley: University of California

Press

Sender, Ramón J. (1990). Seven Red Sundays. Chicago, IL: Ivan R. Dee,

Publisher

Silbener, Edmund (1948). “Proudhon’s Judeophobia.” Historica Judaica

11(1) (April): 61–80

Sjoberg, Gideon (1960). The Preindustrial City: Past and Present.

Glencoe, IL: The Free Press

Smith, Gregory B. (1983). Review of The Ecology of Freedom, by Murray

Bookchin. American Political Science Review 77(1) (March): 540

Solway, Jacqueline S., & Richard B. Lee (1990). “Foragers, Genuine or

Spurious? Situating the Kalahari San in History.” Current Anthropology

31(2) (April): 109–146

Stafford, David (1972). “Anarchists in Britain Today.” In Apter & Joll

(1972), pp. 99–122

Stirner, Max (1978). “Stirner’s Critics.” Philosophical Forum 8(2–4):

66–80

— (1995). The Ego and Its Own. Edited by David Leopold. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press

Tanaka, Jiri (1980). The San Hunter-Gatherers of the Kalahari: A Study

in Ecological Anthropology. Tokyo, Japan: University of Tokyo Press

Thissen, Siebe (1996). De Weg naar Croatan. (De Kunst van het Afhaken.)

Rotterdam, Netherlands: Baalprodukties Sittard

Tocqueville, Alexis de (1969a). Democracy in America. Edited by J.P.

Mayer. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books

— (1969b). “Report Given Before the Academy of Moral and Political

Sciences on January 15, 1848, on the Subject of M. Cherbuliez’ Book

Entitled On Democracy in Switzerland.” In Tocqueville (1969a), pp.

736–749 (Appendix II)

Tuchman, Barbara (1966). The Proud Tower. New York: The Macmillan

Company

Vayda, Andrew P., ed. (1969). Environment and Cultural Behavior. New

York: Natural History Press

Vincent, K. Steven (1984). Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French

Republican Socialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press

Walter, Nicolas (1972). “Anarchism in Print: Yesterday and Today.” In

Apter & Joll (1972), pp. 147–168

Walzer, Michael (1970). Obligations: Essays on Disobedience, War; and

Citizenship. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

Watson, Richard A. (1995). Review of Which Way for the Ecology Movement?

by Murray Bookchin. Environmental Ethics 14(4) (Winter): 437–439

Wilmsen, Edwin N. (1989). Land Filled with Flies: A Political Economy of

the Kalahari. Chicago, IL & London: University of Chicago Press

Woodburn, J. (1982). “Egalitarian Societies.” Man 7: 431–451

Woodcock, George (1962). Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and

Movements. New York: Meridian Books

Yengoyan, Aram A. (1968). “Demographic and Ecological Influences on

Aboriginal Australian Marriage Sections.” In Lee & DeVore (1968), pp.

185–199

Zapatistas (1994). Zapatistas! Documents of the New Mexican Revolution.

Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia

Zerzan, John (1987). Elements of Refusal. Seattle, WA: Left Bank Books

— (1994). Future Primitive and Other Essays. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia &

Columbia, MO: Anarchy/C.A.L. Press

— (1996). Letter to Bob Black, May 20

Zimmern, Alfred (1931). The Greek Commonwealth: Politics and Economics

in Fifth-Century Athens. Fifth Edition, Revised. Oxford: at the

Clarendon Press

Zubrow, Ezra B.W., ed. (1976). Demographic Anthropology: Quantitative

Approaches. Albuquerque, NM: University of New Mexico Press

[1] The Fifth Estate’s David Watson (aka George Bradford) has just

written a valuable critique of major themes in Bookchin’s work titled

Beyond Bookchin: Preface for a Future Social Ecology, published by

Autonomedia (Brooklyn, NY) and Black & Red (Detroit, MI). It was also

stimulated by Bookchin’s abysmal Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism. However, Watson’s work is aimed more towards defending

anarcho-primitivism and rehabilitating a non-Bookchinist Social Ecology

than towards the critique Bob takes on in this volume of Bookchin’s

leftover leftism served in biodegradable ecological and municipalist

wrappings.

[2] Edinburgh, Scotland & San Francisco, CA: AK Press, 1995. All

references consisting solely of numerals in parentheses are page

references to this book. All other references — be they to Bookchin’s

other writings or the writings of others — follow an approximation of

social-science citation style. That is, they consist of a parenthetical

reference to a source by the last name of the author and the year of

publication followed by, in some instances, specific page references.

For example, (Black 1994: 50) refers to page 50 of the book listed in

the Bibliography as follows:

Black, Bob (1994). Beneath the Underground. Portland, OR: Feral House &

Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited

Sometimes the author’s name is omitted if, in context, it is provided or

implied in the text, e,g., (1994: 50) where the text itself has

identified Black as the source.

I request the forbearance of readers who think that in explaining the

almost-obvious I am talking down to them. I expect that nearly all of my

readers are either familiar with this citation system or else would have

no difficulty figuring it out. I chose to use it to supply at least the

rudiments of references simultaneously with what I make of them. I

choose to explain the system here from an excess of caution.

I expect the Bookchinist counterattack to rely heavily on confusionist

quibbling about details, including bibliographic details. Some

anarchists are unduly impressed by the trappings of scholarship, unaware

that, if carefully scrutinized, they are sometimes only claptrappings.

Some are even susceptible to typeset text as such, as if typesetting

were some sort of guarantee that the text is presumptively important

and/or true.

To a considerable extent, Bookchin’s seeming scholarship is shallow or

sham, and that’s especially true of Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism. To demonstrate that, as this essay does, my scholarship will

have to be much better and much more honest. Careful referencing, and a

clear understanding of my method of referencing, is crucial to that

demonstration. For you, gentle reader, the worst is now behind you. Let

the games begin!